" ,-■'■'/' . .■ .■■ '/©>// ii umiu bs^i i W Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029045495 ENGLISH PHILOSOPHERS fJ'^-Z David Hartley AND James Mill BY G. S. BOWER, M. A. NEW YORK G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS 27 and 29 West 23D Street 1881 E.M. . CO UN I' I L- U M \ V li R S I I Y UttRAUY <8> CONTENTS. PART I. Their Lives. PAGE Ch. I. David Hartley 1 Ch. II. James Mill . v 8 PART 11 Theib Philosophical Systems and Opinions. Ch. I. Preliminary remarks on the Theory of Association of Ideasr-Tke Physical Groundwork of the Theory — Hartley's Vibrations — James Mill and Hartley on Sensations — Ideas as copies of Sensations ... 24 Ch. II. The Elementary Postulate?, and First Propositions, of the Theory of Association as laid down by Hartley and James Mill 37 The flornrnnnicatioii of Tdeas — Language — Naming . 46 The Theory of Association, as applied to explain the more important processes and operations of the mind . 65 Belief, as interpreted by the laws of Association . . 79 Leading metaphysical conceptions, forms, and rela- tions, as accounted for on the theory of Association — Sameness — Similarity— rSuccession — Causality — Ex- tension — Motion — Quantity — Quality — Analogy — In- duction Ill Ch. VII. The Active Powers of the Human Mind . . .136 "Ch. VIII. The Will, as explained by Hartley and Mill . . .164 Ch. III. Ch. IV, Ch. V. Cn. VI. iv CONTENTS. Cir. IX. The Practical Laws of Ethics, as resulting from the prin ciples of Association and Utility . . . .178 Ch. X. The Esthetic Doctrines of Hartley and Mill . . . 191 Ch. XI. The Principles of Utilitarianism and Association, as ap plied by Hartley and James Mill to special depart ments of Practical Life — Politics — Legislation — Edu cation — International Law 198 PART III. The Value and Influence of theib Opinions . . . 214 Bibliographical Appendix . . . . 247 HAETLEY & JAMES MILL. part h THEIR LIYES. CHAPTER I. DAVID HARTLEY. David Hartley, the son of a clergyman residing at Armley in Yorkshire, was born on the 30th of August, 1705. He was educated at a private school, and, in*l 720, entered at Jesus College, Cambridge, of which society he subsequently became a fellow. Owing to conscientious scruples with reference to the Thirty-nine Articles, he abandoned his preparation for the clerical profession, for which he was originally intended ; and thenceforth applied himself to the study of medicine. Com- mencing practice at Newark, he afterwards removed to Bury St. Edmund's, and thence to London. In the later years of his life, he took up his residence at Bath. In the exercise of his functions as a physician, he was sympathetic, assiduous, and skilful. He especially devoted himself to the study and cure of the stone, and was the author of several medical pamphlets on Mrs. Stephens' medicine for that disease, 1 besides 1 " Observations made on the persons who have taken the medicament of Mrs. Stephens," 1738. " View of the present evidence for and against . Mrs. Stephens' medicine as a solvent for the stone, containing 155 cases" B 2 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. being the instrument of finally procuring for her the reward of 5000Z. offered by Parliament. 2 He is said to have written against Dr. Warren in defence of inoculation for smallpox; and several other of his medical disquisitions are to be found in the Philosophical Transactions of the time. He was twice married, and had issue by both marriages. He died on the 28th of August, 1757, at Bath, of the disease which he had so patiently investigated in his lifetime. Both the philosophical and the moral character of Hartley were no less conspicuous in his life than in his writings. Philosophically, he was remarkable for patience of research, variety of study, thorough scientific candour, and a constant readiness to receive new impressions and ideas. Morally, he was distinguished by modesty, unaffected openness, and bene- volence. In the one case, his inquisitiveness of intellect well qualified him for a writer on the connexion between body and mind, and their reciprocal influence on one another, — a kind of inquiry where alertness in the seizing of analogies is above all things requisite ; in the other, his sympathy of heart was of eminent service to him in the observation and appreciation of moral phenomena. His great work On Man occupied sixteen years of slow thought and toil in maturing (1730 — 1746); and even for some years before 1730, " the seeds of this work were lying in latent germination/' as he himself used to tell his friends. One cannot fail to notice the results of this steady and per- sistent investigation, (extending over so long a period, and [of which his own was one], " with some experiments and observations," 1739. "Directions for preparing and administering Mrs. Stephens' medicine in a solid form," 1746 (in the Gentleman's Magazine). Alar^e ingredient in this medicine was soap, of which the unfortunate Hartley was said to have himself consumed 200 lbs. before he eventually died of the disease. 3 Gazette, June, 1739. DAVID HARTLEY. into so many different fields), in the astonishing wealth of illustrative matter by which the principles laid down in his book are confirmed. It was first published in two volumes in 1749. Another edition by Dr. Priestley with elucidatory dissertations appeared in 1775. In this the vibration theory, and most of the Second Part on theological questions, were omitted. But the book was, notwithstanding, practically almost ignored till 1791. In 1801, Hartley's son published the entire work, in three volumes, from the German of the Rev. Dr. Herman Andrew Pistorius, rector of Poseritz, in the island^ of Riigen, accompanied with the latter's notes and essays. 3 Hartley himself was not at all sanguine as to the chances of the immediate acceptance of his novel theory. " He did not expect that it would meet with any general or imme- diate reception in the philosophical world, or even that it would be much read or understood ; neither did it happen otherwise than as he had expected. But at the same time he did entertain an expectation that, at some distant period, it would become the adopted system of future philosophers. That period" [writes his son in 1801] "seems now to be approaching," — and by this time it has arrived, and a formi- dable and industrious school of philosophy, known as the Association Psychology, has been constituted on the lines sketched out by him. From a very early age, Hartley had a faney for natural science, experimental philosophy, and mathematics, which he studied under the tuition of a celebrated man in his day, Professor Saunderson. To optics, statics, and other special departments of science, he devoted himself in company with Dr. Hales, Dr. Smith (then Master of Trinity College, Cam- bridge), and some other members of the Royal Society. He * This is the edition to which the references throughout this work are made. B 2 4 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. was a keen observer, in the exercise of his professional duties, of physical peculiarities and habits, and mental diseases and defects ; and acquired early the habit of sound and rapid gene- ralization, which proved so useful to him in the construction of his philosophical system. Historical and chronological researches also claimed a large portion of his spare time ; and he was on intimate terms with N. Hooke, the Roman his- torian. In chronology, so far as physical science could be brought to bear on its numerous problems, as indeed in all kinds of natural science, he was an ardent admirer and dis- ciple of Newton, whose Principia and other works first suggested to him the theory of vibrations. He was much interested in all schemes for the reformation of language, either as written, (e.g. methods of short T hand), or as written and spoken both; and welcomed proposals of universal and philosophical languages and dictionaries, and similar fresh ideas. But it was to mental science, ethics, and theology that Hartley's tastes were principally drawn. In regard to these subjects, the intellectual atmosphere in which he lived was that of Edmund Law, Warburton, Butler, and Jortin, who were his intimate associates and fellow-labourers both in these fields and in that of ecclesiastical history. It was, however — as he himself acknowledges, with his usual candour — from one Mr. Gay that he derived the germ of his association theory — at all events, as applied to morals. It was only the germ, however, that he obtained ; and how fruitful Gay's two short treatises became in Hartley's hands it only needs a comparison of them with the latter philosopher's second volume to show. In the latter part of his life he corresponded very much with Dr. Priestley on their common subject. Nor did Hartley neglect the more distinctly humanizing studies of history, poetry, and art. Of the first of these DA VI D HA R TLE Y. 5 means of cultivation he yvas especially fond. He was a great admirer of some of the poets of his own country, such as Pope, whom he respected not only as a man of genius, but also, and chiefly, because he was a poet who " moralized his song," and pursued by a different road the same goal as himself. On similar grounds he was interested in Dr. Young, and also in Hawkins Browne, the author of a Latin poem, De Animi Immort ali tale. It must be confessed, however, that Hartley does not seem to have been a very enthusiastic lover of poetry, except as a veil for philosophy, and that he was disposed to regard the exercise of the imagination too much in a didac- tical light. Owing to this latter attitude of mind, he even took offence at the Essay on Man, which he thought inspired by Bolingbroke, and calculated to weaken the force and inviolability of the moral law, of which — though charac- teristically charitable in judging individual instances of its perversion in practice — he was extremely jealous. To the " lewd " poets, who discoursed of love and beauty, entirely unmoved by the puzzles of metaphysics and morals, he felt — and frequently displayed in his works — a hearty aversion. In "music he took a passionate delight. He was also a fair classical scholar; and the first prelimi- nary sketch of his system — a little treatise, De Sensu, Motu, ■et Idearum. Generatione, which he published in the form of an appendix to a medical tractate on the stone — was written in elegant Latin. With Hebrew he seems to have been at all events moderately well acquainted. All these vai-ied tastes were reflected in the pages of his work, as we shall have occasion to remark below. 4 So, also, * See Part. III. Cp. the Life by Hartley's son, Observations on Man, vol. ii. p. ix. ''It was from the union of talents in the moral sciences with natural philosophy, and particularly from the professional knowledge of the human frame, that Dr. Hartley was enabled to bring into one view 6 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. was his personal character. His amiability, — no pen was ever freer from gall than his, and in the whole of his work we do not find a single harsh criticism of a personal nature, while his kindly appreciation and recognition of the labours of his precursors is abundant and marked — his openness, and his easy-going laissez-faire tendencies, — all these are mani- fest in the tone of his recorded opinions, and the style of his writing. As his son says, "it may with peculiar propriety be said of him, that the mind was the man." His philo- sophical character was only his personal character in one of its aspects. Hartley's was a quiet, useful, unromantic life, — unromantic in all respects, except in that steady devotion to truth and fact which tinges the most uneventful life with a hue of romance, — too often of pathos. Eminently typical of the century in which he lived, — comfortable, and ready to com- fort others, — disposed to ponder and wait, not very prone to action, unambitious, — he was always in a mood to make allowances for the frailty of others, and to take things as they came, while he was utterly destitute of the " passion for reforming the world," which possessed James Mill. On the other hand, if his life was not lit up by such noble aims as that of his great successor, he had all the compensating advantages incidental to a lack of enthusiasm. While he was not to the same extent as Mill the cause of good to unseen masses of men, he made far more friends and intimates out of those whom he did know. The bitterness and violence, which in Mill's case were engendered by consuming earnestness, were unknown to him. No zeal could eat him up. His philo- sophical system was not converted by him into a dogma or the various arguments for his extensive system, from the first rudiments of sensation through the maze of complex affections and passions in the path of life, to the final, moral end of man." DAVID HARTLEY. discipline; by thus having no practical reference, while it won him no partisans, it made him no enemies. Though accurate and precise in his reasoning, and metho- dical in his daily habits, Hartley was far removed alike from pedantry and fussiness. He was polished and gay in society, and eloquent in conversation, without becoming importunate or a bore ; and he was entirely without the vices of pride, selfishness, sensuality, or disingenuousness. In the endeavour to suggest the proper associations of ideas to the minds of others, and to form their habits on the lines, and with the help, of their position and previous circumstances, he was " the faithful disciple of his own theory." He did what some one has said should always be done by every man, whether Libertarian or, like Hartley, an advocate of the doctrines ot Necessity : in actual life he regarded himself alone as free, and all other men as determined. " His person was of the middle size and well proportioned : his complexion fair, his features regular and handsome; his countenance open, ingenuous, and animated. He was pecu- liarly neat in his person and attire. He was an early riser, and punctual in the employments of the day; methodical in the order and disposition of his library, papers, and writings, as the companions of his thought. " [Observations on Man [Life), vol. ii„ pp. xvii, xviii]. During the nine years that elapsed between the completion of his book and his death, Hartley, though reposing from active work and collection of materials in reference to it, continued to keep his mind open to any further suggestions or discoveries that might have the effect of destroying or modifying any of his doctrines. None such, however, were made of any materiality sufficient to render an alteration of his Observations necessary. 8 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. CHAPTER II. JAMES MILL. James Mill was born at Northwater Bridge, in the parish of Logie Pert, in the county of Angus, on the 6th of April, 1773. His father, a shoemaker, lived in one of the little two- roomed clay-built cottages, some dozen of which made up a hamlet of the parish. Industry, soberness, and piety, with- out any remarkable gifts of intellect, distinguished the elder James Mill in his life and vocation. The mother, Isabel Fenton, was a woman of a somewhat different stamp. She was proud — (being the daughter of a substantial farmer, who had been in very good circumstances before he joined in the Stuart rising of 1745, she probably felt her marriage to have been something of a descent, and was not slow in manifesting her feelings to her neighbours, and in domineering over their wives) — but, together with her pride, possessed some of the good qualities which usually spring out of it. She was most ambitious for her eldest son James, and soon determined to rear him to some destiny higher than his father's workshop. Her influence over her husband was successfully exerted for this purpose, for we find no record of James having ever been required by his parents to assist in his father's trade, or indeed, engage in any manual labour; while there are " emphatic assurances/' as Professor Bain ' tells us, to the 1 Life of James Mill, Mind, vol. i. p. 101. JAMES MILL. contrary. William/ the second son, took to the family busiuess, but the tender hand of his mother reserved James exclusively for study. So that it must be remembered that to her pride and motherly interest we, in some degree, owe the Analysis aud the History of British India. At Montrose Academy, one of the Scotch grammar-schools, James acquired the rudiments of a good classical education, and meanwhile received kindly and constant encouragement in his studies and aspirations from the minister of his parish, Mr. Peters. At about the age of eighteen he came under the notice of Sir John Stuart, of Fettercairn, one of the Barons of the Exchequer in Scotland, a man who, though reputed in the neighbourhood to have been haughty and morose, must always command our respect for his fidelity to his young friend. By Sir John and Lady Jane Stuart's influence James Mill was sent, in the year 1790, to the University of Edinburgh, under the following circumstances : — " Some pious ladies," writes Mr. Bisset, 3 "amongst whom was Lady Jane Stuart (she was then 'Belsches'), "having established a fund for educating one or two young men for the Church, Ladjr Jane applied to the Rev. Mr. Foote, minister of Fetter- cairn, to recommend some one. Mr. Foote applied to Mr. Peters of Logie Pert, who recommended James Mill, both on account of his own abilities, and the known good character of the parents." It was a great advantage to Mill to be able to go to Edinburgh at a mature age (for a Scotch university), instead of receiving his education as a boy at Aberdeen, as, without the intervention of the Stuarts, he would in the ordinary course have been compelled to do. Being at this period destined for the^Church, he was bound to frame his 3 Besides the two sons there was a daughter, Mary, who was the youngest child. 3 In the article on James Mill, in the Encyclopedia Britanmca. 10 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. course of study accordingly. Moral philosophy iu the first place was required; nor, had it not been, can we imagine Mill neglecting it, more especially as the professor and lec- turer was Stewart, of whose discourses on this subject he ever afterwards spoke with the greatest enthusiasm, even declaring that their eloquence was superior to that of the most admired speeches of Pitt and Fox. He is recorded in the registers of the university as having attended the Greek, Latin, natural philosophy, and logic classes, between 1790 and 1792. There is no mention of mathematics, but it is probable that he attended this class, because of Playfair's reputation, and also because he could scarcely have otherwise begun natural phi- losophy and Newton's Principia under Robison. John Stuart Mill {Autobiography) supposes that he may have also studied in the medical classes at this time. During his residence at Edinburgh James Mill became acquainted with a variety of men, who subsequently became distinguished in their different walks of life, and some of whom kept up their intimacy with him to the last. Among these were Brougham, who probably then commenced a friendship which did not terminate with his Chancellor- ship, Professor Wallace, Thomas M'Crie, John Leyden, Jeffrey, and Mountstuart Elphinstone. Mill's divinity studies proper began in 1794, and lasted for four winters. Professor Bain gives a curious list of the works which he took out from the Theological Library at this period, which shows very fairly the bent of his mind. A large proportion of these are philosophical, such as Alison on Taste, of which he afterwards made considerable use in the Analysis, Cudworth's Morality, Smith's Theory of Moral Sen- timents (to which he also refers in the Analysis), Locke, Reid, Hume, Rousseau, Bolingbroke, Ferguson, Jortin (a friend of Hartley's), and especially Plato, of whose influence (strange JAMES MILL. ii as it may seem) many traces are to be found in the method, and even sometimes in the tone, of his philosophy. In other departments of literature, . we find him reading Rousseau's Emile and Discours, Massillon's Sermons, Karnes's Sketches, HakewelFs Apology, Campbell on Rhetoric, (Eiwres de Fene- lon, Maupertuis, Abernethie's Sermons, Whitby on the Five Points, &c. He must, therefore, have become by this time a very fair French scholar. But one sees that divinity was not occupying' a very large share of his time. However, on the 1st of February, 1797, he is introduced by Mr. Peters to the Presbytery of Brechin, with his proper certificates, to be licensed as a preacher. After the due amount of "questionary trials," probationary sermons, lectures, homilies, and the like, he is formally licensed on the 4th of October, 1798. He began to preach in the church of Logie Pert. Those who heard him said that his voice was " loud and clear," but we are told that " the generality of the hearers complained of not being able to understand him ;" and we may easily imagine that his discourses were somewhat over the heads of the good people of Logie Pert. He also preached in Edinburgh, where Sir David Brewster heard him. From 1790 to 1802, Mill acted as private tutor in the Fettercairn family, (where, during the vacations of his Edinburgh course, he instructed Miss Stuart, 4 for whom he always preserved the warmest affection), and also in the family of Mr. Burnet at Aberdeen, (this tutorship he is reported to have given up, owing to an insult put upon him at a dinner-party), and in some others. The tradition as to his haying been tutor to the Marquis of Tvveeddale does not appear to be substantiated. These tutor- 4 This was the lady who married the son of the banker, Sir William Forbes, and was the mother of a distinguished Edinburgh Professor of Natural Philosophy, James David Forbes. Sir Walter Scott was vehe- mently, but fruitlessly, devoted to her before her marriage. 12 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. ships were his first source of income. Meanwhile his parents were becoming somewhat reduced in circumstances. James Mill generally spent what time was spared him from his university studies and tutorial engagements at his home, of which we have the following picture by Professor Bain : " The best room of the house contained two beds along the right hand wall ; in that room the mother hung up a canvas curtain (' cannas ' it was called, being what is laid on the threshing-floor to keep the corn together) ; thus cutting off. from the draught and from the gaze, the further end of the room, including James's bed, the fire, and the gable window. This was his study. . . . Here he had his book-shelves, his little round table and chair, and the gable window-sill for a temporary shelf. He had his regular pedestrian stretches; one secluded narrow glen is called 'James Mill's walk/ He avoided people on the road ; and was called haughty, shy, or reserved, according to the point of view of the critic. . . . His meals were taken alone in his screened study ; and were pro- vided by his mother, expressly for his supposed needs." Cer- tainly it cannot be said that James Mill was not appreciated by his parents, at all events by his mother. Nor did he lack sympathetic friends in David Barclay, Peters, and others, at Logie Pert, besides his little knot of associates in Edin- burgh. In the beginning of 1802 all preaching and tutorial work was given up, and James Mill went up to London in company with Sir John Stuart. Now commenced his journaligfcie career, into which he entered with zeal and energy. Imme- diately on his arrival in London we find him recounting in a letter to his Edinburgh friend, Thomas Thomson (a well- known devotee of science, and especially chemistry), his literary adventures and prospects. He was delighted with the large scope which London life afforded to an ambitious JAMES MILL. 13 spirit, as compared with the life of his "over-cautious country- men at home," where "everybody represses you, if you but propose to step out of the beaten track/' He obtained intro- ductions from Thomas Thomson to Dr. Robert Bisset, and Dr. Gifford, editor of the Anti-Jacobin Review. Besides this, he takes the greatest interest in politics, and often goes to the House of Commons to hear the speeches of Pitt, Fox, and Sheridan. Of the eloquence of the other members whom he heard he had the lowest possible opinion. He has an idea of starting a class of jurisprudence, and of entering one of the Inns of Court, for that purpose, but subsequently abandons it. It may be inferred that he had studied law, or at all events the philosophy of law, at Edinburgh, and had perhaps begun to study Bentham in Dumont's translation. His first few weeks in London were thus full of hopes and schemes and enthusiasm. He soon gets into harness as a journalist. Dr. Bisset first of all tried him as an occasional writer on politics. For Dr. GifFord's Anti-Jacobin Review he writes his fii'st philosophical production, a review of Belsham's Elements of Logic and Mental Philosophy, which is very interesting as containing an attack on Hartley's theory of vibrations, and also on the selfish theory of morals, which "imposes anobligation to be vicious, removes the moral character of the Deity, and renders it im- possible to prove a future state." An argument appears in this connexion, which seems to reflect a turning-point in the history of his religious belief. He contends that till the moral attributes of God are proved, it is useless to offer proofs of revelation. " Unless I know that God is true, how do I know that His Word is true?" Another article from his pen followed shortly after this in the same Review — on his friend Thomson's System of Chemistry. Besides reviewing for Dr. Gifford, he is now writing articles i 4 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. for the Encyclopedia Britannica, on which he hopes to be able to support himself at least for a year. " I am willing to labour hard and live penuriously," he writes to Thomson in May, " and it will be devilish hard, if a man, good for any- thing, cannot keep himself alive here on these terms." The rewriting and rearrangement for Dr. Hunter of a work-called Nature Delineated, brought him in some more money, besides making him known to the booksellers ; so that at the end of May he was able to take rooms by the year in Surrey Street, with an old pupil of Thomson's. Meanwhile he was attending the debates in the House of Commons with the keenest interest. In November Mill had an opportunity of showing his powers not only as a contributor, but as an editor as well. Together with Baldwin he projected a new periodical, to be " devoted to the dissemination of liberal and useful know- ledge," called the Literary Journal. It was to embrace Physics, Literature, Manners, Politics, to commence in January, 1803, and to be issued weekly in shilling numbers. Mill was to be editor and contributor for four years. He corresponded extensively with all his friends, in order to get assistance in the various departments, and especially took counsel with Thomson, whose brother James was to undertake the Literature and Philosophy of the Mind. Thomas Brown, the metaphysician, was also thought of; but, whether he accepted the offer or not, we are not told. Most of the Edin- burgh contributions were very good, but those from London quite the reverse. " His energies and his hopes," Professor Bain tells us, "were concentrated in the success of his bold design. It was no small achievement for a young man to have induced a publisher to make the venture. But he had the power of getting people to believe in him. He was also cut out for a man of business, and shows it now as an editor." The first year of the Literary Journal contains some curious JAMES MILL. IS articles either written or inspired by Mill, such as an essay on the structure of the Platonic dialogue (he always maintained his admiration for the Platonic mode of philosophical pro- dure), another (curiously enough) to prove that Utility is not the foundation of virtue, and another on Stewart's Life of Reid, wherein some of his well-known opinions on the neces- sity of bringing early influences systematically to bear on children are for the first time expressed. In the year 1804- were produced (amongst others) a thoroughly characteristic paper on religious feeling as distinguished from action, 5 and several reviews of apologetic treatises in theology, most of which he is inclined to discourage. In 1805 Mill continues the Journal, and also publishes his translation of Villers' work on the Reformation, adding very copious notes of his own, in which he quotes largely from, and refers to, Dugald Stewart, Robertson, George Campbell, &c, expresses here and there his poor opinion of Voltaire, who " used not only lawful but poisoned arms against religion and liberty," and warmly defends the books of the Bible as comprising " the extraordi- nary code of laws communicated by a benevolent divinity to man." Villers' Kantism is also thrown in his teeth : conse- quently, since Mill was a conscientious man, we must presume thai he had made himself acquainted with the writings and arguments of Kant (probably in some French translation) : also that he was as yet far from having reached the purely negative standpoint in religion. In this year Mill further commenced his editorship of the St. James's Chronicle, about which unfortunately little is known. The proprietor was Baldwin, his co-adventurer in the Journal. The paper lasted for at least two or three years, possibly more. In 1806 the 5 "Religion," he says in it, " without reason may be feeling, it may be the tremors oE the religious nerve, but it cannot be piety towards God, or love towards man." 16 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. form, of the Literary Journal was altered. Henceforth it was announced that a Second Series would come out monthly, and that the plan of the contents would he somewhat varied. This year contains an article on Tooke's Diversions of Purley, which is a hook well-known in connexion with the ohsolete philology of the Analysis, a severe one on Payne Knight's Principles of Taste, and some reviews on works of Political Economy. In one of the articles a reviewer, whether with or without the editor's sanction, takes the side of the clergy against Dugald Stewart and Leslie. Soon after its transformation, however, the Literary Journal had to he given up. Apparently, it had not succeeded. The Chronicle, as we have said, was also abandoned not very long after this date. By these steps a large portion of Mill's income was withdrawn. His burdens, moreover, were increasing, since his marriage had taken place in the preceding year to Harriet Burrow, a lady of considerable beauty and grace, but to whose lack of the necessary intellectual requirements he was at the time quite blind. She, on her side, was soon dis- appointed with the union, which she expected to be productive of more material benefit to herself than it turned out to be. Consequently Mill in this year, to meet the growing demands of his situation, commenced his famous History of British India, which he fondly anticipated would only take three years in the writing. It eventually took twelve ! His steady friend Sir John Stuart ceased in 1807 to come up to London regularly for the Parliamentary sessions, and one more support in his uphill career was, not indeed withdrawn, but necessarily rendered less available. Mill's connexion with the Edin- burgh Review (1808 — 1813) had not yet commenced. A variety of circumstances therefore combined to render the year 1807 one of the gloomiest in his life. After such a brilliant start, everything now seemed to be working against JAMES MILL. 17 him. In strong contrast with his early letters to David Barclay, we find this of the 7th of February, 1807, written in a very doleful and desponding strain : — " I had a letter about the beginning of the winter from Mr. Peters, which informed me that you were all well, and managing your affairs with your usual prosperity, which, you may believe, gave me no little pleasure to hear. I should be happy to see it too. Have you no good kirk yet in your neighbourhood, which you could give me and free me from this life of toil and anxiety which I lead here ? This London is a place in which it is easier to spend a fortune than to make one. I know not how it is ; but I toil hard, spend little, and yet am never the more forward." At this time also his father's complicated affairs were the cause of a demand being made upon him for 501., which not a little distressed him ; and altogether the future looked decidedly dark. During all this period he is recorded to have enjoyed the society of an extensive literary circle, but not to have made many friendships in London, owing to the strong dislikes which he used with great rapidity to conceive, and his unpopularity on other grounds. 6 But in 1S08 came better things. In this year, which was a notable one in Mill's career, commenced his friendships with Bentham, with Ricardo, with General Miranda, and with William Allen, the Quaker and chemist of Plough Court. In this year also his intimacy with Brougham — he had been acquainted with him previously in Edinburgh — was formed, as aleo his connexion with the Edinburgh Review, under the editorship of Jeffrey. Each of these friendships and con- 6 From this point we may pass much more rapidly over the remaining "■round, hoth because Mill's subsequent career was of a more public nature, and the works which record it (such as J. S. Mill's Autobiography) are move generally known ; and also because Part III. in some measure deals with it. C 18 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. nexions gave its separate and distinguishable colour to Mill's habits of thinking, and aims in life, at least during the years 1808 — 1819, while some of them influenced him much longer. During all this time the History of British India was slowly progressing. And in the earlier part of this period his views on religion were becoming fixed, and approaching more and more nearly to absolute negation. The connexion with Bentham was of course the pre- dominating influence of his life. Mill used to stay with Bentham for short periods at his house (called Barrow Green) at Oxted, in the Surrey hills, during the years 1807 — 1814; and afterwards, during much longer portions of the year, at Bentham's new house, Ford Abbey, in Devonshire, during the years 1814 — 1817. When in London, Bentham lived in Queen's Square, which was some distance from Mill's house at Pentonville. Being anxious that Mill should live nearer himself, in 1810 he gave him Milton's house, which was almost adjoining his own. After a few months, however, Mill removed to Newington Green, where he stayed for four years. But in 1814 Bentham leased a house in Queen's Square to Mill, who thus finally became his neighbour in London. The intimacy between the two philosophers was not with- out those little breaks and pauses — those unphilosophical squabbles — which are familiar to us from such well-known histories as that of the intellectual communion of Voltaire and Frederick the Great. In later life Bentham used to apply harsh expressions to his old admirer and disciple, such as " selfishness, coldness," &c. One day in 1814 we read that Bentham was offended because James Mill had left off taking his walk with him for a time, and the latter writes to suggest that they are in the habit of seeing too much of one another. On a later occasion Bentham surrep- JAMES MILL. 19 titiously sent over to Mill's bouse, while toe latter was engaged in the India Office, to take away from it all the books out of his library which he had allowed him to keep there and use, solely owing to some offence which he had taken at his friend's neglect. On the whole, however, their sympathy — personal and intellectual — was most cordial. Ricardo's friendship of course to some extent determined Mill's interest in political economy. Miranda's influence is important, since it is said to have contributed to the formation of Mill's religious scepticism, in conjunction with the authority of Bentham, of whom Miranda was an enthusiastic admirer even to the point of desiring to introduce into his native country, Spain, a Benthamic code. Mill's connexion with Allen, and the joint efforts of the philosopher on the one side, and the practical philanthropist and man of science, on the other, to ameliorate the education of the poor, are worthy of some notice, as they help to explain the former's views on education, about which it is evident from all his works, and from his son's Autobiography, that he felt very strongly indeed. Mill co-operated with Allen in the quarterly jourual called the Philanthropist, and with Allen, Zachary Macaulay, and others, in agitating their various educational projects. Among the proposed methods of educating the poor discussed in the pages of the Philanthropist were the rival systems of Dr. Bell and Mr. Lancaster (a Quaker). Mill, together with Allen, espoused the cause of the latter. The battle between the Bellites and the Lancastrians, as they called themselves, waged long and fiercely in the columns of this journal ; and in the course of the controversy a great many interesting educational questions were threshed out. The best means of civilizing barbarous tribes were also largely considered, as well as the systems in use at home for the reformation of criminals by means of penitentiary houses, and the like, in connexion with c 2 20 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. which Bentham's Panopticon was examined and approved. These and similar subjects, connected with the improvement of the condition of the poor in body or in mind all over the world, justified the description of the Philanthropist by its editor as " a repository for hints and suggestions calculated to promote the comfort and happiness of man." In connexion with Brougham, we may presume that Mill became interested in questions of legal reform. The defects of the English penal system are pointed out even in the Philanthropist, while the Edinburgh Review for these years contains several articles from MilPs pen on subjects connected with law and codification, English and foreign, mainly in relation to speculations and proposed improvements issuino from Bentham. The younger Mill always thought that Brougham exercised a much stronger fascination on his father than was just, and that certain defects of character — such as disingenuousness — were far from being compensated for by his attractive manner. James Mill's contributions to the Edinburgh Review, undei Jeffrey's editorship, extended over some years (1808 1815). Jeffrey used to hack his articles about remorselessly ; and Mill often, like other contributors, complained bitterly of this treat- ment, but was met with apologies, accompanied, however, by steady persistence in the line of conduct reprobated. Jeffrey was continually urging Mill to soften his tone of writing, and on comparing the Fragment on Mackintosh, for instance, with some of the articles by Mill in the Edinburgh Review, as altered by Jeffrey, we cannot help feeling that Jeffrey may have been in the right. The contributions of Mill during the above- mentioned years embraced the following subjects: Political Economy [article on Money and Exchange, Oct. 1808], Law and Codification [Review of Bexon's Code de la Legislation Penale — the first of his articles on Bentham's theories Oct. 1809- JAMES MILL. 21 article on the part of the Code Napoleon referring to criminal procedure, Nov. 1810], Education [the Lancastrian system is discussed in the Feb. number of 1813], Indian Affairs [April 1810, article on the government of the East India Company; July 1812, review of Malcolm's Sketch of the Political History of India; Nov. 181 2, article attacking the commercial mono- poly of the Company; July 1813, review of Malcolm's Sketch of the Sikhs], Religious Toleration [August 1810] ; Politics [review of a French treatise, Sur la Souverainete, by M. Chas, Feb. 1811], the Liberty of the Press [May, 1811] ; and the Emancipation and Condition of Spanish America [two articles in Jan. and July, 1809, evidently inspired by General Miranda.]. During the years 1815 to 1824, Mill furnished the articles to the Encyclopaedia Britannica which were afterwards reprinted in a separate volume, and have now attained some celebrity. In 1817 the History of British India went through the press, and on its appearance, at the beginning of 1818, met with a rapid success. A second edition was demanded in 1819. Meanwhile Mill was gradually rising in the India House, and in 1820 he was drawing a salary of 800£ a year from the Company, with promotion in store. At this time his old friend, Dr. Thomson, the professor of chemistry in Glasgow, wrote to inform him of a vacancy in the Greek chair at that university. Mill is said to have seriously thought of entering himself as a candidate ; but was prevented by considerations of the probable opposition of the Tories at the election, the necessity of signing the Confession of Faith, his possible advancement to the India Office, and the pecuniary loss which such a change in his circumstances, even if successfully brought about, would entail. By gradual advancements, Mill rose in the India House till he became chief examiner, in 1830, at a salary of 1200/. 22 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. which was finally fixed at 2000^. in 1836, a few months before his death. From 1819 to 1830 he was in the revenue depart- ment of the Company, and (as J. S. Mill tells us) introduced, several important reforms into the administration of India, more through his large unofficial influence with the directors, than by the use of any immediate opportunities afforded him by his position. The remaining points of interest during this last stage of Mill's life [1819—1836] are his connexion with the West- minster Review (beginning in 1823), his composition of the Analysis during six summer holidays at his country house in Dorking (1822—1829), the production in 1821 of the Elements of Political Economy, his electioneering efforts in Westminster on behalf of philosophical radicalism, his part in the institution of the London University (afterwards Univer- sity College) for unsectarian education, and his quarrel 7 and subsequent reconciliation with Macaulay, whose appointment to India he afterwards strongly supported with the directors of the Company. 8 One of the most extraordinary educations of modern times, familiar to all from the pages of J. S. Mill's Autobiography, was being concluded during the first two or three years of this period. Meanwhile Mill kept up some of his old intimacies, as those with Brougham, Dr. Thomson, and Allen, and formed some fresh friendships, as those with Grote, the historian, Mrs. Grote, Henry Bickersteth (afterwards Lord Langdale and Master of the Bolls, who advised him as to the toning down of the Fragment on Mackintosh), John Bomilly, and Charles Buller. In 1830 Mill left his house in Queen's Square and took one in Church Street, Kensington, where, as well as at his summer residence in Surrey, he spent 7 Be Macaulay 's Review of the Essay on Government. 8 Before setting out for India, Macaulay was earnestly counselled by Mill (as J. S. Mill tells us) to keep to the line of an " honest politician." JAMES MILL. 23 the remaining six years of bis life in comfort and prosperity. He had now become chief of the India Office. His nine children were all gathered round him in his house, and were one after the other being educated in the same way as J. S. Mill, the eldest, then twenty-four years old, had been trained. "For twenty years," says Professor Bain, "the house had been a school, and it continued so while he lived." In the latter years of his life he was troubled with disease of the chest, which began to affect him seriously in April, 1836. He gradually became worse, and expired on the 23rd of June. Mill's character was in some aspects grand, but scarcely in any lovable. His absolute honesty, his unswerving devotion to the cause or opinion which he considered right, however ,' unpopular it might be, his indomitable energy in overcoming \ apparently insuperable difficulties, his philanthropy — all these are beyond praise ; but his narrowness, his impatience, his \ want of tenderness and sympathy for minds differently con- < stituted from his own — these defects were unfortunately i equally conspicuous, and. should qualify our judgment on his merits. THEIR PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEMS AND OPINIONS. CHAPTER I. PRELIMINARY REMARKS ON THE THEORY OF ASSOCIATION OP IDEAS THE PHYSICAL GROUNDWORK OF THE THEORY HARTLEY'S VIBRATIONS — JAMES MILL AND HARTLEY ON SENSATIONS IDEAS AS COPIES OF SENSATIONS. The theory of Association of Ideas, now so familiar to us as applied to the different practical fields of language, law, morals, politics, education, religion, and sociology, was first formulated as a philosophical system, and made the serious study of a life- time, by Hartley. Obvious enough it seems when stated, and it is only when the question of the extent of its application comes in, that the widest divergency of opinion is manifested. Some sort of belief in it has always been tacitly recognized as the ground of prediction in the common affairs of life, and has been at the root of most of the proverbial philosophy and folk- lore of ages. Nor were more formal, though isolated, admis- sions of its validity wanting in the works of pre-Hartleian philosophers in different countries. Aristotle and Hobbes had noticed the principle (the latter under the name of Mental HISTORY OF THE ASSOCIATION THEORY. 25 Discourse). In France, Condillac (Hartley's contemporary) worked out similar results. The name had been invented by Locke. 1 One Gay had very briefly, but in a lucid and agree- able manner, sketched out his ideas on the subject, and applied the doctrine chiefly to moral phenomena, both in a disserta- tion prefixed to Edmund Law's translation and edition of Archbishop King's " Origin of Evil," and (probably) in an anonymous " Enquiry into the Origin of the Human Appe- tites and Affections " (1747), printed in Dr. Parr's "Meta- physical Tracts of the 18th Century " [pp. 48— 170] . Edmund Law, in his prefatory observations to King's work [pp. lvi, lvii], dwells with enthusiasm on "the power of Association which was first hinted at by Mr. Locke, but applied to the present purpose more directly by the author of the foregoing Dissertation " [the Rev. Mr. Gay], " and from him taken up and considered in a much more general way by Dr. Hartley, who has from thence solved many of the principle appearances in Human Nature, the sensitive part of which, since Mr. Locke's essay, has been very little cultivated, and is perhaps yet to the generality a terra incognita, how interesting soever and entertaining such inquiries must be found to be : on which account it is much to be lamented that no more thoughtful persons are induced to turn their minds that way, since so very noble a foundation for improvements has been laid by both these excellent writers, especially the last, whose work is, I beg leave to say, in the main, notwithstanding all its abstruse- ness, well worth studying, and would have been sufficiently clear and convincing had he but confined his observations to the plain facts and experiments, without ever entering minutely into the Physical Cause of such Phenomena." He speaks, too, with some impatience of the principle of Association being 1 Locke's Essay, — Conduct of the Understanding, § 40, 4th ed., 1690. See J. S. Mill's note on p. 377 of vol. i. of the Analysis of James Mill. 26 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. often slighted as vague and confused by later writers, particu- larly Dr. Hutcheson, 3 and expresses [p. lvii] his own convic- tion that " it will not appear of less extent or influence in the Intellectual World than that of Gravity is found to be in the. Natural." 3 This theory, then, of the Association of Ideas, propounded by Gay, ushered in by Edmund Law with the exuberant hopefulness which has always characterized the Columbuses of philosophy, elaborated by Hartley, and kept alive by Priestley, the elder Darwin, and Brown, was that which subsequently attracted the attention of James Mill, who added to it from the richer scientific stores then at his disposal, while stripping it of certain excrescences not necessary to the vindication and establishment of its truth, and solely due to the physical tastes of Hartley. Let us first find a statement of the doctrine in its very simplest terms. So far Hartley and James Mill are perfectly at one ; we will take the definition given by the latter. " Onr ideas," he says [Analysis, vol. i. p. 78] , 4 "spring up, or exist, 4- in the order in which the sensations existed, of which they are copies. This is the general law of the Association of Ideas, by which term, let it be remembered, nothing is here meant to be expressed but the order of occurrence." Next, what was that physical hypothesis with which, to Edmund Law's regret, Hartley encumbered his theory, and which James Mill, as we s hall see, c ast aside ? Hartley, like many another theorist, strained every nerve to evolve some grand and comprehensive law which should 2 Science of Morals, p. 55, sqq. 3 J. S. Mill uses the same comparison in speaking of the theory. " That which the Law of Gravitation is to Astronomy .... the Law of the Association of Ideas is to Psychology." Comte and Positivism, p. 53. 4 Throughout this work the references are to J. S. Mill's edition of The Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, 1869. VIBRA TIONS. 27 interpret all the phenomena. His bias towards simplifica- tion was excessive; and the consequence was that his foun- dations were not wide enough to support the supersti'ucture. Not content with showing how large a variety of our mental processes are merely instances of the general law of Associa- tion as stated above, and bow many of our complex ideas are, on analysis, reducible to simple ideas (the copies, in his language, of sensations), he endeavoured to prove that the primary law itself was nothing but the experience of a phy- sical change in first, the nerves, and then the brain, produced in the first instance by the impression on the senses of external objects. For this purpose he assumed, on certain (chiefly pathological and medical) analogies, that, when sensations are experienced, vibrations in the infinitesimal particles of the medullary substance of the brain are set going by external objects ; and surmised that, on the removal of these objects, the vibrations survive in the form of miniature vibrations or vibratiuncules which represent or cause what, from the sub- jective point of view, we call ideas. The ideas (or diminu- tive vibrations) would necessarily be of the same nature and constitution, and have the same arrangement and sequence of their elements as the original vibrations (or sensations) themselves. The vibration theory was suggested, as Hartley tell us, by Newton's hints as to the relation between motion and sen- sation, just as, on the intellectual side, the association theory was suggested by Locke and Gay ; and, as a medical man and student of physical science, Hartley saw no reason why an ingenious combination of the two should not be effected. It is easy now to see why such a hypothesis in his time could be nothing but the merest guesswork, since, even at the present day, its lineal successor, the doctrine of " neural tremors" and groupings, under the auspices of such able exponents as G. H. 28 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. Lewes and Dr. Maudsley, does not advance the Association theory much, which is far better left to stand on its own legs as the expression of an ultimate psychological law. In his system of vibrations Hartley had to assume both the causal nexus and the existence of the alleged cause. The theory was doubly hypothetical. Granting the existence of vibra- tions at all, and, further, their activitj' to the extent and under the conditions postulated by him, there still remains unproved their operation in giving birth to sensations and ideas : he at most shows the probability of the concomitance of the physical and mental conditions in a large number of cases. His vibra- tions are like the French chemists' substance X,in being undis- covered and unproved, though unlike it in the fact that, even if their existence were proved, it could not be shown that they caused the phenomena to be accounted for and interpreted. Hartley, at the outset, anticipates that his readers may see little connexion between vibrations and the association of ideas, and modestly expresses his fear that he will be able to do but little in the way of combining the two theories, " on account of the great intricacies, extensiveness, and novelty of the subject." [Observations on Man, vol. i. p. 6. s ] " How- ever," he says — and in these words he betrays the weak point in his attempt — " if these doctrines be found in fact to contain the laws of the bodily and mental powers respectively, they must be related to each other, since the body and mind are." In the reason thus naively assigned the whole question is begged. Starting from Newtonian principles, he first lays down that the immediate instrument of sensation and motion is to be found in the medullary substance of the brain, spinal marrow, and nerves ; and, furthermore, that the medullary substance of 5 Our references throughout are to the edition of Hartley's works in 3 vols.) by his son [1801]. VIBRA TIONS. 29 the brain is the immediate instrument of ideas, so that a change in the former works a corresponding change in the latter. But sensations notoriously persist after the removal or disappearance of the external phenomena which occasioned them. Now, no motion can persist of itself in any space or part of a physical body, except a vibratory one. Therefore, he argues, these surviving sensations must be the result cf vibra- tory motions communicated first to the nerves, and then to the brain, by sensible objects. Then, as if not quite sure of the efficacy of his reasoning, he adds, that if the vibrations could be proved independently by physical arguments, the persistence of sensation after disappearance of the object might be proved from vibrations, instead of vice versa. This latter task he then sets himself to do, and assumes (without proving) certain probable exciting causes, conditions, and media of the vibrations, such, for instance, as a very subtle and elastic fluid or asther, which he holds to be " of great use in performing sensation, thought, or motion." [Vol. i. p. 32.] He speaks also of the infinitesimal character of the particles of the medullary substance operated upon, and their uniformity, continuity, softness, and active powers, as favour- ing his hypothesis. Here again he is taking hints from Sir Isaac Newton. He also brings forward analogies and illus- trations derived from the exercise of his own profession, 6 and attempts to show how the phenomena of pleasure and pain, of sleep, and of light, are agreeable to his theory, and how muscular contractions and motions (automatic, semi-volun- tary, and voluntary, according to his division) are all satis- torily explained by it. The general conclusion is, that vibrations and association mutually support one another. 6 He has a section (vol. i. pp. 264 — 268) on the Relation of the Art of Physic to, and the improvements which it is capable of receiving from, the Vibration Theory, judiciously applied. 30 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. * "One may expect that vibrations should infer association as their effect, and association point to vibrations as its cause." Ultimately, however, he leaves us somewhat in the dark as to which is to be held the cause of the other, and seems to con- tent himself with placing the two laws in juxtaposition, expounding their coiTespondenceand parallelism, and drawing' the inference that the agreement of the doctrines, "both with each other and with so great a variety of the phenomena of the body and mind, may be reckoned a strong argument of their truth." [Vol. i. p. 114.] He even appears to give up the idea of a definite causal relation in the assertion that " as in physics, we may make the quantity of the matter the exponent of the .gravity, or the gravity the exponent of it," so, in inquiries into the human mind, " if that species of motion which we term vibrations can be shown by probable arguments to attend upon all sensations, ideas, and motions, and to be proportioned to them, then we are at liberty either to make vibrations the exponent of sensations, ideas, and motions, or these the exponents of vibrations, as best suits the inquiry, however impossible it may be to discover in what way vibrations cause, or are connected with, sensations or ideas." [Observ. on Man, vol. i. p. 32.J And he then abandons himself for a moment to a wild search for a cause behind the cause, for a hypothetical substance on which to rest a hypothetical kind of motion, and suggests an infinitesimal elementary one, intermediate between the soul and the bodj'. As his work proceeds, however, we find him merely placing side by side with each law of Association successively enun- ciated the corresponding law of the vibration theory, by sub- stituting vibration for sensation, vibratiuncules for simple ideas of sensation (that is, vestiges or images of sensations left behiud in the brain), and complex miniature vibrations (compounded of simple miniature vibrations running into one another) for THE ELEMENTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. 31 complex (or the moi - e intellectual) ideas, compounded of simple ideas of sensation running into one another. These laws of the association, both of vibrations (on the physical or external side), and of sensations and ideas (on the subjective or psy- chical side), Hartley (as stated above) believed to apply also to the association of muscular contractions. Consequently, he expresses his vibration-association theory in its complete shape and threefold application in the following' formula or theorem : — 1. If an}' 2. 3. Sensation A. Idea B. or Muscular Motion 0. be associated for a suffi- cient numbeT of times with any other Sensation D. d, the simple idea belong- it will at last, ing to D. Idea E. „ when occur- . The very idea ring alone, E. Muscular excite The very Motion F, Muscular Motion F. By a comparison of the first branch of this law with the second, it will be seen to express the obvious fact that the recurrence of one of two originally associated sensations does not guarantee the recurrence of the other sensation itself, because such a result depends on the disposition of external phenomena, independent of subjective conditions, but only of the ideas corresponding to it : that is, in any case of asso- ciation, as Mills puts it, the antecedent may be either a sen- sation or an idea, but the consequent must be always an idea. [Anal. i. 81.J I The elements or materials of all our mental states, according to both Hartley and James Mill, may be represented by the following scale or psychological spectrum : — 1. Sensations (impressed by external objects, in most cases, though not in all). 2. Ideas of Sensations, or Simple Ideas (Ideas surviving Sensations after the objects have been removed, or the Ideas most nearly allied to, and indistinguishable from, Sensations). 32 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. 3. Complex Ideas (the more purely intellectual Ideas, com- pounded of the above). It is natural, therefore, that both philosophers should com- mence with some account of the prime data, Sensations, of which they conceive all ideas to be either copies, or com- binations (according to the laws of association) of such copies, and into which, by analysis, they may ultimately be resolved. James Mill does not originate any startling physical theory of the senses : this, indeed, was not his object. He merely wished the student to accustom himself to reflect on the different classes of simple sensations, and learn to discriminate them not only from one another, but from all other feelings or states of mind with which, from their very familiarity, they were in danger of being confused. This was, in his opinion, a necessary step by way of preparing the ground for an examination of " the more mysterious phenomena." He accordingly gives a short account of the five senses of Smell, Taste, Hearing, Touch, and Sight, to which he adds two fresh classes of sensations, viz., those which accompany the muscular actions of the body, and those which have their seat in the alimentary canal, or the feelings associated with digestion. In discussing each of these in order, Mill points out that three conditions are requisite to sensation, — fi rst, i ts .organ, next, the actual, feelin g itself, and, lastly, the -antecedent of sensation, or the external object to which it is referred as effect to cause. "With regard to the muscular sensibilities, he expresses his surprise at the extent to which this part of our consciousness had, up to his day, been neglected by all philoso- phical inquirers in this country except Hartley, Erasmus Darwin, and Brown (all of them, it is noticeable, physicians). He explains this neglect on the ground that they are feelings in the main leading up to more interesting states of mind, to THE CLASSES OF SENSATIONS. 33 which the attention is immediately called off, to the swallowing 1 up of any interest in the former which might otherwise have been taken. In discussing the sensations of the alimentary canal, Mill justly (and somewhat dolefully) observes that " when they become acutely painful they arc precise objects of attention to everybody," though, in their ordinary form, they too, as being merely productive of, or preliminary to, more interesting sensations, are lost sight of and forgotten as soon as the latter supervene. 7 Hartley's description of the classes of sensations [Observ. on Man, vol. i. pp. 115 — 268], as coming from a physician, is fuller and more elaborate ; but, notwithstanding that it is replete with valuable and striking suggestions, its scope and aim is far more indefinite, and it forms a far less coherent and integral part of the general theory, than that given by Mill. In speaking of the various senses and sensations, he seems to have no very determinate object before him. Mill's purpose, on the contrary, was very plain and intelligible. His theory being that ideas are copies, or co mbinations of cop ies, of sensations, he begins with sensations, as being the primary element to which all intel- lectual operations are reducible, and the most simple and primitive of all onr natural states, no less properly than Euclid begins with his definitions, and then proceeds to his postu- lates, axioms, and theorems. And he dwelt on them just long enough for purposes of definition, and no longer. Hartley, on the other hand, though he began with pensation, could not confine himself within proper limits. In his long second chapter on " the application of the doc- ' Besides these, Mill notices the Sensations of Disorganization, or of the approach thereto in any part of the body (such as painful cuts, wounds, &c, and similar feelings) though here there is neither a specific organ nor external object of the sensation. Some of his remarks throw light on Kant's dictum that " pain is the sense of that which destroys life." D 34 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. trines of vibration and association to each of the sensations and motions in particular," Hartley seems to have had at least three objects indistinctly before him at various times : — (1) a division and classification of the senses (though he brings forward no very satisfactory fundamentum divisionis, and often puts species on the same level as genera) ; (2) to show that the vibra- tions accompany ing the special sensations propagated diminutive vibrations representing the simple ideas of those sensations; and (3) to explain how the special sensations contribute to form our intellectual pleasures and pains " in the way of association;" which latter qualification exhibits a certain con- fusion in his mind, since the inquiry into the tones of mind produced by sensations is properly a physical, almost a medical, inquiry, and has nothing to do with Association, which pro- fesses to interpret the sequences of ideas as dependent upon, or related to, the sequences of sensuous impressions. 8 On the whole, then, we may take Mill's classification of the senses and sensations to be quite sufficient as a necessary introduc- tion to the theory of association; and the many interesting observations scattered up and down the corresponding part of Hartley's work need not detain us at present. Ideas are, as we have seen (when simple), copies, or (when complex) combinations of copies, of sensations. We have noticed Mill's succinct account of sensations, the originals: let us now see what he has to tell us, by way of definition and explanation, about the copies, images, or ideas, the other material of consciousness. Like Hartley, Mill first of all examines the idea in its simplest form : and, to both philosophers, the idea in its simplest form 8 James Mill falls occasionally into the same mistake, as, for instance, where he talks of dismal ideas being associated with (instead of beinw, as they are, produced, through direct physical agency, by) intestinal sensa- tions of discomfort [Anal. vol. i. pp. 101, 102]. SIMPLE IDEAS. 35 is that vestige or trace of a sensation which remains in the mind after the external phenomenon which occasioned the sen- sation has been removed. Hartley, indeed, at times seems to be so taken up with this aspect of the simple idea that he apparently disregards the other and far more important points of view from which it may be looked at. He confuses, for instance, the images before the retina of the eye immediately after the disappearance of a bright-coloured object, with the thought of that object at any time after its disappearance — a purely physical with a purely intellectual state or operation. And even Mill does not distinguish quite sharply enough between the mere persistence of a sensuous impression in the mind immediately after the vanishing of the external object, and the reproduction or recollection by the mind of such an impression long afterwards. " When our sensations cease, by the absence of their objects, something remains. This something is a feeling which, though distinguishable from the sensation itself, is yet more like it than anything else, and therefore may not inaptly be called a copy, trace, or representation of the sensation." To this latter class of ■ feelings — to every feeling, that is, other than a sensation in immediate relation to its exciting object — Mill gives the generic name, Ideas, as opposed .to seusations in the above sense ; and as opposed to Sensation in its other sense of the mental process, of which each specific sensation is an example, he proposes with some hesitation a term, which has since been taken up by Dr. Maudsley and others, Ideation. In this way we may be said to have Ideas of Sight, Ideas of Hearing, Ideas of Touch, of Smell, of Muscular Contraction, of Dis- organization, &c. In each of these classes, we experience " something which remains with us after the sensation" [of Sight, Hearing, Touch, &c, as the case may be] " is gone, and which, in the train of thought, we can use as its repre- d i 36 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. sentative." The sound of thunder, for example, the sensation, is the primary state of consciousness ; the thought of it, when it is gone, is the secondary state of consciousness. Music, when soft voices die, Vibrates in the memory : Violets when they die and sicken, Live still in the sense they quicken. Here again we have cases of the secondary state of con- sciousness, as Mill calls it. Up to this point the idea has been regarded solely in the light of a remnant of sensation, and ideation as a sort of dis- solving view, in which the idea represents the fading outline of the figures which were just now distinct and vivid. But Mill soon begins to introduce the discriminative or retentive powers of the mind, though he expresses their operations in his own peculiar language. On tasting a wine, or observing a colour, we often have at the same time a secondary con- sciousness of other sensations of the same class as, but speci- fically unlike, the sensations of which we then have a primary consciousness; we distinguish the two feelings in a train of thought ; and we say that the former sensations of which we have equivalents or images in our minds differ from those of which we have a present experience. Here we see the original conception of an idea as a mere remnant of sensation, a sort of weaker impression on the senses, considerably enlarged. And we shall notice, in the next two chapters, still further amplifications, when Mill comes to divide the ideas into classes corresponding in the main with those of Hartley. n CHAPTER II. THE ELEMENTARY POSTULATES AND FIRST PROPOSITIONS OF THE THEORY OF ASSOCIATION, AS LAID DOWN BY HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. After noticing the persistence of sensations (notably visible and audible sensations) in the sensorium, fancy, or mind — which he takes for his purpose to be equivalent expressions — after their exciting causes have been removed, and then ap- parently feeling conscious that this proposition does not carry us very far, since it merely represents a well-known physical law, Hartley in his eighth Proposition (vol. i. p. 56) begins to introduce us to the Association theory proper, and lays down that " sensations, ly being often repeated, leave certain Types or Images of themselves which may be called Simple Ideas of Sensation " [of Sensation, because, as Mill too says, more like sensations than anything else; and simple, as contrasted with complex ideas, to be noticed presently]. He compares this proposition with the foregoing one [Prop. III.], and points out that, whereas, according to the latter law, the single im- pression produces " a perceptible effect, trace or vestige " for a short time, the repetition, in the former case, produces a more permanent effect, and generates an idea " which shall recur occasionally at long distances of time from the impression of the corresponding sensation." So, too, Mill remarks the con- stant interchange of sensations and ideas in our mental experience, sensations suggesting ideas ; and those ideas sug- 38 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. gesting still further ideas more and more remotely connected with the sensation which set the train of thought in motion, and more and more nearly allied to sensations long past, till the sequence of ideas is broken in upon by some sensation impressed by an external cause independent of us, and a fresh train is constituted. Then do our ideas follow one another at hazard, or according to law ? The latter assuredly ; and the jaw of their succession is ^determined by the order of suc- cession or the order of co-existence of the corresponding sensa- tions. Hartley and Mill agree that there are two orders of sensations— the successive order, or the order which answers usually, but not always, to a sequence in time of their objects; and the synchronous order, or the order which answers to the relation of the corresponding objects to one another in space. When the sensations have been synchronous, the ideas of these sensations are synchronous; and when the sensations have been successive, the ideas of those sensations spring up suc- cessively, though not necessarily, of course, in exactly the same order of succession. From a stone", for example, several sensations are simultaneously derived — those of hardness, weight, roundness, colour, size, &c. When, therefore, the idea of any one of those sensations springs up in the mind afterwards, the ideas of all the others spring up, says Mill, simultaneously with it. 1 The sensation of hearing the thunder, on the contrary, follows the sensation of seeing the lightning- flash : when the idea, therefore, of one of these is recalled, the idea of the other follows in succession, and not simultaneously. The latter branch of the law is also most aptly exemplified by the case of committing passages to memory, where each word in succession suggests the following word. Of course a far 1 This hypothesis is obviously crude and ill-founded, as Professor Bain points out [Analysis, vol. i. p. 79, note], since the same individual sensation has generally a place in many different groupings or clusters. ORDERS OF SENSATIONS AND IDEAS. 39 greater number of our sensations, and therefore also of our icieas, occur in the successive than in the synchronous order. Also nearly all the sensations occurring 1 either simultaneous!}' or successively occur very frequently in their respective orders, and the frequent repetition tends to rivet more firmly the corresponding sequences and associations of the ideas. The above doctrines are expressed by Hartley in a somewhat different way, but to the same effect, in two of the propositions into which he delights to pack up his philosophy, namely, (1) the proposition, already noticed, that sensations, by being often repeated, leave types or images of themselves, called Simple Ideas of Sensation : this would include Mill's per- petuation of the synchronous order of sensations in subsequent ideation, e. g. in the case of the simultaneous sensations excited by a rose through its different sensible qualities: (2) any sensations, A, B, C. &c, by being associated with one another a sufficient number of times, get such a power over the cor- responding ideas, a, b, c, &c, that any one sensation. A, when impressed alone, shall be able to excite in the mind, b, c, &c, the ideas of the rest. [Prop. X., vol. i., p. 65]. This asso- ciation would include both the case of simultaneity and that of succession. Hartley gives us the physical counterpart of the latter of these two laws as follows : Any vibrations, A, B, C, &c, by being associated together often enough, get such a power over a, b, c, &c, the corresponding miniature vibrations, that any one vibration, A, when impressed alone, shall be able to excite b, c, &c, the miniatures of the rest. [Prop. XI.]. The former he translates into vibration lan- guage thus : Sensory vibrations, by being often repeated, beget in the medullary substance of the brain a disposition to diminutive vibrations, or vibratiuncules. Having explained that sensations associated often enough tend to generate similarly associated ideas, Mill goes on to 40 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. show that there are degrees of strength in the associative link itself, as there are degrees of clearness in the associated ideas. The symptoms or criteria of the relative strength of such links are, in the main, their relative permanence, and the relative certainty and facility with which they are formed. This may be seen by comparing the bond of association be- tween names and ideas in a well-known language, science or art, on the one hand, and an imperfectly known one on the other. The causes of strength of association of ideas are two : the vividness of the associated sensations, and the frequency of their association. This Hartley expresses as usual in terms of vibrations. [Vol. i., pp. 30, 31]. That vividness and frequency are two completely distinct causes of strong and intimate associations is shown by the fact that a single instance of a connexion of a highly pleasurable or painful sensation with one which would other- wise have been indifferent, will often be sufficient to forge an almost indissoluble link between the latter sensation, when recurring, or the idea of it, when subsequently springing up in the mind, and the idea of the pleasurable or painful sensa- tion. The sight of a surgical operator, or of a place connected with a delightful meeting, will respectively suggest painful and pleasurable ideas long afterwards to the patient and to the friend, although only once coupled with the sensations corresponding to those ideas. So, too, recently-associated sensations will, as compared with those associated at more distant dates, generate a strong association between the corresponding ideas, or between one of the sensations and the idea of the other, by reason of the vividness and pro- minence in the memory of the original sensations, irrespective of frequency. Conversely, a word frequently associated with a sensation, or the sight of a particular class of citizen frequently associated with the sight of a particular kind of CAUSES OF STRONG ASSOCIATIONS-. 41 dress, will create an equally strong association between the corresponding 1 ideas, though any one of the associations of the original sensations, taken by itself, would have left no impress on the mind at all. The next primary law of the association theory is a very important one. It is that, when several simple ideas are frequently united together in the mind, they gradually merge into a complex whole , the several parts of which are practically indistinguishable, only distinguishable, that is, by a conscious effort of analysis : or, as Hartley puts it shortly, simple ideas will run into a complex idea by means of association, in which case, according to the vibration hypothesis, " we are to suppose " that simple miniature vibrations run into a complex miniature vibration. Mill compares the analogous physical effect of a rapidly revolving wheel, on seven parts of which the seven prismatic colours are painted, and which appears to a spectator white ; and Hartley characteristically instances the apparently simple flavour of a' medicine where the tastes of the several ingredients cannot be distinguished. Such an apparently simple id„a as that of gold is in reality a very complex idea, — one which the ideas (themselves not simple in every case), of hardness, colour, extension, weight, have by frequent union coalesced to form. The complexity of such abstract ideas as those of Humanity, Poetry, or Civilization, is more obvious. This law may be regarded as a case of the law of the generation of synchronous ideas by similarly synchronous sensations. Hartley draws attention to this, and,in his semi-mathematical language, puts the generalization thus: — A + B + C + D (sensations) often occurring together [or — though this does not seem so certain — A equally often occurring with B, C, or D alone,, or with pairs of B + C, B + D, C + D alone] generate the synchronous simple ideas a + b + c + d, and these synchronous simple ideas, by their repeated 42 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. union, coalesce into a cluster or complex idea, abed. He regards the merging of the ideas of the letters of the alphabet into the ideas of syllables, and the ideas of syllables into the ideas of words, — in fact the whole process of learning a language, — as a conspicuous instance of this law ; and says that, similarly, the most abstract ideas are capable, with per- severance, of being analyzed into such simple ideas as are but copies or images of sensations ; since, as simple ideas run into complex ones, so complex run into decomplex ideas; but the complex ideas which go to compose a decomplex idea adhere together less closely than the simple ideas which go to form a complex idea, just as letters adhere together more closely to form a syllable by association than syllables do to form a word, and these latter again than words to form a sentence. It is to be noticed that when a complex idea is made up of several simple ideas, one of which is a visible idea, the visible idea, being the most glaring, so to speak, will generally serve as a symbol to suggest and connect the reSt, just as the first letter of a word, or the first word of a sentence, will often call up the entire word or the entire sentence. In connexion with this part of the theory, Mill just mentions the principle (which will occupy our attention hereafter) of indissoluble association. Two or more simple ideas maybe so constantly and invariably conjoined that they form what may, from one point of view, be called a complex idea, with- out a special name, the parts of which, though specially named, it is impossible to disconnect, — such pairs of simple ideas, for instance, as colour and extension, solidity and figure, two straight lines and unterminated space. The sensations of colour and figure are so firmly associated with the sensations from which we infer distance, solidity, &c, that we even imagine that we see distance and solidity, though in fact we see only the former, and the rest is inference of a somewhat COMPLEX IDEAS. 43 complicated character. "We here have an instance of a sen- sation and an idea being so closely and repeatedly united that they merge into a whole which appears to be a simple sensation. Just as simple ideas thus associated cannot be disjoined, so neither of them can be conjoined by any effort of mind with the opposite of the other. Here we have the law of the in- conceivability of the opposite, about which Mr. Herbert Spencer's views have of late given rise to so much contro- versy. Mill further remarks that another instance of the law now under consideration is the case (already mentioned) of ante- cedent sensations or ideas leading up so rapidly to a train of more interesting consequent ideas, that a complex idea results in which the supervening ideas form the dominant element, and the antecedent sensations or ideas are almost entirely lost. The main principles of associatioh, as enounced by Mill, are compared by him to those which Hume put forward. The two theories, though expressed differently and worked out from a somewhat different starting-point, are found to be in substance much the same. Hume considers the elementary principles, according to which cur ideas are associated, to be Contiguity in Time and in Place, Causation, and Resemblance. Causation, however, even according to Hume himself, and certainly according to Mill, is only a particular case of Con- tiguity in Time; and Contrast, which Hume mentions as another possible principle, he himself admits to be derivative, as being a compound case of Resemblance and Causation, James Mill, indeed, thinks this analysis unsatisfactory, and prefers to call Contrast either a case of Resemblance (as when a dwarf suggests a giant, the two resembling one another in the, fact of both departing from a common standard), or a 44 HARTLEY AND J A MLS MIL L . combined case of Vividness and Frequency, as when the sensation or idea of pain suggests the idea of relief from pain, or of pleasure, because the sensation of pain has often been followed by the sensation accompanying relief from pain, and also, whenever it has been so followed, the associative link has generally been of a vivid and forcible character. There remains then Contiguity in Placfland in Tim^ .together with Resemblance. The two former correspond to Mill's syn- chronous and successive orders; and we have seen that the simultaneity or sequence of our ideas depends on the simul- taneity or sequence of our sensations. As to Resemblance, Mill, in a somewhat hasty generalization, infers that it is merely a case of the law of Frequency, because when we perceive an object by our senses we generally perceive other objects of the same class together with it. This is a very crude and unphilosophical explanation. We perceive, together with any given object, quite as many objects of different classes, at any given moment, as objects of the class to which it belongs, and, therefore, might be expected to have formed quite enough counter-associations to dispel the association which is alleged to be created in this manner. Reduced then to their simplest terms, Mill's primary laws of Association come to this. I. Whenever a strong association is formed between two or more sensations, the recurrence of any one of these sensations, or of the idea of any one of these sensations, will suggest the ideas of the remaining sensations either simultaneously or successively, according as the sensa- tions, of which the suggesting sensation was one, were con- nected together in a synchronous or successive order. II. The strength of the association is caused by either (1) the frequency of the association, or (2) the vividness of the sensations asso- ciated, or one of them, or (3) a combination of both. III. After simple ideas have occurred together a great many times MILL'S PRIMAR Y LA WS OF A SSOOfA TION. 45 simultaneously, or even successively, in an order corresponding to that of the associated sensations, they are apt to coalese into a single complex idea, which, from the close adherence and. interfusion of the parts composing it, will appear to be a simple indecomposable idea ; and when the association has been con- stant and invariable, those parts or elements will in fact, as well as appearance, be inseparable by any effort of imagination. IV. Complex ideas thus formed may, by a similar process, merge into decomplex ideas ; and in this way are formed the most abstract ideas which the human mind can frame. Thus, having, with Hartley's guidance, determined the constitatioa . and con struction of the materials of thought, viz. Sensations, Simple Ideas, Complex Ideas, and Trains of Ideas, Mill has^ayed^t]ae-fflay-iQJ--th g c ons id £iatioji^J,hjg^3nncipal operations i2iLiiiej!um.aja„J»J^^ rials. And first he examines the process by which (through the formation of links of association between ideas and sensible symbols) thought is communicated from mind to mind. This subject demands a chapter to itself. 46 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. CHAPTER III. THE COMMUNICATION OF IDEAS LANGUAGE NAMING. Hartley attaches considerable importance to the process of associating impressions, made by written words and uttered sounds on the senses of sight and hearing respectively, with the corresponding ideas ; and James Mill (always more pre- cise and methodical than his predecessor) gives the theory of Naming a definite and a considerable place in his system. In all the more intricate and complicated states of human con- sciousness, to which, after the explanation of the simple and familiar states, we are now about to proceed, " something of the process of Naming is involved." This artifice, therefore, craves immediate attention. In order to communicate the trains of our thoughts to others, as well as to record for our benefit and use our own past trains in the order in which the ideas composing them actually occurred, it was found absolutely necessary to employ sensible signs or marks. Mind cannot work upon mind directly. One person can only devise aud use visible or audible signs, which shall impress themselves on the senses of another person, and, by means of predetermined associations, call up in his mind ideas in a certain order, and at the same time signify to him that those ideas are passing, or did at some previous time pass, in his (the first person's) mind. Nor can we at will recall any set of ideas we please, still less in the order in which on some past occasion they occurred to us. If VISIBLE AND A UDIBLE MA RKS OF IDEA S. 47 we wish to recall an idea, that idea must be present to our minds in the very act of willing 1 to recall it ; and, of course, we cannot will to will to recall an idea. We have no power over the occasions of our ideas. But by our power over the occasions of our sensations, that is, natural objects, we can devise such an order of them as must necessarily, at any time we wish, raise up a corresponding 1 order of sensible impres- sions. By making, therefore, certain sensible impressions stand for certain ideas, we can ensure the possibility of raising up in our minds at any future time both the connexion and the order of the ideas which have formed part of any of our past trains of thought. For the first of the above-mentioned purposes of language, namely, the immediate communication of sensations or ideas to others, audible signs (owing to their rapidity and variety, and the flexibility of the human voice) are preferable to visible signs, or the language of action and pantomime, which savage tribes use to a considerable extent, and which, of course, is useless in the dark. For the latter purpose, the permanent recording of thought, the converse is the case : visible marks are preferable to audible, durable signs to evanescent. Man- kind first of all invented, by way of visible marks, picture- writing or hieroglyphics, the association here being a direct one between a portrait-representation and the sensible object, the idea of which is intended to be presented to the mind. Gradually the hieroglyphics became less directly pictorial, and more technical ; and began to depend more on the various combinations of certain fixed types or picture-symbols, than on the successive imitations in each case of separate sensible objects ; till, finally, men arrived at a new method of pre- determining the associations requisite for the recording of thought, that, namely, whereby different arrangements of a few letters (which stand for certain simple sounds or motions 48 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. of the vocal organs preparatory to the emission of sound), are associated with the various audible sounds which constitute the evanescent signs by which ideas and their order are com- municated to others. Thus the permanent signs have fixed laws of association with the audible, and the audible again with the ideas which they are intended to convey. The former, therefore, are secondary marks of the ideas, the latter are immediate and primary. It was of the greatest importance to man, in the first instance, to acquire the means of communicating to others the sensations affecting him, in order to secure the co-operation and assistance of his fellow-men in coping with the forces of nature. He, therefore, first devised audible signs of these sensations, such as hot, cold, black, white, pain, pleasure, sweet, bilter, &c. It next became advisable, if only for purposes of economy, instead of repeating on each occasion the marks of the various separate sensations simultaneously affectiug him in the perception of a sensible object, to invent sounds which should symbolize the entire cluster of sensations. Hence the names of External Objects, (the sun, the sky, &c.,) or Clusters of Sen- sations, or, in the language of later philosophy, " permanent possibilities " of clusters of sensations. Of these clusters some included a greater, some a less, number of sensations. Men advanced, no doubt, gradually from the latter to the former. It was then further found necessary to make these marks of sensations on the one hand, and of clusters of sensations on the other, stand for classes of sensations, and classes of clusters of sensations. Mill puts this again on the ground of economy, though, as we shall see, this was not the only motive which prompted the invention of class-names. In the next place, marks for Ideas were required. Ideas, as we have seen, are either Simple or Complex. And, for purposes of Naming, the Complex Ideas are further divisible MARKS OF COMPLEX IDEAS. 49 into those as to which the mind has not exerted itself to form the combination, but the cluster of ideas has been copied directly from a cluster of sensations found ready made, so to speak, in the natural world ; such ideas, that is, as those of external objects, rose, house, river, &c. ; and, secondly, those ideas in respect of which the mind has exercised its active powers in putting together arbitrarily various copies of sen- sations, and has itself constructed the idea of a cluster of sensations, which cluster does not answer to any object in fact existing in the order of physical phenomena ; such ideas, for instance, as centaur, mermaid, sea of glass, snark, &c, or again language, piety, nation, &c. The former of these may be called Sensible Complex Ideas, or copies, of clusters of sen- sations, the latter Mental Complex Ideas (answering to Locke's Mixed Modes), or clusters of copies of sensations. The names of the Mental Complex Ideas as well as those of Simple Ideas and those of Sensible Complex Ideas stand for classes, as well as individuals, in order to be as ex- tensively applicable as possible, and to economize the use of marks. But in the two latter cases, the name (according to Mill, though this seems decidedly doubtful) stands both for the sensation, and the idea of the sensation, for the cluster of sensations, and the idea of the cluster of sensa- tions ; whereas, in the case of Mental Complex Ideas, the name of course only stands for the idea, since there is in the order of nature no cluster of sensations corresponding to the idea. However, in escaping one sort of ambiguity (whether real or not), we are met by another; for, since the idea of the cluster is formed arbitrarily, each man frames his own idea of the cluster,- and therefore cannot be sure when using the name corresponding to it that he is communicating to another the idea which he himself possesses, since there is no actual cluster of sensations experienced, or capable of being experienced to E 50 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. which reference may be made as a standard. One man's idea of religion or of patriotism is not another man's idea. Half the debates and controversies, political, religious, and philo- sophical, which have occupied the attention of the world, divided a house against itself, distracted humanity, and often culminated in bloodshed and war, have arisen in large measure from the impossibility of one man conveying to another by means of names the exact complex idea in possession of his own mind. As soon as a name had been invented to stand for all the individuals of a class, it was found that, in the desire for economy, the name had been made to express too much. Men wished to distinguish between varieties of a class, and to signify sub-classes by signs. For this purpose adjectives were invented. This device, besides sufficiently effecting the ends of economy, had this further advantage, that cross-divisions were rendered possible, as well as (with the assistance of the copula) predication, which is a distinct means, or rather symbolizes a distinct means, of adding to the sum of our knowledge. (This latter feature in the use of adjectives Mill does not seem to properly appreciate.) Were names always to be invented for the smaller parcels into which the main genera are broken up, a language would become too copious for serviceable use ; the appending of adjectives, however, to the names of the classes, when occasion demands, serves the same purpose, while the adjective is available for breaking up, not one' class only, but several, into appropriate sub-classes. If substantives, consequently, are marks, adjectives are marks upon marks, as Mill says. Verbs are similar marks upon marks, and are essentially adjectives, but " receive a particular form, in order to render them at the same time subservient to other purposes." Mill's analysis of the moods and tenses of verbs corresponds with his analysis of the nature and use of CLASS NAMES. 51 adjectives, and exhibits the same incompleteness. He con- ceives the verb to be merely a name qualifying its subject, carving a sub-class out of the class represented by the name of that subject, and stating that the particular phenomenon adverted to belongs to that sub-class. He ignores the fact that a proposition with a verb in it does more than merely name; it involves a predication or affirmation, and is designed to convey information from one person to another as to the occurrence or order of sequence of certain sensations in the mind of the person communicating the information, dependent upon the occurrence or order of sequence of certain natural phenomena. If I inform another that the sun rose at 5 a.m. yesterday, I do not merely carve out of the class of rising suns a sub-class of suns rising at 5 a.m., and name yesterday's sun as belonging to that sub-class. I convey to him infor- mation as to the sequence of my sensations in a particular order and manner. And, similarly, if I say that the rose which I saw yesterday was a yellow one. To subdivide great classes into smaller ones, and save labour and multiplication of names, is not, as Mill seems to think, the sole or most important object either of verb-framing or adjective-framing; nor are verbs merely adjectives so fashioned as to imply " a threefold distinction of agents, with a twofold distinction of their number, a threefold distinction of the manner of the action, and a threefold distinction of its time." Besides the device of special marks to call attention to some one prominent sensation in the midst of a cluster or bundle of sensations, or to denote that a particular sensation or sequence of sensations was experienced along with the cluster of all those sensations usually comprised in its appropriate class- name — the provinces of adjectives and ordinary verbs respec- tively — a symbol has been invented by means of which, when coupled with a name denoting a sensation, or a cluster of E 2 52 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. sensations, we signify the fact that the sensation, or cluster of sensations so denoted, was at some past time in fact experienced hy some sentient being 1 — or is now being- so experienced, or might then have been, or may now, or at any future time, be experienced by any sentient being bringing himself within the range of possibility of being affected by them. This is the verb denoting Existence, the Verb Sub- stantive as it is called. When we say that a thing exists, or is, we mean that we may have sensations from it. This mark is, therefore, the most comprehensive and generical of all the secondary marks that have been invented. But there is an unfortunate peculiarity attending the named signifying Existence in most languages, namely, that this same verb is also used for the copula in predication. Predi- cation, according to Mill, serves two purposes; first, to mai'k the order of the ideas in a train of thought which we wish to communicate or record — (it will readily be seen that this account is insufficient ; we wish the order to be believed in as having corresponded to fact) ; — secondly, to signify that a certain name (the predicate) is the mark of the same idea of which another name (the subject) is also the mark — (here too, the essential element of information as to matter of fact is omitted). A name merely brings an idea of a sensation, or of a cluster of sensations, before the mind ; a predication denotes an order of sensations and ideas, and, supplementing Mill, we may say, that it conveys information and contains an assertion; it represents, in J. S. Mill's words, "some co- existence, or succession of phenomena experienced, or sup- posed capable of being experienced." {Anal. vol. i. p. 162. Editor's note.] Now, whenever we predicate, we employ the word "is;" and we predicate quite as often of sensations merely supposed, for the moment, capable of being expe- rienced, as of sensations actually experienced, or believed THE FALLACY OF THE COPULA. 55 capable of being experienced. Yet, in the former case, where the subject of the predication does not, in fact, exist, nor ever has existed, the copula " is," from its association in other connexions with the idea of existence, induces the habit of belief in the existence, in rerum nalurd, of what is in fact, a nonentity. In this way endless confusion of thought has arisen. James Mill points this out very elaborately, and was, indeed, the first to do so in any detail. Still further evi- dences have, since his day, been forthcoming from the Posi- tivists and others, to show the monstrous hypotheses, theories, and even systems, of philosophy for which this terrible little word is responsible. The Fallacy of the Copula was at the bottom of most of the false views of the ancient Greek, espe- cially the Platonic, philosophy. It has induced the personi- fication, even the deification of essences, qualities, attributes, &c. It has been the great king-maker of the metaphysical world : and from it alone such conceptions as Time, Space, Chance, Fate, Nature, hold their ontological dominion. Mill's further remarks on predication by means of Genus, Species, Differentia, Proprium, Accidens, contain nothing new or remarkable. His account, however, of the different kinds of trains of thought, which are represented by x predi- cation, deserves notice. In communicating or recording we have occasion to mark either (I) the order of sensations expe- rienced by us at any time, or (2) the order of ideas in a train of thought which has passed through our minds. In the former case the order which we desire to communicate or record, may either be the order of succession in time, or of position in space. In the latter, the ideas, the sequence of which we wish to represent by predication, are generally related to one another, either as cause and effect, or in the way of resemblance, or lastly as included under the same name. When a man forbears to strike a match near a barrel of gun- 54 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. powder, Mill says that the train of ideas urging forbearance is merely a sequence, or rather a set of sequences, of ideas : — "I strike the match on a box" — "the stroke produces a spark" — "the spark ignites the gunpowder" — "the ignition of the gunpowder causes an explosion." This set of sequences is all that is involved, according to Mill, in the predication, " This gunpowder will explode if I strike the match against the box." The analysis is here obviously, almost grotesquely, deficient, from the omission once more of the element of conviction. All the above ideas might successively pass through the mind without giving rise to the belief which would warrant a predication of the kind pointed out. \_Anal. i. 187. J. S. Mill's note.J Predication of Resemblance . is in the same way regarded as merely naming, and nothing else. And just as propositions or predications are nothing but naming, so also is the syllogism by which a third propo- sition is elicited from two of such predications as premises. All idea of there being an inferential process, or of fresh information being conveyed in syllogizing, is abandoned. The successive predications: "every tree is a vegetable" — "every oak is a tree" — "therefore, every oak is a vege- table," are, according to Mill, naming, and nothing but naming, throughout. The same criticism which applies to his account of predication will, of course, apply to his account of syllogism, on which we may have something further to say hereafter, and also to his corresponding view of arithmetical and geometrical propositions, as being merely verbal. When (according to Mill), we say that 7 + 5 r: 12, or that the three angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles, we merely call 7 + 5, and the three angles of a triangle respectively, by other names, the marking power of which is more precise and well known to us than that of the names which we first assign to them. NAMES OF NAMES. 55 There is one other bind of predication to be noticed, namely, that in which the subject is a name, and the predicate the name of a name, — predications, for example, which contain descriptions or definitions of terms, such as " argument," "metaphor," "oration," &c. It is somewhat curious that, having specially called attention to this class of predications, Mill failed to see that it is only to this class, as distinct from the others, that his theory of Predication as a mere naming operation is applicable. In such cases as these, and in such only, we really do not mark any sequence of sensations or ideas as having been actually experienced, or even as having been the possible object of experience : we here import no element of belief into the predication, and we do, in fact, what Mill wrongly says that we do in all predications, — " signify- that a certain name is the mark of an idea of which another name is also the mark." Mill's further remarks on the other grammatical forms of language, such as Adverbs, &c, have no very necessary rela- tion to his general system, besides being based on the obso- lete, though ingenious speculations, of Home Tooke, as con- tained in his Diversions of Pur ley. We pass on therefore to Hartley's account of the connexion between words or names and ideas. Hartley does not treat the various classes of words after James Mill's fashion, or show how names are first given to sensations, then to clusters of sensations, then generalized into class-names, out of which sub-classes are carved by means of adjectives and verbs : he proceeds on a rather different tack, and prefers, in accordance with the more physical bent of his studies and observations, to give a sort of natural history of the process by which in the growing mind ideas are gradually associated with words, and thought wedded to language. For, as he says, words and phrases must excite ideas in us by $6 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. association, and can excite them in no other way. Words may (physically) be considered from four points of view. They may be treated as impressions made upon the ear; or as the actions of the organs of speech ; or, again, as impressions made upon the eye by written characters ; or, lastly, as the actions of the hand in writing. And the above is the chronological order of the different ways in which children gradually become conversant with their use. The first of these relations in which words necessarily stand to the mind of a child, affords him some rough notion of their bare mean- ing, sufficient for the common purposes of life : the second makes the knowledge so acquired handy and serviceable : the third enlarges it, and renders it copious by association with other words in the way of definition and description : the last renders the mind "careful in distinguishing, quick in recollecting, and faithful in retaining, the new signi- fications of words " acquired by reading. Thus Hartley's very true account of the distinctive advantages of the methods by which a child learns a language, Hearing, Speaking, Reading, and Writing, corresponds exactly (as regards the last three of these) to Bacon's maxim : " Speaking maketh a ready man : reading maketh a full man : writing maketh an exact man." When a child's attention is directed to a particular object, (say, his nurse) the name of that object will be pronounced to him. This will occur frequently, till a bond of association is formed between the sensation of hearing the sound of the name and the sensation of seeing the face and form of the nurse ; and the child will then, whenever he hears the nurse's name pronounced (supposing him, that is, to have acquired sufficient voluntary power over his motions) turn his head in that direction ; and thus the process of association of the name with the visible idea of the nurse will rapidly be accom- GROWTH OF LANGUAGE IN CHILDREN. 57 plished. Later still, the converse process will take place, and the sensation of seeing the nurse will excite the audible idea of the sound of the name. He will next notice that the name of the nurse will still be repeated in her presence by those around her, notwithstanding change of dress and other acci- dental adjuncts, and that the name of fire, &c, will be pro- nounced notwithstanding that the cluster of sensations of heat, light, &c, may be accompanied on the different occasions of its being named, by different sensations impressed by adjacent objects. He will thus learn to distinguish between the strong associations of the names of nurse and fire with the con- stitutive elements of these objects respectively, and the less strong counter-associations of these names with the variable surroundings of the objects. In this he will be unconsciously performing the process (to which we shall come presently) of Abstraction. He will be creating, or rather re-cognizing for himself, one of those class-names of which Mill gives such a different account. The next stage in his mental progress will be that of associating abstract names, such as whiteness, with the ideas of the attributes common to several white objects, while by means of adjectives he will learn to make cross-divisions of clusters of sensations. He will, at the same time, be forming complex ideas out of simple by the process already mentioned : his idea of the nurse will comprise not only the simple visible idea of her face and form, but also the simple audible idea of the sound of her voice, and the simple idea of the taste of her milk, &c. The use and meaning of particles will be learnt mainly from their association with other names to which meanings have already been attached, they being, like the x, y, z of algebra, " determinable and decipherable, one may say, only by means of. the known words with which they are joined " {Hartley, vol. i. p. 274] . The attempts made by the child himself to express his own wants, then reading, and 58 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. lastly writing, complete the process of associating ideas with language. Though Hartley modestly confesses himself \_Ohs. on Man, vol. i. p. 277] "a mere novice in these speculations," and thinks that he has rendered " by no means a full or satis- factory account of the ideas which adhere to words by asso- ciation/' because, as he says, " it is difficult to explain words to the bottom by words, perhaps impossible," — yet it will be admitted that he must have studied the growth of association very carefully in children — a study of which evidence is afforded in several parts of his work — and that his lucid expo- sition proved of obvious service to James Mill in his more detailed theory of Naming. Words are, according to Hartley, divisible into four classes : — 1. Those that have ideas only : (excluding of course the visible and audible ideas excited by the sight and hearing of the words themselves.) 2. Those that have both ideas and definitions: (including under " defi- nitions," descriptions, and explana- tions by any but synonymous terms.) 3. Those that have definitions only, v4. Those that have neither ideas nor definitions. In the first class are comprised the names of simple sen- sible qualities, of what Hartley calls Simple Ideas of Sensation and Mill Simple Ideas, such as " white," " soft," " hot," &c. These are felt : they cannot be defined. No more can the names of right-hand and left-hand, &c, in any terms that do not involve a definition in a circle. 1 Most names of clusters of 1 On this ground Kant argues against the possibility of spatial relations being abstracted from particular and- individual spaces. That amusin" gossip, Sir Thomas Browne, in his Religio Medici (p. 17, 7th edit.), says " whether Eve was framed out of the left side of Adam, I dispute not; HARTLEY'S DIVISION OF WORDS. 59 sensations (Mill's Sensible Complex Ideas), that is, of most objects of the natural world, vegetable, animal, and mineral, apprehended by science, belong to the second class ; because, besides having ideas corresponding to them, they are capable of being defined by terms representing an analysis of those ideas into ideas of the sensations comprising the aggregates or clusters. To the third class belong what Mill calls Mental Complex Ideas, representing clusters of ideas of sensations connected together arbitrarily by the imagination (such as "centaur," "yahoo," &c), abstract general terms, algebraical quantities (roots, powers, surds,' &c), the technical terms of science and art, and, generally, those names of names which Mill especially notices. Particles, which have a meaning or possibility of explanation only in connexion with other words, come under the fourth head. Hartley (in pm*suance of a favourite analogy of his) compares rather neatly the above four classes to four corresponding kinds of mathematical relations, (language being, as he says, after all, only a kind of algebra). The first class would thus answer to purely geometrical propositions, such as do not admit of being ex- pressed algebraically ; the second to propositions which admit of being thrown into either form, geometrical or analytical ; the third to propositions involving equations of the higher orders, chances, quadratures, &c, which cannot be demon- strated otherwise than algebraically ; the fourth to the algebraical signs representing addition, subtraction, equality, &c, which have no meaning apart from their relation to other symbols. But as, even in the case of purely algebraical propositions, geometrical illustrations and analogies are advan- tageously employed to render intelligible what is otherwise because I stand not yet assured which is the right side of a man ; or ■whether there be any such distinction in Nature." There is not : henco the indefinibility. 60 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. exceedingly abstract and obscure; so fables, metaphors, alle- gories, parables, and myths, will often render vivid, compre- hensible, and easily remembered, the most subtle and purely intellectual conceptions and modes of reasoning. In fact, it is doubtful whether, except for such helps, the deeper truths of religion would ever become intelligible to the masses whom they are designed to reach : and the most influential and penetrating philosophies have been those which have made use of figures, metaphors, and analogies the most ; as, for instance, Plato's doctrines, as compared with those of Aris- totle, and the Baconian system as compared with the Kantian. Indeed, in the case of words of almost all kinds, not those representing abstract ideas alone, men are continually mis- taking one another, because they do not mean the same things by the same words, different ideas being associated with one and the same symbol according to the different surroundings and circumstances of the individual using it. Words, in the first place, may be associated by different speakers, with different sensible impressions; though this mistake is not common, and, when it does exist, is usually the result of a physical defect, such as colour-blindness, and is not, like the other misapprehensions of the meaning of words, an " idol of the tribe, - " or of " the theatre." Secondly, the ideas and definitions attached to a word in one man's mind may, owing to fuller, exacter, and more scientific knowledge, or richer artistic appreciation on his part, exceed in compre- hensiveness the ideas and definition attached to it in another person's mind. A yellow primrose means, both to a botanist and to a poet, infinitely more than it did to Peter Bell. To a Max Miiller the word "mill" means a chapter in the history of the Aryan race ; to an ordinary miller it represents nothing but the means of his livelihood. It is easy to see how, in the communion of thought between scientific and INTERPRE TA TION OF IDEA S. 61 non-scientific minds, artistic and non-artistic imaginations, confusion will inevitably arise, since both may use the same name, while each annexes to it his own meaning — a meaning which is really the result of, almost part of, his own life. But confusion and misinterpretation (as we have already seen) chiefly arise in the employment of names of the third class — names of Mental Complex Ideas — which have definitions, but no ideas directly answering to them ; though, of course, the terms of the definition are usually names (some of them, at least), of simple ideas of sensation. Here not only is it the case that the uninstructed mind will have a different defini- tion from that of the scientific mind of the name used in common by both : and that even when the definition is identi- cal in words, the simple ideas represented by the explanatory terms are often so numerous, that the chances of mistake incidental to the use of the above-mentioned names of the second class are indefinitely multiplied : 2 but it is also true that two cultivated minds, but cultivated in different ways, brought up in different schools of thought, and possessed by opposing theories, are even more constantly misunderstanding one another, and arguing at cross purposes. Neither takes the pains to get within the circle, and imbibe the atmosphere, so to speak, of the other's mental habits, and ways of looking at things. To an Associationist and a disciple of Kant, for instance, the names, "Cause, Will, Motive, Self, Idea," would suggest even more widely different ideas than they would in the case of the philosophic and non-philosophic minds. Can any one suppose that James Mill, for instance, or even J. S. Mill and Mr. Herbert Spencer, have ever really understood the 2 Take the word " cause " for instance. To the philosopher and scientific man this term means something far more precise than to the untrained intellect. In the latter case it includes a variety of relations, rigidly excluded in the former, such as occasion, condition, etc. )3 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. Santian or Hegelian stand-point? or that Coleridge and Mr. Stirling ever completely appreciated the point d'appni of the \_ssociationist ? In some few men, such as Goethe, and, in a ess degree, G. H. Lewes, one sees some capacity of interpreting iach view in terms of the other — a sort of " point of indiffe- rence," where true appreciation of both sides may be possible; nit such men are very rare. Hartley pathetically expresses i hope, rather than an expectation, that " since children learn he use of words most evidently without having any data, my fixed point to go upon, philosophers and candid persons nay learn at last to understand one another with facility and lertainty." [Obs. on Man, vol. i. p. 285. J In the fourth ilass of names mistakes must obviously be of rare occurrence, arer even than in the first, and " could not arise at all," says hartley, " did we use moderate care and candour." Indeed n an even more hopeful, if not in a slightly ironical, strain le subsequently expresses his opinion, that "it seems possible .nd even not very difficult, for two truly candid and intelli- gent persons to understand each other upon any subject." In connexion with this part of his subject Hartley has some udicious observations on the difficulty of translating one's lative into a foreign language, as compared with the ease vith which the converse process is effected, which contrast he dduces as an illustration of that law of association by which, vhen two sensations or two ideas occur together in the order \, B, or a, b, respectively, the sensation B, or idea b, on re- :urring, will not excite the idea a, with the same facility or egularity as that with which the sensation A, or the idea a, vill call up the idea b. He also has ingenious comments and uggestions on the subject of a philosophical and universal anguage — a kind of speculation which has engaged the ittention of philologists and grammarians, since the building >f Babel first elevated comparative philology into the dignity ANALOGY AND METAPHOR. 6$ of a science to the present day — and on the subject of a philo- sophical dictionary to assist "candid and intelligent" persons in understanding' one another ; both of which schemes may be noticed hereafter, together with other curious Hartleian fancies. We must not omit, before concluding this chapter, to notice Hartle3''s remarks on analogies and figurative language. " A figure," he defines as "a word which, first representing the object or idea A is afterwards made to represent B, on account of the relation which these bear to each other." But this is clearly a process applicable to every formation of a class-name. Indeed Hartley, though not very distinctly, admits as much, and says that, when the analogy is very complete, the expres- sion framed on it is considered a literal one (as in the case of class-names) ; when not very complete the expression is called a figurative one. If we suppose that the word " man " has been applied to several individuals, A, B, C, &c, one after the other, and that then the appearance of an indivi- dual X suggests the word " man," and he is denoted by it, because ol the analogy of X to A, B, C, &c, we have an intel- ligible law of association, and one which partly supplies the deficiencies in Mill's account of the framing of class-names with the single deliberate intention of economizing words. The perception of analogy between the individuals comprising a class is, it may be thought, one very necessary element in this mental operation. Of course, as Hartley observes, when a word appropriated ordinarily to the individuals of one genus or species, is applied to an individual belonging to another ; the nearer the two genera or species are to one another in all essential features, the nearer the use of the word as so applied approaches literalness ; and the less features the two genera or species have in common, the nearer the use of the word , approaches analogy proper or metaphor, either of which, when 64 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. duly expanded and improved by means of art, may become a simile, a fable, a parable, or an allegory. Thus a name usually applied to the animal kingdom will with more literal ness, and less metaphor, be applied to a member of the vegetable, than to a member of the mineral, kingdom. Expressions, it is to be remarked, in their original employment and application figurative become, from constant use, literal; and these ex- pressions, literal, so to speak, by second nature, can by further and more extended applications, become analogical again. With his keen eye for the educational uses, which the principle of association of ideas may and should subserve, Hartley notices how in allegories, fables, parables, and other emblema- tic modes of speech, all the properties, whether beauties or defects of, and the feelings of desire or disgust excited by, the images are transferred by association to the things and con- ceptions imaged. " Hence," he concludes, with an almost Platonic sense of the importance of a judicious myth, or ryevvaiov i/reOSo?, "the passions are nursed to good or evil, speculation is turned into practice, and either some important truth felt and realized, or some error and vice gilded over and recommended." 65 CHAPTER IV. THE THEORY OP ASSOCIATION AS APPLIED TO EXPLAIN THE MORE IMPORTANT PROCESSES AND OPERATIONS OF THE MIND. Among the different powers or faculties of the intellect (as a great many philosophers would call them), or the different mental operations and processes (to use the term which Mill would himself prefer), the most general and comprehensive, the one which — if we are to begin from the beginning, and work down from genus to species — immediately suggests itself, is Consciousness. Mill accordingly considers this in the first place. But " can it be called a special feeling, or mental process, at all?" he first asks. No: because "to be conscious of a feeling" " is only another way of saying, " to feel a feeling," which again is a tautological, redundant, and cum- bersome way of saying " to have a feeling." Similarly the feeling of an idea, and the consciousness, or the being con- scious, of an idea are only different ways of expressing the same fact, namely, the having of the idea. Consequently to Mill Consciousness means nothing but Feeling in general. It is not a special feeling, operation, or state, distinct from other feelings, operations, or states; and to suppose (with Reid, for instance) that it is, only tends to introduce confusion and mystery into what is otherwise clear and intelligible. To feel, to remember, to reason, to believe, to judge, are severally identical with the processes described as " being conscious " of feeling, remembering, reasoning, believing, or E 66 HA R TLE Y AND J A MES MILL. judging. The term Consciousness is merely a convenient generical mark. [Anal. vol. i. ch. v.j Mill holds similar opinions as to the meaning of the term Reflection. [Anal. vol. ii. pp. 176 — 180. J He thinks that it, like Consciousness, is merely a class-name. Accepting Locke's definition of the word — " that notice which the mind takes of its own operations " — he again insists that the having a state of consciousness, and the knowing, or the observing, or the taking notice of, that state, are all one and the same thing. The notice is the consciousness, and the consciousness is the notice. Consequently Reflection = Consciousness. When we say that we attended to this sensation more than to that, we mean that we felt this sensation more than that — that this, in fact, was more a sensation than that. The so-called Idea of Reflection has, therefore, according to Mill, nothing mysterious about it. Its formation, as in the case of Con- sciousness and all other class-names, is merely the result of a previous process of generalization from particular instances, — in this case, particular instances of remembering, believing, judging, imagining, &c. The supposition that there is any- thing in the Idea of Reflection other than this has arisen from, the unfortunate double use (already noticed) of the word Idea, to signify both a particular copy of a sensation, that is a fleeting state of consciousness entertained one moment and dismissed the next, and also the state of having ideas in general, which should more properly be called Ideation. The identification of feeling (including under the term the having a sensation and the having an idea) with the act of attention to feeling, is a cardinal tenet of Mill's system, and is continually being reiterated by him. Most later Assoeia- tionists dissent entirely from this position. Mill is on the whole consistent in his belief, though he does not appear to be conscious of all the objections which are capable of being CONSCIOUSNESS AND REFLECTION. 67 urged agaiustit : at least he does not notice them all, or seem to appreciate the importance of those which he does notice. Take the case of reading from a book, or playing a musical instrument; this supplies a ready objection, which does not, however, seem to have occurred to Mill. It might reasonably be urged that we must have had the sensations of seeing the letters composing the several words, while reading, or o£ touching the keys or strings of the instrument, while playing, and yet we cannot be said to have attended to those sensa- tions. Mill's statement is, notwithstanding, completely un- qualified, to the effect that to talk of being conscious and at the same time not attending to that consciousness, is to use as contradictory an expression as if we were to talk of being conscious and not being conscious at one and the same time. The objection here noticed did present itself to Hartley, as well as to the later psychologists, such as Mr. Herbert Spencer, who takes the bull by the horns, and denies that we ever are conscious of the sight of the letters, or of the sight and touch of the keys, in the cases supposed ; but he thinks that these so- called sensations of sight and touch are really organic states, ^which though not sufficient to excite corresponding sensa- tions, are yet just sufficient to hold together the links in the associative chain. [Anal. ypl. i. p. 232. J. S. Mill's note.] Conception, again, according to Mill, is a generical term, but not so generical as Consciousness and Reflection. The former marks a large class of feelings, but the latter terms mark all classes of feelings. Which, then, is the particular class of feelings (using Feeling always in Mill's large sense) denoted by Conception ? In brief — all kinds of complex ideas. Conception, as the name imparts, is " the taking together " of things : the term, therefore, is only applicable to complex ideas, whether of External Objects (Sensible Com- plex Ideas), or of "ideas of sensations arbitrarily put together f 2 68 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. (Mental Complex Ideas). Here again Mill objects to the term, the use of which so strongly illustrates the irresistible force of association, as well when directed into wrong, as when directed into right, channels. The expression seems to attri- bute activity to the mind. Though to have a complex idea is in reality exactly the same state as to conceive, yet the use of the term " I conceive," being in form active, imports into the notion of Conception an element which does not belong to it, and leads us to fancy that the mind is taking a more origi- native part when this form of words is employed than when we say " I have a complex idea." For Mill's views on the subject of Classification we shall have been somewhat prepared by his theory of Class-names, which has been already described. The misapprehension, which he conceives to have existed from the times of Plato and Aristotle to his own, of the nature, object, and signifi- cance of Classification, was merely in his opinion, the outcome of the equally prevalent . misconception of the meaning- of General Terms or Class-names. Hence it was that " the most eminent philosophers" were bewildered, and "the human mind enfeebled " [Aval. vol. i. p. 248]. Mill will have nothing to do with the Platonic IBea, or the Aristotelian etSo? (between which he sees little difference), or the Forms and Essences of other philosophic systems. At modern " Categories " and Hegelian " Notions/' and all such fond things vainly invented, he would doubtless have been inex- pressibly shocked, had he troubled himself to read German philosophy. He cannot understand why so much " mystery " should have been made about the process. The individuals included in a class have, in fact, nothing in common whatso- ever. To say so is to use a misleading figure of speech. We do not — as the ancient philosophers tell us, and as even Hart- ley appears to think — leave out of view the variable accidents CONCEPTION AND CLASSIFICATION. 69 and surroundings attaching to different particulars, and fix our attention exclusively on the essential qualities in which these particulars agree. This is not the process at all : Ab- straction is not the foundation of Classification. Even the Nominalists, who thought that so-called General Ideas were nothing but Names, saw that this was not the case, and (so far) were more in the right than the Realists, who attributed to a General Idea — though that Idea was regarded by them as entering into the composition and partaking in the nature, of the several members of the class represented by it — an independent and separate existence. Just as Class-names were invented according to Mill (though probably all schools of philosophy would now hold his view to be erroneous), solely for purposes of convenience and economy ; so Classifica- tion, or the construction of a class, is merely the forming of a very complex, and therefore necessarily somewhat indistinct, idea compounded of the ideas of that large aggregate of indi- viduals, with which, from those motives of economy, the class-name has been successively associated. Mill thus appa- rently believes the idea of a class to be a complex idea in every sense in which the idea of a horse, or the idea of a cen- taur, is ; and that whenever a class is thought of, a hazy idea of a mass of undefined individuals, to which the class-name has habitually been applied, is instantly called up. Whether this explanation of the process of Classification is more or less " mysterious " than the accounts given by Plato, Harris, Cudworth, and the other Platonists from whose works Mill quotes long extracts, we must leave the reader to judge. The process of classification, says Mill, is> only one among other modes of forming a complex idea by means of asso- ciation. By association the name of an individual external object — say St. PauFs — is connected constantly with the idea of it : the name never occurs without calling up the idea, or ;o HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. the idea without calling up the name. This is the simplest case of all. To take a rather more complicated instance : — a child hears the word " foot " pronounced first in connexion with the sensations which he derives from one of his feet, then with those which he derives from the other : and by degrees he finds the name pronounced indifferently in connexion with either set of sensations. Consequently, the word "foot" soon begins to call up in his mind the idea of either of his feet — at one time the one, at another time the other. It has already been explained — to take another example — how the ideas of synchronous sensations are so welded together by frequent •/association as, though in fact several, to appear only one (Sensible Complex Ideas). So, too, of the ideas of several successive sensations, the same law holds good; and we thus get the complex ideas of a musical tune, a hunt, a horse-race, &c. And, to proceed further, several sensible complex ideas may be combined into a yet more complex, but still sensible, idea ; as (e. g.) the ideas of several trees into the idea of a forest, or the ideas of several soldiers into the idea of an army ; and also the different complex ideas of successive sen- sations may be united into a still more complex idea — the ideas of several tunes into the idea of a concert, the ideas of several sentences into the idea of a discourse, or the ideas of several days into the idea of a year. And we may even obtain a very complex idea in both respects — complex, that is, both as regards the union of synchronous and the union of succes- sive sensations. Such an idea is the idea of Humanity (in one of its senses), which comprises the present together with all successive generations of men, past and to come. It is only a step further to the process of forming a class, which is nothing more or less than the process of associating one name, say "•vegetable," with one external object after another, 1 to save 1 With this further peculiarity, that the idea of, or sensation derived CLA SSTFICA TION. 7 1 the trouble of calling the several objects by several names, and so swelling 1 the extent of language beyond all capacity of remembering it. The name " vegetable," therefore, in this case, is not a name having a very simple idea — the idea of a quality perceived by a certain special activity of the mind to be common to a variety of objects (as the Realists thought) ; nor, on the other hand, is it a name having no idea at all (as the Nominalists held) ; but it is " a word calling up an inde- finite number of ideas, by the irresistible laws of association, and forming them all into one very complex and indistinct but not, therefore, unintelligible idea." [Anal. vol. i. pp. 265, 266.] Classification, then (so far), Mill has pronounced to be merely a device for purposes of abridgment. He even dis- tinctly says [p. 260] that " it is obvious and certain that men were led to class solely for the purpose of economizing in the use of names. Could the processes of naming and discourse have been as conveniently managed by a name for every indivi- dual, the names of classes and the idea of classification would never have existed." But later on in the chapter he seems to become somewhat conscious that this hypothesis will not suffice to account for the facts. After all, men classify according to some principle. There is something that not only leads them to classify, but guides them in classifying. We have a tardy recognition of this defect in the theory at p. 268. But, in answer to the question, What is this principle of classification ? he first tells us again what the purpose is — naming with greater facility than would otherwise be possible. But expe- rience teaches us what method of grouping will best advance this end. Under the guidance of that experience it is that class-names are, by a somewhat perfunctory and unreflecting from, each such external object, is, on each successive occasion, associated back again with the name. 72 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. process — though Mill calls classification a " mighty operation of the human mind " — determined. But we are still unan- swered as to the principle of classification. We have been told its object — economy ; we have heen told its basis — asso- ciation ; and we have been told that experience supplies the principle. Bnt what, then, is the principle ? We are finally told in the last pages of the chapter. [Pp. 270, 271.J " It is easy to see what principle it is which is mainly concerned in classification, and by which we are rendered capable of that mighty operation; on which as its basis the whole of our intellectual structure is reared. That principle is resem- blance." If this is Mill's view, it is more than ever inex- plicable why he should have stopped short here, and have refused to entertain the theory which is the logical and legitimate issue of that view — the theory which most philo- sophers up to the present time, including Hartley, and even the Nominalists, 2 have held — namely, that according to which abstraction is made the ground of classification. Ab- straction is as necessary to classification, according to almost all philosophers, except Mill, as classification itself is — according to several, such as Mr. Herbert Spencer — to ratiocination. Mill, however, marks off classification from both the one and the other by a broad and distinct line — indeed, is compelled to do so by his peculiar view of the former as subserving solely the uses of economy in naming. However, our business is not to criticize here, and we pro- ceed to Mill's account of Abstraction, which, if not acceptable, is at all events clear, definite, and consistent with the rest of his philosophy. In the operation of naming — as has been pointed out above — we first assign names to clusters of sensations, or individual 2 Mill is mistaken in supposing that the Nominalists denied any idea cor- responding to a class-name, or any process corresponding to Abstraction. MILL ON ABSTRACTION. 73 objects; next, we generalize these, to represent classes of objects ; lastly, finding 1 that the class-names have served the purposes of economy at the expense of adequate representation of important varieties of feeling, we carve cub-classes out of classes, and species out of genera, by framing adjectives. But, having done this, we are led to extend the operation in another direction. Having carved out of the class "rose" the sub- class " yellow rose," we perceive that for the very same reason that we call a rose yellow, we may call a gate yellow, or a ball yellow. In the cluster of ideas represented by the name " rose " I single out one, that of colour, and colour of a par- ticular kind, for special attention. But the sensation and the idea of yellow occurs in connexion with other clusters ; con- sequently, by degrees the name " yellow " tends to call up not only the idea of yellow rose, but also the ideas of classes of other yellow objects ; and thus the adjective applied to one class of clusters after another, in all of which the idea cor- responding to that adjective is an ingredient, is associated with all those classes indifferently, just as the idea cor- responding to a class-name is associated with all or any of the individuals of the class indifferently. The word " yellow " is therefore associated with numberless qualifications of the idea of yellow by other ideas which in different cases are com- bined with it. These different qualifying ideas, together with the idea itself of yellow, are at last commingled, or massed, into one indefinite and vague complex idea, just as the ideas of the different individuals composing a class are welded into a complex idea of a similarly indeterminate character. In the former case, we get the formation of the idea corresponding to the adjective, in the latter, of the idea corresponding to the substantive, in language. And, in both cases, the idea and the name exert a reciprocal influence on one another. As the substantive " man " calls up the ideas of a variety of indi- 74 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. vidual men, while any individual man calls up the idea of the name "man," and it again calls up another individual man; so the adjective "yellow" calls up a variety of classes of clusters where yellow colour is an ingredient, any of these clusters calls up the name "yellow," and the name again calls up the idea of some other cluster in which the idea of yellow is a prominent feature. The adjectival name, it will be observed, notes (in James Mill's language), or especially marks and is associated with, the constant and invariable sensation or idea of yellow ; it connotes, or marks along with this principal idea, certain secondary ideas, to wit, those of the variable clusters with which the name is indifferently asso- ciated. Drop the variable and connoted clusters, the conno- tation, as Mill calls it, from the adjectival names or the concretes, "yellow," "bitter," '• large," &c, and the process of abstraction is performed ; and if a suitable mark is appended to the adjectives to indicate this elimination of .the variable clusters, such as (in English) the suffix " -ness," the abstract names "yellowness," "bitterness," &c, are formed. Ab- straction is this, according to Mill, and it is nothing more. It is thus, though analogous to classification, a perfectly dis- tinct process ; and the latter is not necessarily related to, or dependent upon, the former. Hartley's numerous corollaries resemble the postscript of a lady's letter in this, that his best guesses and suggestions are often contained in them. Accordingly, we find in some corollaries to Proposition lxxix. [vol. i. p. 273] some interesting reflections on the process of abstraction. He notices, first, how a particular element in a cluster of sensations or ideas, to which a name is attached, may force itself on the attention more than its other ingredients. Generally this element is a visible idea, but sometimes it is otherwise. This prominent idea, he further remarks, will generally be found to be a HARTLE Y ON ABSTRA CTION. 75 prominent idea, not only in one, but in several kinds of clusters. Hence such ideas as " white," " whiteness," for instance, after having been associated with the different visible appearances of milk, linen, paper, &c, " get a stable power of exciting the idea of what is common to all, and a variable one in respect of the particularities, circumstances, and adjuncts/' Thus, though Hartley does not sufficiently recognize the mind's activity in paying special attention to the common element in a variety of objects, and speaks rather of that element forcing itself upon the notice of the mind, yet he particularly asserts that it is this something common to all the objects of which the mind takes cognizance, when it performs the function of abstraction. He, in fact, adopts the most considerable feature in that theory which his successor pronounces to be " mysterious." To return to Mill. Having expounded what in his view Abstraction is, and what was the purpose for which it was primarily resorted to, namely, the formation of subordinate classes, he admits that this mental operation does, in fact, serve a still more useful purpose. [Anal. vol. i. p. 314.J The relation or order of ideas and sensations most important to mankind is the relation of antecedent and consequent, or the order of succession. On the knowledge of this relation between the various phenomena presented in the natural and the mental world, depends nearly all that part of human science which is available for the uses of life, and, through it, the welfare or the reverse of men. If, therefore, we observe a certain sensation, or cluster of sensations, follow another cluster of sensations, it becomes of paramount importance to us to mark what particular ingredient of all those which go to form this latter cluster produces the former sensation, or cluster of sensations. Now for the purpose of experimenting on the effects of any such ingredient, we must 76 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. be able to isolate it as far as possible not only from tbe re- maining ingredients of tbe particular cluster, in whicb we first observe its existence, but from tbe remaining ingredients of other clusters in which it is equally to be found. It is neces- sary, therefore, to mark the ingredient thus found in company with these different "variable adjuncts," as Hartley would call them, by a special name, and separate it in our thoughts (where we cannot separate it physically), in order to reason out its effects (where we cannot watch them). And this is Abstraction; which is thus seen to be one of the necessary preliminaries to Prediction, while Prediction is necessary to Science, to Happiness, to the business of life — even to Life itself. We now come to those processes of mind which, though closely marked off from one another by most schools of philo- sophy, James Mill, owing to his having committed himself to certain rigid principles relating to the formation or the having of ideas, experienced some difficulty in satisfactorily distin- guishing. We allude to Imagination, as contrasted with Belief on the one hand, and Memory on the other. Imagination, in Mill's view, differs from Conception in that, whereas the latter relates to the having of complex ideas, the peculiarity of which generally is that their component simple ideas are synchronous, the former represents the combining of ideas in ti less or greater number (whether simple or complex) successively. This is the process of Imagination : any particu- lar imagination (the term being, like sensation, used in two senses) is, therefore, a train of ideas, while any particular con- ception (here again there is a corresponding double meaning) is a single, though a complex, idea. Imagination, like Conception, is often loosely used in as wide a sense as Consciousness itself. But in strictness, of course, both the one and the other are far less extensive in scope than Consciousness, and are related to it only as species IMAGINATION. 77 to genus. Imagination is often applied in an exclusive sense to the poet's special gift, but this is merely a popular restric- tion which philosophy cannot notice. In the essential mean- ing of the term, there is no person who has not Imagination, because there is no person who has not trains of ideas in his mind at any given waking moment. The poet differs from other men in his imagination, because to him. trains of ideas and the formation of such trains are ends in themselves, whereas to the lawyer, soldier, or physician, it is ordinarily otherwise. But this does not make the constitutive features of imagination any the less identical in all these cases. Ima- gination is none the less the having or entertaining of suc- cessive ideas, whatever may be the nature, interest, or object of these ideas. In a philosophical sense, the lawyer who con- siders how he will frame an opinion or conduct a case, the general planning a campaign, the scientific man solving a problem, the chess-player at his game, is as much exercising his imagination as the poet, who sees before him " shapes more real than living man, nurslings of immortality." Another inexact use of the term Imagination is apparent, whenever it is applied (as it was by Dugald Stewart) solely to the putting together of ideas in new combinations — in such combinations, that is, or successions of ideas as have not been suggested by previous combinations and successions of sensa- tions. Dugald Stewart further thought that such combina- tions should be destined and directed to some end : and this latter element also Mill very properly repudiated. Hartley's views on this subject differed little if at all from those of Mill. He too was of opinion that the term Imagina- tion simply represents a succession of ideas linked together according to certain laws of association, often unknown or unobserved by us. But, following his usual method, he treats this operation of the mind more physically, perhaps, 78 HAR TLE Y AND J A MES MILL. than psychologically, and has proceeded in his investigation a very short way, when he informs us [vol. i. p. 383] that "in all the cases of imagination and reverie the thoughts depend, in part, upon the state of body or mind," and he goes on to allude to the importance of " a pleasurable or painful state of the stomach/' &c. He flies off at a tangent to those unex- plored fields of physical inquiry (such as dreams, prophecies, visions, and the like), and embarks on those " strange seas of thought" which had such a fascination for him. He does not keep to Mill's severe and philosophical view of the essence and office of Imagination. It may suffice, therefore, just to call the reader's attention to his occasional acute observations, such as that the various scenes in a dream are linked together by association, and, to a certain extent, according to the laws of association, but that we are not offended at the wildest sequences of images, because the counter-associations, which would under ordinary circumstances dispel them, are in abey- ance during sleep ; — to his explanation of the phenomenon in dreaming which has within the last few years been discussed under the name of levitation, and of somnambulism; — to his curious and intelligent remark that the wildness of dreams is necessary to the health of the intellect in one sense, because they tend to break down the accidental associative links, which otherwise might become so cemented by continuance as to be rendered indissoluble, without having, so to speak, any title to this durability, and thus induce even madness in time ; and to the characteristic physician's caution, with which he concludes the chapter, to the effect that men may test their health by the pleasantness or the unpleasantness of their dreams. We now pass on to the two philosophers' analysis of Belief, that of James Mill being almost the turning-point of his whole system, while Hartley's is full and exhaustive, though not so clear as that of his successor. 79 CHAPTER V. BELIEF, AS INTERPRETED BY THE LAWS OF ASSOCIATION. In Belief are included Memory and Judgment; and with Judgment are connected the steps and means by which we arrive at it, Evidence and Ratiocination. But after consider- ing Belief, the genus, it will be necessary, before considering Memory, the first of the two species mentioned, to investigate the elements which have to be added to those comprised in the mental operation of Belief — (the differentia, that is) — in order to constitute Memory. This will involve an examination of the Ideas of Time and Personal Identity. "We propose ac- cordingly in this chapter to give Mill's and Hartley's account of the following intellectual states, and in the following order : — Belief [Time, Personal Identity] : Memory : Judgment [Evidence, Ratiocination], Belief, we have implied, is related to Memory, on the one side, and to Judgment on the other, as genus to species. This, however, is not strictly in accordance with Mill's views, at least as regards the relation of Belief to Memory. He says, indeed, in the chapter on Belief, that "it encroaches on the provinces both of Memory and Judgment •" and even in one passage [vol. i. p. 359] admits Memory to be "a case of Belief," but in the chapter on Memory he nowhere uses such language ; and he appears not to hold this view seriously, at all events to the extent to which J. S. Mill holds it, who thinks that Memory necessarily implies Belief, and cannot 8o HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. exist without it. 1 Moreover, while he treats Judgment under Belief, in his arrangement of intellectual processes, he treats Memory quite apart as a thing by itself: though, according to the more sound view of the editor and commentators of the Analysis, there was no reason why the latter should not have had the same rank and place assigned to it as the former. It will be convenient for purposes of exposition to adopt what should logically have been, rather than what was, James Mill's classification of Belief and the states connected with it. The accompanying table may serve as a clue to our succeeding observations. Belief: f I. Belief in events, real existences. f 1. Belief in p resent events or existences : r{a.) Belief in immediate existences present to our senses. (b.) Belief in immediate existences not present / to our senses, either ( (a) Which we have not perceived < [Testimony]. [ 03) Which we have perceived. 2. Belief in past events or existences : f(a.) When the event or existence has been the object of our senses at some past time. [Memory, Time, Personal Identity.] (b.) When it has not. {(a) Belief of Testimony [Evidence]. 03) Uniformity of Law of Nature [as in 3], 3. Belief in/afore events or existences : [Anticipation- inseparable association of like consequents with k like antecedents]. II. Belief in the Truth of Propositions : Judgment. [Ratioci- nation and Evidence.] Belief in events or real existences is, then, the first of 1 See Analysis, vol. i. p. 342, note, and pp. 411 — 413, where Belief and Memory (as involving it) are both contrasted with Imagination. f BEL IEF IN PRESENT EX IS TENCES. 8 1 Mill's two grand classes of Belief. And, first, as to belief in •present events and real existences, which may either be in immediate relation to my senses at the time of belief, or not. Of belief in the former kind of existences Mill's account is brief and perfunctory. It is based on the ever- recurring formula — " to have a sensation or idea, and to believe that I have it, is one and the same thing." The two states of con- sciousness are not in any way distinguishable. Consequently, belief in the sensations derived from objects present to my senses is neither more nor less than the experience of those sensations. If it be objected that belief in a sensation implies something added to the sensation, namely, the associated idea of the Self; and that, in this sense, sensation may be distinguished from the belief in it; Mill replies that the idea of the Self is associated with the former just as much as with the latter. It, like the ideas of Position and Unity, is as much, and as inseparably, combined with the sensations of sight, for in- stance, derived from an object, as with the belief in the sensa- tion. Sensation, then, in such cases, is itself belief. The curtain here is the picture. But belief in the external object from which we derive the sensation is not the same thing as, and contains more elements than, belief in the sensation. When I am said (in ordinary language) to see a rose, I actually see colour alone : but the object, rose is a combination of colour, extension, figure, &c. Therefore, though I imagine that I see extension, figure, &c. I in reality only infer them ; and that I fancy to myself that I see them, is due to association in one of its strongest forms. Rapid and continually repeated passages of thought from the sensation of colour to the ideas of extension, form, distance position, bulk, &c, lead us to suppose that we become, in the very experience of the sensation, immediately possessed of G 82 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. that information as to the object, which is really the result of association of (in the first instance) visual sensations with tactual sensations, sensations of muscular pressure and re- sistance, and so on. The association in this case produces each of the well-known effects which always follow its opera- tion, when very forcible : namely, first, the blending of the associated feelings into a single complex feeling ; secondly, the riveting of the associative link so fast that it cannot be broken, and .that the mental illusion is rendered permanent and indissoluble ; just as the optical illusion of seeing a stick pre- sent a bent appearance in the water is permanent and innate, so to speak, though the appearance is all the time known not to answer to the fact. This mental illusion is more espe- cially incidental to the sensations of sight, because sight is the primary and leading element in the clusters of sensations im- pressed upon us by external objects; though there are also similar illusions of less power connected with the other senses, as (for example) when we fancy that we hear distance, whereas we hear only modifications of sound, and infer the distance of the object. Visual sensations, however, call up the resi- dues of the clusters with greater facility, frequency, and certainty than any of the sensations proper to the other phj'sical organs. Therefore, when I see an external object, my belief in its existence amounts to nothing more than this : that, with the sensation of colour impressed upon my organs of sight, I have inseparably associated the ideas of a variety of other sensa- tions ; and with them I further have inseparably associated the idea of myself as having them ; that is, I believe that in certain circumstances I should have any one of these sensa- tions. By walking to the object, I should have the sensation of distance ; by touching it, that of hardness or softness ; by the putting forth of muscular energy, I should have the THE UNKNOWN CAUSE OF SENSATIONS. 83 sensations of resistance, solidity, or impenetrability ; by touching, and the expenditure of muscular force combined, I should have that of extension and figure. To our supposed perception, inference, or belief of the ex- istence of an unknown cause of such a cluster of sensations as is described above, nothing in rerum naturd corresponds. The Substratum, as it is called, of certain qualities in the object, which produce sensations in us, is merely a fiction of asso- ciation. We are always observing sequences. The order of succession in phenomena, or rather in our sensations and ideas, is more important to us than any other order. The tendency, consequently, in our minds is to find an antecedent to every consequent, and, if we cannot find one, to invent one. We are compelled by a law of our nature " to look before and after." This is another case of inseparable association. " The perception or idea of an event instantly brings up the idea of its constant antecedent : definite and clear if the antecedent is known, and indefinite and obscure if it is unknown." \_Anal. vol. i. p. 352]. Now constant antecedent is Cause, and Cause is nothing else. Therefore the habit of seeking for such constant Antecedents is of itself quite sufficient to account for the belief in the existence of a supposed Object, as Sub- stance, Cause, or Substratum of its various qualities (cor- responding to the various sensations in us), though that Object or Substratum, except as a convenient and compre- hensive name for the clusters of sensations with which we are simultaneously affected, is non-existent. Now as to the belief in the present existence pf objects not in immediate relation to our senses. Of this there may be two cases, according as>«the objects have or have not been pre- viously at any time perceived by us. The former is the only case which it is necessary to examine now ; since the latter, being an instance of Belief in Events on Testimony, may con- G 2 84 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. veniently be considered below in connexion with the subject of Belief in Past Events on Testimony. What then is implied in my belief in the present existence of Westminster Hall, which, though not now present to my senses, I have seen at some previous time in my life? I imply (for one thing) that if I were at this moment at or near Westminster Hall, I should derive the same sensations from it as I have derived on previous occasions. Put in this form, the belief is a case of Anticipation of the future on the analogies of the past, which will be considered as the third main head of beliefs in real existences. But it may be put in another way. In the belief in the present existence of West- minster Hall is involved my belief, that if any creature endowed with organs of sense like my own is at this moment in or near Westminster Hall, he or it has sensations analogous to the sensations which I myself have experienced when so situated. The explanation of this mental condition is to be found once more in the laws of Association. There is an in- vincible association between the idea of an animal body and sensation. First the association is created between the idea of my own human body and the ideas of my own sensations, — then between the ideas of human bodies other than my own, and the ideas of sensations analogous to my own, — then, similarly, as to the other creatures lower and lower in the scale of the animal kingdom, till we stop short at vegetables, and there the association, to any considerable extent (except in fetichism and poetry, the lowest and the highest intellectual states), fails us. "It is apparent/' Mill therefore concludes [Anal. vol. i. p. 358] "that the case in which I believe other creatures to be immediately percipient of objects, of which I believe that I myself should be percipient if I were so situated as they are, resolves itself ultimately into this par- ticular case of my belief in certain conditional sensations of BELIEF IN PAST EXISTENCES. 85 my own," that is, again, to the case of Anticipation, which we reserve for the present. Our Belief in Past Existences is, in other words, our pre- sent idea of something existing, and the assignment of it to a time past. Here again we have an ohvious ground of sub- division into the two cases, — first, where the object in the past existence of which we believe has, secondly, where it has not, been present to our senses. The former of these kinds of Belief is, according to Mill, neither more nor less than Memory. Just as the belief in the present existence of an object now in relation to my senses is Sensation, and nothing else, so the belief in the past existence of an object which was then present to my senses is Memory, and nothing more. 2 Bemembering a past event, and believing it, are merely two different names for one and the same state of conscious- ness. What, then, we have to ask, is involved in the process of Memory ? Hartley and Mill both give answers to this ques- tion from their respective points of view, — Hartley, as usual, looking to his favourite vibration-theory, and relying largely on physical analogies and proofs, Mill looking to the principles of Association alone, which he wisely accepts as elementary, without seeking to go behind them for a more recondite solution. Memory, says Mill, can only take place through the medium of ideas. Every act, or (as he would prefer to call it) state of memory, involves an idea. But it also involves more than this. The state of memory cannot exist without the idea ; but the idea can exist without the state of memory. A further necessary element is association — association of ideas in trains according to its ordinary laws. This is manifest on 2 Here Mill plainly declares Memory to be a species of Belief, and though it is not treated by him in this connexion, this is clearly its proper and philosophical place. 86 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. an analysis of the process called "trying to remember" (Aristotle's " avd(Lvr)tjL<;," as opposed to passive memory or " fivrjfiri," the mere recurrence of associated ideas without the exercise of any volition on our part). When we try to remember a thing, we run over every idea which we think may have a chance of recalling to our minds, by means of its previously contracted associations, the idea of which we are in quest. Each idea which we have experienced has, we know, been the centre of several threads of association ; we therefore try several ideas at random, in the hope of one of them eventually having a path to the idea which we require. In some cases, of course, we take the precaution to determine the associations beforehand, as in the familiar devices of underlining passages in a book, tying a knot in a handker- chief, &c. Similarly, in order to remember the sequence of words, we repeat them, because we know that repetition is one of the most effective agents in generating association. Hence it is, that if we try to remember words which we have learnt, in any other order than that in which we committed them to memory, we find it difficult, if not impossible, to do so. Mill gives an interesting example of these pre- determined associations for the purpose of securing accurate remembrance, in the practice of some of the ancient orators, who used to create an artificial relation in their own minds between the different parts of a temple, or other building, in the sight of which they were about to speak, and the heads of their intended discourse. By means of occasional glances at the temple, they were thus enabled in a double sense to work up from the foundation to the coping-stone of their orations. Of course, the success of such an experiment would depend on the relation which the speaker's power of remembering pictorial simultaneous representations bears to his power of remembering audible successive sounds. Men vary very MEMOR Y. 87 much in this respect. Some will remember a lecture better than an essay, and an acted than a written play. Even in reading a book some men, with more or less conscious effort, shape to themselves audible ideas of the sounds of the words j illiterate persons even reproduce the audible sounds them- selves ; while others read so rapidly that they are not con- scious to themselves of forming any other than a visible idea of the written symbols. 3 Ideas and Association, then, are necessary to constitute Memory. But are these all ? Imagination involves these, as we have already seen ; and, if these were the only essen- tial ingredients, receptive or representative imagination — imagination, that is, of clusters of sensations, Aristotle's " aicjdrjTiicr) fyavraoia" — would involve as much as " fivtj/iri"; and the active or creative imagination, which frames and deals with clusters of ideas after its own fashion — Aristotle's " ftovXevTiKr) fyavraaia' — would, if this were the case, be tantamount to " avafivqais." What, then, must be added, to ideas and their association in trains to make passive imagination equivalent to passive memory, and active or deliberative imagination equivalent to active memory or re- 3 Professor Max Miiller notices an ingenious attempt (by Don Sinibaldo de Mas in his Ideographic) to create direct associations between ideas and pictorial or visible emblems, by constructing a language consisting of 2600 figures, framed on the pattern of musical notes, and capable of innumer- able variations in meaning, corresponding to those effected by the parts of speech, according to the position of the head of the note (Science of Language, vol. ii. p. 48). This would have commended itself to Hartley. Mr. Shute (in his Discourse on Truth) is, however, afraid that, even as it is, men are more and more losing their power of associating ideas with audible emblems, and tend more and more to assimilate visible signs in preference to them. The whole subject of the differences between the pictorial or local, and the successive or eventual memory, is gone into by Mr. Francis Galton, " Mental Imagery," in Fortn. Rev., September, 1880, and Mind, July, 1880. 88 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. collection? The answer is: The element of recognition. " Suppose that my present state of consciousness is the idea of putting my finger in the flame of the candle. I recognize the act as a former act; and this recognition is followed by another, namely, that of the pain which I felt immediately after. This part of my constitution, which is of so much importance to me, I find it useful to name. And the name I give to it is Memory." \_Analysis, vol. i. pp. 319,320]. But this recognition is a somewhat complex process. What are its elements ? Can it be reduced to a case of Associa- tion? We may remember either sensations or ideas formerly ex- perienced by us. In remembering a sensation— say, the having seen an object at some past date — the following conditions are implied : first, a visible idea of the object ; secondly, the idea of my having seen it. 4 And the former irresistibly calls up the latter idea, and in this we have (so far) merely another case of inseparable association. But into what elements is the idea of my having seen an object resolvable ? First of all, we may break it up into : (1) the idea of my present (the remembering) self; (2) the idea of my past, the then sentient, and now remembered, self. These two ideas are connected at the moment of memory. How? By running over the intermediate states of con- sciousness, and (by means of a rapid process already referred to) uniting the two terms and the intervening links into one very complex idea. And this, again, is association. The remembrance of ideas admits of an exactly similar 4 To these J. S, Mill would add — the belief (independent of the evidence of others) of my having seen the object. And in this he would be clearly right ; but James Mill thinks that there is nothing elementary or unana- lyzable in Belief itself, which he regards as in every case reducible to Association of ideas in the last resort, as will be seen in the sequel. REMEMBRANCE OF PAST IDEAS. 89 explanation. I remember, for example, my idea of Charles I.'s execution. In doing- so, I have, — (1) The ideas of the various acts and objects related and described in the account of the execution ; and (2) [Inseparably associated with the above], the idea of my having had those ideas. And (2) again includes, — (a) The idea of my present self remembering : "I United by asso- (b) The idea of my past self conceiving : ^.ciation into one (c) The idea of the intervening states of consciousness: J complex idea. To put the matter comprehensively (so as to include the remembrance both of past sensations and of past ideas), the necessary elements in the memory of our past experiences, of whatever kind, would seem to be as follows : — i. The idea of my past self sentient or conceiving = (The idea (of a past sensation: or, ■j (of a past idea. (.The idea of the Self, ii. The idea of my present self as remembering = (The idea of the Self < The idea of [Remembering =] Asso- (- ciating. iii. The intervening trains of ideas, the calling up of which depends upon Association. So that the memory of past experiences has now been resolved to Ideas (one of which must always be the Idea of the Self), and Association. Nothing, therefore, now needs eluci- dation, in connexion with memory, except this constant factor, the Idea of Personal Identity, after analyzing which we may 90 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. (since there can be no Memory without involving it in some way) examine the idea of Time. Neither of the two important metaphysical problems of modern times connected with the investigation of the concep- tions, ideas, or forms (as they are variously called) of the Ego and of Time, attracted the attention of Hartley; con- sequently we must be taken as here presenting the views of James Mill alone. Personal Identity, or the Identity of the Ego, must be ex- plained on the same grounds and by the same method as the Identity of other human beings, and this again on the same grounds as the Identity of other animal existences ; and the Identity of animal existences in general can be explained in no other way than the Identity of inanimate objects. [Anal. vol. ii. pp. 164 — 170 ] It is necessary, then, to satisfy our- selves as to the essence of Identity, generically considered, before we can show the nature of that particular species of it called Personal Identity. Now when I say, that the object which I now see is the same which I saw ten years before, or that the words which I now read were written by a certain author 2000 years ago, or that the object which was seen 2000 years ago by one man was the same which was seen 1000 years ago by another, — Belief is involved, and nothing else. The first example pre- sents one case of Belief, the second another, and the third another ; but all alike are Belief. The reader will be some- what surprised to find here what looks very like the inter- pretation of a thing by itself. One of the kinds of Belief, namely, Memory, is alleged to involve, among other elements, the Idea of Personal Identity ; and this idea, as being merely a case of Identity in general, is then found to be a case of Belief. The definition in a circle is rendered still more con- spicuous when we find that, of the three instances of Identity BELIEF IN IDENTITY. 91 given above, Mill would call the first an instance of that specific kind of Belief which is called Memory [the other two being cases of Belief in Evidence or Testimony, or of Belief in the Uniformity of Nature, or of a combination of both] . And as to Identity in general, Mill's own statement is : — " As we have already shown wherein Belief, in all its cases, consists" [it must be remembered that the chapter on Identity was written after all the cases of Belief had been examined — an arrangement from which we have seen reason to depart] " we have implicitly afforded the explanation of Identity " [Anal. vol. ii. p. 165] :— while, in the chapter on Memory, he says, " It is in this process that Memory consists No obscurity rests on any part of this process, except the idea of self, which is reserved for future analysis All this will be more evident when what is included in the notion of Personal Identity is included." [Anal. vol. i. p. 360.] Belief and Identity cannot, on Mill's own showing, be both capable of analysis. Either Belief must involve the idea of Personal Identity as an ultimate and irreducible element, or this latter must similarly imply Belief. In the face of the contradiction in terms patent in Mill's own language, we will not attempt to guess which elenfent he really thought the unanalyzable one. 6 Let us examine, however, his reduction of Personal Identity to a case of Identity in general. We have already seen what is implied when we say that the inanimate external object which we now perceive, is the s J. S. Mill, in his notes to the Analysis, evidently considers that the idea of the Self involves Memory, while Memory involves Belief, and that this Belief is the ultimate element. Judging from the frequency with which he insists on this view, hy way of correction on numerous other occasions where James Mill leaves out of account this ultimate factor in a variety of mental processes, we may, perhaps, conclude that it was Personal Identity which the latter, if pressed, would have admitted to be irreducible. 92 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. same object as that which we have previously perceived. But what do I mean when I say that some object having growth and life is the same now, when present to my senses, as it was when I perceived it at some former date ? Whether that object be a vegetable, an animal of the lower orders, or a human being other than myself, I mean the same thing : I express my belief that there is a certain series (known by experience) of antecedents and consequents, which is called the life of that object; that this series is capable of being marked off and distinguished from all other similar series ; and that my present perception is the last link in that par- ticular series, and no other. In all these cases the Belief involved is one thing, and the essential thing : the evidence for that Belief is another thing, and may be of various kinds. The belief in the identity of another human being is often evidenced by observation, that is, sensation and memory of sensation; or, in other words, it is often evidenced by itself; but more often it rests on evidence and testimony of another kind as well. Now, when I use the word " same" in connexion with my own life, do I imply anything beyond this belief? Nothing whatever. The Belief is the same, and the evidence is the same. So far as my memory extends, my belief in my own identity rests on consciousness and memory, that is (as before), it rests on itself; it is its own evidence. When I get beyond reach of my memory, then my belief in my own identity is supported by exactly the same kinds of external testimony as my belief in the identity of any other person, as to whom observation has not been possible. We have said that, within the range . of memory, the evidence for my own identity is Consciousness and Memory, the evidence for the identity of other men is Observation and Memory. In the latter case we have the memory of past observed facts, in the other we have the memory of past PERSONAL IDENTITY. 93 " i states of consciousness, added, in each case, to a present sensation. But observation itself is nothing but a state of consciousness. Therefore the memory of a series of states of consciousness, coupled with an existing state, is the evidence in both cases. But the states of consciousness remembered in the two cases, though they are equally evidence, become evidence in different ways. And here we come upon a real distinction between the intellectual phenomena of the two processes. In the one case, we remember past states of consciousness in ourselves as pointing to the contemporaneous or prior exis- tence of states of consciousness in others, or as marks of those states in accordance with the laws of association which decree that certain signs, to wit, impressions of certain sensations in us, shall call up in our minds the ideas of certain sensations of others signified by them : whereas, in the other case, we remember states of consciousness in our- selves for their own sakes, and not as pointing to anything else. To use the language of the law-courts, our own state* of consciousness are equally the evidence in either operation ; but in the former they are secondary evidence, in the latter they are primary. In the former, they are imperfect means of inferring the continuity and separate existence of a series of states of consciousness, constituting the thread of life of the person (other than the Ego), in whose identity we assert our belief: in the latter, they are, in fact, themselves the thread of life of the person (the Ego) in whose identity we believe. The difference then between Belief in the Identity of others, and Belief in Personal Identity, is not in the evi- dentiary materials, but in the manner in which these materials evidence the existences or events to which credence is given. In the idea of Time, which falls to be considered in connexion with Memory, Mill sees none of the mystery \ s \ 94 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. which, according to him, other philosophers have found in it. Its supposed necessity he regards as merely another result of inseparahle and irresistible association, since the idea of succession, or of the relation of antecedent and con- sequent, is inseparably associated with the idea of every object. Any theory of Time, as one of the forms imposed by the mind on the matter furnished by sensation, he would, consequently, reject; though he agrees with Kant so far as to deny with him that Time is an inherent property or attribute of objects. Time is nothing but the abstract name of all successive order, just as Space is of all simul- taneous order, [Anal. vol. ii. p. 132], and it is formed no otherwise than as other abstract names are formed. "With the idea of every present event we associate the idea of an antecedent, with this latter idea the idea of an antecedent to that, and so on 'ad infinitum.' The idea of the- present event, coupled with the ideas of the antecedents so associated with it, mate up our idea of the Past, which therefore implies infinite concrete past successions of objects; it notes, that is, in Mill's phraseology, or primarily marks, successions; it connotes, or secondarily marks, objects. Omit the connota- tion, as must be done to form any abstract name, and we get the successions, without the objects, — or Time Past in the abstract. In the above process put consequent for antecedent, and by similar steps we arrive at Time Future in the abstract. Next, regard all real or possible events (or objects, in Mill's language), whether past, present, or future, as successive, lump them together, and we obtain the idea of concrete Time in general ; that is, the successions with the objects. Take away the objects, and we have left the successions without the objects, or the idea of abstract Time in general. Thus Time is an abstract name, the corresponding concrete to which is ultimately built upon an indissoluble association, which forces TIME IN RELA TION TO MEM OR Y. 95 us, in contemplating any event, to go beyond it and look on both sides of it. Whether the above process would not rather give us the abstract idea of Successiveness, and not that of Time at all, we will not here stop to inquire. The connexion of Time with Memory in Mill's system will be best seen in his own words [Anal. vol. ii. p. 120] ; — " Pastness is included under the term Memory. . . . Memory is a connotative term ; what it notes is the antecedence and consequence of the several parts of that which forms the chain of remembrance; what it connotes are the feelings them- selves, the objects remembered. When what it connotes is left out, and what it notes is retained, we have the idea which is expressed by Pastness." Mill would presumably consider an analogous connexion to exist between Anticipation and Futureness. But Anticipation (as we shall see presently) rests on Belief in the Uniformity of Nature, and this again on Association, and the association is based on felt and re- membered cases of succession. There is nothing, therefore, as we are expressly told, in Time distinct from Memory and Sensations. Hartley differs with Mill, and agrees with Reid and most other philosophers, in considering Memory to be a faculty, and not an idea framed in a particular way. It is " that faculty by which traces of sensations and ideas recur, or are recalled, in the same order and proportion, accurately or nearly, as they were once presented." [06s. on Man, vol. i. p. 374]. After this somewhat loose and unsatisfactory definition, Hartley gives us some desultory remarks, prin- cipally of a pathological character, on the relation between the state of the faculty of memory and the state of the brain ; in the course of which he takes occasion to notice that such a connexion would tend to support the vibration theory, since vibrations in the medullary substance of the brain may be 96 HA R TLB Y AND JAMES MILL. presumed to be affected by such causes as disease, concussions, liquors, poison, &c. Hartley appears to hold with Mill, that the exercise of Memory depends almost entirely upon Association ; but he does not enter into any examination of the idea of the Self in connexion with this part of his theory. He answers the in- evitable query as to the nature of the difference (on this hypothesis) between Memory and Imagination in much the same way as his successor. " Let it now be asked," he says [vol. i. p. 377], "in what the recollections of a past fact, consisting of an hundred clusters " [complex ideas] " differs from the transit of the same one hundred clusters over the fancy, in the way of a reverie ? I answer, partly in the vividness of the clusters, partly and principally in the readiness and strength of the associations, by which they are cemented together." The notions of Personal Identity, Belief, Time, as incidental to Memory, are here ignored ; whereas Mill would say that, in every such process as is above described, the idea of the Self, then sentient, and now re- membering, would be irresistibly called into being. Hartley supports his contention, by instancing the remarkable fact, — which Mill also notices, but explains more completely and philosophically, — of a man, by frequent repetition, coming at last to believe a fictitious story told b}' him to be true. This phenomenon, says Hartley, is attributable to the "magnify- ing " of the ideas and the associations by the narrator. Mill on the other hand, in accordance with his more careful ex- position of the idea of the Self as one of the constituents of Memory, asserts the operation to be due to . the loss of one association, and its replacement by another. The narrator used to associate the ideas of the events imagined by him with the idea of himself as imagining or inventing them : this association becomes weaker and weaker, till it finally HARTLEY ON MEMOR V. 97 expires altogether, and a new association, namely that between the ideas of these events and the idea of himself as ex- periencing them, takes its place. It must be admitted, how- ever, that the cause of this latter association supplanting the former, would appear, from Mill's account, to be something- very like Hartley's "magnifying" the one, and ceasing to pay attention to the other. Hartley also refers sagaciously to the case of a man in doubt as to whether his trains of ideas are recollections or reveries. But this phenomenon too might be accounted for more satisfactorily on Mill's, than on Hartley's, hypothesis. The latter is of opinion that such a doubt, (when the ideas are in fact those of remembered events), represents a diminution of the associations between these ideas, and (when the ideas are in fact merely imagined) an increase of the same : but Mill would maintain that such a state of mind would in the two cases respectively indicate either a diminution or an increase of the association between the ideas of the events and the idea of the Self as 'percipient of them. In madness and in dreams, to both of which Hartley is particularly fond of referring, the vividness mentioned is often magnified to an extent which causes the mental picture or image of an action or object to appear the recollection, in some cases, and, in others, the present sensible experience, of it. Mill \_Anal. vol. i. p. 324] explains such phenomena in delirium, madness, or dreams to be the result of a mistake of present ideas for present or past sensations, just as in the above-mentioned case of repeated fiction past ideas are mistaken for past sen- sations. Hartley's account of the attempt to recollect a thing (avd/j,vr] Family. 8. Patriotism. Country. t. (Esprit de Corps. names. names. J Love of one's Order, Class. *\ Church. &c. (.Party-spirit. £. Love of Mankind. Mankind. Here too the distinction between the Affections, Motives, and Dispositions is manifest, though the names are again, unfortunately, the same. In speaking of the last of the above motives, Love of Mankind, Mill takes occasion to observe that large conceptions, such as those of Country, Mankind, and the like, not being directly objects of sense can only be brought home to men's minds through the medium of General Terms. For this purpose, as " an aid to the senses," in Baconian language, Philosophical Education necessary. i 5 6 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. IV. The Acts (as distinguished from the States) both of our- selves, AND OF OUE FeLLOW-CBEATUBES, WHICH CAUSE US PLEASURE OR PAIN. Object. Affection. Motive. Disposition. a. Acts primarily useful to the agent, secondarily to others : — ( (a) when the acts are f Courage. \ Prudence. J our own, ] (b) when the acts are I. those of others. Moral Approbation. |3. Acts primarily useful to The others, secondarily to the agent: — same ( (a) when the acts are f Justice. \ Beneficence. J our own, names. J (b) when the acts are V. those of others. Moral Approbation. y. Acts comprehending all 1 the above :— 1 ( {a) when the acts are Virtue. J our own, j (5) when the acts are Moral Appro- Love of (. those of others. bation, Moral Approbation, Sense, Moral &c. Intention, Moral Fa- culty, Sense of Eight and Wrong, &c. The fourth and last table demands a somewhat detailed explanation. It is to be noticed in the first place that Mill, conformably to his ethical theory as developed in the 'Frag- ment on Mackintosh and Miscellaneous Essays, holds the generic element in the four cardinal virtues to be the conferring of benefits on men, whether ourselves or our fellow-creatures primarily on ourselves in the case of Fortitude and Prudence, PRUDENCE AND COURAGE. 157 primarily on others in the case of Justice and Beneficence. But — and here he seems to be following Gay very closely — since Prudent and Courageous acts best enable us to perform acts of Justice and Benevolence to others, and since, further, our own acts of Justice and Benevolence best dispose others to perform similar acts towards ourselves, it follows that each of these two main classes of acts, the primarily self- regarding, and the primarily altruistic, may he said to have a double aspect; And not only this, — but there is another difference to be observed, according as the acts which cause us pleasure or pain are our own, or those of other men. First let us consider the case where the acts in question are our own. We associate with any of our own acts of Prudence and Courage, as its immediate consequence, some advantage to ourselves, either Pleasure, that is, or the cause of Pleasure : and, moreover, we associate with the ideas of our own acts of Justice and Beneficence the ideas of the pleasurable feelings of a fellow-creature (ideas which are pleasurable in them- selves), and also the ideas of the benefits which we seeondarily derive from our fellow-creatures by the performance of such acts, (the ideas, that is, of causes of pleasure to ourselves). Now to contemplate a Pleasure, together with its cause (how- ever remote), is to have a complex idea, which, after repetition, ceases to be an indifferent, and becomes a pleasurable, idea, that is, an Affection. And to contemplate, in addition, an act of ours as causing that cause, is to have the corresponding Motive. But in this case there is no act of ours to be associated as cause of that cause, because our own act is the cause. Therefore, in this case as in that Class (I), the Motive is the Affection, and the Affection is the Motive. The Disposition in this, as in all instances, is the ready capability, induced by habitual exercise and education (the e£t? induced 158 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. by eOos and SiSaxv in Aristotelian language) of being in- fluenced by the Motive, or, to use Mill's curious phraseology, of " performing the associations." Now as to another man's acts of Prudence, Courage, Justice, and Beneficence. These, though (as we have seen) primarily useful to the agent himself, are also secondarily useful to others, as being the causes or conditions of the performance by him of acts to their advantage, if not (as often in the case of Fortitude) acts directly useful in themselves to others. As such, they are attended by agreeable associations. Our ideas of such prudent or brave acts of another, — of acts, that is, related to our pleasures as causes (however remote) to effects, — become in this way complex pleasurable ideas, or Affections. It is of course still more obvious how Affections are generated, where the ideas of Just and Beneficent acts on the part of others is associated directly with pleasurable ideas of the advantages to be derived therefrom primarily by persons other than the agent himself, and how strong such Affections will become. The generic name for them is Moral Approbation or Disapprobation, Moral Sense, and the like; and this is also the name of the corresponding Motive, or of the association not only of the Prudent, Brave, Just, and Beneficent actions of others as causes with our pleasures as effects, but also of our own acts with, and as causing, these causes. For by what means can we, through our own acts, cause those causes ? Firstly, by performing similar acts our- selves ; but, secondly, by conferring praise on those acts of others of the nature specified, and affixing the stigma of Blame or Dispraise on the reverse. When we associate acts of praise or condemnation on our part as causes with the acts of our fellow-creatures as effects, and these latter acts as causes with our pleasures as effects, such an association will lead to action, and is therefore a Motive, which has received JUSTICE AND BENEFICENCE. 159 some such name as that designated ahove. The same term, or perhaps better Love of Approbation, (it must be admitted that, in all this part of his work, Mill's terminology is terribly confused), serves also for the corresponding Disposition. Some further remarks of Mill on the subject of the special motives and virtues fall to be noticed here. Since Prudence expresses, according to Mill, " the choice made, among all the innumerable acts within our power, of those, the consequences of which, when the pleasurable and painful are balanced against one another, constitute the greatest amount of good " [vol. ii. p. 282] , it follows that to be prudent, a man must have knowledge and experience of all or most of the possible consequences, or successions of con- sequences, which any given act has produced or may produce. Judgment is therefore requisite, as well as a certain disposition, and state of the will : and hence the semi-intellectual character of Prudence. So far most persons would agree : but when Mill goes on to say that knowledge is a condition of Courage as well as of Prudence (in this following Plato), and that Courage is but incurring the danger or possibility of evil for the certainty of ultimate good, — is, in fact, (for Mill, like Plato, 8 goes this length) only a species of Prudence, the analysis will probably be thought faulty. Courage is all the more courage when there is most to be lost, and most chance of its being lost. On any other explanation Mill would be obliged to call the death of the Spartans at Thermopylae an act not of courage but of fatuity, an " immoral act " (as he himself says, when speaking of cases in which no ultimate good to the agent is probable) ; and the courage of a beast (as having less to lose) would be superior to the courage of an Athenian of the age of Pericles. The very fact that we often 8 Plato defines Courage as " a right judgment concerning things to be feared and not to be feared." 160 . HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. call an action brave, but rash, shows the vital distinction between Courage and Prudence. It is when a highly civilized being possesses the greatest appreciation of life, and is bound to it by the strongest and most various ties, that his courage is most peculiarly and markedly courage. As Professor Bain observes in his note [vol. ii. p. 284 of the Analysis}, "the courageous soldier is not he who maintains a post of apparent danger unmoved, knowing that there is no real danger. . . . Something very different is exacted in return for the epithet of a brave man." Justice is similarly considered by Mill to be a section of Beneficence, and just acts to be carved out of the class of beneficent acts merely by reference to the particular legal system in use in a particular country at a particular time. In point of fact, the conventional theory of Justice is adopted. Out of all the various acts of individuals which are productive of good to others, some are so in virtue of their eonforma- bility to the laws of the state in which they are performed. There is no place in Mill's system for any theory of mental construction in the matter, of any constitution by the indi- vidual of an equity within himself, or even of adaptation of mathematical processes and proportions to the facts of the moral world. Mill is a philosopher in this respect re- sembling Plato's litigant, and is obliged to go to the law courts for justice, because he has none of his own making. In connexion with the subject of the influence of Praise and Blame on moral action, Mill notices that the very names of the cardinal virtues and of Virtue itself, signify not only the qualities characteristic of virtuous acts, but also the plea- surable ideas of the benefits resulting from the exercise of those qualities, and the performance of those acts. They are, in Bentham's phraseology, eulogistic terms, while their oppo- sites are dyslogistic. This alone is of immense power in MORAL APPROBATION. 161 attracting' men to Virtue; and every one knows the kind of homage which Vice is forced to pay to it, in assuming the properties and titles of its opponent, in order to secure a tolerable status. The importance of such names is not to be overlooked. History teaches us how much depends on whether the name of assassination or that of national deliverance is assigned to a deed immediately after its committal; and that this often has its appreciable share in determining whether a human being is to be execrated as a Guy Fawkes, or exalted as a Harmodius, a Jael, or a Charlotte Corday. Many im- portant effects may be traced to the designation of a dis- turbance of constitutional relations in a country as a revolution, or as a rebellion ; and much depends on whether a body of reformers succeed in getting themselves called a Constitution or a Convention, a Party or a Faction. Eulogistic terms, then, having by themselves alone so much significance and influence, it may be imagined what a degree of controlling power is exerted on the deeds of our fellow -creatures by the systematic diffusion of applause and condemnation. Praise, as Mill says, extends to all men : whereas our own acts (the alternative means of securing the performance of virtuous acts by others) extend only to a few. In the former case we not only express our own favourable disposition towards the per- son who is its object, but we at the same time point him out to others as a fit object of a similar affection on their parts towards him. From the pleasurable ideas connected with the being praised by others, springs not only that extraordinary case of association, which has already been noticed, the desire of posthumous fame, (when the idea of advantageous conse- quences to ourselves is so firmly associated with the idea of the performance of virtuous actions, that we cannot dissociate the two ideas, notwithstanding that a very little reflection tell us that the two things cannot coexist after death) , but also M 162 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. the desire of being deserving of praise, and the dread of being deserving of blame, — the Love of Praiseworthiness, and the Fear of Blameworthiness ; as also the state of misery attendant on the consciousness of being blameworthy in reference to past actions, which is called Remorse. Hartley makes the pleasures and pains of the Moral Sense a special class of the various pleasures and pains of which human beings are susceptible. He places them at the end of his list, after those of Sensation, Imagination, Ambition, Self- interest, Sympathy, and Theopathy ; and all these latter must, in his view, have been experienced before those of the Moral Sense can be properly appreciated. In his account of this Moral Sense, he differs slightly from Mill, in so far as he bases it less on a conscious regard to the utility of actions. He speaks of "a pleasing consciousness and self-approbation" rising up in the mind of a person who believes himself to be possessed of virtuous qualities, " exclusively of any direct explicit consideration of advantage likely to accrue to him- self" \Observ. on Man, vol. i. p. 493]. Like Mill, he re- marks on the eulogistic character of the names of virtue and the different virtuous qualities ; and also how the pleasurable ideas incidental to the frequent use and application of these names are gradually impressed by education on the minds of children. Like his master in this department of his subject, Gay, he notices the rival theories of Hutcheson, as to the instinctive character of the moral sense, and of the mathe- matical Platonists, Clarke and Cud worth, as to its alleged foun- dation in the eternal relations of things; and he contends that if it be meant that the supposed instinct, or the supposed relations, exist or operate independently of association, then no indubitable instances or proofs of such existence or operation have been produced. All moral judgments, approbations, and disapprobations are, in his opinion, deduced from association HARTLEY ON THE MORAL SENSE. 163 alone; though it is admitted (as we have implied above), that these associations may be " formed so early, repeated so often, riveted so strong," as, in a popular way, to deserve the name of " original and natural dispositions or instincts/' or even of " axioms and intuitive propositions." M 2 164 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. CHAPTER VIII. THE WILL, AS EXPLAINED BY HARTLEY AND MILL. It is characteristic of the Association Theory of Hartley and James Mill, that the "Will occupies a very late place — in Mill's anatysis, the very last — in their examination of moral phenomena. In the systems opposed to the derivative theories of ethics, it comes into prominence at the very outset of the inquiry. Kant, for instance, begins at once with its defini- tion, from which, as a starting-point, he evolves his entire speculations on morals. Schopenhauer, again, a philosopher of a very different type, although he professes to be following out Kant's doctrines to their legitimate issue, considers that this all-powerful Will, the centre of Personality, should be suppressed in favour of the impersonal Intellect, if happiness is ever to be achieved for men. But whether as the mainstay and foundation of morals, or as the incessant obstacle in the path of tranquillity, all philosophers, except Associationists, have concurred in placing the Will in the forefront of their ethical systems. With Hartley and Mill, on the other hand, after everything else is determined, and not till then, the Will follows as the necessary result. Given Association, Affection, Motive, Disposition, to find the Will is, according to this school, not very difficult. The Will, it is to be observed, is, in their view, not a faculty but " a peculiar state of mind or consciousness" [Mill, Analysis, vol. ii. p. 328], that, namely, which precedes an action. It is the cause of the action, in \ MENTAL STATES PRECEDING ACTION. 165 the proper sense of the word, that is, its immediate antecedent. The notion that it is a faculty has arisen from the common mental illusion in subjection to which, not content with having found the cause of a phenomena, we proceed to invest it with a certain imaginary Power, in virtue of which alone it is said to produce its effect. This emanation from, or property of, the cause Mill pronounces to be a fiction. To determine the nature of the Will, we have merely to " discover which is the real state of mind which immediately precedes an action." Now actions, says Mill, may be either those of the Body, or those of the Mind. 1 The former are muscular contractions, and may be preceded either by Sensations — as in the familiar cases of sneezing, vomiting, coughing, and other involun- tary or instinctive movements — or by Ideas, as in yawning, laughter, convulsive fits, on seeing another person yawn, laugh, or fall into convulsions ; or again in the case where a person rapidly shuts his eyelids on seeing an object approach them, which action is consequent on the idea of pain called up by the sight of the object. This last is a good example of association, because an infant will not wink if anything is passed rapidly before its eyes, while an adult will. 2 When these contractions of the muscles are preceded by Sensations, the steps are (I) sensation originating in the ex- tremities of the nerves, (2) " something, we know not what conveyed by the nerves to the brain," (3) a consequent state of the brain, (4) something (also unknown) conveyed by the brain through another set of nerves to the contracting muscles, 1 " A vile phrase " this — " actions of the mind." It is curious how, in this instance, Mill shows himself under the bondage of that habit of constructing metaphor, which he elsewhere (using, too, this very example) so severely reprobates in others. 3 The experiment was performed by Mr. Darwin on his own child, with this result. See his interesting a ccount of these psychological observa- tions in Mini, No. 7, {a Biographical Sketch of an Infant). 1 66 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. followed by (5) muscular contraction. "When they are pre- ceded by Ideas, the first two steps are not present, and the process begins with the third, or with a certain state of the brain. It will be seen, therefore, that in both cases the state of the brain is, strictly speaking, the immediate menial ante- cedent of the contraction : but, for purposes of the present investigation, that state may be distinguished as Sensation or as Ideation, according as it is, or is not, produced by external causes operating directly upon the nerves. The principle of those mental phenomena of the latter class which result from the tendency to imitate the actions, and experience in our own persons the sensations of another, — a species of pheno- mena familiar to physicians, under the name of imaginative diseases, — is that the action, motion, or bodily state, the idea of which is conveyed to us by what we thus perceive in others, " calls up by association the idea of the feelings which pre- cede" that action, motion, or bodily state. "The idea of the feelings exists, and the action follows." [Analysis, vol. ii. p. 343.] Sensations and Ideas, then, are to be considered as the immediate mental antecedents of muscular contraction. Now over sensations we confessedly have no control : they may therefore be dismissed from consideration : and the kind of ideation, hitherto discussed as antecedent to action, clearly does not answer to what we mean by an exercise of the Will. So much only has been established up to the present point: that muscular contractions follow ideas, that to obtain a com- mand over the former we must obtain a command over the latter, and that to produce certain sequences of associated motions, we must have acquired the power, through repetition, or otherwise, of readily calling up the correspondingly asso- ciated ideas. The power of the Will is not, therefore, exerted over the motions, but over the ideas, or trains of ideas which THE ELEMENTS OF VOLITION. 167 precede those motions. The motions or actions which we will must of course he our own, and therefore one at least of the ideas constituting the state of volition must he the idea of such an action as our own. Is there anything more involved in Volition than the above elements? Now in the cases already noticed of the ideas of our actions, preceding these actions, whether in the way of automatic imitation or of repetition, we cannot be said to will them. They are as involuntary (at all events in the adult mind) as those motions which are excited by our own sensa- tions in the manner already indicated. But it is ideas alone in any case which give birth to action : there must therefore be something in the process by which these ideas are gene- rated, when we are said to exercise volition, different from the process whereby these ideas are generated when the acts which follow them are, as in the above instances, styled involuntary. In the latter case they are produced in the way of ordinary association whether by sensations of our own, or by the ideas of the sensations of others (as when we yawn or laugh on seeing another person do so), or by our own ideas, as when we weep on reading a tragedy. But in none of these instances, can we be said to will the performance of the acts. But where strictly voluntary actions are concerned, the ideas of them, — the ideas which precede them, — are accompanied with Desire, which is their distinguishing feature. Now Desire is the idea of a future pleasurable sensation, or exemption from pain. Therefore in the state of mind which precedes what are called voluntary actions, there must coexist, (1) the idea of the action, and the idea of it, of course, as our own, (2) the idea of the pleasurable condition to be enjoyed by us consequent on the performance of the action. In other words, we must have the idea of a future pleasurable state coupled with the idea of an act of ours as causing it. But this is exactly what 168 HARTLEY AND JAMES MILL. Motive was defined as being. Is then Motive the same as Will ? No. The difference is the following. In the train of thoughts constituting the Motive, (as Mill, in a careful elaboration of a well-known Aristotelian principle, 3 points out), we start with the idea of the pleasurable sensa- tion to be obtained, proceed from it to the idea of the action of which it is contemplated as being the immediate result, then to the idea of the step next preceding it, and so on through the ideas of a series of means, till we come to the last link in the chain which ends with ourselves, that is, to the idea of some muscular contraction on our part. Now when mere Motive, unaccompanied by Volition, is present, the pro- cess of association stops at this point ; whereas when the Motive is sufficiently powerful to generate volition, it does not cease, but the mind passes from the idea of some muscular contraction on our part, to the idea of the internal sensations preceding the muscular contraction, which sensations origi- nally produced similar muscular contractions. On this the action follows. It may seem somewhat over-subtle to draw such a fine line of distinction between the idea of the outward appearance of our own action and the idea of the internal sensa- tions which precede that action. But Mill explains that these sensations, and their ideas, — though scarcely ever noticed or even thought to exist, owing to their inevitable absorption in immediately subsequent sensations and ideas, of far greater interest to us, — are yet real. Why the visible idea of an action should at one time call up the idea of the internal sensations preceding it, and at another time not, can only be 3 "o iTparov iv avaKv