THE TAXATION GF LAND VALUES LOUIS . F . P O ST BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF Henril M. Sage 1891 \.3o3..i5.^.. :■: ::.. i^v:b^As. CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 3 1924 096 276 542 The original of tliis book is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http ://www. arch i ve . o rg/detai Is/cu31 924096276542 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES A PHuruGRAl'H h\ ALFULD COX. CHICAGO, OF A MEDALLION, BV E. STIFAKT HINTON TO THE MEMORY OF WILLIAM T. CROASDALE BORN IN 1S4! — DIKD IN ISVl FOUNDFR AND F.DITOR OF THE WILMINGTON "EvERY EvENINg" Editor of the Baltimore "Day" Editor of Henry George's "Standard" "a binelctaxer IB a person who dun something for the Sintletax." — Croasilalc TAXATION OF LAND VALUES AN EXPLANATION WITH ILLUSTRATIVE CHARTS, NOTES AND ANSWERS TO TYPICAL QUESTIONS OF THE LAND-LABOR- AND-FISCAL REFORM ADVOCATED BY HENRY GEORGE By LOUIS F. POST Assistant Secretary of Labor IQ3 INDIANAPOLIS THE BOBBS-MERRILL COMPANY PUBLISHERS E.V. A'3o-37SE First edition : Copyright, 1894, as "Post's Outlines." Second edition (revised) : Copyright, 1899, as "The Single Tax." Third edition (1906) : Copyright, 1899, as "The Single Tax." Fourth edition (revised) : Copyright, 1912, as "The Taxation of Land Values." Fifth edition: Copyright, 1915, as "Taxation of Land Values." By Louis F. Post. 'UO PRESS OF BRAUNWORTH & CO. BOOKBINDERS ANO PRINTBR9 BROOKLVN, N. Yt PREFACE TO FIFTH EDITION When the contents of this book first appeared in print I was using its Charts to illustrate lectures on "The Singletax," "Absolute Freetrade," "The Labor Ques- tion," "Progress and Poverty," "The Land Question," "The Elements of Political Economy," "Socialism" and "Hard Times," which I was then delivering in the United States and Canada. For book publication I adapted the principal points of those lectures to the Singletax, the one theme to which all the subjects are related. They were originally pub- lished in this unified form in 1894 as "Outlines of Post's Lectures." That edition having been exhausted, the sec- ond, somewhat revised, was published in 1899 under the more appropriate title of "The Singletax." The third was issued in 1906 under the same title and without re- vision; and when this edition also had been exhausted, the fourth was issued in response to requests from Great Britain as well as the United States and Canada. In complying with those requests it seemed best to alter the title and the text so as to conform to a habit of speech which, originating in Great Britain and spreading into Canada and the United States, had tended to substitute for "single tax" the phrase "taxation of land values." The fifth edition is in nearly every respect like the fourth which is now out of print. Such differences as there are between taxation of land values and the single tax are explained in the text. In that connection, however, it should be here pointed out that there is a recent tendency to merge the two PREFACE TO FIFTH EDITION words single and tax as the name of a movement, philos- ophy, cult or what you will, into the proper noun Single- tax. This tendency, which accords with usage in paral- lel instances, is also desirable for purposes of distinction. As a descriptive phrase "the single tax" might mean any kind of exclusive tax. It has even been referred to, jocu- larly by some but seriously by others, as a tax upon bachelors. A distinctive name in place of an ambiguously descriptive phrase may prevent such misapprehensions. There is the advantage also of convenience. One is en- abled to write "Singletaxer" and "Singletaxism" without typographical awkwardness. With greater accuracy, too, for those allusions are to a body of economic thought or a species of social agitation in which the idea of public revenues and their sole source in land premiums, as well as their mode of collection, are inseparably associated. The "Singletaxer" as a distinctive name identifies the social reform popularized by Henry George which aims at securing for common use by means of taxation those values of social progress that land premiums express. The Charts in this volume were in the first edition printed in the body of the text; and in that edition the Illustrative Notes were foot notes in smaller type than the type of the text, while the Questions and Answers were in an Appendix. But in succeeding editions the Charts appear between pages of the text as in the present edition. They are placed, however, as near as possible to the particular text which they respectively illustrate. And in the present edition, following the arrangement of the fourth, the Illustrative Notes, in larger type than PREFACE TO FIFTH EDITION before, are put into an Appendix, while the Questions and Answers are placed in the body of the book as Part Four. This edition, the first to issue from a prominent publishing house, is superior in book-making qualities to all the others. One word about the questions in Part Four. They embody the substance of all questions actually put to me from audiences in three lecturing trips which I made in the early '90's across the continent and up and down through the States and into Canada. I think them fairly representative of the questions usually asked even to this day. If there are any new questions now, or any im- portant variations of old ones, I am unaware of it. Whether my answers are conclusive or even satisfactory is for the reader to judge ; but be their value what it may, answers are there to all the objections to the Singletax that I have ever encountered. Louis F. Post. Washington, D. C, July 1, 1915. CONTENTS PART ONE Taxation Methods CHAPTER PAGE I Enumeration of Methods 1 II The Exclusive Land Value Method .... 4 PART TWO Land Value Taxation as a Tax Reform I Direct and Indirect Taxation 6 II The Two Kinds of Direct Taxation .... 8 III Land Value Taxes Are in Proportion to Benefits 10 IV Conformity to General Principles of Taxation . 13 Section 1 — Interference with Production . . 13 Section 2 — Cheapness of Collection .... 14 Section 3 — Certainty 14 Section 4 — Equality IS PART THREE Land Value Taxation as an Industrial Reform I Involuntary Poverty 16 II The Source of Wealth 19 III The Production of Wealth 25 Section 1 — Division of Labor 25 Section 2— Trade 27 Section 3 — The Law of Division of Labor and Trade 28 Section 4 — Dependence of Labor Upon Land . 33 CONTENTS— Co»/i«M£cf CHAPTER PAGE IV The Distribution of Wealth 36 Section 1 — Explanation of Wages and Rent . . 26 Section 2 — Normal Effect of Social Progress Upon Wages and Rent ... 39 Section 3 — Significance of the Upward Tendency of Rent 40 Section 4 — The Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private Use 41 Section S — Effect of Retaining Rent for Common Use 48 Section 6 — Land Value Taxation Tends to Retain Rent for Common Use ... 49 Section 7 — A Reminder 50 V Conclusion 52 PART FOUR Answers to Typical Questions I Elementary 54 II Revenue Problems * 55 III Special Instances 59 IV Economic Effects 63 V Labor Questions 65 VI Business Questions 68 VII Money 74 VIII Miscellaneous Problems 77 Appendix — Explanatory and Illustrative Notes ... 85 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES Taxation of Land Values PART ONE Taxation Methods CHAPTER I ENUMERATION OF METHODS One of the methods of raising public revenues is by Land ValuT^TaBtationT Land va lue taxation is any tax^ levied o n land-own- ers i n proportion to the value of their land, irr espec- ti ve of its improve ments. In most countries land value taxes are familiar enough in connection with other taxes. This is so in the United States, where real estate taxes are (a) in part taxes according to the value of improvements, and (b) in part taxes according to the value of land.^ Land value taxation may thus supply (o) a greater or less proportion of the public revenues, the rest being obtained from taxes on improvements, personal prop- erty, incomes, business licenses, and so on; or (&) it may be exclusive, public revenues being raised from no other source. 1 2 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES When lanfl iralup taYgfi'nn ig pyrliKiivp, it is appro- priately enough c.a.\\e.cl jhg Single Tax, meaning only onet ax and that upon land valu es. The Single Tax (exclusive land value taxation) may vary in degree, from (o) a rate that will supply reve- nues sufficient only for the bare needs of government, to (b) a rate high enough to appropriate to public use approximately the entire annual value of land. The annual needs of a government might coincide approximately with the annual value of the land within its jurisdiction, in which case there would be no prac- tical difference between a land value tax sufficient merely for public needs, and one high enough to ap- propriate approximately all annual land values. The- oretically, however, the difference is to be observed; for there is a difference in theory and there might be in practice. We may make the following enumeration of dif- ferent kinds or degrees of land value taxation : L Land value taxation together with taxation on improvements and personal property. This is com- monly known as the General Property Tax.'' 2. Land value taxation together with taxation on improvements, personal property being disregarded or exempt. This is commonly known as the Real Estate Tax.' 3. Land value taxation to the exclusion of all other revenue taxes, but limited to the needs of government. This may be distinguished as the Single Tax Limited." 4. Land value taxation, whether exclusively such or TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 3 not, which begins with a low rate or none on land of moderate value and increases progressively in rate on land of higher values, with a view to encouraging small holdings and discouraging large ones, is known as the Progressive Land Value Tax. 5. Land value taxation to the exclusion of all other revenue taxes, and to the full rental value approxi- mately of the land. This might be called simply the Single Tax." The first three items in the foregoing enumeration, being fiscal in character, belong especially in Parts One and Two of this volume. The fourth and fifth belong more strictly in Part Three, as methods of industrial reform. The chief object of the fourth is to discourage large holdings and to encourage small ones ; the object of the fifth, comprehending that of the fourth, is to take land values for common use while leaving private earnings to individual earners. It is to be observed, however, that all are fiscal, for any of them would produce public revenues ; and that all are industrial, for any of them would tend to pro- mote freedom of industrial production and justice in the distribution of industrial products. CHAPTER II THE EXCLUSIVE LAND VALUE METHOD Land value tax ation to the exclusion of all other re venue tax es, but limited to the needs of governm ent, was pr oposed by Henry George in Progress an dPov- erty in 187 9. as the best known fiscal met ho JTand one that would moreover, b y force of its own excellence fo r revenue purposes, develop i nto the simplest means of securing to the community as a w hole the value of land, an d to each individual the value of his w ork, therehy at nnre sTi pplying- abundant public revenue s and settling, tho lah or qnpstion on the basis of ju stice. Henry George expressed the idea in these words: "Abolish all taxation save that upon land values."'' This proposal, long known as the S ingle T ax," is coming to be better and more favorably known as Land Va lue Taxati on.'^ Und er its operation all class es^ f workers, w hether manufacturers, merchants, bank ers, profession al men, clerks, mechanics, farm ers, farm- hands, ^or_£th£r_woitoi£_£ksses^w^ be wholly expmpt fr om taxatio n. It is only as men own land that they would be taxed, the tax o f each being m proportiorl, n5t to the a rea, but to the value of his land. And no one would be compelled to pav a higher tax 4 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 5 than others ij his land were improved or used while their4^,jKas not, nor if his were better impr"ovea ~or better 'usedJiajJ theirs/" (Qie va lue of its impr ove- ments ^^"^"^'^ "^t b^ rntr^irlereH in ekimatinft the value of a h olding; site value alone would govern. "\ If a site rose inltb£.Jiiarket. the ta ^ would proportionat ely "in- crease; if it fell.jhe tax woul d proportion ately di- mimeb> Land valuetaxation, therefore, when carried to the point of the Single Tax (whether limited or not) may be concisely defined as^ tax upon land alone, in t he ratio »f y^iii^ ^nH irre^tive of its improvements or it s use. PART TWO Land Value Taxation as a Tax Reform CHAPTER I DIRECT AND INDIRECT TAXATION Taxes are either direct or indirect; or, as they have been aptly described, "straight" or "crooked." ' Indire ct taxes are those that may be shifted by the first payer from himself to others: direct tax es are tho oc that can not bo - s hi f ted/ ^ The shifting of indirect taxes is accom plished by mpans.nf their tenHenry tn increase the prices of com- mn ditipt! npnn which they fall. Their magnitude and incidence^' are thereby disguised. It was for this rea- son that a French economist of the eighteenth century denounced them as "a scheme for so plucking geese as to get the most feathers with the least squawking."^* Indirect taxation costs the real taxpayers much more than the government receives, partly because the middlemen through whose hands taxed commodities pass are able to exact compound profits upon their taxes,^° and partly on account of the extraordinary 6 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 7 expenses of original collection;^' it favors corruption in government by concealing from the people the fact that they contribute to the support of government ; and it tends, by obstructing production, to crush legitimate industry and to establish monopolies.^' The questions it raises are of vastly more concern than the sum total of public expenditures. Whoever calmly reflects and candidly decides upon the merits of indirect taxation must reject it in all its forms. But to do that is to make a great stride toward the taxation of land values ex clusivelv. For thi s is a form of d irect ta xation. Land value taxes can not be shifted." CHAPTER II THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT TAXATION Direct taxes fall into two general classes : (a) taxes that are levied upon taxpayers in proportion to their ability to pay, and (6) ta xes that are levied upon them in prnpngtinti tr. fh(- hpitpfti! rerphjcrt, hy tjipm trnm thp Income taxes are the principal ones of the first class; the land value tax is the only important one of the second class. There should be no difficulty in choosing between the two. To tax in proportion to ability to pav rega rd- less of-benefijtajCficeived, i s not in accord with an y prin- cipl e. of just fynvernm ent. The land value tax, there- ' fore, as the only important tax in proportion to bene- fits, comes nearest to being an ; deal tax. But here we encounter two plausible objections. One arises from the common but mistaken notion that men are not taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes upon every kind of property they own that comes under the protection of government; the other is founded in the assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of the public benefits that each individual enjoys. Though the first of those objections ostensibly ac- 8 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 9 cepts the doctrine of taxation according to benefits,^' yet, as it leads to attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth, it, like the other, is really a plea for taxation according to ability to pay. The two objections stand or fall together. Neither objection would any longer have weight were the fact once generally perceived that the value of the service which the public gives to each individual is fairly measured by land value taxation. We should then no more think of taxing citizens in proportion to their ability to pay regardless of the benefits they receive from the public, than an honest merchant would think of charging his customers in proportion to their ability to pay regardless of the value of the goods they buy of him. CHAPTER III LAND VALUE TAXES ARE IN PROPORTION TO BENEFITS To PERCEIVE tha t land value taxation would justly measure thg value of public benefits which every indi- vidual respectively enjoys, we have only to consider that the mass^qf individu als everjrwhere and now, in paying for the land they use, actually pay for_gublic benefits in prop ortio n to what they receive. He who would enjoy those benefits must use land where the benefits can be enjoyed. He can not, for in- stance, carry land from where government is poor to where it is good; neither can he carry it from where the benefits of good government are few or enjoyed with difficulty to where they are many and fully en- joyed. H e must rent or buy land w here the bene fits of government are avai lable, or forego them. And unless he buys or rents where tEey are greatest or most avail- able, he must forego them in degree. Consequently, if he would work or live where the benefits of "govern- ment are availa ble, and does not already own land there, he will be compelled to rent or buy at a valuation which,-other -things. being_equal, will depend upon the value fifjthegpxernment service that the site he selects enables him to enjoy.^" Thus does he pay~Tor the service of government in proportion' "to' its value to 10 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 11 him. But he doesjiot pay the public, which provide^ the service ; he is required to pay land-owners. The economic principle pursuant to which land- owners are thys, aWe. to charge. JtorMosSteSiti^ for the common benefits of their common g-overnment, points, to the .tnie mfit]],Oid.,Ql-±axation. With the ex- ception of such other monopoly property as is analo- gous to land titles, and which in the purview of the Single Tax is included with land for purposes of tax- ation, ^^ land is the only kind of property that is in- creased in value by government; and the increase tends to be^in proportion to the public, service whic;h..its pos- session secures to the occupant. Therefore, by taxing laiidin proportion to its value, and exempting all other property, kindred monopolies excepted — that is to say, by adopting exclusive land valueJaxation — we should be levyingjaxes according tojafiuefits." Nor would this be in any sense class taxation. In- deed, the cry of class taxation is rather impudent for owners of valuable land to raise against land value taxes, when it is considered that under existing systems of taxation such land-owners are exempt.^* Even the poorest and most degraded classes in the community, besides paying land-owners for such public benefits as come their way, are compelled by indirect taxation to contribute to the support of government. But land-owners as a class go free. They enjoy the protection of the courts, and of the police and fire de- partments, and they have the use of schools and the 12 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES benefit of highways and other public improvements, all in common with the most favored, and upon the same specific terms ; yet, though they go through the form of paying taxes, and if their holdings are of considerable value pose as "the taxpayers" on all important occa- sions, they, in effect, and considered as a class, pay no taxes. Enjoying the same intangible benefits of govern- ment that others do, many of them as individuals and all of them as a class receive in addition a pecuniary benefit which government confers upon no other class of property-owners. The value of their property is enhanced in prop ortion to th e benehts ot good ^vern- ment and other characteristics pf_sqcial improvement which its occupants en joy. To tax them alone^ there- fore, is not to discriminate against them ; it is to charge them for wiiat.tbfiy.get ixsmiXbs^JS&i^^ CHAPTER IV CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION Land value taxation conforms niost closely to the essentkL4udad|il£a»aL Adam Smith's four .classical maxims, which are stated by Henry„XieQrg£f° as fol- lows: "The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is evidently that which will closest conform to the fol- lowiJigxQJiditions : ( 1 ) That it bear as lightly as pos- sible upon production — so as least to check the increase of the ggiifjaLiund. from _>KMc.h, taxes must „be paid and -the" community maintained.^* (2) That, it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall as directly as may be upon the ultimate payers — so as to, take from the people a&-little-as_possibleJa.addition..to what it yields to the-g0v©PHma«Ht.^^ (3) That it be certainr^so as to give the least opportunity, for tyranny oc.gorruption on the part of officials, and the least temptation to law- breaking and evasion on the part of the taxpayers.^* (4) That it bear equally — so as to ^give.no citizen an advantage or put any at^a disadvantage as compared with.aiibers."^« Section 1. — Interference with Production. Indirect"taxes~tSi3^TTctiecFpro3uction and to cause 13 14 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES scarcity by obstructing the processes of production. They fall upon men as they work, as they do business, as they invest capital productively.'" But land value taxes which must be paid and be the same in amount regardless of whether the taxpayer works or plays, or whether he invests his capital productively or wastes it, or whether he uses his land for the most productive purposes'^ or in lesser degree or not at all, lay no penal- ties u pon indiistry ;^n , ( ;], thrift. Therefore they conform to the first maxim quoted above. Section 2. — Cheapness of Collection. Indirect taxes are passed along from first payers to final consumers through many exchanges, accumulating compound profits as they go, until they take enormous sums from the people in addition to what the govern- ment receives.'^ But land value taxes take nothing from the .peflplcin. excess .of the taxT Therefore they conform to the second_ maxim quoted above. Section 3. — Certainty. No other tax, direct or indirect, conforms so closely to the third maxim. "Land lies out of doors." It can not be hidden; it can not be "accidentally" overlooked. Nor can its value be greatly misapprehended, or mis- staitecLJSeither under-apprai'sement'lior over-appraise- ment is possibl&Jto any important extent_ without the connivanee'wI-tiiejuilialejQpmmunity." The land values of a neighborhood are matters of common knowledge. Any intelligent resident can justly appraise them. TAXATION OF LAND VALUES IS and every other intelligent resident can fairly test the appraisement. Therefore the tyranny, corrup- tion, fraud, favoritism, and evasions which are so com- mon in connection with the taxation of imports, manu- factures, incomes, personal property, and buildings — the values of which, even when the object itself can not be hidden, are so distinctly matters of minute special knowledge that only experts can fairly appraise them — would be out of the question if land value taxation were substituted for existing fiscal methods.'* Section 4. — Equality . In conforming to the fourth maxim, thejand yalue tax bears more equally — that is to say, more justly — than anyjather tax. It is the only tax that falls_ upon the taxpayer in proportion to the pecuniary !^gnefit§..he receives from the public, ^^ and its tendency, accelerat- ing with increase of the tax, is to leave to every one the full fruit of his own productive enterprise and effort.^* PART THREE Land Value Taxation as an Industrial Reform CHAPTER I INVOLUNTARY POVERTY Great, however, as are the merits of land value tax- ation as a revenue system, its merits as an industrial refoxtP are of vastly greater importance. '" "" ~^ Urgent need for industrial reform, fundamental in character but simple in detail and progressive in tend- ency, is evident from the persistence of involuntary poverty among producers notwithst anding our miracu- lous _industrial_£rogress. The fact is obvious. General manifestations of poverty are so common that even good men look upon it as a providential provision for enabling the rich to drive camels through needles' eyes by exercising the modern virtue of organized giving.'^ Its acute mani f estatians -in- recurring. periods-of-.-'hard times' ' ' ' are like, epidemics of. ^xLmlenL disease, which excite the most contented to fear that they, even they, may become its victims. Its occasional spasms of violence threaten society with chaos on one hand, and, through 16 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 17 panic-stricken efforts at restraint, with despotism on the other. And it persists and deepens despite the con- tinuous JMXSS.SS.Si.t wealth-producing power. ^° That much of our poverty is involuntary may be proved, if proof be necessary, by the magnitude of charitable work which aims to help only the "deserving poor" ; and as to undeserving cases — the cases of vol- untary poverty — who can say but that they, if not due to birth and training in the environs of degraded poverty,*" are the despairing culminations of long-con- tinued struggles to maintain respectable independ- ence?*^ How can we know that they are not essen- tially like the rest — involuntary and deserving ? It was a profotmd distinction that a clever writer of fiction*^ made when he wrote of "the hopeful and the hopeless poor." There is, indeed, little difference between vol- untary and involuntary poverty, between the "deserv- ing" and the "undeserving" poor, except that the "de- serving" still have hope, while from the "undeserving" all hope if they ever knew any has gone. But it is not alone to objects of charity that the question of poverty calls attention. There is a keener poverty, which pinches and goes hungry, but is beyond the reach of charity because it never complains. And back of all and over all is the fear of poverty, which chills the best instincts of men of every social grade, from recipients of out-door relief who dread the poor- house, to millionaires who dread the possibility of pov- erty for their children if not for themselves.*^ Most men would rather die than lose a steady job or accu- 18 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES mulated property. Why do they fear if no one need be poor? It is poverty and fear of poverty that prompt men of honest instincts to steal, to bribe, to take bribes, to oppress, either under color of law or against law, and — what is worse than all because it is not merely a de- praved act but a course of conduct that implies a state of depravity — to enlist their talents in hireling work against their convictions.** Our civilization can not long resist such enemies as poverty and fear of poverty breed; to intelligent observers it already seems to yield." But how is the development of these social enemies to be arrested? Only by tracing involuntary poverty to its cause, and, having found the cause, deliberately removing it. Poverty of the involuntary kind can not be traced to its__causej, however, without serious thought; not mere reading and school study and other tutoring, but thought.*' To jump at a conclusion is very likely to jump over the cause, at which no class is more apt than the tutored class.*' We must proceed step by step from familiar and indisputable premises. CHAPTER II THE SOURCE OF WEALTH The first necessity is to make sure that we know the source of those thi ng;s that a bolish poverty by satisfy- ing want/° But it is quite unnecessary to specify all, and tediously to trace each to its origin in detail. In searching for the source of one we shall by generaliza- tion discover the source of all the rest. As a common thing of this kind, the production of which is a familiar process, Bread is probably the best example for our purpose. Let us, then, carefully trace bread to its source. To make the results of our inquiry clear to the eye we will construct a chart as we proceed. The chart should begin, of course, with a classifica- tion of Bread with reference to Man, for it is as an object for satisfying the wants of man that^we, con- sideiuhrgad at all. And then our first inquiry should be : Is Bread a part of the personality of Man, or is it an object external to him? The answer is so simple that a child could make no mistake. Obviously, Bread is external to Man. It must, therefore, be classified with what for brevity we wiL call "External Objects Jj meaning ..objects-thal are ex- ternal tqjnan. And inasmuch as bread is a product— 19 20 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES produced, as we have already noted, by a familiar manufacturing process, — and must therefore have con- stituents, we will indicate upon the chart a place for classifying Constituents as well as one for classifying Product. The chart up to this point of completion is distin- guished on Plate I as Chart A. Now let the necessary c onstituents of bread be in- serted. Any housewife, any kitchen girl, knows what they are as well as the most expert baker or learned chemist. In Chart B of Plate I, which is a continua- tion of Chart A, they are named in the place reserved for them : A baker, a lot of land, an oven, a fire, flour, yeast, salt and water. Having noted all the constituents of Bread, let us classify them in respect of their relations to Man, for the satisfaction of whose wants bread is intended. Reference to the same Chart B will show that all these Constituents may be classified either as Man — the baker falling within that category — or as objects external to man, namely. External Objects. This clas- sification is made in Chart C, Plate II. There is, however, a still further classification. Though all the Constituents classified in Chart C as External Objects are alike in the one particular that they are external to Man, some of them may never- theless differ from others in respects which, for clear thinking, must be distinguished. Let us see. Compare the first two External Objects — the lot of land and the oven. A radical difference at once appears. The lot of PLATE I CHART A pro'"*^' co.^"-'""' ^ BAKER A LOT LAND ^^^^^ ^q j^^f^p g^j AN OVEN Z^xferml Oh'ecti BRtAD A rmt FLOUR YEAST SALT WATER CHART B PLATE II prorf"^' A BAKER ^^'^ A LOT ''LAND Z^xkrmi Ol^/ecls BREAD AN OVEN A EIRE FLOUR YEAST SALT WATER £xUr/ii7l O^JecTi CHART C prod"'' const"""" ci«s^'f''"'"" A BAKER '^^^ fixfernal Olr/ects ■ BREAD A LOT«aAND AN OVEN A FIRE FLOUR YEAST SALT — A/alural External Ol'/eets GrliTicial External Oh'ects WATER CHART D TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 21 land is a Natural External Object. The oven is an Ar- tificial External Object. The lot exists independently of man's art; the oven can have no existence whatever, as an oven, but for man's art.*^ When the remaining External Objects are considered the same difference appears. All of them, Bread included, differ from the lot of land precisely as the oven does; they are arti- ficial." Let us note this difference upon our chart, which now takes the form of Chart D, Plate IL Having thus classified or generalized the constituents of bread, it is no longer necessary to name them in- dividually. We may consequently simplify the chart by erasing them, together with the word "bread" itself, retaining only the class names. It will be more appro- priate, too, if for the terms "constituents" and "classi- fication," we substitute the term "factor." All this is done in Chart E, Plate III. But grave danger of confusion is here disclosed. Artificial External Objects, as will be seen by reference to Chart E, are classified both as. J;h,e„ "product' '.and as a "factor." Yet it can not be that any factor of a product is exactly the same as the product itself. There must be some difference, and this difference we shall try to discover. Turn to ChMt„CUia.£lal£,„lI,--.J3illidi. specifies Jie, artificial constituen ts. _Qf-Jir£.ad....naxaeI:K.;..-avxti.„.fire. flour,_yeastj__saltj, water. How do these artificial factors differ from the artificial product, bread ? Simply in this, that the artificial factors are un finis hedhreaAjjwhile the prodiliiJag£aaiii?}££Lliread." The di fference , then, be- 22 TAXATION OF LAND VALtTES tween Artificial External Objects, as a factor, and Arti- ficia l,. External Objects as a final t>roduct. is that as a factor^they are unfinis hed, and as a product they are fi nished. Let us note the distinction upon the chart. It is done in Chart F, Plate III. The language of the chart may now be supplemented with the technical terms of political economy. When comprehended and used with discrimination, these dis- tinguish the differences we have discovered with equal precision and greater brevity than the more cumbrous terms upon which we have so far relied.^^ See Chart G, Plate III. At this point we find all essential differences distin- guished. Every factor of industry and every material object of desire that can be imagined falls into one or another of the four classes of the chart.°^ And from mere inspection of the chart we may see, what was promised when we began its construction, that in_ searching fr>r tlio snnrrp nf qy}e, nf the objects t hat satisf3[Jh,uman wants we have discovered the source of alL-For it is self-evident that the material wants of men are satisfied in no other way than by the consump- tion of finished artificial objects, technically termed Wealih,' and the chart shows that such objects have their source in the combination of the three "factors," namely: (1) the activities of_man, technically termed Lobar; (2) natural..obiects.external tQ-.man. techn icallv termed Land; and (3) unfinished artificial objects, technically termed Capital. PLATE III d^' ,et pro (T/f/Z/'c/W/ External Oly^ts f i^ Afatural £xternal Olr/ecl} (7rt ficial External Ol-Jecfi CHART E yM''' pcior' /^an FiDisM drtif/rinl Zlxternal Oii^/cits //arural £!xtern(Tl Oh'ects unfi/iis/ieJ CJrIif'cial £xternal Ol^jecti CHART F od^' V /Tffijhi/ (7rtiTicial External Oh'eds (WEALTH) fa .lors r//' 'an (LABOR) ,A/olural Exlernal Ol^/ecfi , , (LAND) 'Artificial External Olr/ects (CAPITAL) CHART G PLATE IV f' idacf siflCI •tor* (WEIALTM) /ian (LABOR) A/<7!ural External OA/ech (LAND) CHART H CHART I TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 23 But while these three factors combine to produce all the material objects that tend to satisfy human wants, they do not constitute the ultimate source of those objects. Our analysis is not yet ended; the chart is still incomplete. Reflection assures us that all artificial objects, fin- ished and unfinished, resolve upon final analysis into two factors : (a) the activities of man, and (&) natural external objects ; or, in technical language, all Wealth, finished and unfinished, resolves upon final analysis into Labor and La nd. In final analysis, therefore. Capital is eliminated. It exp^sses nothii^~wliich the two remaining factors do not imply ; f or Jt is by the conju nction of those two factors that Capital is pro- duced."* Unfinished artificial objects and their tech- nical term. Capital, should therefore be erased from the chart. The result appears in Chart H, Plate IV. Thus all-artificial objects external. toyman. (Wealth) are found to have their ultimate source in the conjunc- tion of man's activities (Labor) with natural objects external to man (Lajid). Finally, by dropping cumbersome expressions alto- gether, and using only technical terms, we complete this series of charts"" with Chart I, which formulates the final analysis of productive industry. The chart may be read as follows : Wealth Js-prMducedsaLdy by the..a^lication of Labor to Land.^^ This, then, is the finaLaxLaljrMs_olthe_p_rocessjesJ;hat are prunanlyj^ecessary for..,the abolitionjof^qyerty. In the application of Labor, which includes all human 24 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES effort/'' to Land, which includes the whole material universe outside of man,"* we find the source of Wealth, which includes all the artificial things that sat- is fy_iianJi^* This is the first great truth upon which the Singletax philosophy rests. CHAPTER III THE PRODUCTION OF WEALTH When considered in connection with primitive modes of production, the vital importance of the primary truth that Wealth is produced solely by the application of Labor to Land, is clear."" If primi- tive modes prevailed, in voluntary poverty . could be readily traced either to direct enslaveme nt through owners hip of Lab or, or t o indirect enslavement through ownership of Land.®^ Therecoul^T be no other cause. IF' ^SotK ^auses ^^ere^absent, every in- dividual mi ght, if he wished, enjoy all the Wealth that his own powers were, capable of producing iaJhe primitive^ modes of production, and under the limita- tions of common knowledge,,, that belonged _LQ.l!ls--en- vironment."^ But in the civilized state this principle is so entangled in the complexities of division of labor and trade as to be almost lost in the maze. Many, even of those who recognize it, fail to grasp it as a funda- mental truth. Yet it is no less vital in civilized than in primitive modes of production. Section 1. — Division_of Labor. The essential difference between primitive andciyil- ized mo des of prod uction is not in_ the accumulation of Capital, which characterizes the latter; it is in the 25 26 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES greater scope and minuteness of its division of La- ■bor." Capital is an effect of division of Labor rather t Vian a rm ixe. Division of Labor augments labor power and relieves man from the perpetual pursuit of mere subsistence. It makes civilization possible,"* by the pro- duction and utilization of capital on a large scale. The productive power of division of Labor may be illustrated by considering it as a means for utilizing differences of soil and climate. If, for example, the soil and the climate of two sections of a country, or of two different countries (for the effects of division of Labor are not dependent upon political geography'"), differ inversely, one being better adapted to the pro- duction of corn than of sugar, and the other on the contrary being better adapted to the production of sugar than of corn, they will yield more wealth in corn and sugar with division of Labor than without it. Let us imagine a Mainland and an Island, which, as to the adaptability of their soil and climate to the pro- duction of corn and sugar, so differ that if the people of each should raise their own corn and their own sugar they would produce, with a given unit of Labor force, only 22 of Wealth — 11 in corn and 11 in sugar — as shown on Plate V, Chart A. Production in that manner would ignore the opportunities afforded by na- ture to man for utilizing differences of soil and climate. But by such a wise division as Labor would adopt in similar circumstances, if unrestrained, the same unit of Labor force immensely increases the product, as shown on Plate V, Chart B. PLATE V CORN SUGAR TOTAL MAINLAND 10 / // ISLAND / 10 // TOTAL // // ZZ CHART A CORN SUGAR TOTAL MAINLAND Jio ^0 ISLAND ^^-^ / 0' CHART D TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 39 productive one. See Chart D, Plate XL We now find that all Wages have fallen to the level of Wages on the poorest land that yields anything to the given unit of Labor force; while the Rent of all but that has risen, at the expense of Wages, in proportion to its superior productiveness. °® Reflection will convince us that this must be so. Wages for a given expenditure of Labor force are no more anywhere, for any great length of time, other conditions being the same, than the like expenditure of Labor force will produce from the best land to be hdd for nothing. Rent takes up the difference.'^ Section 2. — Nor mal Effect of Social P rogress Upon ^ Wages and R ent. In the charts on Plates X and XI the effect of social growth is ignored."' We now illustrate that effect. Social growth increases the productive power of La- bor. Let us' suppose, then, that the given expenditure of Labor force as applied to the first closed space in the charts is increased by social growth to 100; as applied to the second, to 50 ; as applied to the third, to 10 ; as applied to the fourth, to 3 ; and as applied to the open space, to 1.°" If the re were n o increased demand for land, the effect on Wages and Rent would 'then be as shown on Chart E, Plate XII. The productiveness^f the poorest land in demand having risen from 1 (Chart D on Plate XI) to 3 (Chart E on Plate XII), Wages on all the la nd in use rise acco rdingly from 1 to 3. They can not be less anywhere than at the place of 40 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES Ipast prnrlnrtrvPTiPss By the same econom ic law , Rent remai ns at zero fo r the fourth space in the chart, that of the least p roductiveness7and r ises in the other s p a g sg respectively from.l. 2^m±USL7. iLaad.97.^ A little study of the charts wi ll sh ow why. r^he lesson to be learned is that Wages as well as Rent tend to rise with increased productive power ; but as a quantity and not as a proportion.^"" As a propor- tion of product, not only does Rent tend to rise with increased productive power, but Wages tend to fall.i We may see and understand this phenomenon if we observe that increase in the productive power of Labor, like increase in the number of laborers (which is indeed much the same thing in economic principle and elifect) , tends to increase demand for land. The fact, both as to numbers and power as well as effect, is indicated on Charts D and E as compared with Chart C ; and this is a fact which observation of business life will show.^"^. Section 3. — Significance of the Upward Tendency of Rent. ~™" ^~~ ""Nowrwhat is the meaning of the tendency of Rent to rise with social progre ss, while Wages tend propor- tionally-la Jail ? Does it not plainly indicate that if Rent be treated as public r evenue, advanc es in produc- tive power will .tend, through orderly and natural growth, to the realization of the best industrial ideals? Is it not likewise a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private capita l. improvementsJn ^iroductiy-e- power PLATE XII WAGES J J ~- -J _.' ^„; 100 yo /o J / RENT // f/' / (J CHART E WACE5 RENT i 1- ? ^ / ^ ,/7 CHART F PLATE XIII WAGES RENT -3 J -#- ■J X / CHART G VACES RENT J -J n ■J z / / 1/ 1 CHART H TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 41 will tend to make slaves of the maii}^ and masters of a few? Does it not mean that common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural social law, and that its pri- vate appropriation is disorderly and destructive? Caused and increased by social growth/"^ the benefits of which should be common, and attaching to land, which should be a common inheritance. Rent emphatic- ally asserts itself as a natural fund for public ex- penses^Y If there be at all such a thing as design in the uni- verse, then has it been designed t hat R ent, the earnings of ind ividuals jointly a s a social whole, shall be taken for the support oiA&Gommunity,, and that Wages, the earning s of indivi duals as individ uals, shall "KTeft to each indivi dual earner in proportion to the v alue of his serske. Section 4. — The Effect of Confiscating Rent to Pri- vate Us e. By giving Rent to individuals, society ignores this just law.^°* It thereby creates social disorder. Upon society, then, and not upon a Providence which has provided bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests responsibility for poverty in civilized conditions. Let us trace the connection and try to make it clear by means of the charts, beginning again with the white spaces on Chart A, Plate X. As before, the first-com- ers take possession of the best land. Their doing so is 42 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES shown in Chart B of Plate X. There is no Rent here ; the whole product goes to Wages. This effect has been already explained, and it is obvious from in- spection of the chart itself. But the first-co mers — in- stead oUgaving for others space they do not them - sel ves need for'T JieTaJ^nTniartsB. C, D and E — now appropriate-the-whQlfi-Qf-tJ jie best space^ usin^ only par t hut c lai ming ownership of the re st. By dis- tinguishing the used part with red color, and that which is appropriated without use with blue, we have Chart F, Plate XII. But what motive is there for appr opriating more of the best space than is used?/SinipIy"tEat"^e ap- propriators may secure the pecumary benefit of future demami~lQX„ the best iand.X What will enable them to. secure that? Our legal system of land monopoly, which confiscates Rent fro m the CQmm ui;i;t y that earns it_and gives .it_Jo_Jand;_owners_who, as^ land-owners, e arn noth ing. ^"^ Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other men come, instead of finding half of the best land still common and free, as in Chart B of Plate X, thpy fin d, all of it ow ned. They are therefore obliged to go upon poorer land or else to buy or rent from ownersof the best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than 1 if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher price in the future; for that represents the full difference between its productive- ness and the productiy.enesa-,Qf.il)SJiex£.,best, But if the fir st-comers, reasoning that the next best land TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 43 will soon be scarce and theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or-to rent~at ffia'frx'ajiati.Qn.lthe new- comers must resort to land of the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly used. Conse- quently land of the first grade commands Rent before it otherwise would. As the seller's price under these circumstances is arbitrary, it can not be stated in the charts j-^ut the nonspeculative buyer's price is limited by the superior- itjTof the best land over that which he can get for nothing. YThe charts may be made to show this, as in Chart G, Plate XIIL The inevitable effect is to make Rent at the expense of Wa ges! As that effect is illus- trateToy the chart, Rent rises from ( Chart F, Plate ,XII) to 1 (Chart G, Plate XIII), and Wages fall from 4 to 3. Owing to the success of the appropriators of the best land in securing more than their fellows for the same expenditure^^ lab-PX force, a rush is then made for unap propriated lan d — not so much to use it as to enable the appropriators to put Rent into their own pockets when further demand for land makes even the poorer land valuable.^"" We may suppose, for illus- tration, that all the remainder of the second space of Chart G on Plate XIII, and the whole of the third, are thus appropriated. The effect is noted in Chart H of Plate XIIL At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall. The reason is that there is no in- creased demand for land for use. The holding of in- ferior land for higher prices, when demand for use is 44 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES at a standstill, is like owning lots in the moon — in- teresting but not profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and the element of profit enters in. The new demand for land must be suppl ied from the open gp^rA.jiKkAak..yia]iAc.hiit 1 tn tkp-glv^r|, \^\\QX fqrrp, or else f£Qd the better grades which are monopoliz ed. That is, prod ucers must go to the frontier fo r free land, being able tlierp tn prnHnrp n^ly ] to ^\]f unit of laboE„ force; ox become tenants of the owners of th e bet ter grad es, paying in annual rent the difference betmeeiL- tlTe prodnc tiv.enesr7^''tTT'e nTefte^ l^n^T affii that -(»f.4bfe-£EeeJand.al-the-irQritier.;,„Qi:Jjuy the better land at a premium price; or hire out on wages" for piece-work or on some form of time wages. The effect would be the same in any case. No producer could geljnQr£lar_the,gixfia. expenditure of labor force than he could get where land was fr ee. As illustrated by the charts this would be only 1. IfJie.got more, it would JiQt^be a s producer from or on.th e land ; it would hf ac mnnnpnli^pr fif t-h^ l^nd. The surplus of his production would go to land-owners (to himself if he owned the land, to others if he did not) either directly on Rent account or indirectly through lowered Wages, as illustrated by Chart I, Plate XIV. The figure 1 as an item of Rent in parentheses on this chart indicates potential Rent. Produceta-would-give that much for the privilege of using th e space, but owners hold out.igir better terms ;.theref pre neither Rent nor Wages is actually produced,_though both might be. The figure 1 as an item of Wages in paren- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 45 theses on the same chart, indicates potential Wages — the increase of the Wages fund that wmnnTesult if the land were used, other things being the same. Notwithstanding that but little space is in produc- tive use on Chart I (indicated with red), the Wages fund is lowered to the same point by the mere mon- opoly of space (indicated with blue), that it would be at if all the space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby appears that under a system which confiscates Rent from the public for private uses, own- ership of land for speculative purposes causes Wages to fall to the minimum long before they would if land were owned only for use. In illustrating this effect we have again ignored the plement nf snrial grnwtVi Let US now assume as before (Chart E, Plate XII), that social growth has increased the productive power of the given expenditure of la- bor force to 100 when applied to the best land, to 50 when applied to the next best, to 10 when applied to the next, to 3 when applied to the next, and to 1 when applied to the poorest. Labor would not be -benefited now — as it was when with the same chart we illustrated the effect of appro- priation of land only for use. Although muchj.ess land is actually used (Chart J), Wages are only 1 in Chart J, whereas they were 3 in Chart^^E; yet the only dif- ference between these two charts is. that,,§JJ,_thg „jTion- opolized Jand^^Chiart^Ej.s^^//3; M?di~.Wt!iJWL^iLO,L it in OiajctJLas>.Ji6Zxo-operate to bring on what we call "good times."\ But n o sooner do "good times" return t han renewedAdemands for-land-set- in. Rent rises again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear, The end of every-~^exiod~ioi-.iihaj;d.4iiH€^- -finds Rent higher and Wages lower, as a proportion of product even if not as a quantity, than at the end of the pre- vio«s-f»&riod.^^° This result is produced by the disorderly system 48 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES under wVtir.h gnn'pty H^vprta 'Rfrjt from rnmmnn tO in- dividualJlSSs. That, maladjiistrnfflt, ifi.th£ fundamental ca use of poverty . And prngrpt;s, so lon g as the m alad- justment rnntinupj;- instP-ad nf tending- iq remnve pnv- erty as naturally progress should, actually generate s amUntsasifies it. Pnvprtv persists w ith increase o f prndiirtlu;e pnwer hpransp ]^n(\ ValUfiS - when Rent is privat ely appropria ted, tend to even further increase. There can be but one outcome : for individu a l s, suf- fering and-iifigxadation ; for socie ty, lawlessn ess and destructioujoj; decay. Section 5. — Effect, of .Exi aining Rent for Common Use^ ' If society rptainpH .Rptit for r,ommnp„,purp9?figv,.aU incentive, tn hold land for any other object than im- mediate usq 'vypuM disappear. The effect may be illus- trated by a comparison of Chart J on Plate XIV with Chart K on Plate XV. There is but one difference between those two charts. In Chari J, Rent is. confeoalsd-tQ private use; whereasjn_Chart K, Rent is taken up for common use. All the labor force ind icated with red in CharF^'does not more than utilize the space to the le ft and part of the adjoining spare nn Chart K ihis WOUld elevate Wages to what could be produced with the given la- bor force from the poorer of the two spaces. Thus. in the figurfiS-jof-the-char-tyW^ei' wouM rise from 1 (Chart J) to -SO (Chart K) ; and increase of Rent PLATE XIV VACK RtNT / / (/) / i T <^ J ^ (/) " Read chapter viii of Social Problems, by Henry George, entitled, "That We All Might Be Rich." 38. Differences between "hard times" and "good times" are but differences in degrees of poverty and in the people who suffer from it. Times are always hard with the multitude. But the voice of the multitude is too weak to be heard at ordinary times through the ordinary megaphones of public opinion. They are not regarded nor 110 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES do they regard themselves as people of any importance in the industrial world, so long as the general wheels of business revolve. It is only when poverty has eaten its way up through the various strata of struggling and pinching and squeezing and squirming humanity, and with its cancerous tentacles touched the superincumbent layers of manufacturing nabobs, merchant princes, rail- road kings, great bankers and great land-owners, that we hear any general complaint of "hard times." 39. "Could a man of the last century — a Franklin or a Priestly — ^have seen, in a vision of the future, the steam- ship taking the place of the sailing vessel, the railroad train of the wagon, the reaping machine of the scythe, the threshing machine of the flail; could he have heard the throb of the engines that in obedience to human will, and for the satisfaction of human desire, exert a power greater than that of all the men and all the beasts of bur- den of the earth combined ; could he have seen the forest tree transformed into finished lumber — into doors, sashes, blinds, boxes or barrels, with hardly the touch of a hu- man hand; the great workshops where boots and shoes are turned out by the case with less labor than the old- fashioned cobbler could have put on a sole ; the factories where, under the eye of a girl, cotton becomes cloth faster than hundreds of stalwart weavers could have turned it out with their hand-looms ; could he have seen steam hammers shaping mammoth shafts and mighty an- chors, and delicate machinery making tiny watches; the diamond drill cutting through the heart of the rocks, and coal oil sparing the whale; could he have realized the enormous saving of labor resulting from improved facili- ties of exchange and communication — sheep killed in Australia eaten fresh in England, and the order given by the London banker in the afternoon executed in San Francisco in the morning of the same day ; could he have cpnceived of the hundred thousand improvements which these only suggest, what would he have inferred as to the social condition of mankind ? It would not have seemed like an inference ; further than the vision went it would TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 111 have seemed as though he saw ; and his heart would have leaped and his nerves would have thrilled, as one who from, a height beholds just ahead of the thirst-stricken caravan the living gleam of rustling woods and the glint of laughing waters. Plainly, in the sight of the imagina- tion, he would have beheld these new forces elevating, society from its very foundations, lifting the very poorest' above the possibility of want, exempting the very lowest from anxiety for the material needs of life. . . . And out of these bounteous material conditions he would have seen arising, as necessary sequences, moral conditions realizing the golden age of which mankind has always dreamed. . . . More or less vague or clear, these have been the hopes, these the dreams born cf the improve- ments which give this wonderful century its pre-emi- nence. . . . It is true that disappointment has followed disappointment, and that discovery upon discovery, and invention after invention, have neither lessened the toil of those who most need respite, nor brought plenty to the poor. But there have been so many things to which it seemed this failure could be laid, that up to our time the new faith has hardly weakened. . . . Now, however, we are coming into collision with facts which there can be no mistaking. . . . And, unpleasant as it may be to admit it, it is at last becoming evident that the enormous increase of productive power which has marked the pres- ent century and is still going on with accelerating ratio, has no tendency to extirpate poverty or to lighten the burdens of those compelled to toil. It simply widens the gulf between Dives and Lazarus, and makes the struggle for existence more intense. The march of invention has clothed mankind with powers of which a century ago the boldest imagination could not have dreamed. But in fac- tories where labor-saving machinery has reached i,ts most wonderful development little children are at work ; wher- ever the new forces are anything like fully utilized large classes are maintained by charity or live on the verge of recourse to it ; amid the greatest accumulations of wealth, men die of starvation, and puny infants, suckle dry 112 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES breasts ; while everywhere the greed of gain, the worship of wealth, shows the force of the fear of want." — Prog- ress and Poverty, Introduction. 40. The leader of one of the labor strikes of the early eighties, a hard-working, respectable and self-respecting man, told me that the deprivations which he himself suf- fered as a workingman were nothing as compared with the fear for the future of his children that he felt when- ever he thought of the repulsive surroundings, physical and moral, in which, owing to his poverty, he was com- pelled to bring them up. IfProfessor Francis Wayland, Dean of the Yale law school, wrote in the Charities Re- view for March, 1893 : "Under our eyes and within our reach children are being reared from infancy amid sur- roundings containing every conceivable element of degra- dation, depravity and vice. Why, then, should we be surprised that we are surrounded by a horde of juvenile delinquents, that the police reports in our cities teem with the exploits of precocious little villains, that reform schools are crowded with hopelessly abandoned young offenders ? How could it be otherwise ? What else could be expected from such antecedents, from such ever-pres- ent examples of flagrant vice? Short of a miracle, how could any child escape the moral contagion of such an environment? How could he retain a single vestige of virtue, a single honest impulse, a single shred of respect for the rights of others, after passing through such an ordeal of iniquity? What is there left on which to build up a better character?" In the Arena of July, 1893, Helen Campbell said : "It would seem at times as if the workshop meant only a form of preparation for the hos- pital, the workhouse and the prison, since the workers therein become inoculated with trade diseases, mutilated by trade appliances, and corrupted by trade associates till no healthy fiber, mental, moral, or physical remains." This testimony bears a distant date, but it is as true now as when it was uttered; and similar testimony only re- cently uttered is abundant. But no further citation is necessary to arouse the conscience of the merciful and JAXATION of: land VALUES 113 the just ; and any amount of proof would not affect those self-satisfied mortals whom Kipling describes when he says that "there are men who, when their own front doors are closed, will swear that the whole world's warm." 41. Some years ago a gentleman now well and favor- ably known in New York public life — ^a judge these many years — told me of a ragged tramp whom he had brought, more to gratify a whim perhaps than in any spirit of philanthropy, from a neighboring camp of tramps to his house for breakfast. After breakfast the host asked his guest, in the course of conversation, why he lived the life of a tramp. This in substance was the tramp's reply : "I am a mechanic and used to be a good one, though not so exceptionally good as to be safe from the competition of the great class of average workers. I had a family — a wife and two children. In the hard times of the seventies I lost my job. For a while we lived upon our little savings ; but sickness came and our savings were used up. My wife and children died. Everything was gone but self-respect. Then I traveled, looking for work which could not be had at home. I traveled afoot ; I could afford no other way. For days I hunted for work, begging food and sleeping in barns or under trees ; but no work could I get. Once or twice I was arrested as a vagrant. Then I fell in with a party of tramps and with them drifted into the city. Winter came on. I still had a desire to regain my old place as a self-respecting man, but work was scarce and nothing that I could do could I find to do except some little job now and then which was given me as pennies are given to beggars. I slept mostly in station houses. Part of the time I was undergoing sentence for vagrancy. In the spring I tramped again. But now I did not hunt for work. My self-respect was gone so completely that I had no ambition to regain it. I was a loafer and a jailbird. I had no family to support, and I had found that, barring the question of self-respect, I was about as well off as were average workmen. After years of tramping this 114 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES opinion is unchanged. I am always sure of enough to eat and a place to sleep in — not very good often, but good enough. I should not be sure of that if I were a workingman. I might lose my job and go hungry rather than beg. I might be unable to pay my rent and so be turned upon the street. I might marry again and have a family which would be condemned to the hard life of the average workingman's family. And as for society, why, I have society. Tramps are good fellows — sociable fel- lows, bright fellows many of them. Life as a tramp is not half bad when you compare it with the workingman's life, leaving out the question of self-respect, of course. You must leave that out. No man can be a tramp for good until he loses that. But a period of hard times makes many a chap lose it. And as I have lost it I would rather be a tramp than a workingman. I have tried both. By the way, Mr. , this is a very good cigar — this brand of yours. I seldom smoke much better cigars." The facts in detail of this man's story may have been false ; they probably were. But so were the facts in de- tail of Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress. There is, how- ever, a distinction between fact and truth, and no matter how false the man's facts may have been, his story, like Bunyan's, was essentially true. Much of the poverty that upon the surface seems to be voluntary and unde- serving comes from a growing feeling among those who work hardest that, as Cowper describes it, they are "Letting down buckets into empty wells, And growing old with drawing nothing up." At Victoria, B. C, in the spring of 1894, I witnessed a canoe race in which there were two contestants and but one prize. Long before the winner had reached the goal his adversary, who found himself far behind, turned his canoe toward the shore and dropped out of the race. Was it because he was too lazy to paddle? Not at alL It was because he realized the hopelessness of the effort. 42. H. C. Bunner, once editor of Puck. TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 115 43. A well-known millionaire is quoted as saying : "I would rather leave my children penniless in a world in which they could at all times obtain employment for wages equal to the value of their work as measured by the work of others, than to leave them millions of dol- lars in a world like this, where if they lose their inheri- tance they may have no chance of earning a decent liv- ing." This millionaire was Tom L. Johnson. What he said was in reply to a question at a public meeting in St. Louis in 1893. 44. "From whence springs this lust for gain, to grat- ify which men tread everything pure and noble under their feet ; to which they sacrifice all the higher possibili- ties of life ; which converts civility into a hollow pretense, patriotism into a sham, and religion into hypocrisy ; which makes so much of civilized existence an Ishmaelitish war- fare, of which the weapons are cunning and fraud? Does it not spring from the existence of want? Carlyle somewhere says that poverty is the hell of which the modern Englishman is most afraid. And he is right. Poverty is the open-mouthed, relentless hell which yawns beneath civilized society. And it is hell enough. The Vedas declare no truer thing than when the wise crow Bushanda tells the eagle bearer of Vishnu that the keen- est pain is in poverty. For poverty is not merely depriva- tion; it means shame, degradation; the searing of the most sensitive parts of our moral and mental nature as with hot irons ; the denial of the strongest impulses and the sweetest affections; the wrenching of the most vital nerves. You love your wife, you love your children ; but would it not be easier to see them die than to see them reduced to the pinch of want in which large classes in every civilized community live? . . . From this hell of poverty it is but natural that men should make every effort to escape. With the impulse to self-preservation and self-gratification combine nobler feelings, and love as well as fear urges in the struggle. Many a man does a mean thing, a dishonest thing, a greedy and grasping and unjust thing, in the effort to place above want, or the 116 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES fear of want, mother or wife or children." — Progress and Poverty, hook ix, ch. iv. 45. "There is just now a disposition to scoff at any implication that we are not in all respects progressing. . . . Yet it is evident that there have been times of decline, just as there have been times of advance ; and it is further evident that these epochs of decline could not at first have been generally recognized. He would have been a rash man who, when Augustus was changing the Rome of brick to the Rome of marble, when wealth was augmenting and magnificence increasing, when victorious legions were extending the frontier, when manners were becoming more refined, language more polished, and lit- erature rising to higher splendors — ^he would have been a rash man who then would have said that Rome was en- tering her decline. Yet such was the case. And who- ever will look may see that though our civilization is apparently advancing with greater rapidity than ever, the same cause which turned Roman progress into retro- gression is operating now. What has destroyed every previous civilization has been the tendency to the un- equal distribution of wealth and power. This same tend- ency, operating with increasing force, is observable in our civilization to-day, showing itself in every progressive community, and with greater intensity the more progress- ive the community. . . . The conditions of social progress, as we have traced the law, are association and equality. The general tendency of modern development, since the time when we can first discern the gleams of civilization in the darkness which followed the fall of the Western Empire, has been toward political and legal equality. . . , This tendency has reached its full ex- pression in the American Republic, where political and legal rights are absolutely equal. . . . It is the pre- vailing tendency, and how soon Europe will be com- pletely republican is only a matter of time, or rather of accident. The United States are, therefore, in this re- spect, the most advanced of all the great nations in a direction in which all are advancing, and in the United TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 117 States we see just how much this tendency to personal and political freedom can of itself accomplish. . . . It is now . . . evident that political equality, co- existent with an increasing tendency to the unequal distribution of wealth, must ultimately beget either the despotism of organized tyranny or the worse despotism of anarchy. To turn a republican government into a despotism the basest and most brutal, it is not necessary to formally change its constitution or abandon popular elections. It was centuries after Caesar before the ab- solute master of the Roman world pretended to rule other than by authority of a Senate that trembled before him. But forms are nothing when substance has gone, and the forms of popular government are those from which the substance of freedom may most easily go. Ex- tremes meet, and a government of universal suffrage and theoretical equality may, under conditions which impel the change, most readily become a despotism. For there despotism advances in the name and with the might of the people. . . . And when the disparity of condition increases, so does universal suffrage make it easy to seize the source of power, for the greater is the proportion of power in the hands of those who feel no direct interest in the conduct of government; who, tortured by want and embruted by poverty, are ready to sell their votes to the highest bidder or follow the lead of the most blatant demagogue ; or who, made bitter by hardships, may even look upon profligate and tyrannous government with the satisfaction we may imagine the proletarians and slaves of Rome to have felt, as they saw a Caligula or Nero raging among the rich patricians. . . . Now, this transformation of popular government into despotism of the vilest and most degrading kind, which must inevi- tably result from the unequal distribution of wealth, is not a thing of the far future. It has already begun in the United States, and is rapidly going on under our eyes. . . . The type of modern growth is the great city. Here are to be found the greatest wealth and the deepest poverty. And it is here that popular government 118 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES has most clearly broken down. ... In theory we are intense democrats. . . . But is there not growing up among us a class who have all the power without any of the virtues of aristocracy? . . . Industry everywhere tends to assume a form in which one is master and many serve. And when one is master and the others serve, the one will control the others, even in such matters as votes. . . . There is no mistaking it — the very founda- tions of society are being sapped before our eyes. . . . It is shown in greatest force where the inequalities in the distribution of wealth are greatest, and it shows itself as they increase. . . . Though we may not speak of it openly, the general faith in republican institutions is, where they have reached their fullest development, nar- rowing and weakening. It is no longer that confident be- lief in republicanism as the source of national blessings that it once was. Thoughtful men are beginning to see its dangers, without seeing how to escape them; are be- ginning to accept the view of Macaulay and distrust that of Jeflferson. And the people at large are becoming used to the growing corruption. The most ominous political sign in the United States to-day is the growth of a senti- ment which either doubts the existence of an honest man in public office or looks on him as a fool for not seizing his opportunities. . . . Thus in the United States to- day is a republican government running the course it must inevitably follow under conditions which cause the unequal distribution of wealth." — Progress and Poverty, book X, ch. iv. A6. "The power to reason correctly on general sub- jects is not to be learned in schools, nor does it come with special knowledge. It results from care in separating, from caution in combining, from the habit of asking our- selves the meaning of the words we use, and making sure of one step before building another upon it — and, above all, from loyalty to truth." — Henry George's Per- plexed Philosopher, p. p. 47. "Harold Frederic, when the London correspond- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 119 ent of the New York Times, reported Mr. Gladstone as having said in substance, in one of his campaign speeches, that the older he grew the more he began to conclude that the highly educated classes were in public affairs rather more conspicuously foolish than anybody else. Mr. Frederic thought that the Tories had since done much to 'breed a suspicion that therein Gladstone touched the outskirts of a great and solemn truth.' But it needed not the action of the Tories to breed that suspicion. In this country as well as in England it is plain to any close ob- server that the highly educated classes, or to speak with more exactness, the highly tutored classes, when com- pared with the common people, are in public affairs but little better than fools. The explanation is simple. The common people are philosophers unencumbered with use- less knowledge, who look upon public affairs broadly, and moralists who pry beneath the surface of custom and precedent into the heart of public questions. The minds of the tutored classes, on the contrary, are dwarfed by close attention to particulars to the exclusion of generals, and distorted by such false morality as is involved in tutorial notions regarding vested rights." — The Standard, July 27, 1892. ^The tendency of tutoring to elevate mere authority above observation and thought is well illustrated by the story of two classes in a famous school. The primary class, being asked if fishes have eyelids, went to the aquarium and observed ; the senior class be- ing asked the same question, went to the library and con- sulted authorities, f "One may stand on a box and look over the heads of his fellows, but he no better sees the stars. The telescope and microscope reveal depths which to the unassisted vision are closed. Yet not merely do they bring us no nearer to the cause of suns and animal- cula, but in looking through them the observer must shut his eyes to what lies about him. ... A man of special learning may be a fool as to common relations." — Henry George's Perplexed Philosopher, Introduction. 120 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES PART THREE, CHAPTER II 48. For it is ability or inability to satisfy his wants that determines whether or not a man is poor. He who has the power to procure what he wants, as he wants it, and in satisfactory quality and quantity, is not poor. No matter how he gets the power, provided he keeps out of the penitentiary, he is accounted rich. 49. This difference is frequently ignored, even by political economists ; but it should be plain to any intelli- gent mind that no reasoning can be trusted which does not distinguish a difference so radical. 50. As to the flour and the yeast, there is no doubt of this. And it is equally true though not so obvious of the fire, which but for the art of man would not exist in the oven ; of the water, which but for that would not be at hand ; and of the salt, which without man's art would be in neither proper form nor place. It follows that, either as to form or place, or as to both, all the external objects, except the lot of land, are artificial. The bread itself is of course artificial. 51. It is because man desires bread that he con- structs ovens, builds fires in them, grinds flour, digs or evaporates salt, prepares yeast, or carries water to the dough-trough. And going farther back, it is because he desires bread that he raises grain, erects mills, and pro- duces machinery for bread-making. This is plain enough in a community of one like that of Robinson Crusoe. But it is just as true in a community of millions. In the community of one the solitary individual performs all the work necessary to produce bread because he wants bread. In the great society individuals divide their work, some doing one part and others other parts; but the motive, still the same, is desire for bread. All the proc- esses of industry to the extent that they are directed to the production of bread, whether they be in the depart- ments of mining, of lumbering, of railroading, of navi- gation, of engineering, of farming, of storekeeping, of baking, or what not, are steps or stages in bread-making ; TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 121 and every artificial object produced for the purpose of facilitating bread-making is to that extent unfinished bread. But bread itself, from the time it comes into the possession of the consumer (for it is not complete until the final dehverer has accomplished his work regarding it), is a finished object. The essential difference, then, between the artificial objects that are classified as "prod- uct" and those that are classified as "factors" is that the former are finished and the latter are unfinished. % Pro- fessor Marshall (Marshall's Prin., book ii, ch. Hi) di- vides artificial objects into "goods of the first order, which satisfy wants directly, such as food, clothing, etc. ; goods of the second order, such as flour mills, which satisfy wants, not directly but indirectly, by contributing toward the production of goods of the first order ;" and "goods of the third order," under which he arranges "all things that are u3ed for making goods of the second order, such as the machinery for making milling ma- chinery." He says we might carry the analysis further if necessary, and so we might ; but though we dragged it out into an interminable catalogue, every artificial item beyond "goods of the first order" would be an unfinished artificial object and for all purposes of economic reason- ing nothing else. His own classification into "consumers' goods" (finished artificial objects) and "producers' goods" (unfinished artificial objects) is complete. 52. It makes no difference what terms are adopted, for they serve only as symbols ; but it is of vital impor- tance that the same terms shall never symbolize things that essentially differ. The technical terms that usage forces upon us in connection with our subject are espe- cially liable to abuse in this respect because they are also loose colloquial words. The term "wealth" is a bewil- dering example. It has been used to symbolize as of one class such diverse things as building lots, houses, farm sites, farm improvements, deeds, mortgages, water power, promissory notes, warehouse receipts and the goods they call for, book accounts, and slaves, thus confusing three or four different kinds of things, instead of distinguish- 122 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES ing one kind from all others. Made to include building lots and farm sites and water power, the term is a symbol for natural objects; made to include houses, farm im- provements, and goods, it is a symbol for artificial objects; by including slaves it symbolizes man; and by including deeds, promissory notes, warehouse receipts, and book accounts, it symbolizes nothing but evidences of legal title as between individual men. When the same term is used to include things so essentially dififerent as "Natural Ob- jects External to Man," "Artificial Objects External to Man," "Man" himself, and indicia of title, it is hopeless to use it in reasoning about the mutual relations of those things. 53. For example: Flour, which is unfinished bread, and therefore unfinished wealth ("Capital"), appears upon analysis to be a compound of grain, a mill site, and a miller. The mill site and the miller are respectively land and labor ; but the grain and the mill are unfinished wealth ("Capital") and may be further analyzed. Pass- ing the mill for a moment to analyze the grain, we find it composed of a farmer, a farm site, and farming improve- ments and implements. The farm site, like the mill site, is land ; and the farmer, like the miller, is labor ; but the improvements and implements, like the mill and the grain, are unfinished wealth — Capital, and may be still fur- ther analyzed. And so on. If analyzed to the last, every constituent of bread, and every constituent of that con- stituent, would resolve into Labor and Land. To follow them step by step would be tedious work and require much special knowledge. It would involve consideration of factories and factory sites, stores and store sites, rail- roads and railroad sites, mining and mines, lumbering and forests, rivers, docks, oceans and ships. But analysis in full detail is not necessary. The conclusion is obvious the moment it is understood. 54. The primary error in most socialistic reasoning on economics consists in ignoring the fact that Capital is but a product of Labor and Land ; or what in effect is the same thing, in disregarding the necessary inference that TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 123 Land is the only implement of Labor. Many Socialists insist that they do not ignore it ; but that, while acknowl- edging Land to be the primary implement of Labor, they see in this only an abstract formula, having at the present stage of civilization no practical importance. Society, they urge, is impossible without Capital; and he who would live in society must have Capital, or be the slave of those who do have it. Therefore, they argue, Capital is in the social state as indispensable as land. Their rea- soning hinges upon the mistaken assumption that Capital is an accumulation of the past instead of being a product of the present. As one socialistic author puts it, "Though labor may have originally preceded Capital, yet it is now as absurd to place one before the other as it is to attempt to say whether the hen originated the egg or the egg the hen." The explanation of the division of labor and trade, one effect of which is overlooked by socialistic philoso- phies, affords a better opportunity than the present for considering this elementary economic error of Socialism, and a brief discussion of the subject will be given in that connection. (See Note 86.) But it may be explained here that much of the confusion of thought on this sub- ject among Socialists is due to unquestioning acceptance for their economic thinking of analyses of business book- keeping. For business accounts it is well enough to enter under the head of "Capital" all objects or values that serve as capital in the particular business. But this is not enough for general economic purposes, where all interests are considered. For such purposes, we must know not alone whether business men call certain objects or values Capital in their own business, but also whether there are any fundamental economic differences of which this or that particular business may not need to take ac- count. Now, there can hardly be a more fundamental economic difference than that which we distinguish by the terms "natural" and "artificial." These terms dis- tinguish such differences as that of metals in their orig- inal state in the earth, from manufactures of metal ; and while the manufacturer may properly account a mineral 124 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES deposit as part of his capital along with his machinery, the economic investigator who does so is like the school- boy who has not yet learned to distinguish between plus and minus. It is from ignoring distinctions between nat- ural capital and artificial capital, that large corporations are considered as capitalists only, and not as landlords. In economic fact they may be enormously greater land- lords than capitalists. The report of the Commission of Corporations of the United States shows that the so- called capital of the Steel Corporation (steel trust), for instance, is so largely of ore-deposit holdings that "in the ore is its highest degree of concentration and control." 55. It may seem at first like a great waste of time and space to have gone through this long analysis for no other purpose at last than to demonstrate the self-evident fact that Land and Labor are the sole original factors in the production of Wealth. But it will have been no waste if it enables the reader to grasp the fact firmly. Nothing is more obvious, to be sure. Nothing is more readily as- sented to. Yet by college professor and economic author and socialistic leader and business man alike, this simple truth is cast adrift at the very threshold of economic argument or investigation. 56. There is ample authority among economic writers for this conclusion. Professor Ely has enumerated Na- ture, Labor and Capital as the factors of production, but he describes Capital as a combination of Nature and Labor. — Ely's Introduction, part ii, ch. Hi. 1| Say de- scribed industry as "nothing more or less than human employment of natural agents." — Say's Trea., book i, ch. ii. ^ And though John Stuart Mill and numerous others wrote of Land, Labor and Capital as the three factors of production, as did Professor Jevons also, most of them, like Jevons, recognized the fact, though in their rea- soning they often failed to profit by it, that Capital is not a primary but a secondary requisite. — Jevons' Pol. Ec, sees. i6, 19. Tf Henry George says : "Land, Labor and Capital are the factors in production. The term Land includes all natural opportunities or forces; the term TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 125 Labor, all human exertion; and the term Capital, all wealth used to produce more wealth. . . . Capital is not a necessary factor in production. Labor exerted upon Land can produce Wealth without the aid of Capi- tal, and in the necessary genesis of things must so pro- duce Wealth before Capital can exist." — Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. i. ^Also: "The complexities of production in the civilized state, in which so great a part is borne by exchange, and so much labor is bestowed upon materials after they have been separated from the land, though they may to the unthinking disguise, do not alter the fact that all production is still the union of the two factors, Land and Labor." — Id., ch. viii. IJ By intel- ligent observers no authority is needed. In all the phe- nomena of human life, whether primitive or civilized, the lesson of the Chart stands out in bold relief. Nothing can be produced without Labor and Land; and nothing can be named which under any circumstances enters into productive processes that is not resolvable into either the one or the other. To satisfy all human wants mankind requires nothing but human labor and natural material, and each of them is indispensable. 57. "The term Labor includes all human exertion in the production of wealth." — Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii. 58. "The term Land necessarily includes, not merely the surface of the earth as distinguished from the water and the air, but the whole material universe outside of man himself, for it is only by having access to land, from which his very body is drawn, that man can come in con- tact with or use nature." — Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii. 59. "As commonly used the word 'Wealth' is applied to anything having exchange value. But . . . Wealth, as alone the term can be used in political economy, con- sists of natural products that have been secured, moved, combined, separated, or in other ways modified by human exertion, so as to fit them for the gratification of human desires." — Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii. 126 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES PART THREE, CHAPTER III 60. If we imagine upon a lonely island a solitary man, without capital, without clothing, without adequate shel- ter, what would be our explanation of his poverty? We could not say that it was caused by a superabundance of goods — by "over-production" ; nor should we be any more likely to attribute it to scarcity of money. We should first ask if the land of the island were barren. Upon being assured that it would yield far more than the solitary inhabitant could consume, we should ask if he were physically or mentally incapable of producing the things he required. If told that not only was he quite capable, but that in the years he had been upon the island he had continually improved in industrial knowl- edge, in inventive acuteness, in manual dexterity, and in muscular power, and yet that he was scarcely if any bet- ter able to satisfy his wants than when first cast ashore, we might ask if he were lazy. If informed that he was not lazy, that he worked almost as many hours as ever and quite as hard and far more productively, we should ask if he were the chattel slave of an exacting master. Satisfied that this was not the case, we should then say : "The only explanation left is that in some way this man's opportunities to use the island are restricted — ^the Labor of the island and the Land of the island do not freely meet." And if we were thereupon advised that a neigh- boring cannibal chief, who claimed the island as his pri- vate property, had granted the lone inhabitant permis- sion to live, upon the sole condition that he yield tribute for the land, and that the tribute had a way of advancing as the worker's productive power increased, we should understand the cause of his poverty. And we should advise him to find a way at once of throwing off that cannibal's yoke, and to postpone all secondary questions until their proper settlement could operate for his own benefit instead of the cannibal's. 61. The ownership of the Land is essentially the own- ership of the men who must use it. "Let the circum- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 127 stances be what they may — ^the ownership of land will always give the ownership of men to a degree measured by the necessity (real or artificial) for the use of land. . . . Place one hundred men upon an island from which there is no escape, and whether you make one of these men the absolute owner of the other ninety- nine, or the absolute owner of the soil of the island, will make no difference either to him or to them." — Progress and Poverty, hook vii, ch. ii. Let us imagine a shipwrecked sailor who, after bat- tling with the waves, touches land upon an uninhabited but fertile island. Though hungry and naked and shel- terless he soon has food and clothing and a house — all of them rude to be sure, but comfortable. How does he get them? By applying his Labor to the Land of the island. In a little while he lives as comfortably as an isolated man can. Now let another shipwrecked sailor be washed ashore. As he is about to step out of the water the first man accosts him: "Hello, there! If you want to come ashore you must agree to be my slave." The second replies: "I can't. I come from the United States, where they don't believe in slavery." "Oh, I beg your pardon. I didn't know you came from the United States. I had no intention of wounding your patriotism, you know. But say, they believe in owning land in the United States, don't they?" "Yes." "Very well; you just agree that this island is mine, and you may come ashore a free man." "But how does the island happen to be yours? Did you make it?" "No, I didn't make it." "Have you a title from its maker ?" "No, I haven't any title from its maker." "Well, what is your title any- how ?" "Oh, my title is good enough. I got here first." Of course he got there first. But he didn't mean to, and he wouldn't have done it if he could have helped it. But the newcomer is satisfied and says : "Well, that's a good United States title, so I guess I'll recognize it and come ashore. But remember, I am to be a free man." "Cer- tainly you are. Come right along up to my cabin." For a time the two get along well enough together. But on 128 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES some fine morning the proprietor concludes that he would rather lie abed than scurry around for his breakfast ; and not being in good humor, perhaps, he roughly commands his "brother man" to cook him a bird. "What?" exclaims the brother. "I tell you to go and kill a bird and cook it for my breakfast." "That sounds big," sneers the second free and equal member of the little community; "but what am I to get for doing this ?" "Oh," the first replies languidly, "if you kill me a fat bird and cook it nicely, then after I have had my breakfast off the bird you may cook the gizzard for your own breakfast. That's pay enough. The work is easy." "But I want you to under- stand that I am not your slave, and I won't do that work for that pay. I'll do as much work for you as you do for me, and no more." "Then, sir," the first comer shouts in virtuous wrath, "I want you to understand that my char- ity is at an end. I have treated you better than you de- served in the past, and this is your gratitude. Now I don't propose to have any loafers on my property. You will work for the wages I offer or get off my land ! You are perfectly free. Take the wages or leave them. Do the work or let it alone. There is no slavery here. But if you are not satisfied with my terms, leave my island!" The second man, if accustomed to the usages of some labor unions, would probably go out and to the music of his own violent language about the "greed of capital," destroy as many bows and arrows as he could, so as to paralyze the bird-shooting industry; and this proceeding he would call a strike for honest wages and the dignity of labor. If he were accustomed to social reform no- tions of the "goo-goo" variety, he would propose arbitra- tion, and be mildly indignant when told that there was nothing to arbitrate — ^that he had only to accept the other's offer or get off his property. But if a perceptive and red-blooded man, he would notify his comrade that the privilege of owning islands in that latitude had ex- pired. 62. While in the Pennsylvania coal regions several years ago I was told of an incident that illustrates the TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 129 power of perpetuating poverty which resides in the mon- opoly of land. The miners were in poverty. Despite the lavish protection bestowed upon them by tariff laws at the solicitation of monopolies which had dictated our tariff policy, the men were afflicted with poverty in many forms. They were poor as to clothing, poor as to shelter, poor as to food, and, to be more specific, they were in extreme poverty as to ice. When the summer months came they lacked ice because they could not afford to buy, and they suffered. But owing to the undermining of the ground and the caving in of the surface here and there, there were great holes into which the snow and the rain fell in winter and froze, forming a passable quality of ice. Now it is frequently said that intelligence, industry and thrift will abolish poverty. But these virtues did not succeed among the men of whom I speak. They were intelligent enough to see that this ice if they saved it would abolish their poverty as to ice, and they were in- dustrious enough and thrifty enough not only to be will- ing to save it, but actually to begin the work. Preparing little caves to preserve the ice in, they went into the holes after a long day's work in the mines and gathered what, so far as the need of ice was concerned, was to abolish their poverty in the ensuing summer. But the owner of that part of the earth — a man who had neither made the earth, nor the rain, nor the snow, nor the ice, nor even the hole — ^telegraphed his agent forbidding the removal of ice except upon payment of a certain sum per ton. The miners couldn't afford the terms. They controlled the necessary Labor, and were willing to give it to abol- ish their poverty ; but the necessary Land was placed be- yond their reach by an owner. In consequence of that, and not from any lack of intelligence, industry or thrift on their own part, their poverty as to ice was perpetuated. 63. It is failure to realize this that accounts for the theory of colleges and Socialists that laborers in the civ- ilized state are dependent upon accumulated capital as well as upon land for opportunities to produce. See bnte. Note 54, and post. Note 86. 130 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 64. Here are two men at a given point. Each has an errand to do a mile to the east, and each has one to do a mile to the west. If each goes upon his own errand each will travel a mile out and a mile back in one direc- tion and the same in the other, making four miles' travel apiece, or eight miles in all. But if one does both errands to the east and the other does both to the west and they trade results, they will travel but two miles apiece, or four in all. By division of labor they free half their energy and half their time for use at other work, or at study, or at play, as their inclinations dictate. 65. No more than are the efifects of a healthful cli- mate. Protectionists who argue that there should be free trade between villages, cities, counties and states in the same nation, but protection for nations, thus making the effect of trade to depend upon the invisible political boundary line that separates communities, are like the Negro woman who, when her house, without being phys- ically moved, had been politically shifted from North Carolina to Virginia by a change of the boundary line, expressed her satisfaction in the remark that she was very glad of it, because she "alius yearn tail dot dat yah Nof K'line was an a'mighty sickly State," and she was glad she didn't "live dyeah no mo' !" 66. Men who devoted themselves to specialties, un- able to exchange their products for the objects of their desire, which alone would be the motive for their special labor, would abandon specialties and resort to less civi- lized methods of supplying their wants. 67. Division of labor, whether adopted to take advan- tage of the different varieties of land, or to secure the benefits of special skill in labor, can not continue without trade; and to the degree that trade is impeded, to that degree division of labor will languish. It is only under absolute free trade between all people and in respect of all products that division of labor can flourish. Any interference with it is economically an enslavement of labor in a degree proportioned to the degree of inter- ference. TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 131 68. It will be seen from this chart that the people of the two places, by dividing their given expenditure of labor in such manner as to utilize the natural advantage peculiar to each place, secure a clear profit of 18. And this is a substantial profit, consisting not merely of figures upon paper, but of real wealth — artificial external ob- jects which serve to satisfy human desires. 69. The people of the Mainland have now sent 10 of their corn to the Island, and the people of the Island have paid for it by sending 10 of their sugar to the Mainland. For simplicity the cost of effecting the trade is omitted. It does not affect the principle. If the cost were so high that more sugar and corn could be got without division of labor than with, division of labor would be abandoned as unprofitable ; if low enough to admit of any profit at all, the trading would go on, unless restrained, precisely as if it involved no cost. It may be well to state, how- ever, that the nearer we get to no cost in trading the bet- ter are we off. Hence, any tariff on trading, whether domestic or fordgn, like railroad or shipping rates for freight, is prejudicial ; for tariffs add to the cost of trad- ing just as freight rates do. Protection has that for its object. When it does not add enough to the price of a foreign product to prevent importation it fails of its pur- pose. And though revenue tariffs have no such object they produce the same effect, only in minor degree. 70. If every man were obliged, unassisted by the co- operation of others, to supply his own needs directly by his own labor, few could more than meagerly satisfy even the simplest of those desires which we have in common with lower animals. Though each labored diligently the aggregate of wealth would be exceedingly small com- pared with the necessities of those who wished to con- sume it, while in variety it would be very limited and in quality of the very poorest kind. But by division of labor, which has been carried to marvelous lengths and is still developing, productive power is so enormously in- creased that the annual wealth products of the present 132 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES time, in quantity and quality, in variety, usefulness and beauty, almost appear to be the work of giants and fairies. 71. Mankind as a whole may be likened to a great man, with eyes to see, brain to invent and direct, nerves for intercommunication, and various muscles for various actions. As different parts of the bodies of men do dif- ferent things, each part contributing co-operatively to the general result, so it is with the body economic, whose different parts — individual men — contribute in different ways to the common good. Trade is to the body eco- nomic what digestion is to the physical body. To pro- hibit it is to deprive the great man of his stomach; to restrict it is to give him dyspepsia. Says Emerson in the "American Scholar," an oration delivered at Cambridge in 1837: "It is one of those fables which out of an un- known antiquity convey an unlooked-for wisdom, that the gods in the beginning divided man into men, that he might be more helpful to himself ; just as the hand was divided into fingers, the better to answer its ends." Re- flection upon the labor-saving power of trade makes it clear that the notion of protectionists that free trade is prejudicial to home industry has no foundation. It would interfere with "home industries" that could be better conducted elsewhere; but by that very fact it would strengthen the industries that belonged at home. When we decide to buy foreign goods we do not thereby decide to employ foreign labor instead of American labor; we decide that the American labor shall be employed in mak- ing things to trade for what we buy, instead of making the identical things that we buy. And we get a better net result or we wouldn't do it. Free trade and labor- saving machinery, which belong in the same industrial category, increase the aggregate wealth of a country where they flourish. Whether or not they tend to impov- erish individuals or classes, depends upon the manner in which the increased wealth is distributed. If they do so tend, the remedy surely does not lie in the direction of obstructing trade and smashing machines so that less TAXATION of: land VALUES 133 wealth may be produced with given labor, but in altering the conditions that promote unjust distribution. 72. The term "production" means not creation but adaptation. Man can not add an atom to the universe of matter; but he can so modify the condition of matter, both in respect of form and of place, as to adapt it to the satisfaction of human desires. To do this is to produce wealth. "Consumption" is the ultimate object of all pro- duction. We produce because we desire to consume. But consumption does not mean destruction. Man has no more power to destroy than to create. His power in consumption, like his power in production, is limited to changing the condition of things. As by production man changes things from natural to artificial conditions in order to satisfy his desires, so by consumption he changes things from artificial to natural conditions in the process of satisfying his desires. Production is the drawing forth of desired things, of Wealth, from the Land ; con- sumption is the returning back of those things to the Land. \ "All labor is but the movement of particles of matter from one place to another." — Dick's Outlines, p. 25. ^ "Production consists merely in changing things." — Ely's Intro., part ii, ch. i; Mill's Prin., book i, ch. i, sec. 2. 1[ "As man creates no new matter but only utili- ties, so he destroys no matter but only utilities. Consumption means the destruction of utility." — Ely's Intro., part v, ch. i, p. 268. ^Production means "drawing forth." — Jevons" Primer, sec. z/. "[["Man can not create material things. . . . His efforts and sacri- fices result in changing the form or arrangement of mat- ter to adapt it better for the satisfaction of wants." — Marshall's Prin., hook ii, ch. Hi, sec. i. ^ "It is some- times said that traders do not produce; that while the cabinet-maker produces furniture, the furniture dealer merely sells what is already produced. But there is no scientific foundation for this distinction." — Id. If "As his [man's] production of material products is really nothing more than a rearrangement of matter which gives it new utilities, so his consumption of them is noth- 134 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES ing more than a disarrangement of matter which dimin- ishes or destroys its utiHties." — Id. \ "In like manner as by production is meant the creation not of substance but of utility, so by consumption is meant the destruction of utility and not of substance or matter." — Say's Trea., book a, ch. i. T[ "All that man can do is to reproduce ex- isting materials under another form, which may give them a utility they did not before possess, or merely en- large one they may have before presented. So that in fact there is a creation not of matter but of utility ; and this I call production of wealth. . . . There is no actual production of wealth without a creation or aug- mentation of utility." — Say's Trea., book i, ch. i. 73. Isn't it significant that while Robinson Crusoe had unsatisfied wants he was never out of a job? 74. Demand for consumption is satisfied not from hoards, of accumulated wealth, but from the stream of current production. Broadly speaking there can be no accumulation of wealth in the sense of saving up wealth from generation to generation. Imagine a man satisfy- ing his demand for eggs from the accumulated stores of his ancestors ! Yet eggs do not differ in this respect from other forms of wealth, except that some other forms will keep a little longer, and some not so long. The notion that a hoarding instinct must be aroused before the great and more lasting forms of wealth can be brought forth is a mistake. Houses and locomotives, for example, are built not because of any desire to accumulate wealth, but because we need houses to live in and locomotives to transport us and our goods. It is not the saving, but the serving, instinct that induces the production of these things ; the same instinct that induces the production of a loaf of bread. ^ Artificial things do not save. No sooner are the processes of production from land complete than the products are on their way back to the land. If man does not return them by means of consumption, then through decay they return themselves. Mankind as a whole lives literally from hand to mouth. What is de- manded for consumption in the present must be pro- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 135 duced by the labor of the present. From current produc- tion, and from that alone, can current consumption be satisfied. "Accumulated wealth" is, in fact, not wealth at all in any considerable degree. It is merely titles to wealth yet to be produced. A share of stock in a mining company, for example, is but a certificate that the owner has an undivided property interest in a natural mineral deposit and the machinery constructed to operate a mine there, and that he is legally entitled to a proportion of the wealth produced and to be produced from that deposit. Titles to future wealth may be both legally and morally valid. This is so when they represent past labor or its products loaned in free contract for future labor or its products; for example, a contract for the delivery of goods of any kind to-day to be paid for next week, or next month, or next year, or in ten years, or later. Or they may be legally but not morally valid. This is so when they represent the profits of a franchise (whether paid for in labor or not) to exact tribute from future labor ; for example, a franchise to confiscate a man's la- bor through ownership of his body, as in slavery, or a franchise to confiscate the products of labor in general through ownership of land. Or they may be both legally and morally invalid, as when they are obtained by illegal force or fraud from the rightful owner. 75. If it be asked how Personal Servants can draw the food out of the retail stores unless they have money, let the questioner inform himself as to the ways in which business is done. No man, unless he be a notori- ous cheat or in extraordinary bad luck, needs money iii order to obtain goods at retail stores, provided he has or can presently get profitable employment. All he needs is employment, or an early prospect of employment, and a reputation for honesty. There is therefore no unwar- ranted assumption in the example, even if we exclude the use of money from consideration. See Note 77. 76. Farmers, millers, bakers, ranchers, butchers, fishermen, hunters, makers of food-producing _ im- plements, food merchants, railroad men, sailors, 136 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES draymen, coal miners, metal miners, builders, bank- ers who by exchanging commercial paper facili- tate trade, together with clerks, bookkeepers, fore- men, journeymen, common laborers, and other hired workmen in all these various branches of food produc- tion, find work seeking for them instead of their seeking for work. To specify the labor that would be profitably affected by this demand would involve the cataloguing of all workmen, all business men, and all professional men who either directly or indirectly are connected with food industries, and the naming of every grade of such labor, from the newest apprentice to the largest supervising em- ployer. Would not this be putting an end to "hard times"? For what is the most striking manifestation of "hard times" ? Is it not "scarcity of work" ? Is it not that there are more men seeking work than there are jobs to do? Certainly it is. And to say this is not to limit "hard times" to hired men. The real trouble with the business man when he complains of "hard times" is that people do not employ him as much as he expects to be employed. Work is scarce with him, just as with those he employs, or as he would phrase it, "business is slack." Let there be ten men and but nine jobs, and you have "hard times." The tenth man will be out of work. He may be a good union man who abhors a "scab" and will not take work away from his brother workman. So he hunts for a job which does not exist, until all his savings are gone. Still he will not be a "scab," and he suffers de- privation. But after a while hunger gets the better of him, and he takes one of the nine jobs away from another man by underbidding. He becomes a "scab." And who can blame him ? Any one would rather be a "scab" than a corpse. Then the man who has lost his place becomes a "scab" too, and turns out some one else by underbid- ding. And so it goes aj;,ain and again until wages fall so low that they but just support life. Then the poorhouse or a charitable institution takes care of the tenth man, who thereafter serves the purpose of a possible labor TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 137 competitor to prevent a rise in wages. Meanwhile, dimin- ished purchasing power, due to low wages, bears down upon business generally. But let there be ten jobs and but nine men. Conditions would be instantly reversed. Instead of a man all the time seeking a job, a job would be all the time seeking a man ; and wages would rise until they equaled the value of the work for which they were paid. And as wages rose, purchasing power would rise, and business in general would flourish. If general de- mand freely directed general production, there would al- ways be ten jobs for nine men, and no longer only nine jobs for ten men. It could not be otherwise while any wants were unsatisfied. 77. The mechanism of these exchanges should be ex- plained : Personal Servants upon demanding food may pay money for it. The retailers might thereupon pass the money along, and it would ultimately return to Per- sonal Servants. Or the Personal Servants may give notes payable at a future time, which being endorsed over would at last be redeemed by them in services. Or they may give checks on banks, which assumes previous work done by them or the discounting of their notes by the banks. As the world's exchanges are almost wholly adjusted by means of checks, and other commercial pa- per which is in effect the same as checks, let us illus- trate that mode by a series of charts adapted from Je- vons. ^We will begin with two traders, A and B. They have no money, but every time that one demands any- thing of the other he must offer in exchange something that the other wants. There must be what is called "a double coincidence" of demand and supply; each must want what the other has. This is primitive barter. It may be represented by the following chart : A B In the civilized state, even in its beginnings, primitive barter must be obstructive to trade, and it gives way to 138 TAXATION OF! LAND VALUES the use of currency — some common medium which is taken for goods not because the taker wants it but be- cause he knows that he can readily exchange it for the goods that he does want. With currency in use, when A wants anything of B he is not obHged to find some- thing that B wants. All he needs is currency. Thus currency reduces the friction of trading. But as the volume of trade augments, demand for cur- rency increases ; and because it is scarce, or troublesome or dangerous to transmit, or all together, easier means of exchange are resorted to, and bookkeeping takes the place of currency as currency took the place of primi- tive barter. At this stage, when A wants anything of B, B charges him; and when B wants anything of A, A charges him. Their mutual accounts being adjusted, the small balance is paid with currency. Thus the de- mand for currency is greatly lowered by bookkeeping, and the friction of trading is correspondingly reduced. Now let us bring in two more traders, C and D : Though all four of these traders keep mutual accounts, the settlement of balances requires more currency than before, and scarcity of currency, together with the dan- ger and expense of transmission, evolves an extension of bookkeeping. A common bookkeeper, called a "Bank," is employed, and all need for currency disappears: Balances are now settled by checks, and all accounts are adjusted in the central ledger at the bank. TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 139 But the introduction of another group of traders, an- other community, renews the demand for currency, and another bank appears. Thus : And now the two banks are in the same position that A and B were in before any bank came. They keep mutual accounts, but they must have currency to settle their balances. And if we bring in more communities the demand for currency further increases. Thus : 140 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES Now the four banks are in the same situation that A, B, C and D were in before there were any banks. This evolves a bank of banks — a clearing-house : All necessity for currency once more disappears. These charts illustrate the principle by which mutual trading is effected. In practice, the need of currency is never_ wholly done away with, but the tendency is con- stantly in the direction of doing away with it. It is supposed that over ninety per cent, of the trading transactions of the world are adjusted in this manner, and less than ten per cent, by means of currency. The clearing-house principle extends over the civilized world. In illustration of this, observe the following chart : lTAXATION of land values 141 MEW YORK PAWS Rio These five cities are like the five banks. The book- keeping of each city is conducted by local banks and clearing-houses, and the central bookkeeping by those of the market town of the world, which in the chart is London. In this way the mobility of labor is in effect enormously increased. Labor in every corner of the world is brought into close trading relations with labor everywhere else, so that only war, pestilence, protection and land monopoly interfere with the full freedom of its movement. 78. Personal Servants, on the basis of their employ- ment by Luxury-makers, demand more food, which keeps Food-makers at work ; Food-makers demand more cloth- ing, which keeps Clothing-makers at work; Clothing- makers demand more shelter, which keeps Shelter-makers at work; Shelter-makers demand more luxuries, which keeps Luxury-makers at work; Luxury-makers demand more services, which keeps Personal Servants at work. And so on indefinitely. If now we add progressive in- vention, so that every one produces more and more 142 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES wealth with less and less labor, instead of finding pov- erty upon the increase, instead of being harried by peri- odical "hard times," we shall find business brisk and every one becoming richer and richer. That is to say, though all work less than before, each obtains better results from others while giving better results in ex- change. And should we improve the verisimilitude of the illustration by bringing in the fact that all workers in civilized society are specialists in a much more minute degree than the division into Clothing-makers, Food- makers, etc., would imply — ^that every one who works does over and over some one thing in one of these branches, as the making of shoes or the baking of bread, or even only part of a thing, as the cutting of shoe soles, and that while giving out a great deal of his own product he demands in pay a little of every other kind of product — the same effect would regularly result. Every man who demands anything for consumption thereby deter- mines the direction of Labor toward the production not only of that thing, but also of all the artificial materials and implements, from the simplest tool to the most ex- pensive and complex machines that are used in its pro- duction. The actual process is much more intricate than that of the charts, but the charts illustrate the principle so that any intelligent person who understands them can apply it to the most complex affairs of industrial life. ^"This principle is so simple and obvious that it needs no further illustration, yet in its light all the complex- ities of our subject disappear, and we thus reach the same view of the real objects and rewards of labor in the intricacies of modern production that we gained by observing in the first beginnings of society the simpler forms of production and exchange. We see that now, as then, each laborer is endeavoring to obtain by his exertions the satisfaction of his own desires ; we see that although the minute division of labor assigns to each producer the production of but a small part, or perhaps nothing at all, of the particular things he labors to get, yet, in aiding in the production of what other producers TAXATION of: LAND VALUES 143 want, he is directing other labor to the production of the things he wants — in effect, producing them himself. And thus if he makes jackknives and eats wheat, the wheat is really as much the .produce of his labor as if he had grown it for himself and left wheat-growers to make their own jackknives." — Progress and Poverty, hook i, ch. iv. 79. There is no end to man's wants. ^"The demand for quantity once satisfied, he seeks quality. The very desires that he has in common with the beast become extended, refined, exalted. It is not merely hunger, but taste, that seeks gratification in food ; in clothes, he seeks not merely comfort, but adornment ; the rude shelter be- comes a house; the undiscriminating sexual attraction begins to transmute itself into subtile influences, and the hard and common stock of animal life to blossom and to bloom into shapes of delicate beauty." — Progress and Poverty, book it. ch. Hi. ^A labor agitator was arguing the labor question with a rich man, the judge of his county, when the judge as a clincher asked: "What do workingmen want, anyway, that they haven't got?" Promptly the agitator replied with the counter-question : "Judge, what have you got that you don't want ?" 80. Regarding society as a unit, the operation of the law is no less indisputable in social than in solitary con- ditions. The demands of society as a whole determine the degree of activity for each department of produc- tion, much as Robinson Crusoe's demand for baskets imposed greater activity upon his arms than upon his legs, or as his demand for goats imposed greater activit)' upon his legs than upon his arms. But it is not neces- sary to regard society as a unit in order to see that in the social as in the solitary state, labor in production is expended in the direction of demand for consumption. Each individual, in the social as in the solitary state, produces the identical wealth that he demands for con- sumption. The man, for example, who wants a coat, and to get it makes shoes that he does not want, but with which he hires some one to make him a coat, really 144 TAXATION OF. LAND VALUES produces the coat; while he who wants shoes, and to get them makes coats which he does not want, but which he trades for shoes, really produces shoes. Similarly, through the whole range of industry, each individual hires other individuals to do what he wants done, and pays for it by doing for others what they want done. The condition is one of reciprocal hiring. Under the common sense legal maxim, qui facit per alium facit per se (what one does by another he does himself), as sound in economics as in jurisprudence, each laborer, by in- ducing others to make the things that he demands, in order to exchange them for what he makes, really pro- duces what he demands. But for his demands, supple- mented by his labor, these things would not be produced. True it is that in general trade goods are usually made in advance of specific demand for them. But it would be superficial reasoning to infer from this that produc- tion determines consumption i«tead of being determined by it. The collection of corrlmodities in the market is analogous to the collection of water in reservoirs for the accommodation of inhabitants of cities. Water is so collected in advance of specific demand, not to induce the people to consume water, but because, being accus- tomed to consuming water, they make a steady demand for it. And this demand determines the supply. There are large reservoirs for large cities and small ones for small cities. So with the comm,ercial reservoir. Stores are filled with goods in advance of specific demand, not to induce demand but in obedience to it. There is an approximate constancy to the demand for wealth, upon which labor relies, and in consequence of which wealth is continually in process of completion. Though orders be supplied from existing stock, the stock is at once re- plenished in accordance with the demand upon it. And this is equivalent to the proposition that demand for consumption determines the direction in which labor will be expended in production. For it makes no difference in economic principle whether a shoe dealer takes his customer's measure and makes him a pair of shoes, or TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 145 keeps shoes in stock, and when he sells a pair buys an- other Uke them. In either case the shoe dealer is pro- viding shoes pursuant to order. In the one he anticipates the order and has the goods ready when they are called for; in the other he obliges his customer to wait until the goods can be made. Though production may often seem to precede demand, as when goods are stored months in advance of any possible demand for consump- tion, and may sometimes precede it actually, as when a new nostrum is placed upon the market, the fact re- mains that general production in any direction rises and falls with the rise and fall of general demand for con- sumption — in other words, is determined by that demand. And this law regulates the supply of wealth not only as to quantity, but also as to quality and variety. 8L "This, then, we may say is the great law which binds society — 'service for service.' " — Dick's Outlines, 82. In the light of this principle how absurd are some of the explanations of hard times. Overproduction! when an infinite variety of wants are unsatisfied which those who are in want are anxious and able to satisfy for one another. Hatters want bread, and bakers want hats, and farmers want both, and they all want machines, and machinists want bread and hats and machines, and so on without end. Yet while men are against their will in partial or complete idleness, their wants go unsatis- fied! Since producers are also consumers, and produc- tion is governed by demand for consumption, there can be no real overproduction until demand ceases. The ap- parent overproduction which we see — overproduction relatively to "effective demand" — is in fact a congestion of some things due to an abnormal underproduction of other things, the underproduction being caused by ob- struction in the way of Labor. Scarcity of capital! when makers of capital in all its forms are involuntarily idle. Scarcity of capital, like scarcity of money, is only a loose expression for lack of employment. But why should there be any lack of employment while men have un- 146 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES satisfied wants which they can reciprocally satisfy? Too much competition! when competition and freedom are the same. It is not freedom but restraint, not compe- tition but monopoly, that obstructs the action and reac- tion of demand and supply which we have illustrated in the chart. 83. See Notes 15 and 16 of this Appendix, and cor- responding text. 84. Demand for food is not only demand for all kinds and grades of Food-makers, but also for as many differ- ent kinds of land as there are different kinds of labor set at work. So a demand for clothing is not only a de- mand for Clothing-makers, a demand for shelter is not only one for Shelter-makers, a demand for Luxuries is not only one for Luxury-makers, a demand for services is not only one for Personal Servants, but these demands are also demands for appropriate land — ^pasture land for wool, cotton land for cotton, factory land, water fronts, railroad rights of way, store sites, residence sites, office sites, theater sites, and so on to the end of an almost endless catalogue. 85. See Notes 23 and 24 of this Appendix, and cor- responding text. 86. Persons with socialistic inclinations argue that while it is true that Labor and Land are the only things necessary in primitive conditions, Capital also is neces- sary in civilized conditions. (See ante. Note 54.) And some of them want to know, sometimes with something like a sneer, what clerks and mechanics and bookkeepers and other specialists in our highly organized industry would do with land even if it were freely open to them. "They don't know how to make food, and they can't eat sand !" I once heard a Socialist exclaim. The same notion is widespread among that large class of Singletax oppo- nents in church and college whom the late Wm. T. Croas- dale described as "people who believe in Socialism, but don't believe in putting it into practice." The idea is best expressed perhaps by a brilliant socialistic writer, Charlotte Perkins pilman, in the following lines_; TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 147 "Free land is not enough. In earliest days When man, the baby, from the earth's bare breast Drew for himself his simple sustenance, Then freedom and his effort were enough. The world to which a man is born to-day Is a constructed, human, man-built world. As the first savage needed the free wood, We need the road, the ship, the bridge, the house, The government, society, and church, — These are the basis of our life to-day — As much necessities to modern man As was the forest to his ancestor. To say to the new born, 'Take here your land ; In primal freedom settle where you will. And work your own salvation in the world ;' Is but to put the last-come upon earth Back with the dim forerunners of his race, To climb the race's stairway in one life! Allied society owes to the young — The new men come to carry on the world — Account for all the past, the deeds, the keys. Full access to the riches of the earth. Why ? That these new ones may not be compelled Each for himself to do our work again ; But reach their manhood even with to-day, And gain to-morrow sooner. To go on, — To start from where we are and go ahead — That is true progress, true humanity." — In This Our World. If one man were turned loose alone upon the earth, or shut off from trading with his fellows, it might in great degree be true, as Mrs. Oilman says, that he would be put "back with the dim forerunners of his race, to climb the race's stairway in one life;" but her criticism does not apply to millions of free men who freely trade. To them the land would be enough. Even though they were denied existing roads and ships and bridges and houses, they would soon make new ones, and starting "from where we are," would "go ahead." For free land means access to all natural materials and forces, and free trade means unobstructed industrial intercourse be- tween laborer and laborer. These are the essential con- ditions, the only conditions, of all production — even of the most civilized. The root of the socialistic idea is 148 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES the thought that we are dependent for modern life upon accumulated capital. This is a mistake. Modern life depends, not upon accumulated capital, but upon accu- mulated knowledge made effective by interchange of la- bor. A laborer who operates some great machine seems to be dependent upon the owner of his machine for op- portunity to work; but the only people upon whom he really depends are laborers who are competent co-oper- atively to make such machines, and who have access to both the land from which the materials must be drawn and that upon which they must group themselves while doing the work. When Socialists lay stress upon the importance of accumulated capital they are attributing to accumulated capital the power that resides in land and trade ; for to control these is to command the bene- fits of accumulated knowledge. Since the production of a machine precedes its use, the inference is almost irresisti- ble, upon a superficial consideration, that opportunities to labor and compensation for labor are governed by the ex- isting supplies of machinery to which labor is allowed ac- cess. But this is of a piece with the old notion of classical political economy that opportunities to labor are depend- ent upon the existing supplies of subsistence that are de- voted to the maintenance of laborers. The inference is wrong in either form. When we once grasp the essen- tial truth of the law illustrated in the text, that the pro- duction of subsistence, or machinery, or any other un- finished object, that is to say, of Capital, is but a form of general wealth production, and that all forms of wealth production are in obedience to demand, we clearly see that labor is in no respect dependent upon Capital either for employment or compensation. In the social as in the solitary state, Labor and Land are the only factors of wealth production. It is not Capital but Land that supplies materials to Labor for its subsistence and its machinery. Instead of capitalists supplying laborers with subsistence and machinery, laborers themselves con- tinuously produce subsistence and machinery from the TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 149 materials that land supplies. Capitalists neither employ nor pay laborers ; laborers employ and pay one another. IfKeir Hardie, the distinguished Labor member of the British Parliament, once objected in a public speech that while the Singletax considers the relation of men to the land it ignores the relation of men to one another. For the latter reason he considered himself as "more than a Singletaxer." Mr. Hardie had evidently ignored the fact that the Singletax includes the principle of free trade; or else the fact that free trade, supplementing free land, would accomplish with reference to the re- lations of men to men what he criticized the Singletax for ignoring. Free trade is that phase of the Single- tax which considers the relation of men to men, even as its other phase considers the relation of men to the land. IfMuch of the socialistic misapprehension of the Singletax is due to confusions of Land with Capital, as if they were identical. For business purposes this identification is immaterial. Whether the "capital" of a business house consists, for instance, of the money value of land, or of machinery, etc., or of both, makes no difference so far as the mere question of marketable assets is concerned. But when the question is political, the difference is very great. Taxation, for instance, op- erates upon land values and machine values quite differ- ently; and rights of ownership have a different moral sanction and different industrial origins and economic effects. For political purposes the difference between land as the natural environment and opportunity for la- bor and artificial tools as products of labor must be dis- tinct. 1[Most of the so-called "capital" of our time is not Capital in contradistinction to Land; it is land the value of which is capitalized. In every effective instance of the power of Capital over Labor, the capital men- tioned consists of a commercial mixture of artificial cap- ital and natural capital — of machinery produced by Labor and land produced by Nature. The commercial mixture is effected by means of evidences of title, such as rail- 150 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES road stocks which represent tracks, etc., (labor prod- ucts), and grants of exclusive rights of way (land) ; and it is the land titles hidden in those stocks that are greatest if the railroad is at all a capitalistic menace. To insist that Capital (as distinguished from Land) is monopolistic because "capital," the commercial mixture of land and labor products, is so, seems very much like asserting that soda water is intoxicating because men may get drunk on whisky and soda. IJThe object of Socialism and that of the Singletax is the same — ^abo- lition of the exploitation of labor. The Singletax pro- posal proceeds upon the theory that abolition of land monopoly will abolish exploitation of labor. Socialists insist that abolition of capital monopoly also is neces- sary. This is conceded by Singletax advocates, but they consider that abolition of land monopoly makes monopoly of capital impossible. In reply, Socialists point to powerful capitalists who own little land; to which the Singletaxer responds that their "capital" proves to be nearly all land when you investigate the source of their incomes. Apart, however, from socialistic misap- prehensions as to the seat of capitalistic power. Socialism sets up a demand for government by the labor class. If by this is meant hired man class alone, the Singletax advocate would disagree ; but in so far as Socialism does not make that limitation, the Singletax advocate agrees, f The one solid rock upon which the Singletax theory rests, moreover, is that no socialistic progress can be secure, however good it may be in itself, unless it is preceded or accompanied by abolition of land monopoly. Control of the land is the corner-stone of all power. Be- cause it rests upon land monopoly Capital is formidable ; until land monopoly is abolished. Labor will be weak. Karl Marx told the whole story in a few words when in his Gotha-platform letter, reprinted in the International Socialist Review (Chicago, May, 1908), he said: "In the society of to-day, the means of labor are monopolized by the landed proprietors. Monopoly of landed property is even the basis of monopoly of capital and by the cap- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 151 italists." ^Read Progress and Poverty, book i, chs. iii, iv, and v. Also read The Story of My Dictatorship, chs. V, vi, vii, and viii. PART THREE, CHAPTER IV 87. "What is paid for labor of any kind is called wages. We are apt to speak of the payments given to the common day-laborer only as wages ; and we give finer names to payments made for some other kinds of serv- ice. Thus we speak of the doctor's or the lawyer's fee ; of the judge's salary; of the teacher's income; of the merchant's profit; of the banker's interest, and of the professor's emoluments. They are all in reality only payments for labor of different kinds, or for different results of labor, — that is, they are all wages." — Dick's Outlines, p. 23. Tf'Wages is what goes to pay for the trouble of labor." — Jevons' Primer, sec. jp. ^"His [the manager's] share is called the wages of superintendence, aiid although usually much larger than the share of a common laborer, it is really wages of the same nature." — Id., sec. 41. l["The common meaning of the word wages is the compensation paid to a hired person for manual labor. But in political economy the word wages has a much wider meaning, and includes all returns for exertion. For, as political economists explain, the three agents or factors in production are land, labor and cap- ital, and that part of the produce which goes to the sec- ond of these factors is styled by them wages. . . . It is important to keep this in mind. For in the stand- ard economic works this sense of the term wages is recognized with greater or less clearness only to be sub- sequently ignored." — Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii. 88. Rent "is what is paid for the use of a natural agent, whether land, or beds of minerals, or rivers, or lakes. The rent of a house or factory is, therefore, not all rent in our meaning of the word." — Jevon/ Primer, sec. 40. lf"The term rent in its economic sense . . . differs in meaning from the word rent as com- 152 TAXATION OFl LAND VALUES monly used. In some respects this economic meaning is narrower than the common meaning ; in other respects it is wider. It is narrower in this : In common speech, we apply the word rent to payments for the use of build- ings, machinery, fixtures, etc., as well as to payments for the use of land or other natural capabilities; and in speaking of the rent of a house or the rent of a farm, we do not separate the price for the use of the improve- ments from the price for the use of the bare land. But in the economic meaning of rent, payments for the use of any of the products of human exertion are excluded, and of the lumped payments for the use of houses, farms, etc., only that part is rent which constitutes the consid- eration for the use of the land — that part paid for the use of buildings or other improvements being property interest, as it is a consideration for the use of capital. It is wider in this: In common speech we only speak of rent when owner and user are distinct persons. But in the economic sense there is also rent where the same person is both owner and user. Where owner and user are thus the same person, whatever part of his income he might obtain by letting the land to another is rent, while the returns for his labor and capital are that part of his income which they would yield him did he hire in- stead of owning the land. Rent is also expressed in a selling price. When land is purchased, the payment which is made for the ownership, or right to perpetual use, is rent commuted or capitalized. If I buy land for a small price and hold it until I can sell it for a large price, I have become rich, not by wages for my labor or by interest upon my capital, but by the increase of rent. Rent, in short, is the share in the wealth produced which the exclusive right to the use of natural capabili- ties gives to the owner. Wherever land has an exchange value there .is rent in the economic meaning of the term. Wherever land having a value is used, either by owner or hirer, there is rent actual; wherever it is not used, but still has a value, there is rent potential. It is this capacity of yielding rent which gives value to land. Un- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 153 til its ownership will confer some advantage, land has no value." — Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. ii. 89. "The primary division of wealth in distribution is dual, not tripartite. Capital is but a form of labor, and its distinction from labor is in reality but a subdivi- sion, just as the division of labor into skilled and un- skilled would be. In our examination we have reached the same point as would have been attained had we sim- ply treated capital as a form of labor, and sought the law which divides the produce between rent and wages; that is to say, between the possessors of the two factors, natural substances and powers, and human exertion — which two factors by their union produce all wealth." — Progress and Poverty, book in, ch. v. IfCare must be taken not to confuse the hire of a house, commonly and legally termed "rent," with economic Rent. House rent is really Wages ; it is compensation for the labor of house building. But economic Rent is not compensation for anything the owner does ; it is simply differential premi- ums for the varying advantages of different locations. 90. Land of every kind may vary in desirableness from other land of the same kind. Certain farming land, for example, is so fertile that it will yield to a given application of labor two bushels of wheat to every bushel that certain other farming land will yield; and it is ob- vious that, other things being equal, farmers would pre- fer the more fertile land. But some fertile land lies so far away from market that less fertile land lying nearer is more productive, because it costs less to exchange its products for what their producer demands ; in such cases farmers would prefer the less fertile land. The same principle applies to all kinds of land. Building lots at or near a center of residence or business are preferable for most purposes of residence or business to lots -equally good in other respects which are far away. Now, the land that is preferable is, of course, most in demand; and if it be all in use, with demand for it unsatisfied, competition for the preference sets in, and gives value to it. All land can not be equally desirable. Some ex- 154 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES eels in fertility. Some is rich with mineral deposits, a species of fertility. On some, towns and cities settle, thereby adding to the productiveness of the labor that uses it, because these sites are thus made centers of co- operation or trade. And yet production in the civilized state requires that the producer shall have exclusive pos- session of the land he needs. This necessity inevitably gives to some people more desirable land than others have, even though all should have an abundance. Conse- quently the returns to equal labor are unequal. The man who has land that is more fertile or better located than that of another gets more wealth than the other in return for a given expenditure of labor. If, for example, one with given labor produces 10 bushels of corn from fertile land, equal, say, to $5 worth of any kind of wealth in the market, and the other with the same labor produces 8 bushels of corn, or $4 worth of any kind of wealth in the market, the first receives 2 bushels (or $1) more for his labor than the other receives for his, though each la- bors with equal effort, skill, and intelligence. Or, if the fertility of the land be the same, but its situation in ref- erence to the market be such that the cost of transporta- tion still preserves the relation of $5 to $4, the same inequality of wages results. It is this phenomenon that gives rise to Rent. Rent is the market value of just such differences in the quality of opportunity as are here illus- trated. It is a premium for choice land, for preferential locations, for site, for space. This premium is a very different thing from compensation for individual labor. Nor is the difference modified when premium-owners first obtain Wages for work, and with them buy the pre- mium-commanding land. Rent can no more be turned into compensation for individual labor by exchanging labor products for mere legal power to exact it, than a man can be turned into Wealth by exchanging Wealth for him. Whether the fruits of purchase or of conquest or of fraud, Rent always constitutes that part of Wealth which is deducted from current production as premiums for superior opportunities for production. Wages and TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 155 Rent are both drawn from Wealth, and both go often to the same individual and in the same form of payment, as when a freehold farmer consumes the grain he raises from more fertile land than his neighbors have, or a city freeholder occupies or receives hire from his house and lot ; but Wages flow from Wealth to labor as compensa- tion for production, while Rent flows from Wealth to land-monopolists in premiums for allowing Labor to pro- duce Wealth from superior locations. Wages are appur- tenant to Labor; Rent is appurtenant to Land. It is as laborer that the individual takes Wages, but as land-mon- opolist that he takes Rent. 91. A unit of labor can not be definitely measured save by the value of some labor product. The day's labor of one may produce less than an hour's labor of another. But for purposes of illustration it is competent to refer to a unit of Labor force as an abstraction, intending thereby to denote all the Labor of muscle and brain requi- site to acquire the necessary knowledge and skill and to produce wealth to a given value from given natural sources. 92. "No land ever pays rent unless in point of fertil- ity or situation it belongs to those superior kinds which exist in less quantity than the demand." — Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec. 2. \ "The produce of labor consti- tutes the natural recompense or wages of labor. In that original state of things which precedes both the appropri- ation of land and the accumulation of stock, the whole produce of labor belongs to the laborer." — Smith's Wealth of Nations, hook i, ch. viii. If "Rent or land value does not arise from the productiveness or utility of land. It in no wise represents any help or advantage given to production, but simply the power of securing a part of the results of production. No matter what are its capabilities, land can yield no rent and have no value until some one is willing to give labor or the results of labor for the privilege of using it ; and what any one will thus give, depends not upon the capacity of the land, but upon its capacity as compared with that of land that can 156 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES be had for nothing. I may have very rich land, but it will yield no rent and have no value so long as there is other land as good to be had without cost. But when this other land is appropriated, and the best land to be had for nothing is inferior, either in fertility, situation or other quality, my land will begin to have a value and yield rent. And though the productiveness of my land may decrease, yet if the productiveness of the land to be had without charge decreases in greater proportion, the rent I can get, and consequently the value of my land, will steadily increase. Rent, in short, is the price of monopoly, arising from the reduction to individual own- ership of natural elements which human exertion can neither produce nor increase." — Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. ii. 93. "Rent is the effect of a monopoly; though the monopoly is a natural one, which may be regulated, which may even be held as a trust for the community generally, but which can not be prevented from existing. ... If all the land of the country belonged to one person he could fix the rent at his pleasure. . . . The effect would be much the same if the land belonged to so few people that they could and did act together as one man and fix the rent by agreement among themselves. . . . The only remaining supposition is that of free compe- tition." — Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec. i. If Rent "considered as the price paid for the use of land is natu- rally a monopoly price." — Smith's Wealth of Nations, book i, ch. xi. 94. The line of separation between the poorest land thus commanding a premium, and the best land for which labor will not pay a premium, was formerly called the "margin of cultivation," probably because the law of rent was not understood with reference to any but agricul- tural land ; but it may now be better called the "margin of production," since the law of rent applies to all kinds of land, including, of course, the building lots of cities. The premium for land falls not into the fund termed Wages, but into the fund termed Rent. When Rent ap- TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 157 >i pears, Vaiges consists not of the entire product of labor, but of io much of that product as might with the same ■ expenditure of labor force be produced from the best land that commands no premium. The remainder goes to the owners of the land from which it is in fact pro- duced, in proportion to the advantages which their land respectively contributes to its production. This excess is the premium. It is what constitutes Rent as distin- guished from Wages. And both the amount of the gen- eral fund Rent, and the amount of rent which each land- owner obtains, are determined by the competition of La- bor for superior opportunities. Thus, in the beginnings, all Wealth would be Wages; but as labor was forced from better to poorer lands, or what is the same thing in its principle of operation, as greater capabilities attached to particular lands in conse- quence of social development, good government, in- dustrial improvement, etc., Rent would arise, and as a proportion of the gross Wealth-product, would increase as Labor was forced to poorer land or new capabilities were added to land by society. The law derived from these phenomena is known as Ricardo's law of rent. Henry George formulates it as follows: "The rent of land is determined by the excess of its produce over that which the same application can secure from the least pro- ductive land in use." — Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. a. ^ As will be noticed, the law is the law of Wages as well as the law of Rent. For whatever determines the proportion of Wealth taken as Rent necessarily deter- mines the proportion left as Wages. With reference to that part of this note which reads, "as greater capabilities attached to particular lands in consequence of social de- velopment, good government, industrial improvement, etc.," a British student of the subject, A. W. Madsen, has asked this question : "As Labor and Land are the two factors in the production of Wealth, is it not a mistake to say that these new capabilities will be added to Land rather than to Labor?" In explanation of his question he adds: "If new capabilities were added to all land, in- 158 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES eluding the land at the margin of cultivation, does it fol- low that Rent will rise? It seems that Rent would rise on all land above the margin only if new capabilities were added to that land in varying proportions." Taking my statement as it appeared in previous editions of this book, and as I retain it here for purposes of correction, I think the criticism may be sound ; for I seem to have mentioned the value of greater capabilities attaching to particular land as added to land in general. I might be understood, therefore, as implying that they would be evenly instead of differentially distributed in Rent. The statement should be altered so as to read : "As greater capabilities attached to particular lands in consequence of social de- velopment, good government, industrial improvement, etc.. Rent on the particular land so affected would arise or increase," etc. The concrete illustration is a city. Mr. George summarizes this point {Progress and Poverty, ch. ii of book iv, p. 241) as follows: "To recapitulate: The effect of increasing population upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent, and consequently to dimin- ish the proportion of the produce which goes to capital and labor, in two ways : First, by lowering the margin of cultivation. Second, by bringing out in land special capa- bilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special capabil- ities to particular lands. I am disposed to think that the latter mode, to which little attention has been given by political economists, is really the more important." 95. Though figures are used, these charts are to be understood not as mathematical demonstrations, but sim- ply as suggestive illustrations. 96. The labor that was forced to the poorest lands would continually bid for the opportunities that the better lands offered, until an equilibrium was reached at the point shown in the previous chart, where the given ex- penditure of labor is as well compensated in one place as in another. If laborer and land-owner be different persons, the laborer receives what is distinguished as Wages, and the land-owner what is distinguished as Rent, TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 159 If the same person, he receives Wages as laborer and Rent as land-owner. 97. But we must not jump to the conclusion that there is any essential wrong in Rent. Rent is nature's method of measuring the value of the dififerences in nat- ural opportunity which different laborers, owing to varia- tions in land, are obliged to accept. And, what in prac- tice is more important, it is nature's method of measur- ing the value to each individual of those advantages which consist in accumulations of common knowledge, in co- operative effort, in good government, in a word, in the benefits that society as a whole confers as distinguished from those which each individual earns. The question is not one of the rightfulness or the wrongfulness of Rent. Personal freedom necessitates Rent, for it neces- sitates the private possession of land, and private posses- sion of land, some locations being more desirable than others, makes Rent inevitable. Nothing short of com- munism could abolish it. The real question is. What shall society do with Rent ? Shall it give it to individuals, or use it for common purposes ? ^ "Were there only one man on earth, he would have a right to the use of the whole earth. When there is more than one man on earth, the right to the use of land that any one of them would have, were he alone, is not abrogated; it is only limited. ... It has become by reason of this limita- tion, not an absolute right to use any part of the earth, but (1) an absolute right to use any part of the earth as to which his use does not conflict with the equal rights of others (i. e., which no one else wants to use at the same time), and (2) a co-equal right to the use of any part of the earth which he and others may want to use at the same time." — A Perplexed Philosopher, p. 45. 1[ It is in the adjustment of co-equal rights that Rent occurs. 98. "The effect of increasing population upon the dis- tribution of wealth is to increase rent ... in two ways : First, by lowering the margin of cultivation. Sec- ond, by bringing out in land special capabilities otherwise 160 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES latent, and hy attaching special capabilities to particular lands." — Progress and Poverty, book iv, chs. ii and Hi. Tf "When we have inquired what it is that marks off land from those material things which we regard as products of the land, we shall find that the fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The right to use a piece of land g;ives command over a certain space — a certain part of the earth's surface. The area of the earth is fixed ; the geometric relations in which any particular part of it stands to other parts are fixed. Man has no control over them ; they are wholly unaffected by demand ; they have no cost of production ; there is no supply price at which they can be produced. The use of a certain area of the earth's surface is a primary condition of anything that man can do ; it gives him room for his own actions, with the enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and the rain which nature assigns to that area ; and it determines his distance from, and in a great measure his relations to, other things and other persons. We shall find that it is this property of land, which, though as yet insufficient prominence has been given to it, is the ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers are compelled to make between land and other things." — Marshall's Prin., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i. 99. Of course social growth does not go on in this regular way. The charts are merely illustrative; they are intended to illustrate the universal fact that as any land becomes a center of trade or of other industrial or social relationship its value rises. 100. "Perhaps it may be well to remind the reader, before closing this chapter, of what has been before stated — that I am using the word wages not in the sense of a quantity, but in the sense of a proportion. When I say that wages fall as rent rises, I do not mean that the quantity of wealth obtained by laborers as wages is nec- essarily less, but that the proportion which it bears to the whole produce is necessarily less. The proportion may diminish while the quantity remains the same or in- creases." — Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. vi. .TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 161 101. The condition illustrated in the last chart would be the result of social growth if all land but that which was in full use were common land. The discovery of mines, the development of cities and towns, and the con- struction of railroads, the irrigation of arid places, im- provements in government, all the infinite conveniences and labor-saving devices that civilization generates, would tend to abolish poverty by increasing the compensation of labor, and making it impossible for any man to be in involuntary idleness, or underpaid, so long as mankind was in want. If demand for land increased, Wages would tend to fall as the demand brought lower grades of land into use ; but they would at the same time tend to rise as social growth added new capabilities to the lower grades. And it is altogether probable that, while prog- ress would lower Wages as a proportion of total product, it would increase them as an absolute quantity. IfThe British critic quoted in a previous note, Mr. Madsen, sug- gests with reference to the above clause of this note as it appeared in previous editions and is here reproduced, that "this is a very indefinite conclusion to come to as the re- sult of an economic argument," because economists ought to be "able to say definitely how wages will be affected by tracing definite causes to their effects and stating posi- tively whether wages will rise or fall." Political economy as a science is one of tendencies. Economists may tell what the general tendency of given general conditions will be ; but they can not tell what specific effects will oc- cur, for all the facts are not available. They can predict, for illustration, that if one man be given an absolute mon- opoly of the planet with power to retain it, he will be sup- ported by the labor of other men ; but they can not tell what proportion each will give him nor how much he will get. The comparison of proportional with quantitative wages is considered with some fullness by Henry George in Progress and Poverty, book iv, chapter iv. The pri- mary efifect of labor-saving improvements is doubtless to delay the need for lower grades of land ; but the second- ary efifect — ^though the first in point of time, if general 162 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES and confident expectation of improvement has set in — is to hurry the demand, even if not the need, for lower grades of land. It is suggested that if we devoted our- selves as a nation to the growing of wheat, labor-saving devices would enable us to grow the same quantity on less land and therefore give the benefit to wages. This is true as a tendency; and it is because it is true as a tend- ency that, under the influence of the expansiveness of human desires and the consequent intensity of monopo- lization of land, it is not true as a fact of actual experi- ence. Able to get a larger quantity of wheat with less labor, we continue doing the same labor, thereby increas- ing our production of wheat, in order to swap the excess for sealskin coats, or other objects of previously ungrati- fied desires. The efifect is a tendency to an increase in the demand for wheat land, and consequently to an in- crease of Rent rather than of Wages. 102. Here, far away from civilization, is a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from government, he needs no public revenues, and none of the land about him has market value. Another settler comes, and another, until a village appears. Some public revenue is then required. Not much, but some. And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and land values are higher. It be- comes a city. The public revenues required are enor- mous, and so are the land values. ^ This criticism has been made: "If the tendency is for wages to fall, under natural conditions, would this not mean that the value of the services of an individual wage-earner would de- crease with social progress ?" The question results from inattention to the point noted in Note 101 (96 of third edi- tion) as to proportional and quantitative wages, and also to the point regarding speculation in land values. It has been the chief object of the Rent diagrams to illustrate this very thing. With social progress wages tend to fall as a proportion of product. Under natural conditions the value of the services of an individual would therefore TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 163 fall, as a proportion of product. But as the product is greater, so the individual's absolute wages are greater. Individually he is richer from less labor ; and socially he should be better off from the common use of increased land values. That would be the natural result. But when land monopoly (an unnatural factor) is introduced, giving the increasing values of land to individuals instead of the community, a speculative pressure sets in. Land is held out of use for higher prices. This diminishes the market supply of land. Thereby its price is increased out of proportion to its greater productiveness. Conse- quently wages diminish not only as a proportion relatively to product, but also as' an absolute quantity. It is not merely social progress that produces the quantitative re- duction of wages; it is social progress under land mon- opoly. This is the theme of Progress and Poverty, and the phenomenon from which the book gets its name. 103. Society, and society alone, causes Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth, and receding with the decline of society, it measures the earning power of society as a whole as distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on the other hand, measure the earning power of the individuals as distinguished from that of society as a whole. We have distinguished the parts into which Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent ; but it would be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as Communal Earnings and Individual Earn- ings. And how can society be justly supported in any other way than out of its own earnings ? ^Criticizing the theory that "rent is simply payment for public service," my British reviewer, Mr. Madsen, says : "It would seem to me that the sum of the Wages of all the laborers [meaning all workers] is the earning power of the na- tion as a whole, and that Rent is purely the payment that these individual laborers must make to one another as compensation for the advantageous positions which they occupy in producing wealth." That seems to me to be a true statement well made ; but doesn't it mean precisely 164 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES what Note 98 of the third edition (the first paragraph of Note 103 of this edition) means? The critic may have been misled by the idea of public service, assuming that this term implies that Rent is determined by service ren- dered by the public through government. That would be a mistake. The idea is that Rent is determined by social service, which includes not only governmental or like public service, but also that untraceable common service which every individual renders to the whole, over and above what he renders to himself, when he engages in specialized production. It is a social or co-operative phe- nomenon — is Rent; and although the more fertile spots will yield Rent when others do not, this is true only in co- operative (t. e., specialized) industry. Even then, the proportion of Rent due to exceptional fertility (including mineral deposits, etc., in that term) is probably very slight in comparison with the proportion due to social or co-operative concentrations. To call Rent the wages of society as a whole, in contradistinction to individual Wages, may be a poor figure of speech, but it is at any rate a figure that conforms closely to the fact. 104. "Whatever dispute arouses the passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so much as to the ques- tion, 'Is it wise ?' as to the question, 'Is it right ?' This tendency of popular discussions to take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law of the human mind ; it rests upon a vague and instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest truth we can grasp. That alone is wise which is just ; that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow scale of individual actions and individual life this truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field of national life it everywhere stands out. I bow to this arbitrament and accept this test." — Prog- ress and Poverty, book vii, ch. i. The reader who has been deceived into believing that Henry George's propo- sition is in any respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is taken. IJAs an illustration of the weakness of the opposing position, the argument advanced by one of the TAXATION OF, LAND VALUES 165 most distinguished men of his time may be read to advan- tage. It will be found in Land and Its Rent, by Gen. F. A. Walker. General Walker was so naively lucid, that one has only to read his book thoughtfully to realize not only that he was wrong, but that if his is the best answer to George, George must have been right. That General Walker was not strongly logical may be inferred from his controversy of 1883 with Henry George, which is reproduced in the Appendix to George's Social Prob- lems; that he was strong neither logically nor morally in reference to civic relationships is evident from the final paragraph of his preface to Land and Its Rent, men- tioned above. Alluding there to his discussion of Henry George's views in the body of Land and Its Rent, Gen- eral Walker says : "For the spirit in which he discusses the views of a writer who deliberately proposes that gov- ernment shall confiscate the entire value of landed prop- erty, without compensation to those who, under the ex- press sanction and encouragement of government itself, have inherited or bought their estates, the author has no apology to offer. Every honest man will resent such a proposition as an insult." This point can have no logical or moral force unless it applies to the value not only of land, but of every other kind of property which may at any time be inherited or bought "under the express sanc- tion and encouragement of government," for General Walker gives no reason for considering landed property especially sacred. It follows, if General Walker thought straight morally and reasoned straight logically, that every honest man would resent as an insult any proposi- tion to confiscate in any way the entire value of any kind of property "without compensation to those who, under the express sanction and encouragement of government itself, have inherited or bought" it. If that position is sound, the sacredness of property is determined not by the moral law but by governmental sanctions irrespective of the moral law. Could any contention be more absurd, either in logic or in morals? If slavery exists, govern- ment must not abolish it without compensating slave own- 166 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES ers! . And this, notwithstanding that Abolitionists who have always opposed it, and slaves who have been born or kidnaped into it, and their descendants as long as the compensation, debt lasted, would be taxed to pay for the losses of those who have favored and profited by slavery. So long as that compensation was withheld, not only would slave-owners continue to profit, but the slaves must continue to suffer confiscation of their work. Query: Could an individual slave confiscate from his master the entire value of himself as a slave, by running away, without exciting the resentment of "every honest man" of the kind for whom General Walker spoke? Observe that the question of whether landed property and slave property are morally on the same level is not involved in General Walker's code of civic morality. The moral question he raises, and the only one, is not whether landed property and slave property are morally the same. He holds that the value of any kind of property whatever, if inherited or bought "under the express sanction and encouragement of government," can not be confiscated morally without compensation to its owners. 105. It is reported from Iowa that a few years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall. Securing possession of it after much digging, he was offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed the money, and the two went to law about it. After an appeal to the highest court of the State, it was finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor by the right of labor, could the work- man have the money, because the title to the meteorite was in the man who owned the land upon which it fell. 106. The text speaks of Rent only as a periodical or continuous payment — what would be called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to selling value that we usually refer in the United States, Canada and Australasia, when dealing in land. Land which has the power of yielding Rent to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 167 used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from it or not. This selling value will be the capitalization of its present or prospective power of producing Rent. In fact, much the larger proportion of land that has a selling value is wholly or partly unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would if fully used. This condition is expressed in the chart by the blue color. ^"The capital- ized value of land is the actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes which it is likely to afford, allowance be- ing made on the one hand for all the incidental expenses, including those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any kind of business, and its advantages, material, social, and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." — Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. p. "The value of land is com- monly expressed as a certain number of times the current money rental, or, in other words, a certain 'number of years' purchase' of that rental; and other things being equal, it will be the higher the more important these direct gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance that they and the money income afforded by the land will rise." — Id., note. 1|"Value . . . means not utility, not any quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality which gives to the possession of a thing the power of ob- taining other things in return for it or for its use. . . . Value in this sense — ^the usual sense — is purely relative. It exists from and is measured by the power of obtaining things for things by exchanging them. . . . Utility is necessary to value, for nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of gratifying some physical or mental desire of man, though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself does not give value. ... If we ask our- selves the reason of . . . variations in . . . value . . . we see that things having some form of utility or desira- bility, are valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most of the things that have value this difficulty or ease of getting them, which determines value, depends on the amount of labor which must be expended in producing 168 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES them ; i. e., bringing them into the place, form and condi- tion in which they are desired. . . . Value is simply an expression of the labor required for the production of such a thing. But there are some things as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements that labor has made on it, often has value. . . . Yet a little examination will show that such facts are but exemplifications of the gen- eral principle, just as the rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . . The value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate struc- ture and appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is resolvable on an analysis into an equivalent of the labor required to produce such a thing in form and place ; while the value of things not produced by labor, but neverthe- less susceptible of ownership, is in the same way resolva- ble into an equivalent of the labor which the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to obtain or save." — A Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v. 107. The paradise to which the youth of our country have so long been directed in the advice, "Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described in Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iv, as follows : "The man who sets out from the Eastern seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation, where he may obtain land without paying rent, must, like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass for long distances through half-tilled farms, and traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches the point where land can be had free of rent — i. e., by homestead entry or pre-emption." 108. Henry Fawcett, in his work on Political Econ- omy, book ii, ch. iii, observes with reference to improve- ments in agricultural implements which diminish the ex- pense of cultivation, that they do not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in addition to the rent already paid him, all that is saved in the expense of cultivation." This TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 169, is true not alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of improvements in all other branches of industry. 109. "The cause which limits speculation in commodi- ties, the tendency of increasing price to draw forth addi- tional supplies, can not limit the speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor diminish; but there is nevertheless a limit to the price of land, in the minimum required by labor and capital as the condition of engag- ing in production. If it were possible to continuously re- duce wages until zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce. But as wages can not be permanently reduced below the point at which laborers will consent to work and reproduce, nor interest below the point at which capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence, speculation can not have the same scope to ad- vance rent in countries where wages and interest are al- ready near the minimum, as in countries where they are considerably above it. Yet that there is in all progressive countries a constant tendency in the speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iv. 110. As Puck once put it, "The man who makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off the grass.' " 111. "That a speculative advance in rent or land values invariably precedes each of these seasons of indus- trial depression is everywhere clear. That they bear to each other the relation of cause and effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary relation between land and labor." — Progress and Poverty, book v, ch. i. 112. What are called "good times" reach a point at which an upward land market sets in. From that point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a rise in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all depart- 170 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES ments of labor and with all grades of laborers. This tendency continues until the fictitious values of land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty merely ; when the same tendency is felt by the class of labor that is distin- guished as "the business interests of the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times" are periodical, because land values, by falling, allow "good times" to set in, and by rising with. "good times" bring "hard times" on again. The effect of "hard times" may be overcome, without much, if any, fall in land values, by sufficient increase in productive power to overtake the fictitious value of land. 113. The laborer would receive in Distribution all that he earned and no more than he earned in Production ; and that is the natural law. In social conditions, where industry is subdivided and trade is intricate, it is impossi- ble to say arbitrarily what is the equivalent of given labor. Hence, no statute fixing the compensation for labor can really be operative. All that we can say is that labor is worth what men freely contract to give and take for it. But it must be what they freely contract to take as well as what they freely contract to give ; and men are not free to contract for the sale of their labor when labor gen- erally is so divorced from land as abnormally to glut the labor market and make men's sale of their labor for almost anything the buyer offers, the alternative of star- vation. Laborers may be as truly enslaved by divorcing Labor from Land as by driving laborers with a whip. 114. "Such dupes are men to custom, and so prone To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead A course of long observance for its use, That even servitude, the worst of ills, Because delivered down from sire to son Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing." — Cowper. It is only custom that makes the ownership of land seem reasonable. I have frequently had occasion to tell of the necessity under which the city of Cleveland, Ohio, TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 171 found itself, of paying a land-owner several thousand dollars for the right to swing a drawbridge over his land. When I described the matter in that way, the story at- tracted no attention; it seemed perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture audience. But when I described the transaction as a payment by the city to a land-owner of thousands of dollars for the privilege of swinging the draw "through that man's air" the audience invariably manifested its appreciation of the absurdity of such an ownership. The idea of owning air was ridiculous ; the idea of owning land was not. Yet who can explain the difference, except as a matter of custom? To the same effect was the question of the Rev. F. L. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at Galveston, Texas, Mr. Hig- gins fell into a discussion with his friend as to the right of government to make land private property. The friend argued that no matter what the abstract right might be, the government had made private property of land, and people had bought and sold upon the strength of the government title, and therefore land titles were morally absolute. "Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the gov- ernment should vest in a corporation title to the Gulf of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or sail there, or do an3rthing in or upon the waters of the Gulf without permission from the corporation. Would that be right ?" "No," answered the friend. "Well, suppose the corpora- tion should then parcel out the Gulf to different parties until some of the people came to own the whole Gulf to the exclusion of everybody else, born or unborn. Could any such title be acquired by these purchasers, or their descendants or assignees, as that the rest of the people if they got the power would not have a moral right to abrogate it?" "Certainly not," said the friend. "Could private titles to the Gulf possibly become absolute in mor- als?" "No." "Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what difference it would make if all the water were taken off the Gulf and only the bare land left?" lis. The late Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New York, author of the famous magazine article on "Who 172 TAXATION OF; LAND VALUES Owns the United States?" and of the work on public revenues entitled Natural Taxation, estimated that sixty-five per cent, of the present annual value of the land in the United States would pay all the present ex- penses of American government — Federal, State, county and municipal. TfMr. Shearman's estimate did not mean that he purposed a tax upon annual values. In harmony with Henry George's views he advocated the taxation of capital values. The effect would be the same; for cap- ital value is the capitalization in the market of annual value, and a tax estimated upon capital values would be paid out of or constitute a deduction from annual val- ues. If, for illustration, a lot of land were yielding, or with proper use would yield, $100 in annual ground rent, it would command a capital value of about $2,000 (disturbing influences ignored for simplicity of calcula- tion) in a land market where commercial interest was five per cent. To tax this capital value two per cent, would reduce the net annual ground rent from $100 to $60, for the annual tax would be $40 and would have to be paid out of the income. This would reduce the capital value from $2,000 ("twenty years' purchase" of a net annual ground rent of $100) to $1,200 ("twenty years' purchase" of a net annual ground rent of $60) ; and inasmuch as the next year's tax at two per cent, on the $1,200 of capital value would not yield $40 to the public treasury, but only $24, it has been objected that a baffling problem arises. This, however, is a mis- take. Although the old rate would not on the lower capital value raise the old revenue, a higher rate would, and without making any difference to the taxpayer. For instance : A tax of 3 1/3 per cent, on the lower capitaliza- tion of $1,200 in the above illustration would yield $40 to the public and leave $60 to the taxpayer; and that rate would produce the same result every year so long as no alteration in the annual ground rent value occurred and commercial interest remained at five per cent. It has been estimated that a tax of 45 per cent, on capital value would take for public use continually enough of TAXATION of: LAND VALUES 173 annual ground rent value to leave to the taxpayer margin sufficient only to pay fairly for land management, and to leave no sufficient basis for injurious speculation in land. Take, for illustration, the previous example of a lot of land with an annual ground rent of $100. If it were certain that this income must bear a tax calcu- lated at 45 per cent, upon its capital value in a market where commercial interest rules at five per cent., the selling value would be about $200; for that value, after payment of 45 per cent, taxes calculated upon it, thus taking $90 out of the $100, would leave $10, which would be the income that investors would probably expect for assuming the risks and managing the affairs of such an investment. None of these figures are offered as pre- cise, except for purposes of simple illustrative calcula- tion, but they are not far from what may be reasonably regarded as approximate. l[Mr. Alex. W. Johnston, an Australian writer on economics (author of Law and Liberty, published by Angus and Robertson, Sydney, New South Wales), objects to any taxation upon the capital value of land. He argues that, whereas "the state has a perfect moral right to appropriate rent for revenue" it has no "moral right to impose a tax on the capital value of land because that is an immoral method," being "artificial, arbitrary and variable" and not based upon principle — "only a partial and half-hearted appli- cation of a principle which seeks justice for the people." The answer is that land is now recognized as private property, that this makes annual ground rents private incomes, that these are on sale in the market at capi- talized values, and that wherever such conditions obtain the wisest way of beginning to get those incomes for public use is by taxing capital values. This would not take all that belongs to the public, but the rest would be, as Henry George wrote, only a matter of "keeping on." And shall we refuse to take less of what belongs to us, until we can take all ? Mr. Johnston quotes Abra- ham Lincoln as saying that "nothing is settled until it is settled right." Sound doctrine that ; but Mr. Johnston 174 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES makes strange use of it when he says that Lincoln "might have added : What is less than right is all wrong." This ignores the law of progress, which may he rendered as "one blessed thing after another" — ^blessed if in the right direction and the reverse if in the wrong direction. Be- fore anything now wrong can be settled right, we must begin to settle it right. In countries where the land mar- j ket is a ground-rent market, ground rent might be appro- \ priated for public use directly, either by taxation or upon ' some plan of public ownership and leasing of land. But in countries where the land market is a capital-value market, the United States or Canada for instance, any attempt to begin getting ground rent otherwise than by\ taxing capital values would be like trying to split logsl with the thick end of the wedge. ^Whether the sin- ' gle tax ever should or would pass from a tax estimated on capital values to one estimated on annual ground rents, is a question for the future. The time to deter- mine this will be when the people have so clearly rec- ognized the common right to land as to be in a frame of mind to deal intelligently with the best method of securing it. 1[The "Single Tax Limited" has made con- siderable practical progress since the text of this book was originally written, twenty-one years ago. A large number of municipalities in New Zealand get all local revenues from land value taxation, and this is true also of a large number in Australia. In Canada, too, the method is in full local operation in several cities, notably Vancouver. England has made advances toward it, and so has Germany, while Norway and Denmark are giv- ing it serious consideration, as are some of the States of the American Union. The fullest account of these advances of which I know in book form may be found in the late Max Hirsch's Land-Value Taxation in Prac- tice, an Australian book, obtainable at "The Single Tax" office, Melbourne, Victoria. Owing to the author's un- timely death the record ends before the greatest advances were made. Full accounts are to be found in the files of The Public, a weekly review, published at Chicago, TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 175 Illinois, U. S. A., since April 9, 1898. In producing prosperous conditions the "Single Tax Limited" wher- ever introduced has been manifest. But fears have arisen that reaction may set in because the land value taxes are not high enough to keep pace with increasing land values. Any such reaction would be in harmony with the doctrines of Progress and Poverty. These teach that improvements in government tend to increase land values; and inasmuch as land value taxation, in lieu of taxes on industry, is an improvement in govern- ment — an improvement of the highest order according to Progress and Poverty — it must be expected that land value taxation will tend to increase land values. If, then, the land value tax is not increased commen- surately, speculation in land will tend to revive. All this was anticipated by Henry George when he wrote as follows in chapter ii of book viii of Progress and Poverty: ". . . it will not be enough merely to place all taxes upon the value of land. It will be nec- essary, where rent exceeds the present governmental rev- enues, comraensurately to increase the amount demanded in taxation, and to continue this increase as society pro- gresses and rent advances. But this is so natural and easy a matter, that it may be considered as involved, or at least understood, in the proposition to put all taxes on the value of land. That is the first step, upon which the practical struggle must be made. When the hare is once caught and killed, cooking him will follow as a matter of course. When the common right to land is so far appreciated that all taxes are abolished save those which fall upon rent, there is no danger of much more than is necessary to induce them to collect the public revenues, being left to individual landholders." IfThe objection that upon the first applications of the "Single Tax Lim- ited," land owners begin after a while to reap their old advantages, is no argument against the "Single Tax Un- limited." The former is only in the way of a beginning. Such criticisms of it are like those of the little boy who said to his father as he saw him going with a shovel 176 TAXATION OF. LAND VALUES toward the barn: "Pa, what are you going to do?" "Going a-fishing," said the father. "May I go with you ?" "Yes, I guess so." And the little chap trudged along, asking questions as he went. "Pa, can you catch fish with a shovel?" "Yes," said his father. "Pa, what kind of fish can you catch with a shovel?" "Pa, how do you catch fish with a shovel ?" and so on and on until they fetched up at the back of the barn, where the father began to dig. Thereupon the questioning was renewed. "Why, pa, you don't catch fish here, do you?" "We begin to, my son," was the answer. "But, pa, I thought you caught fish in the creek." "We do, but we ain't at the creek yet." There was silence until the boy saw his father putting angle worms into a tin cup. He was thoughtful a moment, childishly thoughtful, and then he broke out : "Why, pa, them ain't fish, is they ?" f Some helpful investigations into the sufficiency of land value taxation have been made in recent years. Among the publications reporting these are the Blue Books of the British government, reports of the British Land Enquiry Committee, the annual reports of the Tax Department of New York City, and data of taxation in Oregon coun- ties procured under the direction of Wm. S. U'Ren, of Oregon City, Oregon, and W. G. Eggleston, now of San Francisco. The Rhode Island Tax Reform Association of Providence published a pamphlet in 1911, prepared by John Z. White, of Illinois, which gives the names and taxes of every taxpayer of 1910 in Woonsocket, R. I., and shows how much each would have paid under the "Single Tax Limited." Another us'eful publication in this connection is Benjamin C. Marsh's Taxation of Land Values in American Cities, the Next Step in Exterminating Poverty," which is pub- lished by the author (320 Broadway, New York City) ; and a convenient hand book for speakers and writers as well as students is The A. B. C. of the Land Ques- tion, prepared by James Dundas White, LL. D., M. P., and published by the Land Values organization of Lon- don (20 Tothill St. and 376 Strand). TAXATION of: land VALUES 177 116. This idea of the concealed picture was graphic- ally illustrated with a story by James G. Maguire, at that time a judge of the Superior Court of San Fran- cisco and afterward a Member of Congress from Cali- fornia, in a speech at the Academy of Music, New York City, in 1887. In substance he said : "I was one day walking along Kearney street, San Francisco, when I noticed a crowd around the show win- dow of a store, looking at something inside. I took a glance myself, and saw only a very poor picture of a very uninteresting landscape. But as I was turning away my eye caught the words underneath the picture, 'Do you see the cat?' I looked again and more closely, but saw no cat in the picture. Then I spoke to the crowd : " 'Gentlemen,' I said, 'I see no cat in that picture. Is there a cat there ?' "Some one in the crowd replied : " 'Naw, there ain't no cat there. Here's a crank who says he sees the cat, but nobody else can see it.' "Then the crank spoke up: " 'I tell you there is a cat there, too. It's all cat. What you fellows take for a landscape is just nothing more than the outlines of a cat. And you needn't call a man a crank either, because he can see more with his eyes than you can.' "Well," the Judge continued, "I looked very closely at the picture and then I said to the man they called a crank : " 'Really, sir, I can not make out a cat. I can see noth- ing but a poor picture of a landscape.' "'Why, Judge,' he exclaimed, 'just look at that bird in the air. That's the cat's ear.' "I looked, but was obliged to say : " 'I am sorry to be so stupid, but I can't make a cat's ear of that bird. It is a poor bird, but not a cat's ear.' " 'Well, then,' the crank urged, 'look at that twig twirled around in a circle. That's the cat's eye.' "But I couldn't make an eye of it. " 'Oh, then,' said the crank, a little impatiently, 'look 178 TAXATION OF LAND VALUES at those sprouts at the foot of the tree, and the grass. They make the cat's claws.' "After a rather deHberate examination, I reported that they did look a little like a claw, but I couldn't con- nect them with a cat. "Once more the crank came back at me. 'Don't you see that limb off there? and that other limb under it? and that white space between? Well, that white space is the cat's tail.' "I looked again and was just on the point of replying that there was no cat there so far as I could see, when suddenly the whole cat burst upon me. There it was sure enough, Just as the crank had said; and the only reason that the rest of us couldn't see it was that we hadn't got the right point of view. But now that I saw it I could see nothing else in the picture. The landscape had disappeared and a cat had taken its place. And do you know, I was never afterward able, upon looking at that picture, to see anything in it but the cat." From this story as told by Judge Maguire has come the slang of the Singletax agitation. To "see the cat" is to understand the Singletax. PART THREE, CHAPTER V 117. Progress and Poverty, book v, ch. ii, page 293. 118. "Our primary social adjustment is a denial of justice. In allowing one man to own the land on which and from which other men must live, we have made them his bondsmen in a degree which increases as ma- terial progress goes on. This is the subtile alchemy that in ways they do not realize is extracting from the masses in every civilized country the fruits of their weary toil; that is instituting a harder and more hopeless sla- very in place of that which has been destroyed; that is bringing political despotism out of political freedom, and must soon transmute democratic institutions into anarchy. It is this that turns the blessings of material progress TAXATION OF LAND VALUES 179 into a curse. It is this that crowds human beings into noisome cellars and squalid tenement houses; that fills prisons and brothels ; that goads men with want and con- sumes them with greed; that robs women of the grace and beauty of perfect womanhood ; that takes from little children the joy and innocence of life's morning. Civ- ilization so based can not continue. The eternal laws of the universe forbid it. Ruins of dead empires testify, and the witness that is in every soul answers, that it can not be. It is something grander than Benevolence, something more august than Charity — it is Justice her- self that demands of us to right this wrong. Justice that will not be denied ; that can not be put off — ^Justice that with the scales carries the sword." — Progress and Pov- erty, hook X, ch. V. ilillilil