'yyi^ ft-i. Hr. IK^ -*rr 54 ■^' •^ \ ■ ••♦ ''^li. >lBi??s*F^.^ f DUKE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY Treasure %oom J CRITICAL DISSERTATION OX THE NATURE. MEASURES, AND CAUSES OK VALUE; CHIEFLY IN UEFERENCE TO THE WRITINGS OP MR. RI^ARDO AND HIS FOLLOWERS. BY THE AUTHOR OF ESSAYS ON THE FOHiVIATION AND PUBLICATION OF OPINIONS, LONDON: PRINTED FOR R. HUNTER, ST. PAUL'S CHURCHYARD. MDCCCXXV. LONDON : PRINTED BY CHARLES WOOD, Poppiu'g Court, Fleet Street. 330.1 PREFACE, The subject of the following Dissertation is generally allowed to be one, both of high im- portance and of great difficulty. " From no source," says Mr. Ricardo, '' do so many errors, and so much difference of opinion in the science of political economy proceed, as from the vao^ue ideas which are attached to the word value.*' And the same eminent writer, in the preface to the third edition of the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, emphatically terms it a difficult subject. '' In this edition," says he, " I have endeavoured to explain more fully than in the last, my opinion .on the difficult subject of Value." a 2 40631?^ IV PREFACE. It is remarked by another author, that *' he who is fully master of the subject of Value is already a good political economist." " Even for its own sake," he adds, " the subject is a matter of curious speculation : but in relation to Political Economy it is all in all : for most of the errors (and, what is much worse than errors, most of the perplexity) prevailing in this science take their rise from this source*." Although much has been written and many efforts have been made to overcome the ob- stacles, which present themselves in this part of economical science, it may be affirmed with little risk of contradiction, that the success has not been in proportion to the labour be- stowed. There appears to have been too little circumspection at the outset. The ground- work of the subject has not been examined * The Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy, in the London Magazine for April, 1824, pages 341 and 342. PREFACE. V with that minuteness and closeness of attention which are due to its importance. Writers on political economy have generally contented themselves with a short definition of the term value, and a distinction of the property de- noted by it into several kinds, and have then proceeded to employ the word with various degrees of laxity. Not one of them has brought into distinct view and discussion the nature of the idea represented by this term, or the inferences which a full perception of its meaning immediately suggests ; and the neg- lect of this preliminary labour has created dif- ferences of opinion and perplexities of thought, which otherwise could never have existed. There has been still more laxity, both of thought and expression, regarding the mea- surement of value. The vague manner in which the word measure, necessarily of fre- quent occurrence in the pages of the political VI PREFACE. economist, is constantly employed, would sur- prise even the metaphysician, who is well aware of the extensive prevalence and unbounded in- fluence of the chameleon-like properties of language. No writer (as far as the author of the following pages is acquainted with works on economical science) has ever taken the trouble to analyse the meaning involved in the phrase. To measure value is an expression apparently so simple, so precise, so free from obscurity, that it seems superfluous to bestow a single inquiry on its import. The consequence has been what it generally proves on such occasions : the term has been used without any clear per- ception of a definite sense ; several ideas have been unconsciously and indiscriminately interchanged, and analogies, which had merely an imaginary existence, have been assumed as incontrovertible premises or universally con- ceded postulates^ PREFACE. VU The causes of value have been also too neg- ligently passed over. Little inquiry has been made into the natvire of these causes, or their mode of operation, and to this slightness of examination may be attributed several import- ant errors, manifested in attempts at undue generalization, in perversions of language, and in the rejection of circumstances which have a real and permanent eflfect. A singular confusion has also prevailed with regard to the ideas of measuring and causing value, and in the language employed to express them. The perpetual shifting from one notion to the other, the use of common terms for both ideas, and the consequent ambiguity, vacilla- tion, and perplexity, exhibit a remarkable picture of the difficulty of thinking with close- ness, as well as of the defects of language as an instrument of reasoning. The confusion and obscurity, which mark the VIU PREFACE. works of some of the most celebrated writers on ^ese momentous topics, are sufficient to make the student abandon his inquiries on the very- threshold of the science. Words used without determinate ideas, terms introduced without proper explanations, definitions abandoned al- most as soon as enunciated, principles assumed without first being examined, verbal instead of real simplifications — such are the obstacles which everywhere meet him. That defects of this kind disfigure the science of political economy, no one acquainted with the most recent works on the subject will pro- bably deny, although a difference of opinion may exist regarding the extent to which they prevail. It would be presumptuous in the author of the following treatise to suppose, that he had completely removed them from that part of the science which he has attempted to examine. He trusts, nevertheless, that he has PREFACE. IX done something, if not towards directly effecting that object, at least towards opening the way for subsequent endeavours. If he has not suc- ceeded in putting all his propositions in a clear light, and finally settling the various contro- verted questions which he brings under review^ yet he may hope that he has introduced them in such a manner as will excite in others the interest and attention requisite for their ulti- mate determination. Free, on his own part, from particular attachment to any of the po- sitions which he has maintained, although im- pressed with that clear conviction of their soundness, without which it would be absurd to intrude them on public notice ; and sensible of the thousand ways in which error imposes itself on the understanding in the character of truth, he will be glad of an opportunity of re- considering his opinions, under the guidance of a mind which has reached a his/her point of PREFACE. view than his own ; nor will it greatly surprise him to discover, that he has fallen into errors and misconceptions as deep and as radical as any of those which he has found or fancied in the speculations of others. From the defects here imputed to the science, it is evident that in any work, which professes to examine and remove them, the points discussed must be questions as to the use of terms, the distinction of ideas, the lo- gical dependence of arguments, rather than questions of fact or evidence, and that its cha- racter will be essentiallv critical, and even polemic. In endeavouring to define the nature of ideas, to fix the meaning of terms, to in- vestigate first principles, and to determine the real objects and results of inquiry, it was im- possible, it would have been w^orse than use- less, not to advert to the works of preceding- writers, although at the expense perhaps of PREFACE. XI that neatness and elegance of deduction, of which the subject is susceptible ; and certainly at the risk of incurring, if not hostility, at least the utmost severity of examination from the talents and acumen, which such a course necessarily puts on the defensive. In the pre- sent state of political economy, however, a critical reference to the doctrines of preceding and contemporary economists cannot be avoided, and ought not to be avoided if it could. A mere direct expository treatise would be of far inferior utility. However true a doctrine may be, it is of little service until its relation to other doctrines, and its connection with knowledge already extant, has been shown. Embarrassed as the science is with difficulties on which opinion is divided, it is of the utmost importance for its future progress, not only to explain and establish correct principles, but to expose tlie de- Xll PREFACK. lusion which has formerly misled, to trace the process of error, to mark the particular point where inquiry departed from the right path, or where the unperceived fallacy, which has vitiated a train of reasoning, first insinuated itself into the argument. The science cannot yet be exhibited as a regular and perfect structure. The rubbish must be removed, the ground cleared, the scaffolding taken down, and all unnecessary and cumbrous appendages mast be discarded, before the building can rise upon the eye in that simple beauty in which it is destined hereafter to appear. The writer, on whose doctrines the following treatise principally animadverts, is generally regarded as the ablest economist of his day. It has been unfortunate, perhaps, for Mr. Ri- cardo's ultimate reputation, and certaiidy for the science which he cultivated, that his ad- mirers have extolled him beyond the sobriety PREFACE. Xlll of truth. Strong powers of mind he un- questionably possessed ; otherwise, he could neither have produced the works which have associated his name with the political measures of the age, nor could he have inspired those sentiments of admiration and deference, which have been so warmly manifested by men, them- selves of no common talents. It is probable, however, that the excess of their admiration has blinded them to his defects ; that they have been too much occupied with the excellence of his speculations to note the errors by which they are disfigured. It would be diflicult, on any other supposition, to account for the ex- travagant praises which have been heaped on his Principles of Political Economy and Tax- ation. One of our most distinguished living economists designates it as a " work rivalling the * Wealth of Nations' in importance, and excelling it in profoundness and originality*." * A Disc, on Pol. Econ.,byJ. R. M*Culloch, Esq.,|).65. XIV PREFACE. " The powers of mind," says the same writer, '' displayed in these investigations — the dex- terity with which the most abstruse and diffi- cult questions are unravelled — the unerring sa- gacity with which the operation of general and fixed principles is investigated — the skill with which they are separated and disentangled from such as are of a secondary and accidental nature — and the penetration with which their remotest consequences are perceived and esti- mated — have never been surpassed ; and will for ever secure the name of Ricardo a high and conspicuous place in the list of those, who have done most to unfold the complex mecha- nism of society, and to carry this science to perfection." Conceding that Mr. Ricardo has displayed considerable originality and power of intellect, we may yet be permitted to doubt, whether this splendid eulogium is not far beyond his real de- serts. It is not easy to conceive by what process PREFACE. XV a superiority above Adam Smith, as a profound and original thinker, can be inferred from their respective works. To raise the science from the condition in which it was found by the lat- ter, to that state of dignity and importance in which it appeared in the Wealth of Nations, seems to an ordinary view to have required a far more comprehensive mind, and greater powers of skilful disquisition, than to discover and to follow out to their consequences the ori- ginal truths, few or many, which distinguish the pages of the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. The praise, too, of dexterity in unra- velling difficult questions is surely misapplied. The obscurity which is almost universally felt, and felt even by readers accustomed to close- ness of reasoning, and not sparing of vigorous attention, in many of Mr. Ricardo's discussions, incontestably proves, even on the supposition of their perfect accuracy, a want of skill in the ma- XVI PREFACE. nagement of his materials, a defect either in the disposition of his ideas or the employment of his terms. It is the triumph of dexterity in dissertation to present every proposition in such due order and such perspicuous language, as to lead the reader to imagine, that he should himself have expressed the meaning nearly in the same manner and in the same words. There is scarcely a single train of thought in the Wealth of Nations, which a mere tyro would feel it difficult to follow, and of which the aim and connection with the subject would not be perfectly intelligible : but there are many ob- servations in the writings of Mr. Ricardo, which it requires the effort of a vigorous mind to connect with the other propositions amongst which they stand. His ideas are often imperfectly developed, and his reasoning ap- pears elliptical and disjointed ; defects, in- deed, which have possibly elevated rather PREFACE. XVll than lowered his standing in general estima- tion. The " omne ignotum pro magnifico' is not without its exemplifications in the field of science, and the reputation of an author for pro- fundity is sometimes enhanced by an intermixture of the unintelligible, many readers tacitly as- cribing unusual sagacity to one, who is able to understand what is incomprehensible to them- selves ; while a lucid arrangement of ideas, a manifest dependence of arguments, and a perspi- cuity of language, such as mark a complete mas- tery of the subject, appear too easy and natural to infuse the slightest suspicion of the depth and vigour of intellect from which they proceed, and of which they are the surest indications. The occasional obscurity, which clouds Mr. Ri- cardo's writings, has sometimes been attributed to his style, and sometimes to his ambition of paradox. But if by style we are to under- b XViif PREFACE. stand the selection of words, and the mode of combininof them into sentences, the former solu- tion is incorrect, for his language is uncom- monly precise and perspicuous, and the con- struction of his periods is simple and compact. The latter explication is, if possible, still more unfounded, there being an evident simplicity of aim and steady pursuit after truth in his writ- ings, such as are natural to a mind of any ori- ginality, and which exclude the idea that he indulged the contemptible ambition of per- plexing his readers. The defect had a deeper source, and is to be traced, as the following pages will show, to an original perplexity and confusion in some fundamental ideas, from which he was never able to extricate himself. Although Mr. Ricardo possessed remarkable lo- gical powers, he seems to have been less gifted with analytical subtilty ; and hence his writings furnish an instance of what the observer of the PREFACE. XIX human mind must have frequently seen exem- plified, that the strongest powers of reasoning- are an insufficient security against gross error, if unaccompanied by that incessant analysis of terms and propositions, and that intense con- sciousness of intellectual operations, which are the properties of a metaphysical genius. Of this cast of intellect, the most striking instance perhaps which our own times af- ford is to be found in the writings of the late Professor of Moral Philosophy in the univer- sity of Edinburgh, Dr. Thomas Brown; a. man who possessed, in an almost unrivalled deo-ree, the capacity of looking into the mechanism of his own mind, and seeing the impalpable phe- nomena of thought and feeling, as well as the power of flinging to a distance the embarrassing influence of words, and fixing his eye with keen penetration on the things which they re- presented, stripped of the covering of languao-e, XX PREFACE. and freed from every tinge of feeling and asso- ciation *. To judge from his writings, Mr. Ricardo possessed little of this faculty ; little conscious- ness of the nature of the operations in which he excelled, and little familiarity with the ana- lysis of terms. His was a sort of natural vigour of reasoning, exerting itself without the ad- vantages of discipline, without much acquaint- * The author feels a pleasure in paying this passings tribute to the talents of a philosopher, who has taken a giant-stride in the science to which he devoted him- self, and who will be hereafter considered as one of the most remarkable men of a period prolific in great names. The reputation of writings like his, far in advance of the age in which they appear, making no appeals to the senses, and having no obvious connection with the immediate and palpable affairs of life, is necessarily of slow growth, but it will flourish when hundreds of names, which fill more of the public ear, have passed to that oblivion which certainly awaits them. PREPACK. XXI ance with the instruments employed, or much thought regarding the methods of applying them : and although his logical powers kept him in general to the employment of a term in one uniform sense when he clearly discerned it, yet, in cases where he happened unconsciously to change the meaning, or to be unaware of an ambiguity, his inaptness at analysis precluded all chance of his subsequently correcting any deviation, and the very strictness of his deduc- tions only led him further into error. Startinsf from a given proposition, he would reason from it with admirable closeness, but he seems never to have been sent back, by the strangeness of the results at which he arrived, to a reconsideration of the principle from which he set out, nor to have been roused to a suspicion of some lurk- ing ambiguity in his terms. Hence it might have been predicted, that he would commit oversights in his premises and assumptions, for XXll PREFACE. which no subsequent severity of logic could compensate. Perhaps these remarks will serve to explain how it is, that Mr. Ricardo has been eulogized for his inexorable consistency in the use of words, and particularly for his sternly insisting on the true sense of the word value, and on using it only in one sense*. If the author of the following pages has been at all successful, in establishing the justness of the strictures which he has hazarded, this praise must be al- lowed to be unfounded ; for it will be seen, that in the case of the word value he has almost perpe- tually forsaken his own definition : yet an incon- sistency of this sort is by no means incompatible with a general strictness in the employment of terms. If the preceding observations are cor- rect, a writer may be rigorously consistent in *'\ Templars' Dialogues, Introduction. PREFACE. XXlll the use of his terms throuo^h a Ion gr train of rea- soning, while the whole of his conclusions may be vitiated by an unperceived transition from one meaning to another in the original adjust- ment of his premises, or in the first steps of his argument. Besides Mr. Ricardo,the only writerson whom there are any strictures worthy of notice in the following work, are Mr. Malthus, Mr. Mill, and the author of the Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy, published in the London Magazine ; of whom the two latter may be considered as having adopted the doctrines of Mr. Ricardo with little variation. Mr. Malthus and Mr. Mill are too well known to the students of political economy, to render it necessary to say any thing in this place as to their general merits, and it can ex- cite no surprise that the writings of either should be subjects of examination in a treatise XXIV PREFACE. of this nature. With the Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy, probably fewer are ac- quainted, from the form in which they came be- fore the public ; and on this account, as well as from their state of incompleteness, they would not have occupied so many of the ensuing pages, had not the writer of the present work regarded them as an exposition of several of Mr. Ri- cardo's principles, peculiarly adapted to try their validity. Adopting Mr. Ricardo's doctrines, the author of the Dialogues traces them fearlessly to their legitimate consequences, with a directness of logical deduction which nothing diverts ; with great copiousness and felicity of illustration, great dexterity in putting forward the different parts of his theme, and an occasional humour, which even on a subject of this kind is irresis- tible. It must be obvious that a work of this character, pressing intrepidly forward from the PREFACE. XXV premises to the conclusion, and flinching from no consequences at which it arrives, forms a sort of exyerimentum cruclsy by which the truth or falsity of the principles maintained will be ren- dered manifest, and is the very kind of exposi- tion which an examiner of their correctness would desire. It was in fact the clear, able, and uncompro- mising manner in which the author of the Dia- logues explained the principles of Mr. Ricardo, together with the startling and (the present writer must be permitted to say) the extrava- gant consequences to which he pushed them, that first suggested the following treatise, the author of which takes this opportunity of ex- pressing his regret (a regret shared by many others), that discussions so valuable for either confirmingor disproving the doctrines which they enforced, should not have been conducted to their proper and their promised termination. c CONTENTS. Page CHAPTER 1. On the Nature of Value 1 CHAPTER II. On Real and Nominal Value 3/ CHAPTER III. On the Value of Labour 4t> CHAPTER IV. On Profits 62 CHAPTER V. On comparing Commodities at different Periods, 'l CHAPTER VI. On Measures of Value SeeNoteC. CHAPTER V. ON COMPARING COMMODITIES AT DIF- FERENT PERIODS. Perhaps no part of their investigations has perplexed political economists more than their attempts to compare the value of the same object at different periods of time. It is a direct inference from the explanation of value in the preceding chapters, as de- noting a relation between two commodities, a relation incapable of existing when there is only one commodity, that it cannot exist be- tween a commodity at one period and the same commodity at another period. We cannot ascertain the relation of cloth at one time to cloth at another, as we can ascertain the re- lation of cloth to corn in the present day. All 72 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES that we can do is to compare the relation in which cloth stood at each period to some other commodity. When we say, that an article in a former age was of a certain value, we mean, that it exchanged for a certain quantity of some other commodity. But this is an in- applicable expression in speaking of only one commodity at two diiFerent periods. We can- not say, that a pair of stockings in James the First's reign would exchange for six pair in our own day ; and we therefore cannot say, that a pair in James the First's reign was equal in value to six pair now, without reference to some other article. Value is a relation between contemporary commodities, because such only admit of being exchanged for each other ; and if we compare the value of a con^odity at one time with its value at another, it is only a comparison of the relation in which it stood at these different times to some other commodity. It is not a comparison of some intrinsic, independent qua- lity at one period, with the same quality at AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 73 another period ; but a comparison of ratios, or a comparison of the relative quantities in which commodities exchanged for each other at two different epochs. If a commodity of in the year 100 was worth 2 b, and in 1800 was worth 4 B, we should say that a had doubled its value to b. But this, which is the only kind of comparison we can institute, would not give us any relation between a in 100 and a in 1800 ; it would be simply a comparison of the relation between a and b in each of those years. It is impossible for a direct relation of value to exist between a in 100 and a in 1800, just as it is impossible for the relation of distance to exist between the sun at the former period and the sun at the latter. This perhaps will be still more apparent if we make use of the defi- nition of value instead of the term. It will at once be seen how absurd it would be to talk of the power of a in the year 100, to command in exchange the same commodity in 1800. It may, perhaps, be alleged, that I am here fio^hting with a mere shadow of my own crea- 74 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES tion; for that nobody ever imagined the possi- bility of comparing the value of any commo- dity at one period with its value at another, without reference to some other object, the bare notion of such a comparison being absurd, and scarcely susceptible of being stated in intelli- gible language ; and further, that when the value of a commodity in one year is compared with its value in another, the very terms neces- sarily imply a reference to other articles, and are always so considered. A slight inspection, however, of our princi- pal writers will prove, that if I am fighting with a shadow, which I by no means deny, it is not one of my own creation. When Mr. Ricardo tells us, that a commodity always produced by the same labour is of invariable value, he im- plicitly maintains all I have been attempting to disprove. By the epithet invariable he clearly means, that its value at one time will be pre- cisely the same as its value at another, not in relation to other commodities, for he supposes all other commodities to vary, but in relation to AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 75 itself. He distinctly states, that if equal quan- tities of gold could always be obtained by equal quantities of labour, the value of gold " would be invariable, and it would be emi- nently well calculated to measure the varying value of all other things,'' whence it follows, that this invariableness must be intended to be affirmed of the value of gold compared with itself, and not of any relation between gold and some other commodity. The same remarks apply to all attempts to find out something of invariable value. Adam Smith and Mr. Malthus, in considering labour alone as never varying in its own value, assert by implication, that labour at one period may be compared in value with labour at another period, without reference to any other thing whatever*. I fully concede that such a notion * For further instances see Wealth of Nations, Book i, Chap. V, and Mr. Malthus's Pamphlet on the Measure of Value, p. 24 and 25. When we come to treat on the mea- surement of value, Ave shall find this notion at the bottom of some important errors on that subject. 76 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES involves an absurdity, — that they might have talked with equal propriety of the possibility of comparing the distance of the sun in the year 100 with its distance in 1800, without re- ference to any other body in space — and that language can scarcely be found to express the idea in direct terms, without a palpable contra^ diction : but that such a notion has extensively prevailed no one will doubt, who attentively turns over the pages of the first writers on the subject. The following passage from the Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy, is a conspi- cuous instance of the error in question. " I wish to know," says he, " whether a day's labour at the time of the English Revolution bore the same value as a hundred years after, at the time of the French Revolution, and if not the same value, whether a higher or a lower. For this purpose, if I believe that there is any commodity which is immutable in value, I shall naturally compare a day's labour with that commodity at each period. Some for instance AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 77 have imagined, that corn is of invariable value, and supposing me to adopt so false a notion, I should merely have to inquire what quantity of com a day's labour would exchange for at each period, and I should then have determined the relations of value between labour at the t^vo periods *.'' It scarcely needs pointing out, after the ex- planation I have given, that no relation of value could exist between labour at these two periods : the only point to be ascertained would be, whe- ther the same or a different relation existed at both periods, between corn and labour, and this would be equally well ascertained, without sup- posing the condition of corn being immutable in value. This very supposition implies, either that the fact which it is wished to ascertain is already ascertained, or, that the value of com at one period may be compared with the value of corn at another period, with no re- ference to any other commodity in the world, * Dialogue v, London Mas^azine for May, p. 558. 78 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES Many errors appear to have arisen from this inattention to the real nature of a comparison of objects at different periods in regard to their value. Much indistinctness has also proceeded from blending the comparison of contemporary com- modities with that of the same commodity at different times, particularly when writers have been speaking of the comparative quantity, or the comparative value of the labour concerned in the production of commodities. It is not always clear to their readers, nor does it seem to have been clearer to themselves, whether they intended to compare the same commodity, as to the producing labour, at separate periods, or different commodities at the same period. There appears to me to be considerable confu- sion in this respect in Mr. Ricardo's first sec- tion on value ; a confusion which is probably one of the latent causes of the obscurity felt by many to hang over that section, and which, if I mistake not, is perceptible in the very sentence which forms its title. AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 79 '^ The value of a commodity," says he, *' or the quantity of any other commodity for wliich it will exchange, depends on the relative quan- tity of labour which is necessary for its produc- tion, and not on the greater or less compensa- tion which is paid for that labour." In the first part of this sentence he appears to be speaking of contemporary commodities, but in the latter clause he has chanofed his ground : it does not form a proper logical coun- terpart to the former : there is, I think, an im- plied although an unconscious reference to the same commodity at different periods. For if not, if he is speaking in the latter clause also of contemporary commodities, the amount of the proposition would be this : — " The values of two contemporary commo- dities, A and B, are to each other as the quanti- ties of labour necessary to their production, and they are not to each other as the values of the labour employed in their production." But if commodities are to each other as the quantities, they must also be to each other as the yO ox COMPARING COMMODITIES values ofthe producing labour; for the contrary would necessarily imply, that the two commo- dities A and B might be equal in value, although the value of the labour employed in one was greater or less than the value of the labour employed in the other ; or that a and b might be unequal in value, if the labour em- ployed in each was equal in value. But this difference in the value of two commodities, which were produced by labour of equal value, would be inconsistent with the acknowledged equality of profits, which Mr. Ricardo main- tains in common with other writers '^. It is probable, therefore, that this was not Mr. Ricardo's meaning, but that he uncon- sciously confounded this proposition with an- other, and really intended to say, that the value of A at two different periods, No. 1 and 2, was * In this chapter we are assuming, for the sake of argu- ment, the truth of the doctrine, that commodities are to each other in value, as the quantities of labour respectively employed in their production. It will form a subject of examination hereafter. AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 81 not proportioned to the value of the labour ne- cessary to its production at each period ; that although, for example, the value of the labour were doubled at the latter period, the value of the commodity might not be affected. The proposition expressed more simply is, that the value of a commodity and the value of the la- bour employed in its production, do not bear to each other a constant ratio ; or more simply still, that labour may rise and fall in value with- out affecting the value of the commodity. This is obviously a very diflferent proposition from the other, and depends in fact on the fal- sity of the other, or on the contrary proposition, '' that the values of two contemporary commo- dities a?'e to each other as the values of the labour employed in producing them." For as value must be value in something, let us ask, in relation to what object might the value of a at period No. 2 be, as here asserted, the same as its value at period No. 1, although the value of the producing labour were doubled? In re- G 82 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES lation to other commodities. And why? Be- cause the rise in labour would be the same in all commodities ; but if the values of commo- dities are to each other as the values of the la- bour employed in producing them, and if the labour employed in all commodities rose in equal proportion, there could not possibly be any disturbance of the relations existing be- tween all commodities before the rise, and of course a would be of the same value at period No. 2 as at period No. 1. The only alteration in this instance would be, an alteration in the relation of value between labour and commodities. It would be a sim- ple case of a rise in labour, and (proceeding on the assumption that commodities are determined in value solely by the quantity of labour) the whole amount of the proposition is this, that the values of commodities in relation to each other are not disturbed by an alteration in their values in relation to labour; which is only a particular application of the more general pro- AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 83 position, that when one commodity or thing al- ters its value in relation to other commodities, the mutual relations of these other commodi- ties, cceteris paribus, are not thereby affected *. The reader will notice, that in supposing that while the value of the producing labour was doubled, the commodity remained the same, I have used the expression, " the value of the commodity might not be affected," for this rea- son, that whether it was or was not affected, would depend on the nature of the cause by which the value of the labour was doubled. In the proposition, the values of a and b are to each other as the values of their producing la- bour, the value of labour means aggregate value. Now the aggregate value of the labour necessary for the production of a commodity may be increased in two ways, either by an augmentation of the quantity of the labour at * It may be necessary perhaps to state, that by the qua- lification ccBteris paribus, it is meant to restrict the propo- sition to cases in which the altered commodity either does not enter at all into the composition of other commodities, or enters into them in the same proportion. G 2 84 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES the same rate, or by a rise in the rate, that is in the value of a definite portion of it, while the quantity remains the same. It is only in the latter event (which is the one I have supposed to take place) that the value of the commodity would in general continue the same in relation to other commodities, for the precise reason al- ready assigned, that all commodities would be affected in equal proportions. It would be a positive not a comparative rise in the value of the producing labour of the commodity in ques- tion ; while on the other hand, should the in- crease in the value have arisen from an aug- mentation in the quantity of labour, such in- crease would be probably, although not neces- sarily comparative. As the misconception on the part of Mr. Ricardo here noticed is a fundamental one, I make no apology for presenting the reader with a further attempt to show it. The confu- sion in the proposition will be more apparent by a little alteration in the language. " The value of a commodity a, or the quan- AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 85 tity of any other commodity b, for which it will exchange, depends on the comparative quanti- ties of labour necessary for the production of A and B." So far there is no obscurity, and the position can be construed only in one sense. When Mr. Ricardo, however, adds, " and not on the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour," every one must be sensi- ble of a confusion of ideas. In the former clause he is telling us on what circumstance the mutual value of a and b depends, or, in other words, what circumstance determines the quan- tities in which these two commodities are ex- changed for each other ; in the latter clause it was evidently his business, as it was his design, to tell us on what the mutual value of a and b did 7iot depend ; or, in other words, what cir- cumstance did 7iot determine the quantities in which these commodities are exchanged for each other. Now the only circumstance as- signed is obviously *' the compensation paid for the labour," and the proposition really asserted in this latter clause is, that the mutual value 86 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES of A and B does not depend on the compensa- tion paid for the producing labour of a being equal to, or greater, or less than the compensa- tion paid for the producing labour of b : so that this compensation might be equal in the two cases, while the quantities in which a and b were exchanged for each other were unequal. As far, however, as any thing can be gathered from the confusion of thought and language in Mr. Ricardo's opening section, this is not what he intended to assert. In the first clause he was comparing a and b, and asserting the cause which determined the relation between them ; but dropping b by the way, in this latter clause he is speaking of a alone. By quan- tity of labour in the first clause, he meant quantity of labour necessary to produce a, com- pared with the quantity of labour necessary to produce b ; but by compensation of labour in the latter clause, he does not intend the com- pensation of labour in a compared to the com- pensation of labour in b, but the compensation paid for the labour required to produce a at AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 87 one time, compared with the compensation paid for the producing labour of a at another time. Hence Mr. Ricardo's sentence is a completely false antithesis. The author of the Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy seems to have followed Mr. Ricardo in confounding the two distinct propo- sitions above pointed out. This appears the more extraordinary, since he has laid down the first proposition (which I have supposed Mr. Ricardo did not clearly perceive to be involved in the terms employed) in such bold and un- measured language, as almost to preclude the possibility of its being mistaken either by him- self or his readers for any other. After telling us, that ^^ Mr. Ricardo's doc- trine is, that A and b are to each other in value as the quantity of labour is which produces A to the quantity which produces b," he says, " I assert in the most peremptory manner, that he who says, ' the value of a is to the value of b, as the quantity of labour producing a is to the quantity of labour producing b,' does of 88 ON COMPARING COMMODITIES necessity deny by implication, that the rela- tions of value between a and b are governed by the value of the labour which severally pro- duces them." Again, " so far are the two for- mul(E from presenting merely two different ex- pressions of the same law, that the very best way of expressing negatively Mr. Ricardo s law {viz. A is to B in value as the quantities of the producing labour) would be to say, a is not to B in value as the values of the producing la- bour =^." Let us examine the reasoning employed to support this extraordinary assertion. It is too long to be introduced here, but it amounts to this, that when the producing labour is in- creased in quantity, the commodity produced is increased in value ; but when the producing labour is increased in value, the value of the commodity produced remains unaltered; and therefore the values of commodities are not to each other as the values of the producing la- * London Magazine for April, p. 348. AT DIFFERENT PERIODS. 89 bour. For instance, if a and b were each pro- duced by six days' labour, they would be equal in value ; but if a should from some cause or other require 12 days' labour, then the value of a would be to the value of b as 12 to 6. But suppose that a in 1810 required six days' la- bour at 4^., making 24,!?., and in 1811, 6 days at 6. 104 ON MEASURES respective ratios to it: but the invariable rela- tion of value between a and b can tell me no- thing of the mutual value of c and d ; or, to vary the language, the power which a has to command b, can tell me nothing of that which c has to command d. I do not in any sense measure the relation of value between two commodities, by that existing between two other commodities. Invariable value, there- fore, can be of no service. The only meaning to be attached to the phrase measuring value, the only operation implied in it, is, as we have seen, that comparison of the values of two ob- jects which we are enabled to make by their se- parate relations to a third, or, in other words, by having these values expressed in a common term or denomination. But the capability of expressing the values of commodities has no- thing to do with the constancy of their values, either to each other or to the medium em- ployed; neither has the capability of com- paring these expressions of value any thing to do with it. Whether a is worth 4 b or 6 b, and whether c is worth 8 b or 12 b, are cir- OF VALUE. 105 carastances which make no difference in the power of expressing the value of a and c in b, and certainly no difference in the power of comparing the value of a and c when ex- pressed. This supposition, of the necessity of inva- riable value in any commodity employed as a measure, proceeds, as I have already remarked, on a false analogy. Because a measure of space must be invariable in its length, a mea- sure of value, it has been argued, must be in- variable in its value *. To expose the fallacy of this inference, let us examine in the first place, what are the character and circumstances of that invariableness which is requisite for a measure of length. All that is required ap- *"Asa measure of quantity," says Adam Smith, " such as the natural foot, fathom, or handful, which is continually varying in its own quantity, can never be an accurate measure of the quantity of other things ; so a commodity, which is itself continually varying in its own vjilue, can never be an accurate measure of the value of other commodities." Wealth of Nations, Book i, Chap. 5. 106 ON MEASURES pears to be this, that when we measure the length of two objects by a third object, the length of the latter, or the instrument employed, must remain the same until it have been ap- plied to both the objects which are to be mea- sured ; or if it vary, it must vary in a known degree. Suppose it is v/ished to ascertain the relation of length between two trees lying apart from each other on the ground. The only requisite for doing this is a staff, or rod, or any other instrument which shall continue of the same length during the process of mea- suring. The process over, although the rod might be instantly altered in length, it would be as good a measure as before of the length of these or any other objects : for suppose the measurement to be repeated after this altera- tion in the instrument, the same relation of length between the two trees would be ob- tained. But if the rod varied in its length in an unknown degree, between applying it to the first tree and the second, whether this interval was a minute or an age, it is obvious that it 01? VALUE. 107 could not serve as a measure of their relative length : there would in that case be no com- mon medium of comparison. It is essential to the discovery of the mutual relation of two ob- jects, which cannot be directly compared, that their respective relations to some third object should be known: but in this case, the ratio which the trees were found to bear would not be to the same object, and therefore nothing- could be told as to the ratio of the trees to each other. It is thus indispensable, that the instrument employed as a measure should re- main unaltered, or be altered in a known de- gree, during its successive applications to the objects measured, in order to give us their re- lations to one common object. By this means we obtain a common term or denomination, in which the lengths of the two trees are ex- pressed. This is, in fact, all that is essential to the end in view : the measurement, that is, the actual application of the physical instru- ment to the object, is the means, and the un- varying length of the instrument, or its ascer- 108 ON MEASURES tainable variation during the process, is the ne- cessary condition for obtaining that common expression of the length of the two objects, which will show their relation to each other. But it is obvious that this relation of length would be equally determined in whatever way the common expression was obtained. Now in the case of value, we obtain this common expression without that physical ope- ration here described. We learn the values of two commodities in relation to the third, not from the application of an instrument, first to one commodity and then to the other, but from intercourse with mankind, or from the inspec- tion of documents in which they are regis- tered. We equally obtain a common expres- sion, but we obtain it by different means. But the invariableness in the length of a measure of space, as above described, is a circumstance be- longing to the means employed to obtain a common expression of length ; and as the means of obtaining a common expression of value are totally different, as in fact the common expres- OF VALUE. 109 sion is necessarily implied in the supposition of using any commodity as a medium of com- parison, there is nothing in the latter case in which invariableness of any kind, or in any sense, can be required. In the one case there is an instrument employed in a physical opera- tion, and it is for the purpose of rendering this instrument capable of performing its function, that invariableness is indispensably necessary : in the other case there is no instrument so em- ployed, and therefore there is no invariableness wanted : in the former case invariableness in the instrument (under the modification which it is needless to repeat) is essential to the attain- ment of the common term ; in the latter, the common term being given, there is nothing in which invariableness can have place, or of which it can be predicated. If the length of the rod varied in an unknown degree between applying it to the two objects, we should have two terms of unknown relation to each other, and there could be no comparison of the ob- jects to be measured ; and if the values of the 110 ON MEASIHES two commodities, which we were desirous of comparing, were expressed in different media, there would be the same impossibility. Hence, if in the case of value We were under the neces- sity of finding a counterpart to invariableness of length in the instrument employed to com- pare the dimensions of two objects, it would be, not invariableness of value in the commodity used as a medium to compare the value of two other commodities, but the condition that the value of these commodities should be given in relation to the same medium, or, in other words, expressed in a common denomination. From all this it appears, that the analogy uni- versally supposed to exist in this matter is al- together imaginary, and the phrase, invariable measure of value, proves to be absolutely des- titute of a basis of meaning. The doctrine which exacts invariableness in a measure of value, furnishes one corollary, which has been so frequently maintained and so generally adopted, that although its refuta- tion is contained in the preceding observations, OF VALUE. Ill it appears to require a separate examination. It is argued, that money or any other commodity is a good measure of the value of commodities, only at the same time, because it is liable to vary; while to perform this function correctly, there should be a commodity the value of which did not vary from one age to another ; as to measure the lengths of objects at different pe- riods, there must be an object of invariable length ^. Let us therefore endeavour to ascer- tain what this really amounts to. With regard to the measurement of space, the intervention of time occasions no alteration in the requisite conditions. The preceding remarks are as ap- plicable to the measurement of the length of objects at different times as to the same time. The qualification necessary to constitute an instrument a good measure of space, is in each * " At the same time and place, money is the exact measure of the real exchangeable value of all commodi- ties. It is so, however, at the same time and place only." Wealth of Nations, Book i, Chap. 5. 112 ox MEASURES case identical, namely, invariableness during- its application to all the objects compared. Whether an hour or a century elapses between the successive applications of the instrument makes no difference. The essential requisite is the same in measuring objects in distant ages, or objects existing at the same time. But in the process called measuring value, there is no application of any instrument, and therefore, as I have already shovrn, there is absolutely nothing to which the quality of in- variableness can be attributed, or of which it can be affirmed. The requisite condition in the process is, that the commodities to be mea- sured should be reduced to a common deno- mination, which may be done at all times with equal facility ; or rather it is ready done to our hands, since it is the prices of commodities which are recorded, or their relations in value to money. If money, therefore, is a good me- dium of comparison at one time, it is at all times. OF VALUE. 113 It may be objected, ^' Yes, good enough for commodities at each time, but not between commodities at different times." This objection, however, proceeds on a fun- damental mistake already exposed in a former chapter, namely, that the relation of value can exist between commodities at different periods, which is in the nature of the case impossible ; and if no relation exists there can be no measure- ment of it. It is, in truth, only the value of commodities at the same time that can be mea- sured; another point in which the supposed analogy between the measurement of space and of value completely fails. In the case of length, a direct comparison may be made between two objects, however separated by time, and their ratio to each other found. The length of an object now may be compared with the length of an object in former times, by means of an instrument actually handed down to us ; by an uninterrupted transmission of the same object, or the same space through the medium of different objects, furnishing a com- I 114 ox .MEASURES mon bond of connection between tlie measure- ments of space in all ages. But this circum- stance can evidently have no existence in the measurement of value, w^hich is the ascertain- ment of a relation between contemporary com- modities, and not between objects at different periods. The two cases would be analogous if we supposed no physical measure of length to be transmitted from one period to another, but only a record of the lengths of different objects expressed in a common denomination. Under these circumstances, all that we could do would be to compare the relative dimensions of ob- jects in our ovm days, with the relative dimen- sions of similar objects in past times, as re- corded : but we should have no common me- dium of comparison between one age and ano- ther. Now what in this case would be owing to the want of a transmitted measure, arises in the other case from the very nature of the re- lation with which we have to do. The na- ture of that relation itself interposes as com- plete a disconnection between different ages, as I OF VALUE. 115 would result from the supposed want of a com- mon instrument for measuring space. It is obvious then, that if no relation of value can exist between objects in different ages, there can be no measurement of it, nor consequently can there be any measure or me- dium of comparison required. The only thing to be done, with regard to different periods, is to compare the relation of value subsisting between any two commodities, A and B, at one period, with the relation subsist- ing between them at another; or, in other words, the quantity of a which purchased b at the former time, with the quantity of a which purchased b at the latter. This is evidently a simple comparison, in which neither a nor b perform the function of a measure, or medium, in any possible interpretation of the term. That office has in all likelihood been already discharged in ascertaining the relative quanti- ties of A and B at each period ; and if, as is probable, these quantities have been ascertained by means of the prices of the commodities, money I 2 116 ON MEASURES has been the medium of comparison. But after these quantities have been ascertained, there can be no place whatever in the subse- quent comparison for any medium, no con- ceivable function for it to perform. Should it be urged, that when we compare the price of corn in one year with its price in another, we use money as a medium of com- parison, in the same way as when we compare the prices of com and cloth at the same point of time, the answer is not difficult. In the latter case it is obvious, that the facts furnished to us are the relations of cloth and corn to money, or, the quantities of money for which definite portions of them are exchanged ; and from these we infer another circumstance, namely, the relation of value between corn and cloth, and consequently their comparative power of purchasing all other commodities. In the former case, on the other hand, the facts furnished to us are the prices of corn, or the rela- tions between corn and money, at two different periods : but from these we deduce no other rela- OF VALUE. 117 tion; we do not advance a step beyond the infor- mation given ; there is no inference corresponding to that which is drawn in the other case. We can- not deduce the relation of value, between com at the first and corn at the second period, because no such relation exists, nor consequently can we ascertain their comparative power over other commodities. If we made the attempt, it would be in fact endeavouring to infer the quantities of corn which exchanged for each other at two different points of time, a thing obviously absurd. And further, money would not be here discharging a particular function any more than the other commodity. We should have the value of corn in money, and the value of money in corn, but one would be no more a measure or medium of comparison than the other. These observations are enough to show, that the only use of a measure of value, in the sense of a medium of comparison, is between commodities existing at the same time; and consequently the proposition, that money is not 118 ON MEASURES a good measure of the value of commodities at different periods, is either false or amounts to nothing. If it means that money is not equally a good measure of contemporary commodities at any period, it is directly opposite to the truth : if it means that it is not a good me- dium of comparison between commodities at different periods, it asserts its incapability of performing a function in a case where there is no function for it to perform. In applying the principles developed in the preceding disquisition to the writings of Mr. Ri- cardo, we shall find that he has fallen into the same errors as his predecessors and contempo- raries, as well as into others peculiarly his own. Misled by his radical misconception of the na- ture of value, and particularly by his notions on the subject of real value, he has opened his section "on an invariable measure," with the following passage, the errors of which will be sufficiently apparent to any one who has attended to the foregoing part of the present chapter. " When commodities," says Mr. Ricardo, OF VALUE. 119^ " varied in relative value, it would be desirable to have the means of ascertaining which of them fell, and which rose in real value, and this could be effected only by comparing them, one after another, with some invariable standard measure of value, which should itself be sub- ject to none of the fluctuations to which other commodities are exposed. Of such a measure it is impossible to be possessed, because there is no commodity which is not itself exposed to the same variations as the things, the value of which is to be ascertained ; that is, there is none which is not subject to require more or less labour for its production." It has been already shown in the first chap- ter, not merely that such a commodity is phy- sically impossible, as here conceded by Mr. Ri- cardo, but that the supposition of such a com- modity, for such a purpose, involves contradic- tory conditions'^. We could not in the nature * Should Mr. Ricardo, or rather should any of his fol- lowers, shelter himself under the notion of real value, and thus escape the absurdity here charged upon him, it would only be taking refuge in another absurdity equally great. 120 ON MEASURES of the case have any commodity of invariable value, by which to ascertain the fluctuations of all other things, unless all commodities were of invariable value, in which case there would be no fluctuations to ascertain. We have also seen in the present chapter, that the demand for invariablenes of value in any commodity to be used as a measure, is founded altogether on a false analogy; that fluctuations in value are not ascertained by any measure, but by historical evidence ; that a measure of value can signify nothing but a medium of comparison for contemporary com- modities ; and that we have as good a measure in this sense, not only as it is possible to have, but as it is possible to conceive. Besides these errors, there is to be disco- vered in Mr. Ricardo's views, as to the uses of a measure of value, a singular confusion of thought, which I shall here endeavour to ex- plain. The specific error of Mr. Ricardo on the sub- ject of invariable value consists, as before explained, in supposing, that if the causes of OF VALUE. 121 value affecting one commodity remained the same, the value of that commodity could not vary, overlooking the circumstance, that value denotes a relation between two objects, which must necessarily alter with an alteration in the causes affecting either of them. He incessantly identifies constancy in the quantity of pro- ducing labour with constancy of value. Hence he maintains, that if we could find any commodity invariable in the circumstances of its production, it would be in the first place invariable in value ; and, secondly, it would indicate, or would enable us to ascertain, the variations in value of other commodities. It is curious enough that he should never have clearly discerned v^^hat such a commodity would really serve to indicate: it would not, as he asserts, serve to indicate the variations in the value of commodities, but the variations in the circumstances of their production. It would enable us to ascertain, not any fluctua- tions in value, but in which commodity those lluctuations had originated. He has in truth 122 ON MEASURES confounded two perfectly distinct ideas, name- ly, measuring the value of commodities, and ascertaining in which commodity, and in what degree, the causes of value have varied. For suppose we had such a commodity as he requires for a standard : suppose, for instance, all commodities to be produced by labour alone, and silver to be produced by an invari- able quantity of labour. In this case silver would be, according to Mr. Ricardo, a perfect measure of value. But in what sense ? What is the function performed ? Silver, even if in- variable in its producing labour, will tell us nothing of the value of other commodities. Their relations in value to silver, or their prices, must be ascertained in the usual way, and when ascertained, we shall certainly know the values of commodities in relation to each other : but in all this there is no assistance derived from the circumstance of the producing labour of silver being a constant quantity. But it is the fluctuations of commodities which this invariable standard is to ascertain or OF VALUE. 123 measure. Let us trv to discover liow far it would assist us here. Suppose cloth in the year 1600 was worth 12^. a yard, and in 1800 only 6s. Here we have a fluctuation in the value of cloth, in re- lation to the standard commodity; in 1800 it was worth only half as much silver as it was in 1600. This, however, is not, let it be ob- served, a fluctuation ascertained by the cir- cumstance of silver being produced by an in- variable quantity of labour. Had silver varied in the circumstances of its production, our in- formation as to the relation between cloth and silver would have been equally attainable, and equally complete. What then could be ascer- tained, in this case, from the metal being in- variable in the quantity of its producing la- bour? What inference would this circum- stance enable us to draw ? No inference, ob- viously, as to the value of cloth and silver ; for, on this point, the prices of the former tell us all that it is possible to know. The in- ference we should draw would be, that the 124 ON MEASURES cause of the change in the relation between cloth and silver had been in the former, and as labour is, by the supposition, the sole cause of value, we might more particularly infer, that the producing labour of cloth had been abridged to half its former quantity. A commodity, therefore, under these con- ditions, produced by an invariable quantity of labour, would enable us to ascertain, not the fluctuations in value between two or more com- modities (for these are facts to be gathered from appropriate evidence), but the fluctuations in the quantity of labour w^hich produced them : and in truth, if we examine what is the par- ticular advantage which Mr. Ricardo himself supposes we should be able to derive from the possession of such a commodity, we shall find it to be in reality that which is here described, the power of ascertaining, not the variations in value, but the variations in the producing la- bour of commodities. Speaking of the inter- change of game and fish, in the earlier stages^ of society, he says, — OF VALUE. 125 " If with the same quantity of labour, a less quantity of fish, or a greater quantity of game were obtained, the value of fish would rise in comparison with that of game. If, on the con- trary, with the same quantity of labour a less quantity of game, or a greater quantity of fish was obtained, game would rise in comparison with fish. *^ If there were any other commodity, which was invariable in its value, we should be able to ascertain, by comparing the value of fish and game with this commodity, how much of the variation was to be attributed to a cause which affected the value of fish, and how much to a cause which affected the value of game. " Suppose money to be that commodity. If a salmon were worth £1, and a deer £2, one deer would be worth two salmon. But a deer might become of the value of three salmon, for more labour might be required to obtain the deer, or less to get the salmon ; or both these causes might operate at the same time. If we had this invariable standard, we might easily as- 126 ox MEASURES certain in what degree either of these causes operated. If salmon continued to sell for £1, whilst deer rose to £3, we might conclude that more labour was required to obtain the deer. If deer continued at the same price of £2, and salmon sold for 13^. Ad, we might then be sure that less labour was required to obtai?! the salmon ; and if deer rose to £2. 10^. and salmon fell to 16^. ^d. we should be Qonvmcediihzi both causes had operated in producing the alteration of the relative value of these commodities." Here we have a very accurate description, by Mr. Ricardo, of what a commodity pro- duced by an invariable quantity of labour (not a commodity of invariable value, as he erroneously terms it) would enable us to ascer- tain, under the supposition that all things were determined in value by quantity of labour. He does not tell us that such a commodity would enable us to ascertain the value of fish or game, or their variation in value, but this variation being given, that it would enable us to infer how much of it was to be attributed to a OF VALUE. 127 change in the labour required to obtain the salmon, and how much to a change in that re- quired to obtain the deer. In this and other passages it will be found, that although Mr. Ricardo is professedly speak- ing of a commodity produced by invariable la- bour, in the character of a measure of value, he is in reality, without being conscious of the dif- ference, altogether occupied with the considera- tion of that commodity as capable of indicating variations in the producing labour of other com- modities*. Instead of a measure of value, * The same remark will apply to economists in general. Their real object in seeking for a measure of value (how- ever little they may be aware of it) is to determine m which commodities any changes of value have originated, and not to ascertain the extent of these changes, which, as I have repeatedly stated, are matters of record and evidence, and a knowledge of which is in reality pre-supposed in any ap- plication of what they call a measure. It is not, there- fore, a measure of value which they are in pursuit of, but a commodity which would indicate the sources of variation. Whether there is any one object which would do this better than another, would at all events be a rational, and might prove a useful inquiry. 128 ON MEASURES such a commodity as he describes would be a measure of labour, or a medium of ascertain- ing the varying quantities of labour which commodities required to produce them. Be- fore it could be employed in regard to any ob- ject, the value of that object, or its relation to the standard commodity, must be given, and then all that could be deduced from the datum would be the quantity of labour bestowed on its production. But perhaps the most remarkable circum- stance of all is, that for this latter purpose, that invariableness in the quantity of labour, which he has insisted upon as so essentially requisite, would be of no peculiar service. On the sup- position that labour was the sole determining principle of value, a commodity produced by an invariable quantity of labour would afford us no assistance even as a measure of labour, which could not be equally derived from a commodity the producing labour of which was variable, provided we were furnished with the same data. OF VALUE. 129 For in the above comparison of cloth in 1600 and cloth in 1800, mark all that is specifically ascertained. If silver had been liable to variation in the quantity of its producing labour, we should still have been informed, from the same source that supplied the information in the other case, what was its relation to cloth, for this is equiva- lent to saying, that we should still have been in- formed of the prices of cloth at the two different periods specified. These are historical facts, and not deductions from the invariableness of the labour employed in the production of silver. Were this labour then a variable quantity, we should still learn, that a yard of cloth in 1600 was 12^. and in 1800 6s. ; but we should, it is alleged, be at a loss to discover, whether the change in the relation between silver and cloth had been owing to the former or the latter. This then is the sole circumstance by which the two cases are supposed to be distinguished, and in fact it amounts to this ; we could tell that, in the former case, cloth in 1800 required only K 130 ON MEASURES half the labour necessary for its production in 1600, while in the latter case we could not tell whether the quantity of producing labour in the cloth had been reduced one half, or whether that required for the production of money had been doubled. In answer to this I say, that the ratio between the quantities of labour necessary for the production of cloth in 1800, and in 1600, might be equally ascertained, although the quantity of labour employed in the produc- tion of silver had varied, provided that the data in the two cases were equal. The data in the first case are the prices of cloth at each period, and the ratio subsisting between the I quantity of labour employed at each period in the production of silver. The circumstance of this ratio being that of equality makes no difference. Now suppose, in the second case, that we are furnished with the prices of cloth at both periods, and with the ratio subsisting between the quantities of the labour necessary for the production of silver, which ratio, by the sup- OF VALUE. 131 position, not being that of equality, suppose to be as 2 in 1600 to 1 in 1800, or, in other words, suppose that silver in 1800 is produced by half the labour required in 1600. With these data it is obvious, that we could deduce the ratio of labour employed in the production of cloth at these periods, with as much accuracy as we could under the condi- tions of the first case. If in 1600 the cloth was 12^. per yard, and in 1800 only 6s,, the producing labour of silver at the latter period being only half of what it was at the former period, then the producing labour of cloth would have been reduced to a quarter of its former quantity. For in 1600 a yard of cloth being 12^. in value, the yard of cloth and the 12^. took equal quantities of labour to produce them : but in 1800 the producing labour of 12.y. is by the supposition reduced one half, and consequently the quantity of labour in 6s, must be a quarter of the quantity which had been necessary to produce 12.9. in 1600. Now as 6.?. in 1 800 exchange for a yard of cloth, the pro- lyl 2 132 ON MEASURES ducing labour of the yard of cloth must be equal to the producing labour of the 6s. ; that is, a quarter of the quantity of labour employed to produce a yard of cloth in 1 600. It may probably be alleged, however, as an advantage peculiar to the first case, that the quantity of producing labour being invariable, we are saved from all that research into its com- parative quantity at different periods which would be necessary on the contrary supposition. But it is to be recollected, that the circumstance of a commodity having been always produced by the same quantity of labour, is an historical fact quite as difficult to ascertain as the vari- ations of another commodity. We might, it is true, be saved from all investigation of this nature, if there existed a commodity, which, from some obvious and insuperable necessity, was always the product of the same labour; yet even this advantage is not dependent on the in- variableness of the labour; for if, what is equally easy to suppose, and quite as likely to happen, we had a commodity which necessarily OF VALUE. 133 varied every year in a given proportion, we should be equally spared the pains of historical research. To have a commodity, whether pro- duced by a variable or by an invariable quan- tity of labour, which saved us the trouble of inquiry, would doubtless be an advantage, but we might as well suppose fifty other arbitrary aids *. In concluding this discussion, it may not be useless to advert more particularly to one of the objects, which economists have proposed to themselves in the attempt to discover an inva- riable measure or standard of value. It appears to have been to determine the efficiency of re- venues, salaries, and wages of different classes of people at different periods, in what condi- tion such revenues enabled them to live, or what power it enabled them to wield. This, it is supposed, would be accomplished, did we possess some object of immutable value. " If we are told," says Mr. Malthus, " that the wages of day-labour in a particular coun- * See Note E. 134 ON MEASURES try are, at the present time, four pence a day ; or, that the revenue of a particular sovereign, 700 or 800 years ago, was 400,000/. a year, these statements of nominal value convey no sort of information respecting the con- dition of the lower classes of people in the one case, or the resources of the sovereign in the other. Without further knowledge on the subject, we should be quite at a loss to say, whether the labourers in the countrv mentioned were starving, or living in greater plenty ; whether the king in question might be consi- dered as having a very inadequate revenue, or whether the sum mentioned was so great as to be incredible. " It is quite obvious, that in cases of this kind, and they are of constant recurrence, the value of wages, incomes, or commodities, esti- mated in the precious metals, will be of little use to us alone. What we want further is some estimate of a kind which may be deno- minated real value in exchange, implying the quantity of the necessaries and conveniences of life, which those wages, incomes, or commodi- OF VALUE. 135 dities will enable the possessor of them to com- mand *." Now to suppose that we can have any one object by which this information can be ob- tained, would imply a gross misconception of the nature of value. I have already repeatedly stated, that to know the value of an article at any period, is merely to know its relation in exchange to some other commodity. From this fact, which must be ascertained like other facts, no inference whatever can be drawn as to the value of any thing beyond the two commo- dities in question. From the relation of corn and money nothing can be inferred as to the relation of corn and labour, or of money and labour. If, proceeding a step farther, we learn from the proper records the relation also of la- bour and money, then we can deduce the rela- tion of labour and corn ; but we should not be able to make any inference to any other object. The only practicable inference on the subject * Principles of Pol. Econ., p. 59. 136 ON MEASURES of value, is the mutual relation of two commo- dities from their separate relations to a third. It follows, that if we wish to ascertain the state of comfort or luxury in which any class of people lived at any assigned period, there is no possible method of effecting the object, but ascertaining from the proper documents the amount of their incomes, and then, particular by particular, the relation which these incomes bore to commodities. If the incomes are stated in corn, or silver, nothing can be inferred from the statement, as to their power over other things. Supposing the income to be a certain amount of money, then the inquirer must find records of the prices of those arti- cles to which his curiosity is directed, and a simple calculation will teach him the power of the income to command them. If he wishes, for example, to ascertain the condition of the labouring class at any given period, he must first find the rate of wages, or, in other words, the mutual relation of labour and money. This is one step in the investiga- OF VALUE. 137 tion, but it will not of itself throw any light on the food, clothing, and comfort, which the la- bourers are able to procure ; and he must there- fore search in the proper registers for the prices of such commodities as constitute these necessaries and conveniences. He can ascer- tain nothing but what is shown by the histori- cal documents which he consults. When he has found the price of labour, the price of corn, of cloth, of hats, of stockings, of fuel, of house-room, he will be able to tell how much of each of these commodities a week's or a years labour could command : in other words, the condition of the labouring class of society in these respects will become manifest. But these are all separate particulars, to be separately ascertained: one will not disclose another ; each must be individually established by independent evidence. There can be no commodity, by a reference to which the power of a given income over any or all other com- modities may be shown. 138 MEASURES OF VALUE. Conclusions such as these are so obvious, that they would scarcely require to be for- mally stated had they not been frequently over- looked. Even the author of the Templars' Dialogues, who observes, " that Mr. Malthus, in common with many others, attaches a most unreasonable importance to the discovery of a measure of value," seems to sanction the pre- vailing errors, when he goes on to remark, that such a measure " would at best end in answer- ing a few questions of unprofitable curiosity^." Sufficient, it is hoped, has been said to show, that we are in possession of the only kind of measure which can be had or conceived, and that we must look for the gratification of our curiosity, not to any measure of value whatever, but to the records of former times, and a few simple calculations from the data which they furnish. * London Magazine for May 1824, p. 560. CHAPTER VII, \ ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. After the conclusions established in the pre- ceding chapter, it would be a superfluous task to examine the various measures of value which may have been imagined or proposed by dif- ferent economists. As that, nevertheless, which has been recently advocated by Mr. Malthus, and which was originally brought forward by Adam Smith, has attracted some attention^ it may deserve a cursory notice. This measure is labour, considered as an exchangeable commodity, or, in other words, the labour which commodities command : and proceeding on the false principle, that a measure of value must be itself immutable in 140 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE value, Mr. Malthus maintains that the value of labour is invariable. The discussions in which we have already been engaged, furnish a variety of methods in which the errors of this doctrine may be ex- posed. It has been shown, for example, that the value of labour, like that of any other exchangeable article, is denoted by the quantity of some other commodity for which a definite portion of it will exchange, and must rise or fall as that quantity becomes greater or smaller, these phrases being in truth only different expressions of the same event. Hence, unless labour always exchanges for the same quantity of other things, its value cannot be invariable ; and consequently, the very supposition of its being at one and the same time invariable, and capable of measur- ing the variations of other commodities, in- volves a direct contradiction. It has also been shown, that to term any thing immutable in value, amidst the fluctua- tions of other things, implies that its value at one time may be compared with its value at PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. 141 another time, without reference to any other commodity; which is absurd, value denoting a relation between two things at the same time : and it has likewise been shown, that in no sense could an object of invariable value, if attain- able, be of any peculiar service in the capacity of a measure. These considerations are quite sufficient to overturn the claims of the proposed measure, as maintained by its advocate, but it may be inquired, how far would it be useful in the sense of a medium of comparison. In order to sa- tisfy this inquiry, let us suppose a simple case. I wish to know, for instance, the mutual value of corn and cloth in the year 1600 ; and in the ordinary way I find, that corn was 6s, a bushel and cloth 12^. a yard, and I thence perceive, that a bushel of corn was worth half a yard of cloth. This appears to be the only informa- tion wanted ; but this is using money as the medium of comparison ; and to apply Mr. Mal- thus's measure, we must find the value of corn and cloth in relation to labour. Of this, how- ever, I probably shall find no record, and there- 142 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE fore the measure proposed cannot be used. I may find, it is true, the prices of labour, corn, and cloth : I then may proceed to calculate the value of a yard of cloth and a bushel of corn in labour ; and their separate relations to labour will show their relation to each other : but this I have already learned from their prices or separate relations to money. Their value in labour, therefore, is perfectly superfluous towards ascertaining their mutual relation, consequently labour in this case is perfectly useless as a mea- sure of value. The way in which Mr. Malthus attempts to establish the invariable value of labour is re- markable enough, and his table, drawn up with that view, is certainly one of the most curious productions in the whole range of political economy*. In the first column he supposes certain quantities of corn to be produced by ten men, * As the subsequent remarks could scarcely be under- stood without a reference to tliis table, a copy of it is pre- sented to the reader at the end of the present chapter. PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. 143 according to the varying fertility of the soil. In the second column he states the yearly corn wages of each labourer, determined by the de- mand and supply. The first case supposes the yearly wages of a labourer to be 12 quarters, the last only 8 quarters ; in other words, the value of labour in relation to corn is in the first case 12 quarters, and in the last 8. Hence it is obvious, that to prove the invariable value of labour, he begins by supposing it to be variable ; singular premises, certainly, from which to de- duce such a conclusion. And the process of deduction is no less sino;ular. Takino: the first case, he proceeds thus: If 1 man obtain 12 quarters per annum for wages, 10 men will ob- tain 120 quarters, and as the whole product of these 10 men is 150 quarters, profits will be 25 per cent. Now as 150 quarters are the product of 10 men, 120 quarters must be produced by 8 men, and the profits being equal to the labour of 2 men, the value of the whole 120 quarters is 10, But 10 what? Evidently 10 men's labour: that is, in other words, the quantity of corn 144 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE given to 1 men for their labour, is equal in value to the labour often men, which is just equi- valent to saying, that the number of shillings which any one gives for a yard of cloth, is equal in value to the yard of cloth for which the shillings are exchanged ! In a word, Mr. Mal- thus sets out from the premises, that 120 quar- ters of corn are given as wages to 10 men, and, after journeying through two columns of figures, he arrives at the conclusion, that the said 1 20 quarters are worth the labour for which they are given. In the same manner he goes through all the other cases, and as whatever quantity of corn is given to 10 men as their wages must be equal in value to that for which it is exchanged, that is, to the labour of 10 men, he constantly succeeds in alighting at the point from which he set out. Having accomplished thus much, he appears to proceed as follows : " If I give a commodity, which is as valuable at one time as at another, for another commodity at eacli of these periods, that other commodity must be equally constant in value. Now the wages of PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. 145 10 men having been proved to be as valuable at one time as at another, the value of the la- bour for which they are exchanged must be also constant." By wages he means the aggregate quantity of corn ; and how has he shown these wages to be of invariable value ? He has shown them to be invariable, estimated in labour : his argument consequently is, that because the wages of ten men are always of the same value, estimated in labour, therefore the labour for which they are exchanged must be of invaria- ble value. In the same way any article might be proved to be of invariable value; for instance, 10 yards of cloth. For whether we gave £5 or £10 for the 10 yards, the sum given would always be equal in value to the cloth for which it was paid, or, in other words, of invariable value in relation to cloth. But that which is griven for a thing of invariable value, must itself be in- variable, whence the 10 yards of cloth must be of invariable value. It is scarcely necessary to expose the futility 146 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE of reasoning like this. Instead of proving la- bour to be of immutable value, it proves the re- verse. An alteration in the mutual value of two articles means, that the quantities in which they are exchanged for each other are altered : a definite quantity of one is exchanged for a greater or smaller portion of the other than be- fore. Now the only commodities in question, in Mr. Malthus's table, are corn and labour ; and if, as he supposes, the labour of 10 men is at one time rewarded with 120 quarters of corn, and at another time with only 80 quarters, the only condition required for an alteration of value is fulfilled, and labour, instead of being invariable, has fallen one-third. The fallacy lies in virtually considering or speaking of wages, as if they were a commo- dity ; while, as the term is used by Mr. Mal- thus, it really implies an aggregate quantity of corn, in the same way as the term sum implies an aggregate quantity of money; and it is just the same kind of futility to call wages invariable in value, because though variable in quantity PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. 147 they command the same portion of labour, as to call the sum given for a hat, of invariable value, because, although sometimes more and sometimes less, it always purchases the hat. In speaking of the rise and fall in value of commodities, we have nothing to do with ag- gregate quantities which really vary in amount, and have no identity but in name ; our business is with definite portions : and the precise rea- son why the labour in one case, and the hat in the other, are not of invariable value, is, that the quantities of corn and of money given for them have varied, although these quantities un- der every variation continue to be designated by the terms '' wages," and " sum." It is true enough, that if a commodity ex- changes at one time for 10 men's labour, and at another time for the same, it has not altered in value to labour : both the commodity and the labour have been constant in value to each other ; but as wages are not a commodity, as in Mr, Malthus's nomenclature they signify an aggregate quantity of corn, if this aggregate l2 148 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE t^uantity, given for a definite portion of labour, is sometimes larger and sometimes smaller, tlie corn of which the aggregate is composed varies accordingly in value in relation to the labour for which it is given, and the labour varies in value in relation to the corn. From these remarks the reader will perceive, that Mr. Malthus's " Table illustrating the in- variable value of labour," absolutely proves nothing. It exhibits merely the results of a few simple operations in arithmetic, as a slight in- spection of the annexed copy will show. Co- lumn 1 contains the quantities of corn produced, according to the varying fertility of the soil, by the yearly labour of 10 men, which quantities are assumed, and not deduced from other data. The second column exhibits the quantities of corn given yearly to each labourer, and these quantities are also assumed, not deduced. Column 3 contains the quantities of corn given yearly to 10 men, obtained by multiplying the quantities in column 2 by the number 10. Column 4 shows the rate of profit, or how much PROPOSED BY MR. MALTHUS. 149 per cent, the quantities of corn in column 1 ex- ceed the corresponding quantities in cohimn 3 ; or, in other words, how much per cent, the quantities of corn produced by 10 men exceed the quantities given to 10 men for their labour. Column 5 exhibits the quantities of labour, or number of men required to produce the quan- tities of corn in the third column, obtained by a simple operation in the rule of three : if 10 men produce 150 quarters, how many will be required to produce 120? Column 6 shows the profits estimated in la- bour, after the rate in the fourth column ; or, what is the same thing, it shows the quantities of labour which the quantities of corn in column 3 will command, over and above what produced them. Column 7 contains the quantities of labour commanded by the corn in column 3, ajid is nothing but a repetition of what was be- fore told us in the third column : for we are there informed, that the quantities of corn enu- merated, severally commanded the yearly labour of 10 men, and in this seventh column there 150 ON THE MEASURE OF VALUE. are fourteen distinct reiterations of the same piece of information. Column 8 is merely another enumeration of results obtained by simple operations in the rule of three. It shows the quantities of labour which 100 quarters of corn would command, at the different rates ac- cording to which labour is rewarded in the third column. Column 9 is a similar enumeration of results, obtained in the same manner, and exhibits the quantity of labour which the products of the labour of 10 men in column 1 would respectively command, or the value of those aggregate quan- tities estimated in labour. This cursory review evinces, that the for- midable array of figures in the table yields not a single new or important truth ; and that the seventh column, which was intended to afford the grand result of this tabular argument, ex- hibits merely a constant repetition of one of the assumptions on which the whole is built"^. ' * See Note F. tfl O H-1 > c (1) bo CO O M ^ BC Cn „ o I - s g. GO* " "2 .= 5 ^ e S = h X g "^^ tJ _- S E =i- 3 s ? a c t; 3 3 ii o 3 .> ^ ^ — :- > 3 i£ -<" CO C^ -^ lO (>! G^ — " LO — <' (>J o" rc O (M — ' C^ — < (N ^ CO CO C^ CTi CO t>. ?0 O CO O »' t^ O CO ci X o ci — ^ — c^i c^ oooooooooooooo >■. — t/: t- 17 2 « s fo -i: * u o ^^ ~. en ~ ^ — O -3 ^ «_. « = S J, —• ^-^ "^.t; g o i r 5 e I, t sc- ^£ c3 = — ss r ii 3 O -1 s " = t„ _ — Vi_ -- ») OS o f '-> • ^ o >> r 3 ?, 3 -5 = 3 = -J 2 ©"^•— .©s • ^ © _ --« S "3 ^U^ —•- 1. O C/ •l^l©=|-::i i I i « I i ^ i CO-TfTf— .?^ cTj X •o CO 'O X CI -H ro o -— X X xx^cixi>.o^t>.aiXcriXCiXx a. t. Tt* _u tr 3 5 '© O 3 • - * 2 3 X CO •O CI ro ,i; CO O CI ro CN — ; lo "r.iooosot^xoasooci-^voici ^i* C^ — lO -^ G^l CO 01 ^ 01 ^ (M ^ — « u - aj /'OOOOOOOOOOC: C 5 oi ^0 w oi — I 0^ c; — ' o o ci cTi X X — U O) t^irs • r; a -3 ^ 3 j^ © ^ .-3 2 c- i- «j s S — cS br g t. o X SS 0^ CO O iCI -^ CI O — I O O Oi Ci X X ® 3 i; =v_ ?"' "3 2 -r © . 3 rH :-- O'o >,® S «oooooooooo ^^^lOTr-TTcococ^c^ — ' o o o O O 05 1- O ^ © ^ s ■3- g.3 C ^ -££55-2 c-3 ^i|) in n9\is CHAPTER Vlll. ON METHODS OF ESTIMATING VALUE. The discussion respecting the measurement of value naturally leads to the consideration of the methods of estimating value. To measure and to estimate value are often considered as im- plying the same operation, and are used indis- criminately. The explanation, however, of the former, which I have given in a preceding chapter, establishes a useful distinction bet\^ een them. By measuring value I mean finding the mutual relation of two commodities by their separate relations to a third. Estimating value is the same thing as expressing it *, except that * See Note G. ESTIMATION OF VALUE. 153 the latter is more appositely used in regard to a single definite portion of a commodity, or at least in the simpler cases of valuation; while the former may be appropriated to cases of greater complexity, where we compute the value of a mass or number of commodities. When I say a yard of cloth is worth twenty shillings, or a pound, I express the value of the cloth in relation to silver. When I say that 1000 yards of cloth, 500 quarters of corn, and 20 tons of iron, are worth 3000 guineas, I estimate the value of these articles in gold. If it is ne- cessary to establish a distinction between ex- pressing and estimating value, it may therefore be stated to be, that the latter involves the idea of computation, which is not necessarily implied ill the former. The distinction, however, is not essential, and the indiscriminate use of the terms can scarcely lead to error. Mr. Ricardo frequently insists, that if by im- provements in the methods of production the whole produce of a country were doubled, while the labour employed remained the same, this doubled produce would be only of the same 154 ON METHODS OF aggregate value as the former produce, while each individual commodity would have fallen fifty per cent, in value. It is obvious, however, that the truth of this and similar positions en- tirely depends on the medium in which we es- timate value. Suppose, for the sake of simpli- fication, that the country had no foreign com- merce, and produced its own money : then if all commodities (money of course included) were produced in double quantity, the effect would be, that while the value of the aggregate would be doubled, the value of each individual com- modity would remain as before. For by the value of an individual commodity we mean its power of commanding other things in exchange. If a pair of stockings were formerly worth a shilling, it would still be worth a shilling. Every commodity would in the same way con- tinue to be exchanged in the same quantity against every other commodity. So far as to the value of individual commodities. With regard to the aggregate, value being in strict propriety a relation existing amongst the several parts, it cannot be predicated of the whole, ex- ESTIMATING VALUE. 155 cept in reference to some of its parts. If the value of the whole means any thing, it can be only its value estimated or computed in some individual commodity ; and in this sense, as the quantity of every thing would be doubled, the aggregate value would be doubled. If a pairof stockings continued to be worth a shilling, 2000 pair, which would now be produced for every thousand pair previously, would be worth 2000 shillings ; and thus, with regard to every other commodity, we should have a double value in shilling's, and the sum of all these values would be double. Labour is the only thing in relation to which any commodity would not necessarily appear to be of the same value*, but here we are of course leaving labour out of consideration. On the sup- * Commodities might appear of the same value even in relation to labour ; that is to say, there would be no incon- sistency or repugnance amongst the terms and ideas in- volved in the supposition, although the circumstance would be one not likely to happen : a point, indeed, in which it only resembles the other parts of this hypothetical case. 156 ox METHODS OF position that all commodities were doubled in quantity, this is the result, in whichever of the commodities or parts we choose to estimate the whole. But if any one commodity is supposed to be produced in the same quantity by the same labour as before, and the whole of the other commodities are estimated in this one, it will be true enough, that the whole produce continues of the same value, while the parts have fallen one half*. From this it is evident, that in all such cases the result depends on the commodity chosen as the medium of estima- tion. As by value we always imply value in something, a commodity may be said by one person to rise, and by another to fall, and with equal truth, if they speak wit^ tacit reference to different commodities ; but a general affirma- tion of this nature is worse than useless. The assertion of a rise or fall in any thing should be accompanied by a mention of the commo- * Assuming that commodities are to each other in value as the quantities of labour concerned in their production. ESTIMATING VALUE. 157 dity in relation to which it has thus varied, or, at all events, the commodity should be clearly indicated by the tenour of the language em- ployed. Otherwise, two disputants in Political Economy may share the fate of the two knights, who fell sacrifices to their obstinacy in maintaining, the one that a shield was of gold, the other that it was of silver, both being equally correct in their assertions, and their difference arising, as a thousand differences arise, from the simple circumstance of having looked at opposite sides of the same object. The present subject may be further elucidated by citing a passage from Mr. Ricardo. '' The labour of a million of men in manufactures,' says he, " will always produce the same value, but will not always produce the same riches. By the invention of machinery, by improve- ments in skill, by a better division of labour, or by the discovery of new markets, where more advantageous exchanges may be made, a million of men may produce double or treble the amount of riches, of necessaries, conve- 158 ON METHODS OF niences, and amusements, in one state of so- ciety, that they could produce in another, but they will not on that account add any thing to value; for every thing rises or falls in value in proportion to the facility or difficulty of pro- ducing it, or, in other words, in proportion to the quantity of labour employed on its pro- duction*." All this may be safely pronounced unmeaning and nugatory f. It conveys no information, nor can we judge of its correctness or inaccuracy, till we know what is the commodity, in relation to which it is meant to assert, that the product of the labour of this million of men will always prove of the same value, or in other words, until we are told what is the commodity em- ployed as a medium of estimation. If these men produce treble the quantity of all articles of exchange whatever, then the aggregate valxie of the product of their labour will be treble, * Principles of Pol. Econ., p. 320, 3d edit. t See Note H. ESTIMATING VALUE. 150 estimated in any article we please. It any ar- ticles still require the same labour, and we esti- mate the rest in these, then the aggregate value will remain the same. In the sequel of the passage above cited, Mr. Ricardo maintains, that when the labour of a certain number of men, formerly capable of producing 1000 pair of stockings, becomes by inventions in machinery productive of 2000 pair, the value of the o^eneral mass of commodi- ties will be diminished, because the stockings manufactured before the improvement must fall to the level of the new goods. This again depends on the mode of estimation. Estimated in stockings, the aggregate value of the ge- neral mass of commodities would rise ; esti- mated in any thing else it would fall : and al- though it may seem ludicrous to talk of esti- mating the value of all commodities in stockings, the principle is still the same as if gold or any other commodity happened to be the me- dium of valuation. Hence it appears, that these propositions, / 160 ON METHODS OF which carry, so profound and paradoxical an air, really amount to nothing but this, that a commodity may rise or fall in relation to one commodity and not to another, and therefore that the estimation of commodities in dift'erent media will necessarily yield different results. It may be here remarked, that Mr. Ricardo employs the term estimate in a manner alto- gether incorrect. In the preceding pages it has been shown, that we can express the value of a commodity only by the quantity of some other commodity, for which it will exchange. Now if to estimate has the same meaning as to express value, with the accessory idea of com- putation annexed, it follows that we can esti- mate value only in the same manner. Should we therefore at any time employ labour as the medium of estimation, it must be the labour for which a commodity will exchange. But Mr. Ricardo speaks of estimating commodities by the labour which is required to produce them. Nor is this to be regarded merely as a verbal inaccuracy, for it appears to have led ESTIMATING VALUE. 161 him into that erroneous method of estimating the value of labour, which has been already pointed out. It may be said, at least, that a clear apprehension of the precise meaning of the term would have been incompatible with his doctrine on the real value of wages, if not with the fundamental error which runs through his speculations, and of which his doctrine on the subject of the real value of wages is but a ramification. M CHAPTER IX. ON THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN VALUE AND RICHES. In the last chapter the subject of the present one has been in some degree anticipated. It has been there shown what is the real amount of the assertion, that the riches of a so- ciety may be doubled or trebled without any thing being added to their value. The sub- ject, however, is of so much importance, that it will be necessary to enter into a closer ex- amination of it. The distinction between riches and value is sufficiently obvious, riches signifying the com- modities themselves (with one or more accessory ideas annexed), and value denoting the relation in exchange between any of these commodities. ox VALUE AND RICHES. 163 Mr. Ricardo, nevertheless, has been singularly unfortunate in his attempt to discriminate them. His elaborate chapter, which contains it, ap- pears to me to be a remarkable tissue of errors and unmeaning conclusions, arising from his fundamental misconception of the nature of value. Throughout the whole of this chapter, he speaks of value as the positive result of la- bour : whence it follows, that the same quantity of labour must always produce the same value, however much its productive powers may have increased. Riches, therefore, may be inde- finitely multiplied, while no more labour is em ployed ; but the value of the riches, under this condition, remains invariably the same. Such is the sum and substance of his argu- ment. The error of stating^ the value to re- main constant has been sufficiently considered. There is still, however, an ambiguity or ob- scurity in the meaning of the term riches, which requires to be cleared up, Mr. Ricardo has regarded it as synonymous, sometimes, with commodities, and at other times with ahundance M 2 164 ON THE DISTINCTION of conmiodities. It is evidently used in a col- lective sense ; it is a term expressive of aggre- gation, if not of plenty. The adjective rich is never applied but to denote the possession of abundance, or the means of commanding it, and it may be doubted whether the sub- stantive riches is ever used without an im- plication of the same idea. If it were merely a general expression for commodities, without any accessory idea, it might be discarded from our speculations, and the latter word substituted in its stead. But such an experiment would not answer. We could not with any propriety change the title of Adam Smith's great work into " An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Commodities of Nations." We should approximate more nearly to the meaning of the original, were we to translate it, " An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the greater or smaller abundance of Commodities possessed by Nations." Whether the idea of abundance, however, is involved in the meaning of riches or not, BETWEEN VALUE AND RICHES. 165 the idea of aggregation or collection cannot be excluded. A single grain of wheat is not wealth, although it may be said to be an article of wealth. The idea of possession also seems essential to it. Riches are not simply commo- dities as things existing, but as things pos- sessed. The most useful articles in an unin- habited country could not be termed wealth, because they would have no proprietor. The country, it is true, might be denominated rich in such articles, but only inasmuch as it would be the container or possessor of them. There would still be the same idea of possession in- volved in our lang^uao^e. Whatever difficulty may be found in furnish- ing a good and complete definition of riches, there can be none in establishing the difference between the terms riches and value, as used in the science of Political Economy. Riches are the attribute of men, value is the attribute of commodities. A man or a community is rich ; a pearl or a diamond is valuable. He pos- 166 ON THE DISTINCTION sesses riches who is the owner of commodities which themselves possess value*; and, fur- ther, he is rich in proportion to the value of the objects possessed. Mr. Ricardo, indeed, denies that value is the measure of riches ; but a slight consideration will show, that it is the only criterion by which we can determine whe- ther one man or one community is richer than another. If the wealth of two men consisted in one single commodity, then, without entering into the question of exchange or value, we might determine that one was richer than the other, from mere excess of quantity. Even, however, in the simplest imaginable case of * Colonel Torrcns is of opinion, that value is not essen- tial to the idea of riches : it may be questioned, however, whether it is not always implied, and whether the latter term would have been invented in a state of society in which there was no interchange of commodities. It is a point, at all events, of little importance ; as, in those cases which come under the notice of the political economist, value in exchange is a constant adjunct of wealth. Vide Essay on the Production of Wealth, chap. i. BETWEEN VALUE AND RICHES. 167 this kind, there would necessarily be a supe- riority of value, if such an idea came at all into question, as well as of wealth. If the sole commodity in possession of the two indi- viduals were corn, of which one possessed 500 quarters and the other 1000, the latter would not only be richer, but the proprietor of pro- duce, the aggregate value of which was greater. In all but this very simplest case, it would be impossible to decide with accuracy on the superiority of two individuals in point of riches, except by estimating their value in some common medium. Suppose the individual who possessed the 500 quarters of corn, was worth also 500 yards of cloth, while the other, who had 1000 quarters of corn, possessed only 100 yards of cloth ; in what imaginable method could their riches be compared, and the supe- riority of one over the other be ascertained, except by means of their value, computed in some common medium of estimation, or re- duced into one denomination ? 168 ON THE DISTINCTION With regard to heterogeneous commodities, there are in fact only two conceivable criteria of riches : one, the utility of any possessions ; the other, their value. The first is in the highest degree unsteady and indeterminate, and altogether inapplicable. Iron, as Mr. Ricardo remarks, may be more useful than gold, but the possession of a pound of the former metal would not constitute a man as rich as that of an equal weight of the latter. Value, there- fore, is the only criterion of riches which is left to us. In determining, then, the question whether riches could be increased, without an increase of value, we must recur to the principles laid down in the last chapter. The answer in each particular case will depend on the medium of estimation. There is one additional remark, however, which may be here introduced. In the chapter referred to, a case was supposed, in which all commodities were produced in double quantity by the same labour, with the exception of one solitary article, and it was BETWEEN VALUE AND RICHES. 169 admitted, that if the whole were estimated in this one commodity, the aggregate value would be unaltered. In this hypothetical case, ne- vertheless, it still remains to be determined how we are to estimate the value of the com- modity chosen as the medium. In estimating the whole produce in this medium, we neces- sarily include the latter, and compute it as being worth itself. But value is a relation between two objects, and had we in any case to express the value of the medium, we must have recourse to one of the other commodities, when its value would appear to be doubled. Hence, although according to the supposed estimate, the aggregate value of the other commodities would be the same, the value of the medium would be twice as orreat as before ; and thus it might be truly said, that let us adopt what medium of estimation we please, no increase of riches can take place without an increase of value. CHAPTER X. ON THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE. Any one who takes the trouble of minutely ex- amining the writings of the most celebrated political economists will be astonished, not only at the looseness of expression, but at the vague- ness of design by which they are too frequently distinguished. It is often far from being ma- nifest, what is the precise doctrine or propo- sition they are intending to support, or to over- throw ; or rather, it is evident that they them- selves have not succeeded in defining it clearly to their own understandings. No department of political economy has suf- fered more from this indefiniteness of purpose, and ambiguity of language, than that which is^ A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE. 171 occupied with investigating the measures and causes of value. It would seem, on a first view, that the ideas of measuring and causing value were sufficiently distinct to escape all danger of being confounded ; yet it is remark- able, that both the ideas themselves, and the terms by which they are expressed, have been mixed and interchanged and substituted, with an apparently total unconsciousness of any dif- ference existinor- between them. The author of the Templars' Dialogues on Political Economy is the only writer who ap- pears to me to have been fully aware of this confusion of two separate and distinct ideas ^. He traces it partly to an ambiguity in the word determine. ^' The word determine," says he, " may be taken subjectively for what determines X in relation to our knowledge, or objectively, for what determines x in relation to itself. * This was written before 1 had seen the second edition of Mr. Mill's Elements, in which the distinction is for the first time introduced. His language on this point, never- theless, is not uniformly consistent, as will be shown in the next chapter. 172 DIFFERENCE BETWEEN Thus if I were to ask, ^ What determined the length of the race course?' and the answer were, ^ The convenience of the spectators, who could not have seen the horses at a greater distance ;' or, ' The choice of the subscribers ; ' then it is plain, that by the word ' determined,' I was understood to mean ' determined objec- tively,' in relation to the existence of the object; in other words, what caused the race-course to be this length rather than another length: but if the answer were, ' An actual admeasurement,' it would then be plain, that by the word * de- termined,' I had been understood to mean * de- termined subjectively," i. e. in relation to our knowledge; what ascertained it^?" The writer just quoted is wrong, however, in supposing Mr. Ricardo to be free from am- biguity in this point. A very cursory inspec- tion of the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation will show, that he has fallen into the same confusion as other economists ; and it is astonishino' to find the author of the Dia- o * London Magazine, Dec. 1823, p. 588: article en- titled *' Measure of Value." A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE. 173 iogues asserting, that Mr. Ricardo did not propose his principle of value (namely, the quantity of labour) as the measure of value. The fact is, that he sometimes speaks of it as the cause, and sometimes as the measure, in such a way as proves that he had not attained to any distinct conception of the difference be- tween the two ideas. Thus in the first section of his book he ac- cuses Adam Smith of erecting the labour, which a commodity will command, into a standard measure, instead of the labour bestowed on its production, the latter of which he asserts to be, " under many circumstances, an invariable standard, indicating correctly the variations of other things*." Farther on he speaks of es- timating food and necessaries " by the quantity of labour necssary for their production ; " con- trasting it with measuring them " by the quan- tity of labour for which they will e.vchange'\ T In the second section, after speaking of la- * Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, p. 5, 3d edition. t Ibid, p. 7- f'he Italics are Mr. Ricardo"s 174 DIFFEllEXCE BETWEEN hour as being the foundation of all value, he adopts in a note the language of Adam Smith, which designates labour as the real measure of the exchangeable value of all commodities*". In another chapter of his work he is still more explicit. " A franc," says he, " is not a measure of value for any thing, but for a quantity of the same metal of which francs are made, unless francs and the thing to be measured can be referred to some other measure, which is com- mon to both. This I think they can be, for they are both the result of labour ; and, there- fore, labour is a common measure, by which their real as well as their relative value may be estimated f." And to support this doctrine he cites a pas- sage from M. Destutt de Tracy, the scope of which is to show that labour is the cause of value. Surely nothing can more decisively prove a confusion of ideas on this point than adducing a passage, which asserts labour to be * Ibid., p. 13. t Ibid., p. 333. A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE. 175 the cause of value, in confirmation of a propo- sition that it is the measure of value. Mr. Malthus, who has himself fallen into the same confusion of ideas and terms, is suf- ficiently justified by these passages in attri- buting to Mr. Ricardo the act of bringing forward his principle as a measure. That Mr. Ricardo has more frequently spoken of it as a cause of value, only proves that he has deviated into inconsistencies. How the author of the Dialogues could be led to maintain, in the face of these passages, that " Mr. Ricardo never dreamed of offering it as a standard or measure of value," it is difficult to imagine. It will possibly be urged by the admirers of Mr. Ricardo, in order to defend him from the charge of inconsistency or ambiguity of lan- guage, that if quantity of labour is truly the sole cause of value, then it must also be a cor- rect measure or criterion of value ; and as one of these circumstances necessarily follows the other, it is indifferent in which capacity we speak of it. 176 DIFFERENCE BETWEEN It is certainly true, that, provided quantity of labour were the sole cause of value, we should always be able to deduce the value of two com- modities from a knowledge of the quantities of labour which they respectively required to pro- duce them; and in this sense, quantity of la- bour would be at once the cause and the mea- sure of value. But even under these circum- stances, an author would not be justified in an indiscriminate use of the terms ; nor could he fall into such an error, had he a distinct ap- prehension of the difference between the two ideas. It would by no means follow, however, from quantity of labour being the cause of value, that it would be of any service as a measure. On this point we may adopt the language of the author of the Dialogues : " If it had been proposed as a measure of value, we might justly demand that it should be ready and easy of application ; but it is manifestly not so ; for the quantity of labour employed in producing A, ' could not in many cases' (as Mr. Malthus A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE, 177 truly objects) ' be ascertained without con- siderable difficulty :' in most cases, indeed, it could not be ascertained at all. A measure of value, however, which cannot be practically applied, is worthless*." It was probably some obscure and undefined impression of this truth, which, when Mr. Ri- cardo deliberately set himself to treat on the subject of a measure of value, influenced him to speak, not of labour itself in that capacity, but of a commodity produced by an invariable quantity of labour. If the quantity of pro- ducing labour really determines the value of commodities, it seems on a first view useless to require for a measure an object of which the producing labour is invariable, when we may have recourse to the labour itself. But Mr. Ri- cardo probably perceived, that a knowledge of the quantity of producing labour in objects would be in most cases difficult of attainment, and therefore betook himself to the considera- * London Magazine for May, 1824, page 559. N ]78 A MEASURE AND A CAUSE OF VALUE. tion of a commodity in which a definite por- tion of it was embodied*. All that is really meant by a measure of value we have already seen, and what is im- plied by a cause of value will be examined in^ the following chapter. The object of the pre- ceding brief discussion is not to consider the nature of either, but merely to show the es- sential distinction between the ideas which they involve. * There was a further reason, namely, that the real object which he contemplated in a measure of value was to ascer- tain by it the changes whicli commodities might undergo in regard to the quantity of labour required to produce them. Now to use labour itself as a measure implies this object to be already accomplished. See Note 1. CHAPTER XI. ON THE CAUSES OF VALUE. It may seem, that an inquiry into tlie causes of value should have had an earlier place in the present treatise ; but it is in reality the natural method of proceeding to make ourselves ac- quainted with the nature of an effect, before we attempt to investigate its causes. Although, in point of time, a cause must precede its effect, yet in the order of our knowledge the case is commonly reversed, and we ascend from the phenomena before us to the active principles concerned in their production. Our first object in this investigation must be to ascertain what is really meant by a cause of value, or what is its true nature, that we may have some criterion which will show us, on the n2 180 ox THE CAUSES one hand, whether any circumstance assigned as a cause can be correctly admitted to rank un- der this denomination, and, on the other hand, whether any circumstance alleged to have no influence can be justly excluded. It was explained in the first chapter, that value, although spoken of as a quality ad- hering to external objects, or as a relation be- tween them, implies a feeling or state of mind, which manifests itself in the determination of the will. This feeling or state of mind may be the result of a variety of considerations con- nected with exchangeable commodities, and an inquiry into the causes of value is, in reality, an inquiry into those external circumstances, which operate so steadily upon the minds of men, in the interchange of the necessaries, comforts, and conveniences of life, as to be subjects of inference and calculation. These circum- stances may either act directly on the mind, as considerations immediately influencing its views, or they may operate indirectly, by only causing certain uniform considerations to be presented OF VALUE. 181 to it. In either case, if they are steady in their operation, they may be equally regarded as causes of value. We may often assign an ef- fect to a cause, when perhaps we are unable to trace the exact series of changes occurring be- tween them, or, in other words, the less pro- minent links in the chain of causes and effects by which they are separated in time, but con- nected in efficiency. In reference to the present subject, this may be easily illustrated. The equality in the cost of production of two ar- ticles, for example, is a cause of their exchanging for each other. This we know is the general effect of such circumstances ; but it would be difficult to trace with precision the mode in which the effect was produced, and which in- deed might vary on different occasions without disturbing the result. Suppose two persons, a and B, of whom the former has linen, which he wishes to exchange for woollen cloth, and the latter has woollen cloth, which he wishes to ex- chano^e for linen. The matter would be abun- dantly plain, if, besides knowing what his own 182 ON THE CAUSES article cost him, each had a knowledge of the producing cost of the article to be received in exchange. But it is likely enough that they do not possess this latter knowledge, and in this case the defect will be supplied by the compe- tition of the producers, which is itself governed by the cost of production ; and thus, although the two parties to the bargain may not be guided by a knowledge of what each article has cost to produce it, they are determined by considerations, of which the cost of production is the real origin. This is still more strikingly the case in other instances, A clergyman, who received his tithes in kind, and exchanged raw produce for cloth, might be ignorant of the cost of either, yet the terms of his bargain would be determined by the general cost of both. The cost would regulate the point at which the competition of the producers would fix each article, or their ordinary prices; and a knowledge of these prices would operate on his mind in the exchanges which he made. Whatever circumstances, therefore, act with OF VALUE. 183 assignable influence, whether mediately or im- mediately, on the mind in the interchange of commodities, may be considered as causes of value. Although, in the subsequent remarks, I may sometimes have to bring into view the mental operations implied in all cases of interchange, yet, to avoid prolixity, instead of speaking of cir- cumstances operating on the mind in regard to any commodity, I shall frequently speak of those circumstances as operating on the commodity itself. While this will save circumlocution, it will not, it is hoped, give rise to ambiguity, as such language will be employed with a tacit reference to the real nature of the occurrence which it is intended to designate. I have already had occasion to remark, that since value is a relation between two objects, it requires no proof that it cannot arise from causes affecting only one of the objects, but from two causes, or two sets of causes respec- tively operating upon the objects between whicli the relation exists. If a is equal in 184 ON THE CAUSES value to B, this must be owing, not only to causes operating on a, but also to causes ope- rating on B. In investigating the sources of value, however, it will be necessary to treat of these causes separately ; and it may not be useless to recollect, that although value must in every instance arise from the combination of two sets of causes, any alteration, any rise or fall of value, may proceed from only one. The value of A and b is the effect of causes acting on both, but a change in their mutual value may arise from causes acting on either : as the distance of two objects is to be referred to the circum- stances which have fixed both of them in their particular situation, while an alteration of the distance between them might originate in cir- cumstances acting on one alone. What then are the causes which determine the value of commodities, and an alteration in which is followed by a change in their rela- tions? Or, in other words, what are the causes which determine the quantities in which commo- dities are exchanged for each other ? OF VAlA't. 185 In order to answer this question, it will be necessary to attempt some classification of ex- changeable articles. Commodities, or things possessing value, maybe divided into three classes. 1. Commodities which are monopolized, or protected from competition by natural or ad- ventitious circumstances. 2. Commodities, in the production of which some persons possess greater facilities than the rest of the community, and which there- fore the competition of the latter cannot in- crease, except at a greater cost. 3. Commodities, in the production of which competition operates without restraint. A cursory attention to these classes will at once show, that their respective causes of value cannot be the same. Let us therefore take them in detail, and examine the causes operating on each class. ] . Monopolies may be divided into two kinds ; those in which there is only one interest con- 18(3 ON THE CAUSES cerned, and those in which there are separate interests. In the first case, "the competition," (as Mr. Ricardo justly remarks) " is wholly on one side — amongst the buyers. The monopoly price," he continues, " of one period, may be much lower or higher than the monopoly price of another, because the competition amongst the purchasers must depend on their wealth, and their tastes and caprices. Those peculiar wines which are produced in very limited quantity, and those works of art, which from their ex- cellence or rarity have acquired a fanciful value, will be exchanged for a very different quantity of the produce of ordinary labour, according as the society is rich or poor, as it possesses abun- dance or scarcity of sucll produce, or as it may be in a rude or polished state '^'." The second kind of monopoly differs from * Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, p. 290, thiril edition OF VALUE. 187 the first in the obvious circumstance, that there may be a competition amongst the sellers as well as amongst the buyers. Where there is only one interest concerned in the monopoly, it may be to the advantage of the party to withhold his article from the market in times of dull demand, or even to destroy a part of it to enhance the value of the remainder ; a policy which is said to have been pursued by the Dutch in the spice trade. But when a monopoly is in the hands of different individuals, with separate interests, such a line of policy is impracticable : for al- though it might be to the advantage of the whole body if the quantity of the monopolized ar- ticle were proportionately reduced to each holder, yet as, by the supposition, there is no combination of interest, every individual finds it beneficial to dispose of all that he possesses. To destroy any part of it, would be to injure himself for the benefit of his brother monopo- lists. While on the one hand he is fenced in by an exclusive privilege or possession from the competition of the public, he is on the other 188 ON THE CAUSES hand compelled by his own interest to bring to market the whole of his supply, and he is obliged by the same principle to produce the greatest supply in his power, so long as the average price pays him a higher profit than the ordinary employment of capital. It deserves to be remarked, that all commodities, which re- quire any considerable period of time for their production, are liable to be occasionally forced into the class of articles owing their value to this second kind of monopoly, by a sudden alteration in the relative state of the demand and supply. Hence arises w^hat is called by political economists market value. Should the relative demand for any of these commodities increase, as it could not, according to the sup- position, be immediately answered by a cor- respondent supply, the possessors of the com- modities would enjoy a temporary monopoly ; for a while they would be protected from com- petition by the impossibility of producing a fur- ther quantity. On the contrary, should the relative demand OF VALUE. 189 decrease, the possessors of the commodities would be exposed to the necessity of bringing them to market at a reduced rate, especially if they were commodities of which the supply could be neither immediately stopped, nor ad- justed to the new state of the demand. The holders, in this case, would be exposed to all the disadvantages incident to a monopoly in which there were separate interests. The com- petition amongst themselves would force the whole of their supply into the market. Occurrences of this kind must not be con- sidered as rare or unimportant. Mr. Tooke, in his recent valuable work " on the High and Low Prices of the Thirty Years, from 1793 to 1822," has most strikingly shown the fre- quency and extent of excesses and defi- ciences in the supply of corn, as well as the momentous effects which they occasion. These effects are all referable to the principle of a temporary monopoly. Foreign supplies being put out of the question, the holders of corn have obviously a monopoly of the article till 190 ON THE CAUSES the ensuing harvest ; and as it is an article wliich cannot be dispensed with, should the supply be less than usually required, the price may rise to an almost indefinite height. If, on the con- trary, the supply should exceed the ordinary demand, which from the nature of the com- modity admits of little augmentation, the holders suffer the disadvantages before de- scribed ; the interest of each lies in the dis- posal of as large a quantity as possible, and the competition thus engendered infallibly brings down the value. The larger quantity may in this way become of less aggregate value than the smaller quantity at the previous high prices. Were the commodity in the hands of an individual, or, what is the same thing, in- dividuals combined by one interest, this is a circumstance which could never occur. Labour must be considered as falling under this class of exchangeable commodities, and as being determined in value by the same causes which operate on articles monopolized in the second method here described. If a man em- OF VALUE. 191 ploy his capital in production, lie must pur- chase labour, and the demand for labourers will therefore be in proportion to the capital destined for this purpose. But there are only a certain number of labourers in existence ; these cannot for the time be either purposely increased or diminished, and they consequently possess a monopoly of their peculiar commo- dity. The greater the demand, therefore, for their labour, the higher it will rise, exactly as other monopolized commodities in the same circumstances. This monopoly, too, is at- tended with the disadvantao^es common to all monopolies in the hands of conflicting interests. Under all circumstances the labourers must live, and must therefore sell their labour ; and should the demand for it decrease, as they cannot purposely diminish or keep back their numbers, competition will soon reduce the value of their labour. Besides the general monopoly which the la- bourers naturally possess, and which may be advantageous or disadvantageous, according to 192 ox THE CAUSES circumstances, there are divers subordinate monopolies, occasioning labour to be paid after different rates. In trades, which require application for a greater or smaller period be- fore they are learned, the workmen are evi- dently protected from immediate competition ; and should there be an increase in the de- mand for their work, their labour would rise in value, and remain enhanced till more ar- tizans possessed of their peculiar skill had been formed. It scarcely needs to be mentioned, in this place, that although labourers cannot be pur- posely augmented or reduced in number by the application of capital, or its diversion into different channels, like material commodities, yet they may be augmented or reduced in another way. The high value of labour, com- pared with commodities in general, enabling the labourers to live in abundance, marriages are en- couraged, or at least more children are reared, and population is increased ; so that, after the lapse of a certain interval, the same effect is pro- OF VALUE. 193 duced as if men could be purposely created. On the other hand, a material fall in the value of labour operates to check population by the pe- nury and hardship which it spreads among the labouring classes; and the supply of labour becomes eventually adjusted to the demand by disease and death. 2. The second class of commodities em- braces articles of more importance (with the exception of labour) than that which we have just considered. When a commodity is of a kind which admits of being increased by in- dustry and competition, but only at a greater cost, the possessor of the cheaper means of producing it has evidently a monopoly to a certain extent, and the value of the commodity will depend on the principles already explained, until it reach such a height as will afford the ordinary profit to those who produce it at a greater expense. The same causes will be in operation, but instead of the value of the ar- ticle having no assignable boundary, it will be limited by the watchful competition, which is 194 ON THE CAUSES ever ready to act upon it the moment it has exceeded a particular point. Under this head we may class the important articles of corn, raw produce in general, metals, coals, and several others. As one commodity, however, will elucidate the rest, we may con- fine our observations to the first. The value of that corn which is produced on lands paying rent, is not, it is acknow- ledged, in proportion either to the capital or to the labour actually expended in its production. It must be owing, therefore, to some other cause ; and the only other cause is the state of the supply and demand, or the competition of the purchasers. This competition might raise the price to an indefinite height, if it were not for the existence of other lands, which although they could produce corn only at a greater cost, would be brought into cultivation as soon as the price had risen sufficiently high to pay the ordinary profits on the capital required. It is, therefore, the possibility of producing corn, or the actual production of it, at a greater OF VALUE. 195 cost, which forms the limit to its value. But although this is the limit beyond which its value cannot rise, it cannot be said to be the cause of its value. It is the cause of its being no higher, not the cause of its being so high. A perforation in the side of a vessel, at any dis- tance from the bottom, would effectually pre- vent its being filled to a greater height with water, but it would be no cause of the water attaining that height. At the utmost it could be considered as only a joint cause of the result. We accordingly find that the expression used by Mr. Ricardo on this subject is, not that the value of corn is caused, but that it is regulated by the cost of production on the least fertile lands. The owners of land of superior fer- tility enjoy a monopoly, which, however, does not enable them to raise their commodity in definitely, according to the varying wants and caprices of mankind, but which is bounded by the existence of inferior soils. It is simply out of this monopoly-value that rent arises. Rent proceeds, in fact, from the o 2 196 ON THE CAUSES extraordinary profit which is obtained by the possession of an instrument of production, pro- tected up to a certain point from competition. If the owner of this instrument, instead of using it himself, lets it out to another, he re- ceives from him this surplus of profit under the denomination of rent. In this view of the subject, the extraordinary profit might exist, al- though the land in cultivation were all of the same quality ; nay, must exist before inferior land was cultivated ; for it could be only in consequence of extraordinary gains obtained by the monopolizers of the best land, that ca- pital and labour would be expended on soils of a subordinate order. Rent, therefore, might ex- ist, while all the land under cultivation was of equal fertility. Perhaps it might not exist under these circumstances during any long period, but its existence at all would prove that it was the effect of monopoly, an extra- ordinary profit, and not the consequence of the cultivation of inferior soils. The extraordinary profit out of which rent OF VALUE. 197 arises, is analogous to the extraordinary remu- neration which an artizan of more than common dexterity obtains beyond the wages given to workmen of ordinary skill. In so far as com- petition cannot reach them, the owner of the rich soil and the possessor of the extraordinary skill obtain a monopoly price. In the one case this monopoly is bounded by the existence of inferior soils, in the other of inferior degrees of dexterity. It has been made a question, whether rent forms a component part of the price or value of produce. *' Rent," says Mr. Ricardo, ** does not and cannot enter in the least degree as a component part of its price." The expression is in reality figurative, and the only meaning of the assertion, that rent is a component part of price, must be, that it is one of the causes of the value of produce. But we have just seen that rent is a consequence of the extraor- dinary value of a monopolized commodity, and it cannot therefore be one of the causes of its value. Although not the cause of the value of 198 ON THE CAUSES corn or other produce, rent must be an accurate representation of the additional value conse- quent on the monopoly of the land on which the corn is grown : therefore, if one part of the price of corn, from any particular land, is con- sidered as representing' the share of the la- bourer, another the share of the capitalist, the remainder, if any, will be representative of the rent ; and it is probably this consideration which has led economists to speak of it as a component part of price. In whatever way the expression is used, it is at the best vague and indefinite, and ought to be banished from a science, which owes half its difficulties to the laxity and ambiguity of language, 3. The third class of commodities, those which can be increased by industry, and on which competition acts without restraint, are the next to claim our consideration. The value of these commodities owes no- thing to monopoly ; what then are the causes which determine the quantities in which they are exchanged for each other ? OF VALUE. 199 There is, perhaps, at the bottom, little actual diflference amongst economists as to these causes, but they do not agree either in their methods of explanation, or in the language they employ. It has been shown, that the im- mediate causes of value are the considerations which act on the minds of human beinsrs, and that the circumstances, which form or furnish these considerations, must be the causes into which the economist has to inquire. Our pre- sent object, therefore, is to find those circum- stances which act upon the mind with certainty and precision, in the interchange of commodities of the class under our notice. A moments reflection on the subject will suffice to discover, that the principal of these circumstances must be the cost of production. No man, who bestows his time and attention on the production of a commodity, will continue to produce it for the purpose of exchanging it against another commodity, which he knows costs less to the producer than his own : and, on the other hand, every producer will be willing 200 ON THE CAUSES to sell as large a quantity of his commodity as he can dispose of at the same price as his fel- low producers. It is not, indeed, disputed, that the main cir- cumstance, which determines the quantities in which articles of this class are exchanged, is the cost of production ; but our best economists do not exactly agree on the meaning to be at- tached to this term ; some contending that the quantity of labour expended on the produc- tion of an article constitutes its cost; others, that the capital employed upon it is entitled to that appellation. Let us look at the state of the facts. If a man exchanges an article which he has produced by a day's labour, for another article, also the produce of a day's labour, it is plain that the cost of production is the labour bestowed. If another man expends £100 in producing a quantity of cloth, that is, in the purchase of materials as well as in the wages of labour, and exchanges it for a quantity of linen which has cost his neighbour £100, the cost of production is the capital employed. OF VALUE. ' 201 Cost of production may be, therefore, either a quantity of labour or a quantity of capital. What the labourer produces without capital, costs him his labour ; what the capitalist pro- duces costs him his capital. Such appears to be the simplest view of the subject ; but it is contended, that as the value of the capital itself has been caused by labour, it is more accurate to say, that cost of produc- tion consists in the quantity of labour. It must be recollected, however, that we are inquirino- into the circumstances which determine men to give a certain quantity of one commodity for a certain quantity of another ; and what really acts upon the minds of two capitalists in exchanging their respective goods, is not the labour which in a thousand different ways has been expended upon the articles constitutino- the capital employed, but the amount of capital which they have parted with, in order to ob- tain the commodity produced. So that granting for the present that the value of capital may be resolved (to use the common language on this 202 ON THE CAUSES subject) into a previous quantity of labour, it would still be a correct statement of facts to say, that tlie cost of production consists in the quantity of capital expended : or to lay aside the term cost of production altogether, that the amount of capital expended is the cause which determines the value of the commodity pro- duced. It is impossible, under this view of the sub- ject, to agree with the following passage in Mr. Mill's Elements of Political Economy. ** To say, indeed, that the value of commo- dities depends upon capital as the final stan- dard, implies one of the most obvious of all absurdities. Capital is commodities. If the value of commodities, then, depends upon the value of capital, it depends upon the value of commodities ; the value of commodities depends upon itself. This is not to point out a standard of value. It is to make an attempt for that purpose clearly and completely abortive'^." * Elements of Political Economy, p. 94, 2(1 edition. OF VALUE. 203 This passage, which seems to have a tacit reference to the speculations of Col. Torrens, appears to me to show the power of words over the clearest and strongest minds. By the potent magic of a term, the value of commo- dities is first made something single and indi- vidual ; and then it follows of course, that an individual thing cannot depend upon itself as a cause. But this is not asserted by those who contend that capital causes or determines value. The value of commodities may not be capable of depending on itself, but the value of one commodity, which is one thing, may very easily depend on that of another, which is a different thing ; and if it did not in point of fact, there would be no logical absurdity in asserting it. He who maintains that the mutual value of two commodities is chiefly determined by the com- parative quantity of capital expended in their production, undoubtedly maintains that it is de- termined by the value of preceding commodities; and this is quite consistent with the value of those preceding commodities having been de- 204 ON THE CAUSES termined by their comparative quantities of pro- ducing labour, or by any other cause. The latter would be a step further back in the se- quence of causes and effects. There can be nothing absurd in assigning one thing as the proximate cause of an effect, merely because it is possible that another may be assigned as its remote cause. Mr. Mill's language, too, is unusually lax. He confounds the standard with the cause of value. The proposition, that the values of com- modities are determined by the capitals ex- pended in producing them, affirms a cause, but certainly does not point out any standard of value ; nor would Mr. Mill's own doctrine fur- nish such an auxiliary. A standard, whatever meaning it may have in this connection, must at all events be something clearly defined and easily accessible; and if Mr. Mill purposes to set up the quantity of labour in a commodity from first to last, through all its various meta- morphoses, in that capacity, it will be one seldom within his reach. In reality, however, OF VALUE. 205 the preceding part of his section is occupied in proving labour to be the cause of value ; and it is only at the conclusion that he deviates into this laxity of expression*. It appears, therefore, that if we do not aim at undue generalization, but are content with a simple statement of facts, the value of objects, in the production of which competition operates without restraint, may be correctly stated to arise principally from the cost of production ; and that cost of production may be either la- bour or capital, or both. Whatever the mere labourer produces costs him his labour: if a man is a capitalist as well as a labourer, what * In the second edition of his Elements, Mr. Mill himself, in the section succeeding that containing the passage here animadverted upon, has distinctly pointed out the diflFerence between what he calls " the regulator," and the measure of value, and has mentioned two circumstances which, he says, render it impossible that the former should be era- ployed in the latter capacity. It is therefore surprising that he should have retained a passage, which confounds what he has subsequently taken express pains to distin- guish. 206 ON THE CAUSES he produces costs him both : if he is only a capitalist, it costs him only capital. In a civi- lized country instances of each kind may be found, but the mass of commodities are de- termined in value by the capital expended upon them. The amount of capital is thus the chief, but by no means the sole cause of value. Other circumstances vs^hich have a regular influence, cannot v^ith any propriety be excluded. The discredit, the danger, the disagreeableness of any method of employing capital, all tend, as vs^ell as pecuniary expenditure, to enhance the value of the product. The time, too, which a commodity requires before it can be brought to market, is another circumstance affecting va- lue, and frequently to a considerable extent. It would be an extraordinary phenomenon, in- deed, if, in the interchange of commodities, the minds of men should be influenced by one ex- clusive consideration: if, imbued as thev are with feelings of shame, and fear, and impa- tience, and others not necessary to enumerate, OF VALUE. 207 these passions should leave no regular traces of their operation in the daily business of produc- tion and exchanofe. I have hitherto been contending, that even if capital could be resolved into previous labour, it would still be a correct statement of facts to say, that the value of commodities is chiefly determined by the capital expended upon them. It is an interesting inquiry, however, how far this doctrine, which we have taken for granted, is true, and I shall therefore proceed to ex- amine its claims to be received in that cha- racter. It is manifest that if the unqualified doctrine, as laid down by some writers, were correct, the value of any commodity would be strictly re- presentative of the quantity of labour expended on its production from first to last. " If," as Mr. Mill expresses it, " quantity of labour in the last resort, determines the proportion in which commodities exchange for one another * ; " * Elements of Political Economy, p. 94, 2d edition. 208 ON THE CAUSES or, as it is stated by the author of the Tem- plars' Dialogues, " commodities are to each other in value as the quantities of labour em- ployed in their production*;" or, as it is laid down by Mr. M^Culloch, '^ the exchangeable value, or relative vy^orth of commodities, as compared with each other, depends exclusively on the quantities of labour necessarily required to produce themf;" then it follows, that any two commodities, which at any time exchange for each other (putting aside all fluctuations of market value), must have been produced by exactly the same quantity of labour. If a quarter of wheat is exchanged for a piece of linen, these two commodities must have re- quired the same labour to bring them to the condition in which they are exchanged:}:. * Dialogue 1, passim. t A Discourse on the Science of Political Economy, p. 66. X This is stated in the strongest conceivable terms by the second-mentioned writer. " No cause can possibly aflfect the value of any thing, i. e. its exchangeable relation to OF VALUE. 209 Now this cannot be true if we can find any instances of the following nature : 1. Cases in which two commodities have been produced by an equal quantity of labour, and yet sell for different quantities of money. 2. Cases in which two commodities, once equal in value, have become unequal in value, without any change in the quantity of labour respectively employed in each"*^. Cases of the first kind are exceedingly nu- merous. Every one at all acquainted with ma- nufactures must know, that there are in the same, as well as in different occupations, va- rious degrees of skill and rapidity of execution other thing's, but an increase or diminution of the quantity of labour required for its production : and the prices of all things whatsoever represent the quantity of labour by which they are severally produced ; and the value of a is to the value of B universally as the quantity of labour which pro- duces A to the quantity of labour which produces b." — London Magazine, April 1824, p. 352. * This last case is resolvable into the first, but the sub- ject will be better illustrated by keeping them distinct. P 210 ON THE CAU.SES amongst artizans, various kinds and gradations of talent and acquirement, which enable some of them to earn double the money obtained by their less fortunate compeers in the same time. There are also circumstances of insalubrity, or disagreeableness, or danger, which affect the pecuniary recompense. The value of the ar- ticles produced by these various classes of workmen, and under these various circum- stances, bears no proportion to the mere quan- tity of labour expended. It is no answer to this to say, with Mr. Ricardo, that " the esti- mation in which different qualities of labour are held, comes soon to be adjusted in the market with sufficient precision for all practical purposes;" or with Mr. Mill, that " in esti- mating .equal quantities of labour, an allow- ance would, of course, be included for different degrees of hardness and skill." Instances of this kind entirely destroy the integrity of the rule. Difference of skill is a circumstance which practically affects value, as well as dif- ference in quantity of labour, and therefore the OF VALUE, 211 latter cannot, with any propriety, be said to be the sole cause of value. What should we think of an assertion, that coats are to each other in value as the quanti- ties of cloth contained in them, or that their com- parative value depends exclusively on the quan- tities of cloth required to make them ? And if it were added, that due allowances must be made for the different qualities of the cloth, where would be the truth or the utility of the first mathematically strict position ? The pro- position would, in fact, be reduced to its nega- tive, that coats are not to each other in value as the quantities of cloth contained in them. In Mr. Ricardo's language on the subject of the different qualities of labour, there is some inconsistency and much indistinctness. The second section of his first chapter is headed, " Labour of different qualities differently re- warded. This no cause of variation in the re- lative value of commodities." By this it is to be presumed he means, not what the words really imply, that the different compensation p 2 212 ON THE CAUSES given to labour of different qualities does not originally affect the value of commodities, but that when the influence of this cause is once adjusted, it subsequently occasions no variation in value. In the body of the section, however, he softens this expression into " inconsiderable variation." '' We may fairly conclude," says he, *' that whatever inequality there might ori- ginally have been in them, whatever the in- genuity, skill, or time necessary for the ac- quirement of one species of manual dexterity more than another, it continues nearly the same from one generation to another ; or at least that the variation is very inconsiderable from year to year, and therefore can have little effect for short periods, on the relative value of commo- dities." It is, ?iowever, a mere assumption, that " the scale, when once formed, is liable to little va- riation ; " nor, if this could be established, would it furnish any aid to the doctrine which we have at present under consideration. If the dif- ferences of skill in different employments are so OF VALUE. 213 little variable as here represented, it proves only that they are circumstances which perma- nently affect value, and that it must be alto- gether incorrect to designate quantity of labour the sole cause, when quality of labour is so steady in its effects. This cause of value is, in fact, on precisely the same footing as any other. A variation in it, small or great, would occasion a corresponding variation in the value of the article on which the labour was em- ployed ; and however inconsiderable its effects may be, they cannot be consistently either denied or overlooked. The whole of the sec- tion appears to have been dictated by a lurking impatience of any thing which seemed to break into the beautiful simplicity of the iiile, that value is determined by quantity of labour. Else why not freely allow the exceptions wherever they occur, and qualify the expression of the general rule accordingly*?" * The only place in Mr. Ricardo's work, where I have been able to find the expression of the general rule pro- 214 ON THE CAUSES But the most singular circumstance in this section is, that it unsettles all our notions re- specting quantity of labour itself. The grand principle of Mr. Ricardo's work, which seemed as precise and definite as it could be, the doc- trine that quantity of labour is the cause of value, which appeared to be fast anchored in the understanding, is unloosed from its moor- ings. We are here told of " the difficulty of comparing an hour's or a day's labour in one employment with the same duration of labour in another." The language of Adam Smith is quoted, to show ^' that it is often difficult to ascertain the proportion between two different quantities of labour. The time spent in two different sorts of work will not always determine this proportion." If this be true, then quantity of labour has no determinate criterion, and Mr. Ricardo has perly qualified, is the Index He there says, '* the quan- tity of labour requisite to obtain commodities the principal source of their exchangeable value." OF VALUE. 215 proposed, not only as the cause but the measure of value, that which is itself ,unascertainable. There are only two possible methods of com- paring one quantity of labour with another ; one is to compare them by the time expended, the other by the result produced. The former is applicable to all kinds of {abour; the latter can be used only in comparing labour bestowed on similar articles. If therefore, in estimating two different sorts of work, the time spent will not determine the proportion between the quantities of labour, it must remain undeter- mined and undeterminable. 2. We are furnished with cases of the second kind (namely, those in which two commodities, once equal in value, have become unequal in value without any change in the quantity of la- bour respectively employed in aech) by Mr. Ri- cardo himself. Take any two commodities of equal value, A and B, one produced by fixed capital and the other by labour, without the intervention of ma- chinery ; and suppose, that without any chano-e 216 ox THE CAUSES whatever in the fixed capital or the quantity of labour, there should happen to be a rise in the value of labour; according to Mr. Ricardo's own showing, a and B would be instantly al- tered in their relation to each other ; that is, they would become unequal in value. At the former period being equal in value, they must, according to the doctrine under consideration, have been the products directly or indirectly of equal quantities of labour ; but if at the latter period their values were taken as repre- sentative of the relative quantity of labour ex- pended on each, the result obtained would be, that they were the products of unequal quantities of labour. The doctrine, therefore, that the values of commodities are representative of the respective quantities of labour required for their production, which is a direct corollary from the proposition that commodities are to each other in value as is their producing labour in quantity, cannot possibly be true. This again, it may be said, is allowed by Mr. Ricardo and his followers-, but if they OF VALUE. 217 allow it, why persist in calling quantity of la- bour the sole determining principle of value ? Why attempt to give the science an air of sim- plicity which it does not possess ? To these cases we may add the effect of time on value. If a commodity take more time than another for its production, although no more capital and labour, its value will be greater. The influence of this cause is admitted by Mr. Ricardo, but Mr. Mill contends, that time can do nothing; " how then," he asks, *' can it add to value?'' "Time," he continues, ^-'is a mere abstract term. It is a word, a sound. And it is the very same logical absurdity to talk of an abstract unit measuring value, and of time creating it*." The alleged absurdity, however, will disap- pear, if we recur for a moment to the mental operation implied in every creation of value. The time necessary to produce a commodity, * Elements of Pol. Econ. p. 99, 2d edition. The cre- dit of this argument, however, is due to Mr. M'Culloch, whose authority is cited by Mr. Mill. 218 ON THE CAUSES may, equally with the requisite quantity of la- bour, be a consideration which influences the mind in the interchange of useful or agreeable articles. We generally prefer a present pleasure or enjoyment to a distant one, not superior to it in other respects. We are willing, even at some sacrifice of property, to possess ourselves of what would otherwise require time to pro- cure it, without waiting during the operation ; as of what would require labour, without personally bestowing the labour. If any arti- cle were offered to us, not otherwise attainable, except after the expiration of a year, we should be willing to give something to enter upon pre- sent enjoyment. On the part of the capitalist, who produces and prepares these articles, the time required for the purpose is evidently a consideration which acts upon his mind. If the article is wine, he knows that the quality is im- proved by keeping; he is aware that the same excellence cannot be imparted to any wine, without the employment of capital for an equal period ; and that people will be found to give OF VALUE. 219 him the usual compensation rather than employ their own capitals in producing a similar re- sult. Thus time is really a consideration which may influence both buyers and sellers; nor is it necessary here to enter into any metaphysical inquiry into its nature in order to prove its effects. The author of the Elements of Political Economy has made a curious attempt to re- solve the effects of time into expenditure of la- bour. " If," says he, '' the wine which is put in the cellar is increased in value one tenth by being kept a year, one tenth more of labour may be correctly considered as having been expended upon it*." Now if any one proposition can be affirmed without dispute, it is this, that a fact can be correctly considered as having taken place only when it really has taken place. In the instance adduced, no human being, by the terms of the supposition, has approached the wine, or spent upon it a moment or a single motion of his * Elements, p. 97, 2d edition. 220 ON THE CAUSES muscles. As therefore no labour has been really exercised in any way relating to the wine, a tenth more of labour cannot be correctly con- sidered as having been expended upon it, un- less that can be truly regarded as having oc- curred which never happened. Doctrines of this kind, which attempt to re- duce all phenomena to a uniform expression, ought to be rigidly scrutinized. In the present instance, the eminent writer just quoted ap- pears to have been seduced by a preceding false generalization, that, namely, which designates capital as accumulated or hoarded labour. This is at best an aukward mode of expression, which can answer no good purpose. When we accu- mulate we add one thing to another, and it is essential to the process, that both should re- main in existence. But labour, consisting in the mere exertion of muscular power, or in the equally evanescent motions of the brain, con- tinually perishes in detail, and therefore admits of no accumulation. It may be alleged, ne- vertheless, that when a series of days' labour OF VALUE. 221 has been bestowed on any article, we may fairly say that there has been an accumulation of labour ; one day's labour has been added to another day's labour till they have amounted to a given number, suppose, for example, a hun- dred. The only accumulation here, however, is not an actual but an arithmetical one, and admitting the accuracy of the expression in this sense, it amounts to this, that a hundred days' labour is an accumulation of labour, not that the article produced is accumulated labour. The article produced is the result of labour, not labour itself. To designate capital or commo- dities by the term accumulated labour is to call the effect an accumulation of the cause. In a rhetorical declamation, in the com- pressed and vigorous eloquence of a great mind disclosing its own comprehensive views by a few master strokes of expression, such an iden- tification of cause and effect is often a positive beauty. The " Knowledge is power" of Lord Bacon, is felicitous and forcible: but in philo- sophical discussion, phrases of this kind as 222 ON THE CAUSES grounds of reasoning, or as' correct expressions of fact, mislead the mind intent on the pursuit of truth ; and I have no fear, that to those who are adequately aware of the importance of words in all moral and political researches, the objection, which I have urged to the language under consideration, will either appear frivolous or unfounded. In this attempt to show that the value of ca- pital cannot be traced entirely to the quantity of producing labour, I have taken into view those commodities only, the production of which is perfectly free to competition : and so far as we have proceeded, the strictures, which I have ventured to offer, apply rather to the manner in which the doctrine is asserted than to any thing actually maintained by its supporters. But the great defect of this theory is, its overlooking the important fact, that capital consists, not only of commodities of this class, but also of the commodities belonging to the other two classes of our enumeration. To assert, that the value of capital may be resolved into quantity of la- OF VALUE. 223 hour, is to lose sight both of the modifications generally admitted, and, what is of far greater moment, of causes which extend themselves in every direction through the mass of exchange- able products. It must be recollected, that although we have arranged commodities under three divisions, yet they are all, not only promiscuously ex- changed for each other, but blended in pro- duction. A commodity, therefore, may owe part of its value to monopoly, and part to those causes which determine the value of unmono- polized products. An article, for instance, may be manufactured amidst the freest competition out of a raw material, which a complete mono- poly enables its producer to sell at six times the actual cost ; and the quantity of the raw mate- rial necessary might be so proportioned to the quantity of labour required to work it up, that they would equally contribute to the value of the finished fabric. In this case it is obvious, that although the value of the article might be 224 ON Tin: CAUSES correctly said to. be determined by the quantity of capital expended upon it by the manufac- turer, yet no analysis could possibly resolve the value of the capital into quantity of labour. Nor must it be supposed that is this a case of rare occurrence. In scarcely any instance could the value of capital be traced to the quantity of labour as its only source, liable as every process of production is to the intrusion of articles de- riving their value from other causes. Hence for those economists, v^ho object to the doctrine of the value of commodities being chiefly determined by the quantity of capital expended in their production, that it does not satisfy the whole of the inquiry, since they want to know what has determined the value of the capital, the answer is easy. The value of the capital was probably determined by the value of pre- ceding capital, which was in its turn deter- mined by preceding capital in the same manner. Does any one ask, what determined the value of the first of these capitals, trace them as far OF VALUE. 225 back as we will ? I answer, perhaps monopoly, perhaps the quantity of labour, or perhaps the value of labour ; or possibly some combination of these. Let us take, for example, a piece of linen. The value of this has been proximately deter- mined by the capital expended in its manufac- ture. The capital expended consisted, we will suppose, of food for the workmen and flax as the material. We have then to inquire what has caused the value of the food and the flax ; and we mio^ht find it to be owins; to the labour expended in raising it, or more probably to a monopoly possessed by the owners of land. In the former case it may be urged, the value of the capital is ultimately resolvable into the quantity of producing labour; and not the less so in the latter, since the value of the produce grown on superior soils is determined by the value of that grown on lands not coming mider any description of monopoly, or in other words paying no rent. But it does not follow in the first case, that the value of the produce should Q 226 ON THE CAUSES have been determined by the mere quantity of labour : it may have been affected by the value of that labour, since the skill of those con- cerned in raising it may have been better paid than in other employments, or have done the work with half the usual number of hands, or there may be some peculiarity of hardship, aris- ing from the nature of the employment itself. In the second case, if the value of produce from a superior soil is regulated by the quantity of labour necessary to raise the same kind on inferior soils, it is not determined by the labour actually employed in raising such produce, and therefore the value of the produce is not resolv- able into quantity of labour. Hence it appears, that the value of capital may possibly be traced to quantity of labour as its origin, but it is not necessarily traceable to it; and we therefore could not pronounce, that because a and b are equal in value, these two articles have been either directly or indi- rectly the products of equal quantities of la- bour, although no other circumstance existed OF VALUE. 227 to render such a conclusion erroneous. If two samples of corn of equal quality, but from different soils, were submitted to us, and we were told that their prices were equal, we could not pronounce with any certainty that they were the results of equal labour. One might have been produced by a fourth part of the labour required for the other, and yet they are of the same value. If gold and corn, or cloth and corn, were compared in the same way, there would be a similar impossibility of telling that portions of these commodities of equal value had been produced by equal quantities of labour. We shall now be prepared to take a general survey of Mr. Ricardo's doctrine on the subject of the causes of value, and estimate it at its real worth. He commences by stating, that '* commodities derive their exchangeable value from two sources : from their scarcity, and from the quantity of labour required to obtain them.' Articles of the first kind he regards as compa- ratively unimportant, and therefore professes to q2 228 ON THE CAUSES restrict his inquiries to " such commodities only as can be increased in quantity by the exertion of human industry, and on the production of which competition operates without restraint." Instead, however, of confining himself to these commodities, he enters into the consideration of the value of labour, of corn, of gold, and of other articles, in the production of which competition certainly does not operate without restraint ; but which he is obliged to bring un- der that head, from the imperfect classification with which he sets out. According to his own division, the value of these things should be determined by the quantity of labour necessary to produce them: but of none of them can this be asserted ; for the value of labour can in no sense be said to be determined by the quan- tity of labour necessary to produce it : the value of corn in general is determined, on his own principles, by the quantity of labour required to raise corn on the worst soils in cultivation, and not by the quantity of its own producing labour; and in the same way the OF VALUE. 229 value of gold itself depends, not on the la- bour necessary to produce every individual portion of it, but on the labour necessary to extract it from the least fertile mines that are worked. Mr. Ricardo did not, evidently, allow suf- ficient importance to that source of value which he calls scarcity; nor did he consistently bear in mind, that it was the very same principle which enabled the owner of land, or of mines, of more than common fertility, to raise the value of their articles beyond what would afford the customary profit. Instead of scarcity, or, in other words, monopoly, or protection from competition, bemg ah unimportant source of value, and the commodities which owe their value to it forming a very small part of the mass of commodities daily exchanged in the market, we have seen that it is a most extensive source of value, and that the value of many of the most important articles of interchange must be referred to this as its origin. With regard to the causes of the value of 230 ON THE CAUSES these commodities, which are left in every way perfectly free to competition, the practical truth inculcated by Mr. Ricardo is this, that if the quantity of labour necessary for the production of a commodity is increased or decreased, it rises or falls in value in relation to other com- modities, of which the quantity of producing labour is not altered. This, however, is a truth not dependent on the quantity of labour being the sole cause of value, but on its being one of the causes. The same is true of every other cause of value. Any effect is necessarily in- creased if we increase any of its causes. Mr. Ricardo, indeed, explicitly allows the influence of other causes; such as time, differ- ences in the proportion of fixed and circulating capital, and inequalities in the durability of capital, by which he admits the value of com- modities is liable to be affected. Notwithstand- ing these modifications, however, his followers continue to lay down the position of quantity of labour being the sole cause of value in the most precise and positive terms ; not that they OF VALUE. 231 deny the exceptions, but they appear to lose sight of their existence, and frequently fall into language incompatible with their admission ; while they altogether overlook the source of value to be found in partial or incomplete mo- nopolies, and the intermixture in production of commodities which are indebted for their value to different causes. On a review of the subject it appears, that economists attempt too much. They wish to resolve all the causes of value into one, and thus reduce the science to a simplicity of which it will not adn:iit. They overlook the variety of considerations operating on the mind in the interchange of commodities. These considera- tions are the causes of value, and the attempt to proportion the quantities in which commo- dities are exchanged for each other to the degree in which one of these considerations exists, must be vain and ineffectual. All in reality that can be accomplished on this subject is to ascertain the various causes of value ; and when this is done, we may always infer, from 232 ON THE CAUSES OF VALUE. an increase or diminution of any of them, an increase or diminution of the effect. If Mr. Ricardo, as his admirers allege, has really enriched the science of political economy with any new and important truths (a point which this is not the place to decide), we may safely pronounce that they are not inferences from the doctrine, that the quantity of labour employed in the production of commodities is the sole determining principle of their value. It may be affirmed, without any hazard of error, that there is not one of them, whatever they may be, which would not equally flow from the more accurate proposition, that it is the principal cause. A false simplification in matters of fact can be of no service, and can only tend to per- plex the mind of the inquirer by those perver- sions of language, those distortions of expres- sion, and those circuitous expedients of logical ingenuity, which it unavoidably engenders. NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. NOTE A {page 38). Mr. Ricardo introduces his notion of real value in a somewhat obscure and indirect manner. He gives us no formal preliminary definition or explana- tion of the terra, and had not perhaps, at the outset, de- fined it clearly in his own mind, although the idea seems to have mingled itself with all his speculations. In the opening of his book, the only kinds of value which he points out are value in use and value in exchange, as dis- tinguished by Adam Smith ; the latter of which is defined to be the power of purchasing. At the third page, neverthe- less, we find another kind of value introduced, without comment or explanation, in an extract from the Wealth of Nations. " The real price of every thing, what every thing really costs to the man who wants to acquire it, is the toil and trouble of acquiring it. What every thing is reallj/ worth to the man who has acquired it, and who wants to dispose of it, or exchange it for something else, is the toil and trouble which it can save to himself, and which it can impose upon other people." 234 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. In adopting this passage, however, Mr. Ricardo makes no use of the new kind of value introduced to his readers, and we hear nothing more of real value, till he applies the epithet to the value of wages, in the sense men- tioned in the text. See pages 11 and 12 of the Principles of Pol. Econ. and Taxation, third edition. At page 15 he introduces another kind of value, which he terms " ab- solute," in a sense which I have not been able to seize, but this is only incidentally, and no consequences are de- duced from it. At page 41 he says, " when commodities varied in relative value, it would be desirable to have the means of ascertaining which of them fell and which rose in real value J*^ This appears to be the first passage in which relative value and real value are fairly placed in contrast; and we gather from it, that the value, which he calls real, is not of a relative nature. We subsequently come to the passage quoted in the text, wherein he uses the phrase real value as synonymous with the quantity of labour and capi- tal employed in producing a commodity : whence it follows, that the real value of an object has no relation to the quan- tity of any other object which it will command, but solely to the cost of production, or rather it is the cost of pro- duction itself. If the cost of production is always the same, the real value is always the same. It may perhaps be contended, that Mr. Ricardo had a right to use the term real value in any sense he chose, and that all which could be required of him was consistency in NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 235 its employment. Conceding this for the sake of argument, we may yet remark, that it is an apologfy inapplicable in the present case, because he had already given us his defini- tion of value, and was therefore bound to adhere to it, by the very principle here supposed to be offered in extenuation. If he had a right to use the term in any sense he pleased, he had no right to destroy the essence of his own defini- tion by an epithet annexed to the term defined. His defi- nition of the term, as the power of purchasing, makes it essentially relative to something to be purchased, and it is annihilating his own meaning to transmute value, by the force of an epithet, into something in which no relation of this kind is implied. It may still possibly be urged, that Mr. Ricardo is not liable to the charge of having deviated from his definition of value, that he has strictly adhered to one meaning, and that the term real has not the neutralizing effect here assigned to it. If this were true, we might of course substitute the definition for the term, which w^oiild yield some curious re- sults. The real value of an object in this case must be its real power of purchasing or commanding other objects in exchange ; and we have already seen, that a power of commanding in exchange can be expressed only by a quan- tity of the commodity commanded. What then is the com- modity in which real value can be expressed ? Mr. Ricardo tells us, that the value of a thing in money, hats, coats, or corn, is only nominal value. In what commodity then shall 236 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. we express real value ? His answer must be, in none. This illustration is itself suflScient to show, that Mr. Ricardo's notion of real value is totally irreconcilable and incompa- tible with his previous definition of the only kind of value of which he professes to treat. The argument is short and conclusive : value, as the power of purchasing, can be expressed only by a quantity of the commodity to be pur- chased — real value cannot be so expressed — therefore value and real value are used in senses incompatible and contradictory. In a foot-note to the text we have stated, that real value, as used by jVfr. Ricardo, has no relation to any commodity unless it be to an imaginary one ; namely, a commodity produced by an invariable quantity of labour. But it must be observed, that if we had such a commodity, it would still not enable Mr. Ricardo or any body else to furnish an expression of real value ; it would only enable him to ex- press a variation in real value. For suppose gold to be such a commodity, and take any point of time, for exam- ple A. D. 1600 : suppose further, an object a to be worth at that period so much gold, so much corn, so much cloth : in this case, the value of a in gold would have no more claim to the title of real value (even on Mr. Ricardo's or any other person's theory) than its value in corn or cloth. But we next compare the value of a in gold, corn, and cloth, in the year 1800, and we find that it is worth only half as much gold, although worth as much corn as before, NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 237 and worth more cloth. Here then, according to Mr. Ri- cardo's doctrine, a has fallen to half its former real value, because worth only half as much gold, which by the suppo- sition is invariable in real value. But although we can tell how much a has fallen in real value, we are no nearer obtaining an expression of real value than we were before. Still the value of a in gold would be no more its real value, than the value of a in corn or cloth. Hence it is plain, that real value, in Mr.Ricardo's sense, is not value in rela- tion to any commodity whatever : conseciuently it does not mean power of purchasing, and Mr. Ricardo has used the word value, when coupled with the epithet real, in an ac- ceptation which excludes the whole of his own defi- nition. The same remarks will apply to Mr. IMalthus's notion of absolute value. " If we could suppose," says he, *' any ob- ject always to remain of the same value, the comparison of other commodities with this one would clearly show which had risen, which had fallen, and which had remained the same. The value of any commodity, estimated in any mea- sure of this kind, might with propriety be called its absolute or natural value," &c. &c. — The Measure of lvalue stated and illustrated, page 2. To pass over the inconsistency already exposed, of sup- posing a commodity to remain of the same value, and to take it as implying constancy in the circumstances of its production, it is evident, that, at an assigned period, the 238 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. value of any commodity a, in this invariable commodity which we may term x, would have no more right to the ap- pellation of real value than the value of a in any other com- modity. Assume another period, and the same remark would be applicable : if commodities had varied in the cir- cumstances of their production, the change in their value to X would show such variation, which Mr. Malthus calls a variation in their absolute value, but still their value in x would not be absolute value, in Mr. Malthus's sense, any more than their value in B, C, or D. It is to be remarked, that Mr. Ricardo is any thing but consistent in the use of the term under consideration, or of the doctrine which it implies. In fact, the more I examine his writings, the more I am convinced that he had not formed any clear notions on the subject, that there was a radical confusion in his views regarding it. It is only occasionally that he intimates to his readers that he is speaking of real value : in general he professes to be speaking of " exchangeable value," sometimes of " relative value," as contradistinguished from that which is " absolute" and " real." It is, in truth, curious to note the diflferent kinds of value of which he speaks in the course of his speculations. The following enumeration will show how far he is entitled to credit for the precision of his language and ideas on this subject. NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 239 Page Value in use 1 Value in exchange, or exchangeable value 1, 4. Real Ditto 11, 41, 50. Absolute Ditto 15. Relative Ditto 15,41. Nominal Ditto 50. Natural Ditto 80, 85. If the view of the subject unfolded in these pages is at all correct, all these epithets (except perhaps the last) may be at once swept away. Even the adjunct exchangeable is tautological, the term value implying in itself a relation in exchange, or the power of commanding in exchange, and consequently any epithet which merely expresses the same idea being perfectly superfluous. The word, too, is ill adapted to convey the meaning imposed upon it. It is easy to understand what an exchangeable commodity is ; a commodity, namely, which is capable of being exchanged : and this is the proper meaning of the epithet ; but what is meant by an exchangeable value is not so clear. The words import a value capable of being exchanged ; and although it is possible to speak of exchanging the value of a for the value of B without absolute absurdity, yet this is evi- dently not the sense in which tlie epithet is employed. All that is meant by it is value in exchange, and not value ca- pable of being exchanged. The same epithet is sometimes 240 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. coupled with the term relation, in which case the impro- priety is still more g-laring. It would be difl&cult for the greatest ingenuity to find out any way in which the rela- tion between two commodities can be capable of being ex- changed. If it were permitted to introduce a new term, perhaps the epithet exchan^ive might be useful to mark the particular kind of relation which we are now obliged to designate by the phrase " relation in exchange." The ex- chanu^ive relation of a commodity would be less objection- able than the exchangeable relation ; and if this term were adopted, it would supply a deficiency which most writers on political economy must have occasionally felt. In the text, I have noticed the improper use of the terms real and nominal value, in our English economists only. The celebrated French writer, M. Say, commits precisely the same error. " If different commodities," says he, "have fallen in different ratios, some more, others less, it is plain they must have varied in relative value to each other. That which has fallen, stockings for instance, has changed its value relatively to that which has not fallen, as butcher's meat; and such as have fallen in equal proportion, like stockings and sugar in our hypothesis, have varied in real, though not in relative value. — There is this difference be- tween a real and a relative variation of price ; that the for- mer is a change of value, arising from an alteration of the charges of production ; the latter, a change arising from NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 241 an alteration of the ratio of value of one particular com- modity to other commodities." — Treatise on Pol. Econ. translated by C. R. Prinsep, book ii, chap. 3. NOTE B (page 61). The source of such barren and paradoxical proposi- tions as are noticed in the text, is to be found in the notion of real value ; and that notion being conceded as a preliminary, these propositions logically follow from it. We must look for the original fallacy therefore in the notion itself, the intrinsic inconsistency of which has been already sufficiently exposed. NOTE C (page 70). To avoid misconception it may be necessary to state, that in this and the preceding chapter ic has been intended simply to explain the nature of a rise in the value of labour and a rise in profits, not the causes on which they depend, or the way in which they actually take place. In main- taining that there is no inconsistency in supposing a simul* taneous rise of labour and of profits, I profess not to en- ter into the question whether such a rise does ever or can ever take place, but contend solely, that in cases of im- proved productive power, the product might be so divided, that the rate of profits should be increased, while the value of labour was enhanced ; and that this would be ne- 242 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. cessarily the result, were the product divided in the way described in tlie hypothetical case adduced by Mr. Ricardo. NOTE D (page 103). The universality of the supposition, that a commodity must itself be invariable in order to serve as a measure of value, will appear from the following extracts. *' As a measure of quantity, such as the natural foot, fathom, or handful, which is continually varying- in its own quantity, can never be an accurate measure of the quantity of other things ; so a commodity, which is itself continually varying in its own value, can never be an accurate measure of the value of other commodities. Equal quantities of labour at all times and places, may be said to be of equal value to the labourer. In his ordinary state of health, strength, and spirits, in the ordinary degree of his skill and dexterity, he must always lay down the same portion of his ease, his liberty, and his happiness. The price which he pays must always be the same, whatever may be the quantity of goods which he receives in return for it. Of these, indeed, it may sometimes purchase a greater and sometimes a smaller quantity ; but it is their value which varies, not that of the labour which purchases them. At all times and places, that is dear which it is difficult to come at, or which it costs much labour to acquire ; and that cheap which is to be had easily, or with very little la- bour. Labour alone, therefore, never varying in its own \ NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 243 value, is alone the ultimate and real standard by which the value of all commodities can at all times and places be es- timated and compared." — Wealth of Nations, by Adam S?nith, book i, chap. 5. *' That money, therefore, which constantly preserves an equal value, which poises itself, as it were, in a just equi- librium between the fluctuating proportion of the value of things, is the only permanent and equal scale by which value can be measured." — An Inquiry into the Principles of Pol. Econ., by Sir James Stuart, book iii, chap. 1. " Incapacities of the Metals to perform the Office of an invariable Measure of Value." — Ibid. Title to chap, iii, book 3. " As nothing can be a real measure of magnitude and quantity, which is subject to variations in its own dimen- sions, so nothing can be a real measure of the value of other commodities, which is constantly varying in its own value." — A71 Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Pub- lic Wealth, by the Earl of Lauderdale, page 25, second edit. " Le principal caractere d'un mesure est d'etre inva- riable. C'est en appliquant successivement une mesure invariable a des quantit^s variable, qu'on peut se former une id^e de leur rapports ; mais quand on applique une mesure variable a des quantites qui le sont aussi, on n'ap- prend rien. Une poignee, une coudee, ne sont pas des me- sures propre a comparer les dimensions, puisqu'elles va- rient dans chaque individu ; il en serait de m6me d'un nu- r2 244 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. m^raire dont la valeur varierait, soit dans le mfime temps dans diff^rens endroits, soit dans le m^me endroit dans dif- f^rens temps ; il ne pourrait guere servir a mesurer d'au- tres valeurs." — Coiirs D'Economie Politique, par Henri Storch, Premifere Partie, liv. v, chap. 2. " Silver is more valuable, when it will purchase a large quantity of commodities, than when it will purchase a smaller quantity. It cannot, therefore, serve as a mea- sure, the first requisite of which is invariability." — A Treatise on Pol. Econ., by J. B. Say, translated from the French, by C, R. Prinsep, book i, chap. 21, " When commodities varied in relative value, it would be desirable to have the means of ascertaining which of them fell and which rose in real value, and this could be eflfected only by comparing them, one after another, with some in- variable standard measure of value, which should itself be subject to none of the fluctuations to which other commo- dities are exposed." — Principles of Pol. Econ. and Taxa- tion, by D. Ricardo, Esq., page 42, third edition. " Labour, like all other commodities, varies, from its plenty or scarcity compared with the demand for it, and at different times, and in different countries, commands very different quantities of the first necessary of life ; and fur- ther, from the different degrees of skill, and of assistance from machinery with which labour is applied, the products of labour are not in proportion to the quantity exerted. Consequently, labour, in any sense in which the term can NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 245 be applied, cannot be considered as an accurate and stan- dard measure of real value in exchange." — Principles of Pol. Econ., by Rcd. T. R. Malthus, page 125. It is to be remarked, that in the preceding passage, Mr. Malthus rejects labour as an accurate measure of value, because it is not invariable. In his pamphlet on this sub- ject he has altered his views, and maintains labour to be an accurate measure, because it is invariable. In both cases he proceeds equally on the doctrine, that invariable- ness of value is necessary in a measure of value. " A standard, by a reference to which we may ascer- tain the fluctuations in the exchangeable power of other things, must itself possess an exchangeable value fixed and unalterable. " Nothing can be an accurate measure of value, except that which itself possesses an invariable value." — An Es- say on the Production of Wealth, by R. Torrens, Esq., pages 56 and 59. " There is no point so difficult to ascertain as a varia- tion of value, because we have no fixed standard measure of value ; neither nature nor art furnish us with a commo- dity, whose value is incapable of change ; and such alone would afford us an accurate standard of value." — Conver- sations on Pol. Econ., by Mrs. Mnrcet, page 330. " Money, that is, the precious metals in coin, serves prac- tically as a measure of value, as is evident from what has immediately been said. A certain quantity of the previous L 246 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. metal is taken as a known value, and the value of other things is measured by that value ; one commodity is twice, another thrice the value of such a portion of the metal, and so on. " It is evident, however, that this can remain an accu- rate measure of value only if it remains of the same value itself. If a commodity, which was twice the value of an ounce of silver, becomes three times its value ; we can only know what change has taken place in the value of this commodity, if we know that our measure is un- changed." — Elements of Pol. Econ., by James Mill, Esq. second edit., page 108. " A standard is that which stands still, while other things move, and by this means serves to indicate or mea- sure the degree in which they have advanced or receded."^** And a standard of value must itself stand still, or be sta- tionary in value." — The Templars' Dialogues on Pol. Econ., London Magazine, May 1824, page 558. " That great desideratum in political economy, an uni- form measure of value." — Observations on the Effects pro- duced by the Expenditure of Govern?ne7it, by Wm. Blake ^ Esq. It will not be thought uninteresting to examine what no- tions on the subject of a measure of value were enter- tained by so clear a thinker as Locke. He considered, that the value of commodities is determined by "the proportion of their quantity to the vent ;" that the vent of money being NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 247 always " sufficient and more than enough,"— *' its quantity alone is enough to regulate and determine its value, with- out considering any proportion between its quantity and vent, as in other commodities." Hence he argues, that so long as the quantity of money in a country remains the same, its value is invariable, and it will serve to measure the varying value of other things. In his own words -— '' IMoney, whilst the same quantity of it is passing up and down the kingdom in trade, is really a standing mea- sure of the falling and rising value of other things, in re- ference to one another : and the alteration of price is truly m them only. But if you increase or lessen the quantity of money current in traffic, in any place, then the altera- tion of value is in the money : and if, at the same time, wheat keep its proportion of vent to quantity, money, to speak truly, alters its worth, and wheat does not, though it sell for a greater or less price than it did before. For money, being looked upon as the standing measure of other commodities, men consider and speak of it still as if it were a standing measure, though, when it has varied its quantity, it is plain it is not." In this passage may be remarked the same error, that I have pointed out in other economists, of supposing an al- teration in value can take place in one commodity, while the commodity compared with it remains the same; " money alters its worth and wheat does not." Yet in the subsequent paragraph, the sound sense of this profound 248 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. reasoner carried him to the truth, although into some ap- parent inconsistency 5 for he adds, "But the value or price of all commodities, amongst which money passing in trade is truly one, consisting in proportion, you alter this, as you do all other proportions, whether you increase one, or lessen the other." — Considerations on the lowering of Interest and raising the Value of Money. It may he further remarked on the former of these pas- sages, that, taking him on his own theory, the measure which he describes, like the measures of other economists, would not enable us to ascertain any variations of value, for these are necessarily exhibited in the prices of commodities, but would indicate in which commodities the changes origin- ated. While money remained unaltered as to the causes of value operating upon it, which it would do on his princi- ples as long as it remained the same in quantity, all varia- tions in the prices of commodities must necessarily pro- ceed from alterations in the proportion between the quan- tities of such commodities and their vent, and this is all that, under the circumstances supposed, Mr. Locke's stand- ing measure would show. On reviewing this subject from first to last, it appears to me, that nearly the whole of the vagueness, confusion, and perplexity in which it has been involved, may be traced to an unconscious vacillation between two distinct ideas. There are evidently two senses in which the term measur- ing value is employed, and it is the unconscious passing NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 249 and repassing from one to the other, which has been the source of the mischief : one of these senses, and the only pro- per sense, is, ascertaining the mutual value of two commo- dities by their separate relations to a third ; the other is, as- certaining, when two commodities have varied in value, in which of them the variation has originated. The transition from one of these ideas to the other is, I think, perceptible in the doctrine examined in the text, that money is a good measure of value for commodities at the same time, but not for commodities at different times. In the first part of this proposition, the term measure is used in the former sense, and it is meant to assert, that the value of commodities to each other is shown by their prices, or values in money. In the latter part of the proposition, a transition is made to the second meaning, and it is intended to say, that the value of a commodity in money at different periods does not show whether there has been any alteration in the cir- cumstances of its production ; whether any variation in its price has originated with it, or with the money in which its value is expressed. If we do not suppose this transi- tion to be made, but that one sense is rigidly adhered to, the proposition is liable to all the objections brought against it in the text. It is probably the latter construction of the term measure, under which invariableness has been so generally supposed requisite. But this, as is shown in the course of the pre- sent chapter, would not be invariableness of value, but in- 250 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. variableness of cost, or invariableness in the circumstances of production ; and what would be measured by it would be that cost, or those circumstances, and not value. NOTE E (page 133). The reasoning in the text shows, that on the supposition that coramoditities were to each other in value as the quan- tities of labour required to produce them, any commodity produced by labour alone, however variable the quantity of that labour, would enable us to ascertain all that Mr. Ri- cardo regards as to be derived exclusively from a commo- dity produced by an invariable quantity of labour ; pro- vided a register were kept of the varying quantities of the producing labour required. In both cases, the prices of the standard (if we may so call it) at different periods, would be equally necessary. In the one case, the circum- stance of invariableness in the labour expended would save the trouble of keeping such a register, and simplify our calculations ; but in the other case, the result would be attained, if not with equal ease, at least with equal cer- tainty. NOTE F {page 150). The author of the Templars' Dialogues has also exa- mined this table, but it appears to me that he has fallen NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 251 into some singular misconceptions of Mr. Malthus's mean- ing. At least he has construed it differently from what it is represented in the text, and consequently either he or myself must be in error — possibly the latter. I can only say, that I have been at pains to understand and scrupulous not to misrepresent the scope of Mr. Malthus's argument. At the same time I must confess, that with all the patient attention which I have given to the speculations of the latter, there are many parts of " The Measure of Value stated and illustrated" which I am unable to comprehend. NOTE G {page 15). It is to be observed, that many writers consider mea- suring and expressing value as the same thing. This is directly maintained by M.Say, in the following passage. " Quant a la mesure de la valeur de deux objets qui sont en presence, leur deux valeurs se mesurent I'une par I'autre. Si Ton a dix livres de ble pour une livre de cafe, le cafe vaut dix fois autant que le ble ; et chacune de ces choses est la mesure de I'autre. La monnaie n'a a cet egard aucun privilege. Trente sous sont la valeur d'une Jivre de cafe, et une livre de cafe marque la v.aleur des trentes sous aussi bien que les diverses choses que Ton peut acquerir avec cette monnaie." — Note in M. Say's Edition (page 124, vol. i) of <' Cours d'Economie Politique, par Henri Storch/' It is not correct, however, to regard these two opera- 252 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. tions as identicaL To measure implies, either directly or indirectly, the ascertainment of a ratio between two objects by the intervention of a third. We say, it is true, that we have measured the length of a building, when we have found its ratio to a yard or a foot, but this is because the length of other objects in feet is known to us, and there- fore, when we have the length of the building in feet, we have it in a common denomination : the ratio of the building to the foot, determines its place in the common scale ; or, in other words, determines its ratio to a variety of other objects. We should scarcely consider the length of a building to be measured, if its ratio was determined only to a staff or rod, the length of which in relation to any other object could not itself be ascertained. In the same way, when we say the value of a commodity A is measured when expressed in money, it is because we know already the relations in value between money and a variety of other commodities, and therefore the value of a in money instantly determines its relation to all these ob- jects. The idea of intermediation is still implied. But although to express the value of a commodity in money may thus be considered as equivalent to measuring it, we could not with propriety apply the latter term to the ex- pression of the value of a commodity in another commo- dity of no known or ascertainable relation to any thing else. The following passage from one of Locke's able tracts on NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 253 raising- the value of money, so accurately describes the only process which can be termed with propriety measur- ing- value, that I cannot resist the temptation of inserting it here in confirmation of my own views. " By this measure of commerce, viz. the quantity of silver, men measure the value of all other things. Thus to measure what the value of lead is to wheat, and of either of them to a certain sort of linen cloth, the quantity of silver that each is valued at, or sells for, needs only be known ; for if a yard of cloth be sold for half an ounce of silver, a bushel of wheat for one ounce, and a hundred weight of lead for two ounces ; any one presently sees and says, that a bushel of wheat is double the value of a yard of that cloth, and but half the value of an hundred weight of lead." — Further Considerations concerning raising the Value of Bloney. NOTE H (page 158). Many of the strictures which have been made on Mr. Ricardo's writings, in this and other chapters, would be in some degree obviated if two things were conceded, namely, if we assumed that he was constantly speaking of real value, and if we were to grant him the absurdity which we have shown this expression to imply ; or, in other words, if we were to consider it as importing cost of production, without relation to the power of commanding in exchange. But then, although some inconsistencies 254 NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. "would by this means be obviated or explained away, we should obtain in their place a number of others equally irreconcilable, and also a series of unmeaning and identi- cal propositions. For instance, the proposition that a million of men always produced the same value, but not the same riches, would be reduced to this, that what a mil- lion of men produced always cost the labour of a million of men : a = a. The truth appears to be, that the idea of real value was seldom distinctly present to his mind, although there was almost constantly an obscure reference to it. NOTE I {vage I78). In speaking sometimes of a commodity produced by an invariable quantity of labour as a measure, and sometimes of the labour itself in that character, Mr. Ricardo has in fact used the term in the two senses mentioned in note D, and passed from one to the other without being conscious of it. When he says, that a commodity produced by an invariable quantity of labour would serve to measure the variations of other things, his meaning, as we have before shown, amounts to this, that such a commodity would serve to indicate the variations in the cost of production, or pro- ducing labour of other commodities. But to employ the quantity of producing labour itself as a measure in this sense would be endeavouring to ascertain what is already NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS. 255 presupposed. When, therefore, he affirms labour itself to be a common measure of value, he makes a transition to the other sense of the phrase, and means, that when the quantities of labour respectively required to produce com- modities are known, their values in relation to each other are thereby determined. This distinction, constantly borne in mind, would, I am persuaded, throw great light upon the obscurity which clouds many discussions in political economy, and clearly show the source whence it has proceeded. THE END. LONDON : PRINTED BY CHARLES WOOD. Poppiii's Court, Fleet Street, '^l i i ^Tk :<-'• ^^'Ki <'