■ 1 Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2013 http://archive.org/details/historyofphiloso01schw_0 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IN EPITOME, BY DE. ALBEET SCHWEGLEE. TRANSLATED FROM TEE ORIGINAL GERMAN, BY JULIUS H. SEELYE. FIFTH EDITION. KEW YORK: D. APPLETON AND COMPANY, 443 & 445 BROADWAY. LONDON: 16 LITTLE BRITAIN. 1866. 4 EiTTEEED, according to act of Congress, in the year 1856, By Julius H. Seelte, In the Clerk's Oflace of the District Court of the TJnited States for the Northern District of New York. m. INTKODUCTOEY NOTE BY HENBY B. SMITH. D. D. The History of Philosophy, by Dr. Albert Schwegler, is considered in Germany as the best concise manual upon the subject from the school of Hegel. Its accoimt of the Greek and of the German systems, is of especial value and importance. It presents the whole history of specu- lation in its consecutive order. Though following the method of Hegel's more extended lectures upon the pro- gress of philosophy, and though it makes the system of Hegel to be the ripest product of philosophy, yet it also rests upon independent investigations. It will well re- ward diligent study, and is one of the best works for a IV INTRODUCTORY NOTE. text-book in our colleges, upon this neglected branch of scientific investigation. The translation is made by a competent person, and gives, I doubt not, a faithful ren dering of the original. Henet B. Smith. Union TnEOLoaicAii Sesiinary, New York, Nov. 6, 1855. TRANSLATOE'S PEEFACE. Schwegler's History of Philosophy originally appeared in the Neue EncyMojpadiefuT Wissenscliaftenund KunsteP Its great value soon awakened a call for its separate issue, in which form it has attained a very wide circulation in Germany. It is found in the hands of almost every stu- dent in the philosophical department of a German uni- versity, and is highly esteemed for its clearness, concise- ness, and comprehensiveness. The present translation was commenced in Germany three years ago, and has been carefully finished. It was undertaken with the conviction that the work would not lose its interest or its value in an English dress, and with the hope that it might be of wider service in such a form 1 vi translator's preface. to students of philosophy here. It was thought espe- cially, that a proper translation of this manual would supply a want for a suitable text-book on this branch of study, long felt by both teachers and students in our American colleges. The effort has been made to translate, and not to para- phrase the author's meaning. Many of his statements might have been amplified without diffuseness, and made more perceptible to the superficial reader without losing their interest to the more profound student, but he has so happily seized upon the germs of the different systems, that they neither need, nor would be improved by any farther development, and has, moreover, presented them so clearly, that no student need have any. difficulty in ap- prehending them as they are. The translator has there- fore endeavored to represent faithfully and clearly the original history. As such, he offers his work to the American public, indulging no hope, and making no ef- forts for its success beyond that which its own merits shall ensure. J. H. S. Schenectady, N. Y., January^ 1856. CONTENTS. PAOK INTRODUCTORY NOTE, by Hexrt B. Smith, D. D. . . . iii TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE v TABLE OF CONTENTS vii Skctiok L— what is meant BY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY . 11 II.— CLASSIFICATION 16 IIL— GENERAL 'VIEW OF THE PRE-SOCRATIO PHILOSOPHY . 17 1. The Ionics ........ 17 2. The Pythagoreans ....... 18 3. The Eleatics 18 4. Heraclitus ........ 18 5. The Atomists , 19 6. Anasagoras ........ 19 7. The Sophists ....... 20 IV.— THE IONIC PHILOSOPHERS . . .... 21 1. Thales 21 2. Anaximander ........ 22 3. Anaximenes 23 4. Retrospect 23 V.-PYTHAGOREANISM 23 1. Its Relative Position ....... 23 2. Historical and Chronological ..... 23 3. The Pythagorean Principle ...... 24 4. Carrying out of this Principle ..... 25 VI.— THE ELEATICS 27 1. The Relation of the Eleatic Principle to the Pythagorean . 27 2. Xenophanes ........ 28 8. Parmenides ........ 28 4. Zeno ......... 80 viii CONTENTS. PAGB Sect. VIL— HERACLITUS 31 1. Eelatlon of the Heraclitic Principle to the Eleatlc . . 81 2. Historical and Chronological . . . . , 82 8. The Principle of the Becoming ..... 32 4. The Principle of Fire ...... 33 5. Transition to the Ato mists ...... 83 VIII— EMPEDOCLES 35 1. General View ........ 85 2. The Four Elements ...... 85 3. The Two Powers ....... 36 4. Eelation of the Empedoclean to the Eleatlc and Heraclitic Philo- sophy ........ 36 IX.— THE ATOMISTIC PHILOSOPHY 37 1. Its Propounders ....... 87 2. The Atoms 37 3. The Fulness and the Void ..... 88 4. The Atomistic Necessity ...... 33 5. Eelative Position of the Atomistic Philosophy ... 89 X.— ANAXAGORAS 40 1. His Personal History ...... 40 2. His Relation to his Predecessors ..... 41 3. The Principle of the j/oDs ...... 41 4. Anaxagoras as the close of the Pre-Socratic Realism , . 42 XI -THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY . . . . 43 1. The Relation of the Sophistic Philosophy to the Anaxagorcan Prin- ciple 43 2. Relation of the Sophistic Philosophy to the Universal Life of that Age ........ 44 8. Tendencies of the Sophistic Philosophy . , . .46 4. Significance of the Sophistic Philosophy from its relation to the Culture of the Age . .... 47 5. Individual Sophists ....... 48 6. Transition to Socrates, and characteristic of the following Period 51 XXL— SOCRATES 52 1. His Personal Character ...... 52 2. Socrates and Aristophanes ...... 55 3. The Condemnation of Socrates ..... 57 4. The Genius of Socrates ...... 60 5. Sources of the Philosophy of Socrates .... 61 6. Universal Character of the Philosophizing of Socrates . . 62 7. The Socratic Method 64 8. The Socratic Doctrine concerning Virtue . . . .66 XIII.— THE PARTIAL DISCIPLES OF SOCRATES ... 67 1. Their Relation to the Socratic Philosophy . . . .67 2. Antisthenes and the Cynics ... . . . 68 CONTENTS. ix Sect. Xlll.— (continued.) page 3. Aristippus and the Cyrenians 69 4. Eiiclirt and the Megarians ...... 70 5. Plato as the complete Socraticist ..... 71 XIY.-PLATO 72 I. Plato's Ltfe ....... 72 1. His Youth 72 2. His Years of Discipline ..... 73 3. His Yi'ars of Travel 73 4. His Years of Instruction ..... 74 II. The Inner Development of the Platonic Philosophy and WpvItings ........ 75 III. Classification of the Platonic System . . 82 lY. The Platonic Dialectics ...... 83 1. Conception of Dialectics ..... 83 ■ 2. What is Science ? 84 (1.) As opposed to Sensation .... 84 (2.) The Relation of Knowing to Opinion . . . 86 (3.) The Relation of Science to Thinking . . 86 8. The Doctrine of Ideas in its Genesis . ... 87 4. Positive Exposition of the Doctrine of Ideas . . 91 5. The Relation of Ideas to the Phenomenal World . . 93 6. The Idea of the Good and the Deity ... 95 V. The Platonic Physics 96 1. Nature ........ 96 2. The Soul 98 YI. The Platonic Ethics ...... 100 1. Good and Pleasure ...... 100 2, Yirtue 102 8 The State 102 XY.— THE OLD ACADEMY 107 XYI.— ARISTOTLE 103 I. Life and Writings of Aeistotlb .... 103 II. Universal Character and Division of the Aristotelian Phi- losophy ........ 109 III. Logic and Metaphysics ...... 112 1. Conception and Relation of the Two .... 112 2. Logic ........ 113 3. Metaphysics ....... 115 (1.) The Aristotelian Criticism of the Platonic Doctrine of Ideas ....... 116 (2.) The Forir Aristotelian Principles, or Causes, and the Relation of Form and Matter . . . .120 (3.) Potentiality and Actuality .... 123 (4.) The Absolute Divine Spirit .... 124 lY. The Aristotelian Physics ..... 127 1. Motion, Matter, Space, and Time .... 127 2. The Collective Universe ..... 128 8. Nature . .129 4. Man 129 X CONTENTS. Sect. XV L— (continued.) pagh V. The Akistotelian Etuics ..... 131 1. Eelation of Ethics to Physics .... 131 2. The Highest Good 132 8. Conception of Virtue ...... 134 4. The State , . . . • . . . .135 VI. The Peripatetic School ..... 136 VII. Ti'.A>-SITION TO THE PoST-ArISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY . . 137 XVII.— STOICISM 13S 1. Logic ......... 139 2. Physics ........ 140 3. Ethics 142 (1.) Kespecting the Eelation of Virtue to Pleasure . . 142 (2.) The View of the Stoics concerning External Good . 142 (3.) Farther Verification of this View ... 143 (4.) Impossibility of furnishing a System of Concrete Moial Duties from this Standpoint .... 143 XVIII.-EPICUEEANISM 145 XIX.-SCEPTICISM AND THE NEW ACADEMY . . .143 1. The Old Scepticism 149 2. The New Academy . ..... 150 3. The Later Scepticism ...... 151 XX.— THE EOMANS 152 XXL— NEW PLATONISM 154 1. Ecstasy as a Subjective State ..... 154 2. The Cosmical Principles ...... 154 3. The Emanation Theory of the New Platonists . . .155 XXIL-CHEISTIANITY AND SCHOLASTICISM ... 157 1. The Christian Idea ....... 157 2. Scholasticism ....... 159 3. Nominalism and Eealism ..... 160 XXIIL— TEANSITION TO THE MODEEN PHILOSOPHY . . 161 1. Fall of Scholasticism ....... 161 2. The Eesults of Scholasticism ..... 162 3. The Eevival of Letters ...... 163 4. The German Eeformation . . . . . 164 5. The Advancement of the Natural Sciences . . . 165 6. Bacon of Verulam ...... 166 7. The Italian Philosophers of the Transition Epoch . . 167 8. Jacob Boehme ....... 169 XXIV.— DESCAETES 172 1. The Beginning of Philosophy with Doubt ... 173 2. Cogito ergo sum ....... 173 8. The Nature of Mind deduced from this Principle . . 173 4. The Universal Eule of all Certainty follows from the same . 174 CONTENTS. Xi Sect. XXIY.— (continued.) pagr 5. The Existence of God 174 6. Eesults of this Fact in PLilosophy . . , . .176 7. The Two Substances 177 8. The Anthropology of Descartes . . . . .177 9. Eesults of the Cartesian System ..... 178 XXV. — GEULINCX AND MALEBEANGHE . . . .180 1. Geulincx 180 2. Malebranche 182 8. The Defects of the rhilosophy of Descartes ... 183 XXVI. -SPINOZA . . 1S4 1. The One Infinite Substance 185 2. The Two Attributes ....... 186 3. The Modes 1S8 4. His Practical Philosophy ...... 189 XXVIL— IDEALISM AND EEALISM 192 XXVIII.— LOCKE 193 XXIX.— HUME 193 XXX— CONDILLAC . . 201 XXXI.— HELVETIUS 203 XXXIL— THE FEENCH CLEAEING UP AND MATEEIALISM . . 205 1. The Common Character of the French Philosophers of this Age 205 2. Voltaire . " . . . . . . .206 3. Diderot ........ 206 4. La Mettrie's Materialism ...... 207 5. Syst^me de la Nature ...... 208 (1.) The Materiality of Man 208 (2.) The Atheism of this System .... 209 (3.) Its Denial of Freedom and Immortality . . . 2-10 (4.) The Practical Consciuences of these Principles . 210 XXXIIL-LEIBNITZ 211 1. The Doctrine of Monads ...... 213 2. The Monads more accurately determined . . . 214 3. The Pre-established Harmony . . . , .215 4. The Eelation of the Deity to the Monads ... 216 5. The Eelation of Soul and Body 217 6. The Theory of Knowledge 218 7. Leibnitz's Theodic6e ....... 219 XXXIV.— BEEKELEY 220 XXXV.-WOLFP 222 1. Ontology ........ 224 2. Cosmology ........ 225 8. Eational Psychology ...... 225 4. Natural Theology ....... 226 CONTENTS. PAGH Sect. XXXVI.— THE GERMAN CLEARING UP 227 XXXVII.— TRANSITION TO KANT 229 1. Examination of the Faculty of Knowledge . . . 230 2. Three Chief Principles of the Kantian Theory of Knowledge 232 XXXVIII.-KANT 235 I. Ckitick of Puee Reason . . , . . 23S 1. The Transcendental Esthetics . . .233 (1.) The Metaphysical Discussion ... 239 (2.) The Transcendental Discussion . . .239 2. The Transcendental Analytic .... 241 3. The Transcendental Dialectics .... 246 (1.) The Psychological Ideas .... 247 (2.) The Antinomies of Cosmology . . . 248 (3.) The Ideal of the Pure Reason ... 249 (a.) The Ontological Proof . . .249 (&.) The Cosmological Proof ... 250 (c.) The Physico-Theological Proof . . 250 II. Critick of the Pkactical Reason . • . . 252 (1.) The Analytic . . . . . .254 (2.) The Dialectic : What is this Highest Good ? . 256 («.) Perfect Virtue or Holiness . , . 257 (&.) Perfect Happiness .... 258 (c.) Kant's Views of Religion . . . 259 III. Ckitick of the Faculty of Judgment . . . 262 1. Critick of the ^Esthetic Faculty of Judgment . . 263 (1.) Analytic ...... 263 (2.) Dialectic 265 2. Critick of the Teleological Faculty of Judgment . 266 (1.) Analytic of the Teleological Faculty of Judgment . 267 (2.) Dialectic 267 XXXIX.— TRANSITION TO THE POST-KANTIAN PHILOSOPHY . 268 XL.— JACOBI 271 XLL— FICHTE 279 I. The Fichtian Philosophy in its Original. Form . 282 1. The Theoretical Philosophy of Fichte, his "VVissenschafts- lehre, or Theory of Science .... 282 2. Fichte's Practical Philosophy .... 295 II. The Later Form of Fichte's Philosophy . . .301 XLII.-HERBART 303 1. The Basis and Starting-Point of Philosophy . 304 2. The First Act of Philosophy .... 304 3. Remodelling the Conceptions of Experience . 305 4. Herbart's Reals ..... 806 5. Psychology connected with Metaphysics . . 310 6. The Importance of Herbart's Philosophy , 811 CONTENTS. xiii PAGH Bbot. XLIII. -SCHELLING ........ 312 I. First Period: Schelling's Procession from Fichte . 314 II. Second Period: Standpoint op the distinguishing be- tween THK Philosophy of Nature and of Mind . 318 1. Natural Philosophy . . . , . . 313 (1.) Organic Nature . . . . . .319 (2.) Inorganic Nature ..... 321 (3.) The Eeciprocal Determination of the Organic and Inor- ganic World ...... 321 2. Transcendental Philosophy ..... 322 (1.) The Theoretical Philosophy . . . .323 (2.) The Practical Philosophy .... 324 (3.) Philosophy of Art 324 III. Third Period : Period of Spinozism, ok the Indifference of THE Ideal and the Eeal ..... 326 ly. Fourth Period: The Direction op Schelling's xhilosophy AS Mystical, and allied to New Platonism '. . 333 Y. Fifth Period: Attempt at a Theogony and Cosmogony, AFTER THE MANNER OF JaCOB BoEHME . . . 335 (1.) The Progressive Development of Nature to Man . 337 (2.) The Development of Mind in Histoiy . . 387 VI. Sixth Period ....... 333 XLIV.— TEANSITION TO HEGEL 339 XLV.— HEGEL 343 I. Science of Logic ...... 346 1. The Doctrine of Being ...... 347 (1.) Quality 347 (2.) Quantity 348 (3.) Measure ...... 343 2. The Doctrine of Essence . . . . .349 (1.) The Essence as such .... 349 (2.) Essence and Phenomenon .... 350 (3.) Actuality ...... 351 8. The Doctrine of the Conception . . . .352 (1.) The Subjective Conception . . , 352 (2.) Objectivity 353 (3.) The Idea 353 II. The Science op Nature ...... 353 1. Mechanics ....... 354 2. Physics ...... . . 355 3. Organics ....... 355 (1.) Geological Organism ..... 355 (2.) Vegetable Organism .... 355 (3.) Animal Organism ..... 356 III. Philosophy of Mind ...... 356 1. The Subjective Mind ...... 356 2. The Objective Mind ..... 358 & The Absolute Mind 862 XIV CONTENTS. Sect. XLV. — (continued.) pagh (1.) Esthetics 863 (a.) Architecture . . . . .863 (p.) Sculpture 862 (c.) Tainting ...... 864 Id.) Music 864 (e.) Poetry ...... 364 (2.) Philosophy of Ecligion .... 864 (a.) The Natural Keligion of the Oriental World . 864 (?>.) The Pteligion of Mental Individuality . 364 (c.) Eevealed, or the Christian Keligion . 365 (a) Absolute Philosophy .... 865 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. SECTION I. WHAT IS MEANT BY THE HISTOKY OF PHILOSOPHY. To philosophize is to reflect ; to examine things, in thought. Yet in this is the conception of philosophy not sufficiently defined. Man, as thinking, also employs those practical activities concerned in the adaptation of means to an end ; the whole body of sciences also, even those which do not in strict sense belong to philosophy, still lie in the realm of thought. In what, then, is philosophy distinguished from these sciences, e. g. from the science of astronomy, of medicine, or of rights ? Certainly not in that it has a different material to work upon. Its material is precisely the same as that of the different empirical sciences. The construction and disposition of the universe, the arrangement and functions of the human body, the doctrines of property, of rights and of the state — all these materials belong as truly to philosophy as to their appropriate sciences. That which is given in the world of experience, that which is real, is the content like- wise of philosophy. It is not, therefore, in its material but in its 12 A HISTORY OF , PHILOSOPHY. form, in its method, in its mode of knowledge, that philosophy Is to be distinguished from the empirical sciences. These latter derive their material directly from experience ; they find it at hand and take it up just as they find it. Philosophy, on the other hand, is never satisfied with receiving that which is given simply as it is given, but rather follows it out to its ultimate grounds ; it examines every individual thing in reference to a final principle, and considers it as one link in the whole chain of knowledge. In this way philosophy removes from the individual thing given in experience, its immediate, individual, and accidental character ; from the sea of empirical individualities, it brings out that which is common to all ; from the infinite and orderless mass of con- tingencies it finds that which is necessary, and throws over all a universal law. In short, philosophy examines the totality of experience in the form of an organic system in harmony with the laws of thought. From the above it is seen, that philosophy (in the sense we have given it) and the empirical sciences have a reciprocal influence; the latter conditioning the former, while they at the same time are conditioned by it. We shall, therefore, in the history of the world, no more find an absolute and complete philosophy, than a complete empirical science {EmpiriJc). Rather is philosophy found only in the form of the difi'erent philosophical systems, which have successively appeared in the course of history, advancing hand in hand with the progress of the empirical sciences and the universal, social, and civil culture, and showing in their advance the difi'erent steps in the development and im- provement of human science. The history of philosophy has, for its object, to represent the content, the succession, and the inner connection of these philosophical systems. The relation of these difi'erent systems to each other is thus already intimated. The historical and collective life of the race is bound together by the idea of a spiritual and intellectual pro- gress, and manifests a regular order of advancing, though not always continuous, stages of development. In this, the fact har- monizes with what we should expect from antecedent probabilities. Since, therefore, every philosophical system is only the philo* WHAT IS MEANT BY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 13 sophical expression of the collective life of its time, it follows that these different systems which have appeared in history will dis- close one organic movement and form together one rational and internally connected (gegliedertes) system. In all their develop- ments, we shall find one constant order, grounded in the striving of the spirit ever to raise itself to a higher point of consciousness and knowledge, and to recognize the whole spiritual and natural universe, more and more, as its outward being, as its reality, as the mirror of itself. Hegel was the first to utter these thoughts and to consider the history of philosophy as a united process, hut this view, which is, in its principle, true, he has applied in a way which would destroy the freedom of human actions, and remove the very conception of contingency, i. e. that any thing should be contrary to reason. Hegel's view is, that the succession of the systems of philosophy which have appeared in history, corresponds to the succession of logical categories in a system of logic. According to him, if, from the fundamental conceptions of these different philosophical systems, we remove that which pertains to their outward form or particular application, &c., so do we find the different steps of the logical conceptions (e. g. being, becoming, existence, being j9er se (f msichseyn) quantity, &c.). And on the other hand, if we take up the logical process by itself, we find also in it the actual historical process. This opinion, however, can be sustained neither in its prin- ciple nor in its historical application. It is defective in its prin- ciple, because in history freedom and necessity interpenetrate, and, therefore, while we find, if we consider it in its general aspects, a rational connection running through the whole, we also see, if we look solely at its individual parts, only a play of numberless con- tingencies, just as the kingdom of nature, taken as a whole, reveals a rational plan in its successions, but viewed only in ita parts, mocks at every attempt to reduce them to a preconceived plan. In history we have to do with free subjectivities, with in- dividuals capable of originating actions, and have, therefore, a factor which does not admit of a previous calculation. For how- 14 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. ever accurately we may estimate tlie controlling conditions which may attach to an individual, from the general circumstances in which he may be placed, his age, his associations, his nationality, &c., a free will can never be calculated like a mathematical pro- blem. History is no example for a strict arithmetical calculation. The history of philosophy, therefore, cannot admit of an apriori construction ; the actual occurrences should not be joined together as illustrative of a preconceived plan; but the facts, so far as they can be admitted, after a critical sifting, should be received as such, and their rational connection be analytically determined. The speculative idea can only supply the law for the arrangement and scientific connection of that which may be historically furnished. A more comprehensive view, which contradicts the above- given Hegelian notion, is the following. The actual historical development is, very generally, different from the theoretical. Historically e. g. the State arose as a means of protection against robbers, while theoretically it is derived from the idea of rights. So also, even in the actual history of philosophy, while the logi- cal (theoretical) process is an ascent from the abstract to the con- crete, yet does the historical development of philosophy, quite generally, descend from the concrete to the abstract, from intui- tion to thought, and separates the abstract from the concrete in those general forms of culture and those religious and social cir- cumstances, in which the philosophizing subject is placed. A system of philosophy proceeds synthetically, while the history of philosophy, i. e. the history of the thinking process proceeds analytically. We might, therefore, with great propriety, adopt directly the reverse of the Hegelian position, and say that what in reality is the first, is for us, in fact, the last. This is illustra- ted in the Ionic philosophy. It began not with being as an ab- stract conception, but with the most concrete, and most apparent, e. g. with the material conception of water, air, &c. Even if we leave the Ionics and advance to the being of the Eleatics or the becoming of the Heraclitics, we find, that these, instead of being pure thought determinations, are only unpurified conceptions, and WHAT IS MEANT BY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 15 materially colored intuitions. Still farther, is the attempt im- practicable to refer every philosophy that has appeared in history to some logical category as its central principle, because the most of these philosophies have taken, for their object, the idea, not as an abstract conception, but in its realization as nature and mind, and, therefore, for the most part, have to do, not with logical questions, but with those relating to natural philosophy, psycho- logy and ethics. Hegel should not, therefore, limit his compari- son of the historical and systematic process of development simply to logic, but should extend it to the whole system of philosophical science. Grranted that the Eleatics, the Heraclitics and the Atomists may have made such a category as the centre of their systems, and we may find thus far the Hegelian logic in harmony with the Hegelian history of philosophy. But if we go farther, how is it ? How with Anaxagoras, the Sophists, Socrates, Plato, Aristotle ? We cannot, certainly, without violence, press one central principle into the systems of these men, but if we should be able to do it, and could reduce e. g. the philosophy of Anaxa- goras to the conception of " the end," that of the Sophists to the conception of " the appearance," and the Socratic Philosophy to the conception of " the good," — yet even then we have the new difficulty that the historical does not correspond to the logical succession of these categories. In fact, Hegel himself has not attempted a complete application of his principle, and indeed gave it up at the very threshold of the Grecian philosophy. To the Eleatics, the Heraclitics and the Atomists, the logical categories of "being," " becoming," and being per se may be successively ascribed, and so far, as already remarked, the parallelism extends, but no farther. Not only does Anaxagoras follow with the con- ception of reason working according to an end, but if we go back before the Eleatics, we find in the very beginning of philosophy a total diversity between the logical and historical order. If Hegel had carried out his principle consistently, he should have thrown away entirely the Ionic philosophy, for matter is no logical category he should have placed the Pythagoreans after the Eleatics and the Atomists, for in logical order the categories of 16 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. quantity follow those of quality ; in short, he would have been obliged to set aside all chronology. Unless this be done, we must be satisfied with a theoretical reproduction of the course which the thinking spirit has taken in its history, only so far as we can see in the grand stages of history a rational progress of thought ; only so far as the philosophical historian, surveying a period of de- velopment, actually finds in it a philosophical acquisition, — the acquisition of a new idea : but we must guard ourselves against applying to the transition and intermediate steps, as well as to the whole detail of history, the postulate of an immanent conformity to law, or an organism in harmony with our own thoughts. His- tory often winds its way like a serpent in lines which appear retro- gressive, and philosophy, especially, has not seldom withdrawn herself from a wide and already fruitful field, in order to settle down upon a narrow strip of land, the limits even of which she has sought still more closely to abridge. At one time we fimd thousands of years expended in fruitless attempts with only a negative result ; — at another, a fulness of philosophical ideas are crowded together in the experience of a lifetime. There is here no sway of an immutable and regularly returning law, but history, as the realm of freedom, will first completely manifest itself at the end of time as the work of reason. SECTION II. CLASSIFICATION. A FEW words will suffice to define our problem and classify its elements. Where and when does philosophy begin ? Manifestly, according to the analysis made in ^ I., where a final philosophical principle, a final ground of being is first sought in a philosophical way, — and hence with the Grecian philosophy. The Oriental — Chinese and Hindoo — so named philosophies, — but which are rather theologies or mythologies, — and the mythic cosmogonies of GENERAL VIEW OF THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. 17 Greece, in its earliest periods, are, therefore, excluded from our more definite problem. Like Aristotle, we shall begin the history of philosophy with Thales. For similar reasons we exclude also the philosophy of the Christian middle ages, or Scholasticism. This is not so much a philosophy, as a philosophizing or reflecting within the already prescribed limits of positive religion. It is, therefore, essentially theology, and belongs to the science of the history of Christian doctrines. The material which remains after this exclusion, may be naturally divided into two periods ; viz : — ancient — Grecian and Groeco-Romanic — and modern philosophy. Since a preliminary comparison of the characteristics of these two epochs could not here be given without a subsequent repetition, we shall first speak of their inner relations, when we come to treat of the transition from the one to the other. The first epoch can be still farther divided into three periods ; (1.) The pre-Socratic philosophy, i. e. from Thales to the Sophists inclusive; (2.) Socrates, Plato, Aristotle; (3.) The post- Aris- totelian phil:^sophy, including New Platonism. SECTION III. GENEKAL VIEW OF THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. 1. The universal tendency of the pre-Socratic philosophy is to find some principle for the explanation of nature. Nature, the most immediate, that which first met the eye and was the most palpable, was that which first aroused the inquiring mind. At the basis of its changing forms, — beneath its manifold appearances, thought they, lies a first principle which abides the same through all change. What then, they asked, is this principle ? What is the original ground of things ? Or, more accurately, what ele- ment of nature is the fundamental element ? To solve this inquiry was the problem of the Ionic natural philosophers. One 18 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. proposes as a solution, water, another, air, and a third, an original chaotic matter. 2. The Pythagoreans attempted a higher solution of this problem. The proportions and dimensions of matter rather than its sensible concretions, seemed to them to furnish the true ex- planation of being. They, accordingly, adopted as the principle of their philosophy, that which would express a determination of proportions, i. e. numbers. " Number is the essence of all things," was their position. Number is the mean between the immediate sensuous intuition and the pure thought. Number and measure have, to be sure, nothing to do with matter only in so far as it possesses extension, and is capable of division in space and time, but yet we should have no numbers or measures if there were no matter, or nothing which could meet the intuitions of our sense. This elevation above matter, which is at the same time a cleaving to matter, constitutes the essence and the character of Pythago- reanism. 3. Next come the JEleatics, who step absolutely beyond that which is given in experience, and make a complete abstraction of every thing material. This abstraction, this negation of all divi- sion in space and time, they take as their principle, and call it pure being. Instead of the sensuous principle of the Ionics, or the symbolic principle of the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, there- fore, adopt an intelligible principle. 4. Herewith closes the analytic, the first course in the development of Grecian philosophy, to make way for the second, or synthetic course. The Eleatics had sacrificed to their principle of pure being, the existence of the world and every finite existence. But the denial of nature and the world could not be maintained. The reality of both forced itself upon the attention, and even the Eleatics had affirmed it, though in guarded and hypothetical terms. But from their abstract being there was no passage back to the sensuous and concrete ; their principle ought to have ex- plained the being of events, but it did not. To find a principle for the explanation of these, a principle which would account for the becoming, the event was still the problem. Heraclitus solved GENERAL VIEW OF THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. 19 it, by asserting that, inasmuch as being has no more reality than not being, therefore the unity of the two, or in other words the becoming, is the absolute principle. He held that it belonged to the very essence of finite being that it be conceived in a continual flow, in an endless stream. " Every thing flows." We have here the conception of original energy, instead of the Ionic original matter ; the first attempt to explain being and its motion from a principle analytically attained. From the time of Heraclitus, this inquiry after the cause of the becoming, remained the chief interest and the moving spring of philosophical development. 5. Becoming is the unity of being and not-being, and into these two elements is the Heraclitic principle consciously analyzed by the Atomists. Heraclitus had uttered the principle of the becoming, but only as a fact of experience. He had simply ex- pressed it as a law, but had not explained it. The necessity for this universal law yet remained to be proved. Why is every thing in a perpetual flow — in an eternal movement? From the dy- namical combination of matter and the moving force, the next step was to a consciously determined distinction, to a mechanical division of the two. Thus Empedocles combining the doctrines of Heraclitus and Parmenides, considered matter as the abiding being, while force was the ground of the movement. But the Atomists still considered the moving mythic energies as forces ; Empedocles regarded them as love and hate ; and Democritus as unconscious necessity. The result was, therefore, that the be- coming was rather limited as a means for the mechanical explana- tion of nature, than itself explained. 6. Despairing of any merely materialistic explanation of the becoming, Anaxagoras next appears, and places a world-forming Intelligence by the side of matter. He recognized mind as the primal causality, to which the existence of the world, together with its determined arrangement and design (zweckmdssigkeit) must be referred. In this, philosophy gained a great principle, -viz. — an ideal one. But Anaxagoras did not know how to fully carry out his principles. Instead of a theoretical comprehension of the universe — instead of deriving being from the idea, he grasped 20 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. again after some mechanical explanation. His " world forming reason" serves him only as a first impulse, only as a moving power. It is to liim a Deus ex machina. Notwithstanding, therefore, his glimpse of something higher than matter, yet waa Anaxagoras only a physical philosopher, like his predecessors Mind had not yet appeared to him as a true force above nature, as an organizing soul of the universe. 7. It is, therefore, a farther progress in thought, to compre- hend accurately the distinction between mind and nature, and to recognize mind as something higher and contra-distinguished from all natural being. This problem fell to the Sophists. They en- tangled in contradictions, the thinking which had been confined to the object, to that which was given, and gave to the objective world which had before been exalted above the subject, a sub- ordinate position in the dawning and yet infantile consciousness of the superiority of subjective thinking. The Sophists carried their principle of subjectivity, though at first this was only nega- tive, into the form of the universal religious and political chang- ing condition (Aufkldrung). * They stood forth as the destroy- ers of the whole edifice of thought that had been thus far built until Socrates appeared, and set up against this principle of empirical subjectivity, that of the absolute subjectivity, — that of the spirit in the form of a free moral will, and the thought is pos- itively considered as something higher than existence, as the truth of all reality. With the Sophist closes our first peri- od, for with these the oldest philosophy finds its self-destruction (Selhstaufldsung). * This word literally means clearin^j up, but has a philosophical sense for •which no precise equivalent is found in the English language. When used physically, it denotes that every ohstruction which prevented the clear sight of the bodily eye is removed, and when used psychologically it implies the same fact in reference to our mental vision. The AvfUarung in philosophy is hence the clearing up of difficulties which have hindered a true philosophical insight. To express this, I know of no better word than the literal rendering, " jtp-clearing" or clearing w^," which the reader will find adopted in the fol- lowing pages. — Trakslator. THE IONIC PHILOSOPHERS. 21 SECTION IV. THE IONIC PHILOSOPHERS. 1. Thales. — At the head of the Ionic natural philosophers, and therefore at the head of philosophy, the ancients are generally agreed in placing Thales of Miletus, a cotemporary of Croesus and Solon ; although this beginning lies more in the region of tradi- tion than of history. The philosophical principle to which he owes his place in the history of philosophy is, that, " the principle (the primal, the original ground) of all things is water ; from water everything arises and into water every thing returns." But simply to assume water as the original ground of thing%- was not to advance beyond his myth-making predecessors and their cos- mologies. Aristotle, himself, when speaking of Thales, refers to the old " theologians," — meaning, doubtless. Homer and Hesiod, — who had ascribed to Oceanus and Thetis, the origin of all things. Thales, however, merits his place as the beginner of philosophy, because he made the first attempt to establish his physical principle, without resorting to a mythical representation, and, therefore, brought into philosophy a scientific procedure. He is the first who has placed his foot upon the ground of a logical {verstdndig) explanation of nature. We cannot now say with certainty, how he came to adopt his principle, though he might have been led to it, by perceiving that dampness belonged to the seed and nourishment of things ; that warmth is developed from moisture ; and that, generally, moisture might be the plastic, liv- ing and life-giving principle. From the condensation and expan- sion of this first principle, he derives, as it seems, the changes of things, though the way in which this is done, he has not accurately determined. The philosophical significance of Thales does not appear to extend any farther. He was not a speculative philosopher after a later mode. Philosophical book-making was not at all the order 22 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. of his day, and he does not seem to have given any of his opinions a written form. On account of his ethico-political wisdom, he is numbered among the so-named " seven wise men," and the char- acteristics which the ancients furnish concerning him only testify to his practical understanding. He is said e. g. to have first cal- culated an eclipse of the sun, to have superintended the turning of the course of the Halys under Croesus, &c. When subsequent narrators relate that he had asserted the unity of the world, had set up the idea of a world-soul, and had taught the immortality of the soul and the personality of God, it is doubtless an unhistorical reference of later ideas to a stand-point, which was, as yet, far from being developed. 2. AxAxiMANDER. — Auaximaudcr, sometimes represented by the ancients as a scholar and sometimes as a companion of Thales, but who was, at all events, younger than the latter, sought to carry out still farther his principles. The original essence which he assumed, and which he is said to have been the first to have named principle (apx>y), he defined as the " unlimited, eternal and unconditioned," as that which embraced all things and ruled all things, and which, since it lay at the basis of all determinateness of the finite and the changeable, is itself infinite and undeter- minate. How we are to regard this original essence of Anaxi- mander is a matter of dispute. Evidently it was not one of the four common elements, though we must not, therefore, think it was something incorporeal and immaterial. Anaximander proba- bly conceived it as the original matter before it had separated into determined elements, — as that which was first in the order of time, or what is in our day called the chemical indifi'erence in the opposition of elements. In this respect his original essence is indeed " unlimited " and " undetermined," i. e. has no determina- tion of quality nor limit of quantity, yet it is not, therefore, in any way, a pure dynamical principle, as perhaps the " friendship" and " enmity" of Empedocles might have been, but it was only a more philosophical expression for the same thought, which the old cosmogonies have attempted to utter in their representation of 3haos. Accordingly, Anaximander sufiers the original opposition THE IONIC PHILOSOPHERS. 23 of cold and warm, of dry and moist {i. e. the basis of the four elements) to be secreted from bis original essence, a clear proof that it was only the undeveloped, unanalyzed, potential being of these elemental opposites. 3. Anaximenes. — Anaximenes, who is called by some the scholar, and by others the companion of Anaximander, turned back more closely to the view of Thales, in that he made air as the principle of all things. The perception that air surrounds the whole world, and that breath conditions the activity of life, seems to have led him to his position. 4. Retrospect. — The whole philosophy of the three Ionic sages may be reduced to these three points, viz: — (1.) They sought for the universal essence of concrete being; (2.) They found this essence in a material substance or substratum ; (3.) They gave some intimation respecting the derivation of the ele- ments from this original matter. SECTION V. PYTHAGOREANISM. 1. Its Relative Position. — The development of the Ionic philosophy discloses the tendency to abstract matter from all else; though they directed this process solely to the determined quality of matter. It is this abstraction carried to a higher step, when we look away from the sensible concretions of matter, and no more regard its qualitative determinateness as water, air, &c., but only direct our attention to its quantitative determinateness, — to its space-filling property. But the determinateness of quantity is number, and this is the principle and stand-point of Pythagorean- ism. 2. Historical and Chronological. — The Pythagorean doc- trine of numbers is referred to Pythagoras of Samos, who is said to have flourished between 540 and 500 B. C. He dwelt in the 24 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. latter part of his life at Crotonia, in Magna Grecia, where he founded a society, or, more properly, an order, for the moral and political regeneration of the lower Italian cities. Through this society, this new direction of philosophy seems to have been introduced, — though more as a mode of life than in the form of a scientific theory. What is related concerning the life of Pytha- goras, his journeys, the new order which he founded, his political influence upon the lower Italian cities, &c., is so thoroughly inter- woven with traditions, legends, and palpable fabrications, that we can be certain at no point that we stand upon a historical basis. Not only the old Pythagoreans, who have spoken of him, de- lighted in the mysterious and esoteric, but even his new-Plato- nistic biographers. Porphyry and Jamblichus, have treated his life as a historico-philosophical romance. We have the same un- certainty in reference to his doctrines, i. e. in reference to his share in the number-theory. Aristotle, e. g. does not ascribe this to Pythagoras himself, but only to the Pythagoreans gene- rally, i. e. to their school. The accounts which are given respect- ing his school have no certainty till the time of Socrates, a hundred years after Pythagoras. Among the few sources of light which we have upon this subject, are the mention made in Plato's Phae- don of the Pythagorean Philolaus and his doctrines, and the writings of Archytas, a cotemporary of Plato. We possess in fact the Pythagorean doctrine only in the manner in which it was taken up by Philolaus, Eurytas and Archytas, since its earlier adherents left nothing in a written form. 3. The Pythagorean Principle. — The ancients are united in affirming that the principle of the Pythagorean philosophy was number. But in what sense was this their principle — in a material or a formal sense ? Did they hold number as the material of things, i. e. did they believe that things had their origin in num- bers, or did they regard it as the archetype of things, i. e. did they believe that things were made as the copy or the representa- tion of numbers ? From this very point the accounts given by the ancients diverge, and even the expressions of Aristotle seem to contradict each other. At one time he speaks of Pythagorean- PYTHAGOREANISM. 25 ism in the former, and at another in the latter sense. From this circumstance modern scholars have concluded that the Pytha- gorean doctrine of numbers had different forms of development ; that some of the Pythagoreans regarded numbers as the substances and others as the archetypes of things. Aristotle, however, gives an intimation how the two statements may be reconciled with each other. Originally, without doubt, the Pythagoreans regarded number as the material, as the inherent essence of things, and therefore Aristotle places them together with the Hylics (the Ionic natural philosophers), and says of them that " they held things for numbers " (Metaph. I., 5, 6). But as the Hylics did not identify their matter, e. g. water, immediately with the sensuous thing, but only gave it out as the fundamental ele- ment, as the original form of the individual thing, so, on the other side, numbers also might be regarded as similar fundamental types, and therefore Aristotle might say of the Pythagoreans, that " they held numbers to be the corresponding original forms of being, as water, air, &c." But if there still remains a degree of uncertainty in the expressions of Aristotle respecting the sense of the Pythagorean doctrine of numbers, it can only have its ground in the fact that the Pythagoreans did not make any dis- tinction between a formal and material principle, but contented themselves with the undeveloped view, that, " number is the essence of things, every thing is number." 4. The carrying- out of this Principle. — From the very nature of the " number-principle," it follows that its complete ap- plication to the province of the real, can only lead to a fruitless and empty symbolism. If we take numbers as even and odd, and still farther as finite and infinite, and apply them as such to astronomy, music, psychology, ethics, &c., there arise combina- tions like the following, viz. : one is the point, two are the line, three are the- superficies, four are the extension of a body, five are the condition [heschaffe^iheit), &c. — still farther, the soul is a musical harmony, as is also virtue, the soul of the world, &c. Not only the philosophical, but even the historical interest here ceases, since the ancients themselves — as was unavoidable from the 2 26 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. arbitrary nature of such combinations — ^bave given the most con- tradictory account, some affirming that the Pythagoreans reduced righteousness to the number three, others, that they reduced it to the number four, others again to five, and still others to nine. Naturally, from such a vague and arbitrary philosophizing, there would early arise, in this, more than in other schools, a great diversity of views, one ascribing this signification to a certain mathematical form, and another that. In this mysticism of num- bers, that which alone has truth and value, is the thought, which lies at the ground of it all, that there prevails in the phenomena of nature a rational order, harmony and conformity to law, and that these laws of nature can be represented in measure and number. But this truth has the Pythagorean school hid under extravagant fancies, as vapid as they are unbridled. The physics of the Pythagoreans possesses little scientific value, with the exception of the doctrine taught by Philolaus respecting the circular motion of the earth. Their ethics is also defective. What we have remaining of it relates more to the Pythagorean life, i. e. to the practice and discipline of their order than to their philosophy. The whole tendency of Pythagoreanism was in a practical respect ascetic, and directed to a strict culture of the character. As showing this, we need only to cite their doctrines concerning the transmigration of the soul, or, as it has been called, their " immortality doctrine," their notion in respect of the lower world, their opposition to suicide, and their view of the body as the prison of the soul — all of which ideas are referred to in Plato's Phaedon, and the last two of which are indicated as belonging to Philolaus. THE ELEATICS. 27 SECTION YI THE ELEATICS. 1. Relation of the Eleatic Principle to the Pythago- rean. — Wliile the Pythagoreans had made matter, in so far as it is quantity and the manifold, the basis of their philosophizing, and while in this they only abstracted from the determined ele- mental condition of matter, the Eleatics carry the process to its ultimate limit, and make, as the principle of their philosophy, a total abstraction from every finite determinateness, from every change and vicissitude which belongs to concrete being. While the Pythagoreans had held fast to the form of being as having existence in space and time, the Eleatics reject this, and make as their fundamental thought the negation of all exterior and pos- terior. Only being is, and there is no not-being, nor becoming. This being is the purely undetermined, changeless ground of all things. It is not being in becoming, but it is being as exclusive of all becoming ; in other words, it is pure being. Eleaticism is, therefore, Monism, in so far as it strove to carry, back the manifoldness of all being to a single ultimate principle ; but on the other hand it becomes Dualism, in so far as it could neither carry out its denial of concrete existence, i. e., the phenomenal world, nor yet derive the latter from its presup- posed original ground. The phenomenal world, though it might be explained as only an empty appearance, did yet exist ; and, since the sensuous perception would not ignore this, there must be allowed it, hypothetically at least, the right of existence. Its origin must be explained, even though with reservations. This contradiction of an unreconciled Dualism between being and ex- istence, is the point where the Eleatic philosophy is at war with itself — though, in the beginning of the school — with Xenoptianes^ it does not yet appear. The principle itself, with its results, is only fully apparent in the lapse of time. It has three periods 28 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. of formation, whicli successively appear in three successive gen- erations. Its foundation belongs to Xenoplianes ; its systematic formation to Parmenides ; its completion and partial dissolution to Zeno and Melissus — tlie latter of whom we can pass by. 2. Xenophanes. — Xenopbanes is considered as the originator of the Eleatic tendency. He was born at Colophon ; emigrated to Elea, a Phocian colony in Lucania, and was a younger cotem- porary of Pythagoras. He appears to have first uttered the proposition — " every thing is one," without, however, giving any more explicit determination respecting this unity, whether it be one simply in conception or in actuality. Turning his attention, says Aristotle, upon the world as a whole, he names the unity which he finds, Grod. God is the One. The Eleatic " One and All " {%v KOL irav) had, therefore, with Xenophanes, a theological and religious character. The idea of the unity of God, and an opposition to the anthropomorphism of the ordinary views of re- ligion, is his starting point. He declaimed against the delusion that the gods were born, that they had a human voice or form, and railed at the robbery, adultery, and deceit of the gods as sung by Homer and Hesiod. According to him the Godhead is wholly seeing, wholly understanding, wholly hearing, unmoved, undivided, calmly ruling all things by his thought, like men neither in form nor in understanding. In this way, with his thought turned only towards removing from the Godhead all finite determinations and predicates, and holding fast to its unity and unchangeableness, he declared this doctrine of its being to be the highest philosophical principle, without however directing this principle polemically against the doctrine of finite being, or carrying it out in its negative application. 3. Par]\ienides. — The proper head of the Eleatic school is Parmenides of Elea, a scholar, or at least an adherent of Xeno- phanes. Though we possess but little reliable information re- specting the circumstances of his life, yet we have, in inverse proportion, the harmonious voice of all antiquity in an expression of reverence for the Eleatic sage, and of admiration for the depth of his mind, as well as for the earnestness and elevation THE ELEATICS. 29 of his character. The saying — " a life like Parmenides," became afterwards a proverb among the Greeks. Parmenides embodied his philosophy in an epic poem, of which we have still important fragments. It is divided into two parts. In the first he discusses the conception of being. Rising far above the yet unmediated view of Xenophanes, he attains a conception of pure single being, which he sets up as absolutely opposed to every thing manifold and changeable, i. e., to that which has no being, and which consequently cannot be thought. From this conception of being he not only excludes all becoming and departing, but also all relation to space and time, all divisi- bility and movement. This being he explains as something which has not become and which does not depart, as complete and of its own kind, as unalterable and without limit, as indivisi- ble and present though not in time, and since all these are only negative, he ascribes to it, also, as a positive determination — thought. Being and thought are therefore identical with Par- menides. This pure thought, directed to the pure being, he de- clares is the only true and undeceptive knowledge, in opposition to the deceptive notions concerning the manifoldnessL and muta- bility of - the phenomenal. He has no hesitancy in holding that to be only a name which mortals regard as truth, viz., becoming and departing, being and not-being, change of place and vicissi- tude of circumstance. We must therefore be careful not to hold " the One " of Parmenides, as the collective unity of all concrete being. So much for the first part of Parmenides' poem. After the principle that there is only being has been developed according to its negative and positive determinations, we might believe that the system was at an end. But there follows a second part, which is occupied solely with the hypothetical attempt to explain the phenomenal world and give it a physical derivation. Though firmly convinced that, according to reason and conception, there is only " the One," yet is Parmenides unable to withdraw him- self from the recognition of an appearing manifoldness and change. Forced, therefore, by his sensuous perception to enter 30 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. upon a discussion of the phenomenal world, he prefaces this sec- ond part of his poem with the remark, that he had now closed what he had to say respecting the truth, and was hereafter to deal only with the opinion of a mortal. Unfortunately, this sec- ond part has been very imperfectly transmitted to us. Enough however remains to show, that he explained the phenomena of nature from the mingling of two unchangeable elements, which Aristotle, though apparently only by way of example, indicates as warm and cold, fire and earth. Concerning these two ele- ments, Aristotle remarks still farther that Parmenides united the warmth with being, and the other element with not-being. It is scarcely necessary to remark that between the two parts of the Parmenidean philosophy — between the doctrine concern- ing being and the doctrine concerning appearance — there can ex- ist no inner scientific connection. What Parmenides absolutely denies in the first part, and indeed declares to be unutterable, viz., the not-being, the many and the changeable, he yet in the second part admits to have an existence at least in the represen- tation of men. But it is clear that the not-being cannot once exist in the representation, if it does not exist generally and every where, and that the attempt to explain a not-being of the representation, is in complete contradiction with his exclusive recognition of being. This contradiction, this unmediated jux- taposition of being and not-being, of the one and the many, Zeno^ a scholar of Parmenides, sought to remove, by affirming that from the very conception of being, the sensuous representation, and thus the world of the not-being, are dialectically annihilated. 4. Zexo. — The Eleatic Zeno was born about 500 B. C. ; was a scholar of Parmenides, and the earliest prose writer among the Grecian philosophers. He is said to have written in the form of dialogues. He perfected, dialectically, the doctrine of his mas- ter, and carried out to the completest extent the abstraction of the Eleatic One, in opposition to the manifoldness and determi- nateness of the finite. He justified the doctrine of a single, sim- ple, and unchangeable being, in a polemical way, by showing up the contradictions into which the ordinary representations of the HERACLITUS. 81 phenomenal world become involved. While Parmenides affirms that there is only the One, Zeno shows in his well-known proofs (which unfortunately we cannot here more widely unfold), that the many, the changing, that which has relation to space, or that which has relation to time, is not. While Parmenides affirmed the being, Zeno denied the appearance. On account of these proofs, in which Zeno takes up the conceptions of extension, manifoldness and movement, and shows their inner contradictory nature, Aristotle names him the founder of dialectics. While the philosophizing of Zeno is the completion of the Eleatic principle, so is it at the same time the beginning of its dissolution. Zeno had embraced the opposition of being and ex- istence, of the one and the many, so abstractly, and had carried it so far, that with him the inner contradiction of the Eleatic principle comes forth still more boldly than with Parmenides ; fcTi. the more logical he is in the denial of the phenomenal world, so much the more striking must be the contradiction, of turning, on the one side, his whole philosophical activity to the refutation of the sensuous representation, while, on the other side, he sets over against it a doctrine which destroys the very possibility of a false representation. SECTION YII. HERACLITUS. 1. Relation of the Heraclitic Pe.inciple to the Ele- \ ATic. — ^Being and existence, the one and the many, could not be united by the principle of the Eleatics ; the Monism which they had striven for had resulted in an ill-concealed Dualism. He- raclitus reconciled this contradiction by affirming that being and - not-being, the one and the many, existed at the same time as the becoming. While the Eleatics could not extricate themselves from the dilemma that the worlcj is either being or not-being; 82 A mSTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Heraclitus removes the difficulty by answering — it is neither be- ing nor not-being, because it is both. 2. Historical and Chronological. — Heraclitus, surnamed by later writers the mystic, was born at Ephesus, and flourished about 500 B. C. His period was subsequent to that of Xeno- phanes, though partially cotemporary with that of Parmenides. He laid down his philosophical thoughts in a writing " Concern- ing Nature," of which we possess only fragments. Its rapid transitions, its expressions so concise, and full of meaning, the general philosophical peculiarity of Heraclitus, and the antique character of the earliest prose writings, all combine to make this work so difficult to be understood that it has long been a proverb. Socrates said concerning it, that " what he understood of it was excellent, and he had no doubt that what he did not understand was equally good ; but the book requires an expert swimmer." Later Stoics and Academicians have written commentaries upon it. 3, The Principle of the Becoming. — The ancients unite in ascribing to Heraclitus the principle that the totality of things should be conceived in an eternal flow, in an uninterrupted move- ment and transformation, and that all continuance of things is only appearance. " Into the same stream," so runs a saying of Heraclitus, we descend, and at the same time we do not de- scend ; we are, and also we are not. For into the same stream we cannot possibly descend twice, since it is always scattering and collecting itself again, or rather it at the same time flows to us and from us." There is, therefore, ground for the assertion that Heraclitus had banished all rest and continuance from the totality of things ; and it is doubtless in this very respect that he accuses the eye and the ear of deception, because they reveal to men a continuance where there is only an uninterrupted change. Heraclitus has analyzed the principle of the becoming still more closely, in the propositions which he utters, to accounc for the origin of things, where he shows that all becoming must be conceived as the product of warring opposites, as the harmonious tinion of opposite determinations. Hence his two well-known HERACLITUS. 3P propositions : " Strife is the father of things," and " The One setting itself at variance with itself, harmonizes with itself, like the harmony of the bow and the viol." " Unite," so runs another of his sayings, " the whole and the not-whole, the coalescing and the not-coalescing, the harmonious and the discordant, and thus we have the one becoming from the all, and the all from the one." 4. The Principle of Fire. — In what relation does the prin- ciple of fire, which is also ascribed to Heraclitus, stand to the principle of the becoming ? Aristotle says that he took fire as his principle, in the same way that Thales took water, and Anax- imenes took air. But it is clear we must not interpret this to mean that Heraclitus regarded fire as the original material or fundamental element of things, after the manner of the Ionics. If he ascribed reality only to the becoming, it is impossible ,that he should have set by the side of this becoming, yet another ele- mental matter as a fundamental substance. When, therefore, Heraclitus calls the world an ever-living fire, which in certain stages and certain degrees extinguishes and again enkindles itself, when he says that every thing can be exchanged for fire, and fire for every thing, just as we barter things for gold and gold for things, he can only mean thereby that fire represents the abiding power of this eternal transformation and transposition, in other words, the conception of life, in the most obvious and efi"ective way. We might name fire, in the Heraclitic sense, the symbol or the manifestation of the becoming, but that it is also with him the substratum of movement, i. e. the means with which the power of movement, which is antecedent to all matter, serves it self in order to bring out the living process of things. In the same way Heraclitus goes on to explain the manifoldness of things, by affirming that they arise from certain hindrances and a partial extinction of this fire. The product of its extremest hindrance is the earth, and the other things lie intermediately between. 6. Transition to the Atomists. — We have above regarded the Heraclitic principle as the consequent of the Eleatic, but we o* 34 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. might as properly consider the two as antitheses. While Herar clitus destroys all abiding being in an absolutely flowing becoming, so, on the other hand, Parmenides destroys all becoming in an absolutely abiding being ; and while the former charges the eye and the ear with deception, in that they transform the flowing becoming into a quiescent being, the latter also accuses these same senses of an untrue representation, in that they draw the abiding being into the movement of the becoming. We can therefore say that the being and the becoming are equally valid antitheses, which demand again a synthesis and reconciliation. But now can we say that Heraclitus actually and satisfactorily solved the problem of Zeno ? Zeno had shown every thing actual to be a contradiction, and from this had inferred their not-being, and it is only in this inference that Heraclitus deviates from the Eleatics. He also regarded the phenomenal world as an existing contradiction, but he clung to this contradiction as to an ultimate fact. That which had been the negative result of the Eleatics, he uttered as his positive principle. The dialectics which Zeno had subjectively used against the phenomenal, he directed objec- tively as a proof for the becoming. But this becoming which the Eleatics had thought themselves obliged to deny entirely, Hera- clitus did not explain by simply asserting that it was the only true principle. The question continually returned — why is all being a becoming? Why does the one go out ever into the many ? To give an answer to this question, i. e. to explain the becoming from the pre-supposed principle of being, forms the stand-point and problem of the Empedoclean and Atomistic philosophy. EMPEDOCLES. 85 SECTION VIII. EMPEDOCLES. 1. General View. — Empedocles was born at Agrigentum, and is extolled by the ancients as a natural philosopher, physician and poet, and also as a seer and worker of miracles. He flourished about 440 B. C, and was consequently younger than Parmenides and Heraclitus. He wrote a doctrinal poem concerning nature, which has been preserved to us in tolerably complete fragments. His philosophical system may be characterized in brief, as an attempt to combine the Eleatic being and the Heraclitic becom- ing. Starting with the Eleatic thought, that neither any thing which had previously been could become, nor any thing which now is could depart, he sets up as unchangeable being, four eternal original materials, which, though divisible, were indepen- dent, and underived from each other. In this we have what in our day are called the four elements. With this Eleatic thought he united also the Heraclitic view of nature, and suffered his four elements to become mingled together, and to receive a form by the working of two moving powers, which he names unifying friendship and dividing strife. Originally, these four elements were absolutely alike and unmovable, dwelling together in a di- vine sphere where friendship united them, until gradually strife pressing from the circumference to the centre of the sphere {i. e. attaining a separating activity), broke this union, and the forma- tion of the world immediately began as the result. 2. The Four Elements. — With his doctrine of the four ele- ments, Empedocles, on the one side, may be joined to the series of the Ionic philosophers, but, on the other, he is excluded from this by his assuming the original elements to be four. He is dis- tinctly said by the ancients to have originated the theory of the four elements. He is more definitely distinguished from the old Ionics, from the fact that he ascribed to his four " root-elements" a changeless being, by virtue of which they neither arose from 36 A fflSTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. each other nor departed into each other, and were capable of no change of essence but only of a change of state. Every thing which is called arising and departing, every change rests there- fore only upon the mingling and withdrawing of these eternal and fundamental materials ; the inexhaustible manifoldness of being rests upon the different proportions in which these elements are mingled. Every becoming is conceived as such only as a change of place. In this we have a mechanical in opposition to a dynamic explanation of nature. 3. The Two Powers. — "Whence now can arise any becoming, if in matter itself there is found no principle to account for the change ? Since Empedocles did not, like the Eleatics, deny that there was change, nor yet, like Heraclitus, introduce it in his matter, as an indwelling principle, so there was no other course left him but to place, by the side of his matter, a moving power. The opposition of the one and the many which had been set up by his predecessors, and which demanded an explanation, led him to ascribe to this moving power, two originally diverse directions, viz. : repulsion and attraction. The separation of the one into the many, and the union again of the many into the one, had in- dicated an opposition of powers which Heraclitus had already recognized. While now Parmenides starting from the one had made love as his principle, and Heraclitus starting from the many had made strife as his, Empedocles combines the two as the prin- ciple of his philosophy. The difficulty is, he has not sufficiently limited in respect to one another, the sphere of operation of these two directions of his power. Although to friendship belonged peculiarly the attractive, and to strife the repelling function, yet does Empedocles, on the other hand, suffer his strife to have in the formation of the world a unifying, and his friendship a dividing effect. In fact, the complete separation of a dividing and unify- ing power in the movement of the becoming, is an unmaintainable abstraction. 4. Relation of the Empedoclean to the Eleatic and Heraclitic Philosophy. — Empedocles, by placing, as the prin- ciple of the becoming, a moving power by the side of his matter, THE ATOMISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 37 makes his philosopliy a mediation of the Eleatic and Heraclitic principles, or more properly a placing of them side by side. He has interwoven these two principles in equal proportions in his system. With the Eleatics he denied all arising and departing, i. e. the transition of being into not-being and of not-being into being, and with Heraclitus he shared the interest to find an ex- planation for change. From the former he derived the abiding, unchangeable being of his fundamental matter, and from the latter the principle of the moving power. With the Eleatics, in fine, he considered the true being in an original and undistinguishable unity as a sphere, and with Heraclitus, he regarded the present world as a constant product of striving powers and oppositions. He has, therefore, been properly called an Eclectic, who has united the fundamental thoughts of his two predecessors, though not always in a logical way. SECTION IX. THE ATOMISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 1. Its Propounders. — Empedocles had sought to effect a combination of the Eleatic and Heraclitic principle — the same was attempted, though in a different way, by the Atomists, Leu- oippus and Democritus. Democritus, the better known of the two, was the son of rich parents, and was born about 460 B. C. in Abdera, an Ionian colony. He travelled extensively, and no Greek before the time of Aristotle possessed such varied attain- ments. He embodied the wealth of his collected knowledge in a series of writings, of which, however, only a few fragments have come down to us. For rhythm and elegance of language, Cicero compared him with Plato. He died in a good old age. 2. The Atoms. — Empedocles derived all determinateness of the phenomenal from a certain number of qualitatively determined and undistinguishable original materials, while the Atomists de- 38 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. rived the same from an originally unlimited number of constituent elements, or atoms, which were homogeneous in respect of quality, but diverse in respect of form. These atoms are unchangeable, material particles, possessing indeed extension, but yet indivisible, and can only be determined in respect of magnitude. As being, and without quality, they are entirely incapable of any transfor- mation or qualitative change, and, therefore, all becoming is, as with Empedocles, only a change of place. The manifoldness of the phenomenal world is only to be explained from the different form, disposition, and arrangement of the atoms as they become, in various ways, united. 3. The Fulness and the Yoid. — The atoms, in order to be atoms, i. e. undivided and impenetrable unities, — must be mutually limited and separated. There must be something set over against them which preserves them as atoms, and which is the original cause of their separateness and impenetrability. This is the void space, or more strictly the intervals which are found between the atoms, and which hinder their mutual contact. .The atoms, as being and absolute fulness, and the interval between them, as the void and the not-being, are two determinations which only represent in a real and objective way, what are in thought, as logical conceptions, the two elements in the Heraclitic becom- ing, viz. being and the not-being. But since the void space is one determination of being, it must possess objective reality no less than the atoms, and Democritus even went so far as to expressly affirm in opposition to the Eleatics, that being is no more than nothing. 4. The Atomistic Necessity. — Democritus, like Empedocles, though far more extensively than he, attempted to answer the question — whence arise these changes and movements which we behold ? Wherein lies the ground that the atoms should enter into these manifold combinations, and bring forth such a wealth of inorganic and organic forms ? Democritus attempted to solve the problem by affirming that the ground of movement lay in the gravity or original condition of the material particles, and, there- fore, in the matter itself, but in this way he only talked about the THE ATOMISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 39 question without answering it. The idea of an infinite series of causalities was thus attained, but not a final ground of all the manifestations of the becoming, and of change. Such a final ground was still to be sought, and as Democritus expressly de- clared that it could not lie in an ultimate reason (voOs), where Anaxagoras placed it, there only remained for him to find it in an absolute necessity, or a necessary pre-determinateness (avdyK-rj). This he adopted as his '* final ground," and is said to have named it chance (tvxii)j opposition to the inquiry after final causes, or the Anaxagorean teleology. Consequent upon this, we find as the prominent characteristic of the later Atomistic school (Diagoras the Melier), polemics against the gods of the people, and a con- stantly more publicly affirmed Atheism and Materialism. 5. Relative Position of the Atomistic Philosophy. — He- gel characterizes the relative position of the Atomistic Philosophy as follows, viz. : — " In the Eleatic Philosophy being and not-being stand as antitheses, — ^being alone is, and not-being is not ; in the Heraclitic idea, being and not-being are the same, — ^both together, i. e. the becoming, are the predicate of concrete being ; but being and not-being, as objectively determined, or in other words, as appearing to the sensuous intuition, are precisely the same as the antithesis of the fulness and the void. Parmenides, Heraclitus and the Atomists all sought for the abstract universal ; Parme- nides found it in being ^ Heraclitus in the jjrocess of being per se, and the Atomists in the determiyiation of being per s^." So much of this as ascribes to the Atomists the characteristic predi- cate of being per se is doubtless correct, — ^but the real thought of the Atomistic system is rather analogous with the Empedoc- lean, to explain the possibility of the becoming, by presupposing these substances as possessing being per se, but without quality. To this end the not-being or the void, i. e. the side which is op- posed to the Eleatic principle, is elaborated with no less care than the side which harmonizes with it, i. e. that the atoms are without quality and never change in their original elements. The Atom- istic Philosophy is therefore a mediation between the Eleatic and tbe Heraclitic principles. It is Eleatic in affirming the undivided 40 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. being per se of the atoms ; — Heraclitic, in declaring their mul- teity and manifoldness. It is Eleatic in the declaration of an absolute fulness in the atoms, and Heraclitic in the claim of a real not-being, i. e. the void space. It is Eleatic in its denial of the becoming, i. e. of the arising and departing, — and Heraclitic in its affirmation that to the atoms belong movement and a capa- city for unlimited combinations. The Atomists carried out their leading thought more logically than Empedocles, and we might even say that their system is the perfection of a purely mechanical explanation of nature, since all subsequent Atomists, even to our own day, have only repeated their fundamental conceptions. But the great defect which cleaves to every Atomistic system, Aris- totle has justly recognized, when he shows that it is a contradic- tion, on the one hand, to set up something corporeal or space-filling as indivisible, and on the other, to derive the extended from that which has no extension, and that the consciousless and inconceiv- able necessity of Democritus is especially defective, in that it totally banishes from nature all conception of design. This is the point to which Anaxagoras turns his attention, and introduces his principle of an intelligence working with design. SECTION X. ANAXAGORAS. 1. His Personal History. — Anaxagoras is said to have been born at Clazamena, about the year 500 B. C. ; to have gone to Athens immediately, or soon after the Persian war, to have lived and taught there for a long time, and, finally, accused of irreve- rence to the gods, to have fled, and died at Lampsacus, at the age of 72. He it was who first planted philosophy at Athens, which from this time on became the centre of intellectual life in Greece. Through his personal relations to Pericles, Euripides, and other important men, — among whom Themistocles and Thucydides ANAXAGORAS. 41 should be named — he exerted a decisive influence upon the cul- ture of the age. It was on account of this that the charge of defaming the gods was brought against him, doubtless by the political opponents of Pericles. Anaxagoras wrote a work " Con- cerning Nature,''^ which in the time of Socrates was widely circu- lated. 2. His Relation to his Predecessors. — The system of An- axagoras starts from the same point with his predecessors, and is simply another attempt at the solution of the same problem. Like Empedocles and the Atomists so did Anaxagoras most vehe- mently deny the becoming. " The becoming and departing," — so runs one of his sayings — " the Greeks hold without foundation, for nothing can ever be said to become or depart ; but, since ex- isting things may be compounded together and again divided, we should name the becoming more correctly a combination, and the departing a separation. From this view, that every thing arose by the mingling of different elements, and departed by the withdraw- ing of these elements, Anaxagoras, like his predecessors, was obliged to separate matter from the moving power. But though his point of starting was the same, yet was his direction essen- tially different from that of any previous philosopher. It was clear that neither Empedocles nor Democritus had satisfactorily apprehended the moving power. The mythical energies of love and hate of the one, or the unconscious necessity of the other, explained nothing, and least of all, the design of the becoming in nature. The conception of an activity which could thus work designedly, must, therefore, be brought into the conception of the moving power, and this Anaxagoras accomplished by setting up the idea of a world-forming intelligence (i/o9?), absolutely sepa^ rated from all matter and working with design. 3. The Principle of the voS?. — Anaxagoras described this intelligence as free to dispose, unmingled with any thing, the ground of movement, but itself unmoved, every where active, and the most refined and pure of all things. Although these predi- cates rest partly upon a physical analogy, and do not exhibit purely the conception of immateriality, yet on the other hand 42 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. does the attribute of thought and of a conscious acting with de- sign admit no doubt to remain of the decided idealistic character of the Anaxagorean principle. Nevertheless, Anaxagoras went no farther than to enunciate his fundamental thought without attempting its complete application. The explanation of this is obvious from the reasons which first led him to adopt his princi- ple. It was only the need of an original cause of motion, to which also might be attributed the capacity to work designedly, which had led him to the idea of an immaterial principle. His vovs, therefore, is almost nothing but a mover of matter, and in this function nearly all its activity is expended. Hence the uni- versal complaint of the ancients, especially of Plato and Aris- totle, respecting the mechanical character of his doctrine. In Plato's Phsedon Socrates relates that, in the hope of being directed beyond a simple occasioning, or mediate cause, he had turned to the book of Anaxagoras, but had found there only a mechanical instead of a truly teleological explanation of being. And as Plato so also does Aristotle find fault with Anaxagoras in that, while he admits mind as the ultimate ground of things, he yet resorts to it only as to a Deus ex machina for the explanation of phenomena, whose necessity he could not derive from the causality in nature. Anaxagoras, therefore, has rather postulated than proved mind as an energy above nature, and as the truth and actuality of natural being. The further extension of his system, his doctrine concerning the homoiomeria (constituent elements of things), which according to him existed together originally in a chaotic condition until with their separation and parting the formation of the world began — can here only be mentioned. 4. Anaxagoras as the close of the pre-Socratic Real- isiii. — With the Anaxagorean principle of the vot)?, i. e. with the acquisition of an absolutely immaterial principle, closes the real- istic period of the old Grecian Philosophy. Anaxagoras com- bined together the principles of all his predecessors. The infinite matter of the Hylics is represented in his chaotic original ming- ling of things ; the Eleatic pure being appears in the idea of the THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 43 vovs; the Heraclitic power of becoming and the Empedoclean moving energies are both seen in the creating and arranging power of the eternal mind, while the Democritic atoms come to view in the homoiomeria. Anaxagoras is the closing point of an old and the beginning point of a new course of development, — the latter through the setting up of his ideal principle, and the former through the defective and completely physical manner in which this principle was yet again applied. SECTION XI. THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 1. Relation of the Sophistic Philosophy to the Anaxa- GOREAN Principle. — Anaxagoras had formed the conception of mind, and in this had recognized thought as a power above the objective world. Upon this newly conquered field the Sophistic philosophy now began its gambols, and with childish wantonness delighted itself in setting at work this power, and in destroying, by means of a subjective dialectic, all objective determinations. The Sophistic philosophy — ^though of far more significance from its relation to the culture of the age than from its philosophy — had for its starting principle the breach which Anaxagoras had com- menced between the subjective and the objective, — the Ego and the external world. The subject, after recognizing himself as something higher than the objective world, and especially as some- thing above the laws of the state, above custom and religious tradition and the popular faith, in the next place attempted to prescribe laws for this objective world, and instead of beholding in it the historical manifestation of reason, he looked upon it only as an exanimated matter, upon which he might exercise his will. The Sophistic philosophy should be characterized as the clear- ing up reflection. It is, therefore, no philosophical system, for its doctrines and afi&rmations exhibit often so popular and even trivial 44 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. a character that for their own sake they would merit no place at all in the history of philosophy. It is also no philosophical school in the ordinary sense of the term, — for Plato cites a vast number of persons under the common name of " Sophists," — but it is an intellectual and widely spread direction of the age, which had struck its roots into the whole moral, political, and religious character of the Athenian life of that time, and which may be called the Athenian clearing up period. 2. Relation of the Sophistic Philosophy to the Univer- sal Life of that Age. — The Sophistic philosophy is, theoreti- cally, what the whole Athenian life during the Peloponnesian war was practically. Plato justly remarks in his Eepublic that the doctrines of the Sophists only expressed the very principles which guided the course of the great mass of men of that time in their civil and social relations, and the hatred with which they were pursued by the practical statesmen, clearly indicates the jealousy with which the latter saw in them their rivals and the destroyers of their polity. If the absoluteness of the empirical subject — i. e. the view that the individual Ego can arbitrarily determine what is true, right and good, — is in fact the theoretical principle of the Sophistic philosophy, so does this in a practical direction, as an unlimited Egoism meet us in all the spheres of the public and private life of that age. The public life had become an arena of passion and selfishness ; those party struggles which racked Athens during the Peloponnesian war had blunted and stifled the moral feeling ; every individual accustomed himself to set up his own private interest above that of the state and the common weal, and to seek in his own arbitrariness and advantage the measuring rod for all his actions. The Protagorean sentence that " the man is the measure of all things " became practically carried out only too faithfully, and the influence of the orator in the assemblies of the people and the courts, the corruptibility of the great masses and their leaders, and the weak points which showed to the adroit student of human nature the covetousness, vanity, and factious- ness of others around him, ofl'ered only too many opportunities to bring this rule into practice. Custom had lost its weight ; the THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 45 laws were regarded as only an agreement of the majority, the civil ordinance as an arbitrary restriction, the moral feeling as the effect of the policy of the state in education, the faith in the gods as a human invention to intimidate the free power of action, while piety was looked upon as a statute which some men have enacted and which every one else is justified in using all his elo- quence to change. This degradation of a necessity, which is con- formable to nature and reason, and which is of universal validity, — to an accidental human ordinance, is chiefly the point in which the Sophistic philosophy came in contact with the universal con- sciousness of the educated class of that period, and we cannot with certainty determine what share science and what share the life may have had in this connection, — whether the Sophistic philosophy found only the theoretical formula for the practical life and tendencies of the age, or whether the moral corruption was rather a consequence of that destructive influence which the principles of the Sophists exerted upon the whole course of cotemporaneous thought. It would be, however, to mistake the spirit of history if we were only to bewail the epoch of the Sophists instead of admitting for it a relative justification. These phenomena were in part the necessary product of the collective development of the age. The faith in the popular religion fell so suddenly to the ground simply because it possessed in itself no inner, moral support. The grossest vices and acts of baseness could all be justified and ex cused from the examples of mythology. Even Plato himself, though otherwise an advocate of a devout faith in the traditional religion, accuses the poets of his nation with leading the very moral feeling astray, through the unworthy representations which they had spread abroad concerning the gods and the hero world. It was moreover unavoidable that the advancing science should clash with tradition. The physical philosophers had already long lived in open hostility to the popular religion, and the more con- vincingly they demonstrated by analogies and laws that many things which had hitherto been regarded as the immediate efi'ect of Divine omnipotence, were only the results of natural causes 46 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. SO much the more easily would it happen that the educated classes would become perplexed in reference to all their previous convic- tions. It was no wonder then that the transformed consciousness of the time should penetrate all the provinces of art and poesy ; that in sculpture, wholly analogous to the rhetoric art of the Sophistic philosophy, the emotive should occupy the place of the elevated style ; that Euripides, the sophist among tragedians, should bring the whole philosophy of the time and its manner of moral reflection upon the stage ; and that, instead of like the earlier poets, bringing forward his actors to represent an idea, he should use them only as means to excite a momentary emotion or some other stage effect. 8. Tendencies of the Sophistic Philosophy. — To give a definite classification of the Sophistic philosophy, which should be derived from the conception of the general phenomena of the age, is exceedingly difficult, since, like the French "clearing up" of the last century, it entered into every department of knowledge. The Sophists directed the universal culture of the time. Prota- goras was known as a teacher of virtue, Grorgias as a rhetorician and politician, Prodicus as a grammarian and teacher of syn- onyms, Hippias as a man of various attainments, who besides astronomical and mathematical studies busied himself with a theory of mnemonics ; others took for their problem the art of education, and others still the explanation of the old poets ; the brothers Euthydemus and Dionysidorus gave instruction in the bearing of arms and military tactics; many among them, as Gorgias, Prodicus, and Hippias, were intrusted with embassies : in short the Sophists, each one according to his individual ten- dency, took upon themselves every variety of calling and entered into every sphere of science ; their method is the only thing com- mon to all. Moreover the relation of the Sophists to the educated public, their striving after popularity, fame and money, disclose the fact that their studies and occupations were for the most part controlled, not by a subjective scientific interest, but by some ex- ternal motive. With that roving spirit which was an essential peculiarity of the later Sophists, travelling from city to city, and I I THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 47 announcing themselves as thinkers by profession — and giving their instructions with prominent reference to a good recompense and the favor of the rich private classes, it was very natural that they should discourse upon the prominent questions of universal inter- est and of public culture, with occasional reference also to the favorite occupation of this or that rich man with whom they might be brought in contact. Hence their peculiar strength lay far more in a formal dexterity, in an acuteness of thought and a capacity of bringing it readily into exercise, in the art of discourse than in any positive knowledge ; their instruction in virtue was given either in positive dogmatism or in empty bombast, and even where the Sophistic philosophy became really polymathic, the art of speech still remained as the great thing. So we find in Xeno- phon, Hippias boasting that he can speak repeatedly upon every subject and say something new each time, while we hear it ex- pressly affirmed of others, that they had no need of positive knowledge in order to discourse satisfactorily upon every thing, and to answer every question extemporaneously ; and when many Sophists make it a great point to hold a well-arranged discourse about something of the least possible significance {e. g. salt), so do we see that with them the thing was only a means while the word was the end, and we ought not to be surprised that in this respect the Sophistic philosophy sunk to that empty technicality which Plato in his Phaedrus, on account of its want of character, subjects to so rigid a criticism. 4. The Significance of the Sophistic Philosophy from its RELATION to THE CuLTURE OF THE Age. — The Scientific and moral defect of the Sophistic philosophy is at first view obvious ; and. since certain modern writers of history with over-officious zeal have painted its dark sides in black, and raised an earnest accu- sation against its frivolity, immorality, and greediness for pleasure, its conceitedness and selfishness, and bare appearance of wisdom and art of dispute — it needs here no farther elucidation. But the point in it most apt to be overlooked is the merit of the Sophists in their effect upon the culture of the age. To say, as is done, that they had only the negative merit of calling out the opposi- 48 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. tion of Socrates and Plato, is to leave the immense influence and tlie high fame of so many among them, as well as the revolution which they brought about in the thinking of a whole nation, an inexplicable phenomenon. It were inexplicable that e. g. Socrates should -attend the lectures of Prodicus, and direct to him other students, if he did not acknowledge the worth of his grammatical performances or recognize his merit for the soundness of his logic. Moreover, it cannot be denied that Protagoras has hit upon many correct principles of rhetoric, and has satisfactorily established certain grammatical categories. Generally may it be said of the Sophists, that they threw among the people a fulness in every department of knowledge ; that they strewed about them a vast number of fruitful germs of development ; that they called out investigations in the theory of knowledge, in logic and in lan- guage ; that they laid the basis for the methodical treatment of many branches of human knowledge, and that they partly founded and partly called forth that wonderful intellectual activity which characterized Athens at that time. Their greatest merit is their service in the department of language. They may even be said to have created and formed the Attic prose. They are the first who made style as such a separate object of attention and study, and who set about rigid investigations respecting number and the art of rhetorical representation. With them Athenian eloquence, which they first incited, begins. Antiphon as well as Isocrates — the latter the founder of the most flourishing school of Greek rhetoric — are offshoots of the Sophistic philosophy. In all this there is ground enough to regard this whole phenomenon as not barely a symptom of decay. 5. Individual Sophists. — The first, who is said to have been called, in the received sense, Sophist, is Protagoras of Abdera, who flourished about 440 b. c. He taught, and for wages, in Sicily and in Athens, but was driven out of the latter place as a reviler of the gods, and his book concerning the gods was burnt by the herald in the public market-place. It began with these words : "I can know nothing concerning the gods, whether they exist or not ; for we are prevented from gaining such knowledge THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 49 not only by the obscurity of the thing itself, but by the shortness of the human life." In another writing he develops his doctrine concerning knowing or not-knowing. Starting from the Heraclitic position that every thing is in a constant flow, and applying this preeminently to the thinking subject, he taught that the man is the measure of all things, who determines in respect of being that it may be, and of not-being that it may not be, i. e. that is true for the perceiving subject which he, in the constant movement of things and of himself, at every moment perceives and is sensible of — and hence he has theoretically no other relation to the ex- ternal world than the sensuous apprehension, and practically no other than the sensuous desire. But now, since perception and sensation are as diverse as the subjects themselves, and are in the highest degree variable in the very same subject, there follows the farther result that nothing has an objective validity and deter- mination, that contradictory affirmations in reference to the same object must be received as alike true, and that error and contra- diction cannot be. Protagoras does not seem to have made any efforts to give these frivolous propositions a practical and logical application. According to the testimony of the ancients, a per- sonal character worthy of esteem, cannot be denied him ; and even Plato, in the dialogue which bears his name, goes no farther than to object to his complete obscurity respecting the nature of morality, while, in his Gorgias and Philebus, he charges the later Sophists with affirming the principles of immorality and moral baseness. Next to Protagoras, the most famous Sophist was Gorgias. During the Peloponnesian war (426 b. c), he came from Leontium to Athens in order to gain assistance for his native city against the encroachments of Syracuse. After the successful accomplishment of his errand he still abode for some time in Athens, but resided the latter part of his life in Thessaly, where he died about the same time with Socrates. The pompous ostentation of his ex- ternal appearance is often ridiculed by Plato, and the discourses through which he was wont to exhibit himself display the same character, attempting, through poetical ornament, and florid 3 50 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. metaphors, and uncommon words, and a mass of hitherto unheard of figures of speech, to dazzle and delude the mind. As a phi- losopher he adhered to the Eleatics, especially to Zeno, and attempts to prove upon the basis of their dialectic schematism, that universally nothing is, or if there could be a being, it would not be cognizable, or if cognizable it would not be communicable. Hence his writing bore characteristically enough the title — " Con- cerning Not-heing or Nature?'' The proof of the first proposition that universally nothing is, since it can be established neither as being nor as not-being, nor yet as at the same time both being and not-being, rests entirely upon the position that all existence is a space-filling existence (has place and body), and is in fact the final consequence which overturns itself, in other words the self-destruction of the hitherto physical method of philosophizing. The later Sophists with reckless daring carried their conclu- sions far beyond Gorgias and Protagoras. They were for the most part free thinkers, who pulled to the ground the religion, laws, and customs of their birth. Among these should be named, prominently, the tyrant Critias, Polus, Callicles, and Thrasy- machus. The two latter openly taught the right of the stronger as the law of nature, the unbridled satisfaction of desire as the natural right of the stronger, and the setting up of restraining laws as a crafty invention of the weaker ; and Critias, the most talented but the most abandoned of the thirty tyrants, wrote a poem, in which he represented the faith in the gods as an invention of crafty statesmen. Hippias of Elis, a man of great knowledge, bore an honorable character, although he did not fall behind the rest in bombast and boasting; but before all, was Prodicus, in reference to whom it became a proverb to say — " as wise as Pro- dicus," and concerning whom Plato himself and even Aristophanes never spoke without veneration. Especially famous among the ancients were his parenetical (persuasive) lectures concerning the choice of a mode of life (Xenophon's Memorabilia, II. 1), con- cerning external good and its use, concerning life and death, &c., discourses in which he manifests a refined moral feeling, and hia observation of life ; although through the want of a higher ethical THE SOPHISTIC PHILOSOPHY. 51 and scientific principle, lie must be placed behind Socrates, whose forerunner he has been called. The later generations of Sophists, as they are shown in the Euthydemus of Plato, sink to a common level of bufibonery and disgraceful strife for gain, and comprise their whole dialectic art in certain formulas for entangling fallacies. 6. Transition to Socrates and Characteristic of the fol- lowing Period. — That which is true in the Sophistic philosophy is the truth of the subjectivity, of the self-consciousness, i. e. the demand that every thing which I am to admit must be shown as rational before my own consciousness — that which is false in it is its apprehension of this subjectivity as nothing farther than finite, empirical egoistic subjectivity, i. e. the demand that my accidental will and opinion should determine what is rational ; its truth is that it set up the principle of freedom, of self-certainty ; its un- truth is that it established the accidental will and notion of the individual upon the throne. To carry out now the principle of freedom and self-consciousness to its truth, to gain a true world of objective thought with a real and distinct content, by the same means of reflection which the Sophists had only used to destroy it, to establish the objective will, the rational thinking, the absolute or ideal in the place of the empirical subjectivity was the problem of the next advent in philosophy, the problem which Socrates took up and solved. To make the absolute or ideal subjectivity instead of the empirical for a principle, is to affirm that the true measure of all things is not my {%. e. the individual person's) opinion, fancy and will ; that what is true, right and good, does not de- pend upon my caprice and arbitrary determination, or upon that of any other empirical subject ; but while it is my thinking, it is my thinking, the rational within me, which has to decide upon all these points. But my thinking, my reason, is not something specially belonging to me, but something common to every rational being; something universal, and in so far as I am a rational and thinking being, is my subjectivity a universal one. But every think- ing individual has the consciousness that what he holds as right, as duty, as good or evil, does not appear as such to him alone but 52 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. to every rational being, and that consequently his thinking has "the character of universality, of universal validity, in a word — of objectivity. This then in opposition to the Sophistic philosophy is the stand-point of Socrates, and therefore with him the phi- losophy of ohjective thought begins. What Socrates could do in opposition to the Sophists was to show that reflection led to the same results as faith or obedience, hitherto without reflection, had done, and that the thinking man guided by his free conscious- ness and his own conviction, would learn to form the same judg- ments and take the same course to which life and custom had already and unconsciously induced the ordinary man. The posi- tion, that while the man is the measure of all things, it is the man as universal, as thinking, as rational, is the fundamental thought of the Socratic philosophy, which is, by virtue of this thought, the positive complement of the Sophistic principle. With Socrates begins the second period of the Grecian philoso- phy. This period contains three philosophical systems, whose authors, standing to each other in the personal relation of teacher and pupil, represent three successive generations, — Socrates, Plato, Aristotle. •♦> SECTION XII. SOCRATES.'''" 1. His Personal Character. — The new philosophical princi- ple appears in the personal character of Socrates. His philosophy is his mode of acting as an individual ; his life and doctrine can- not be separated. His biography, therefore, forms the only com- plete representation of his philosophy, and what the narrative of Xenophon presents us as the definite doctrine of Socrates, is con- sequently nothing but an abstract of his inward character, as * The article on Socrates, from page 52 to page 64, "was translated by Prof. N. G. Clark, of the University of Vermont. SOCRATES. 53 it found expression from time to time in his conversation. Plato yet more regarded his master as such an archetypal personality, and a luminous exhibition of the historical Socrates is the special object of his later and maturer dialogues, and of these again, the Symposium is the most brilliant apotheosis of the Eros incarnated in the person of Socrates, of the philosophical impulse transformed into character. Socrates was born in the year 469 B. C, the son of Sophro- niscus, a sculptor, and Phgenarete, a midwife. In his youth he was trained by his father to follow his own profession, and in this he is said not to have been without skill. Three draped figures of the Graces, called the work of Socrates, were seen by Pausanias, upon the Akropolis. Little farther is known of his education. He may have profited by the instruction of Prodicus and the musician, Damon, but he stood in no personal connection with the proper philosophers, who flourished before, or cotemporaneously with him. He became what he was by himself alone, and just for this reason does he form an era in the old philosophy. If the ancients call him a scholar of Anaxagoras, or of the natural phi- losopher, Archelaus, the first is demonstrably false, and the second, to say the least, is altogether improbable. He never sought other means of culture than those afforded in his native city. "With the exception of one journey to a public festival, the military campaigns which led him as far as Potidasa, Delion, and Amphi- polis, he never left Athens. The period when Socrates first began to devote himself to the education of youth, can be determined only approximately from the time of the first representation of the Clouds of Aristo- phanes, which was in the year 423. The date of the Delphic oracle, which pronounced him the wisest of men, is not known. But in the traditions of his followers, he is almost uniformly represented as an old, or as a gray-headed man. His mode of instruction, wholly different from the pedantry and boastful osten- tation of the Sophists, was altogether unconstrained, conversa- tional, popular, starting from objects lying nearest at hand and the most insignificant, and deriving the necessary illustrations and 54 A mSTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. proofs from the most common matters of every day life ; in fact, he was reproached by his cotemporaries for speaking ever only of drudges, smiths, cobblers and tanners. So we find him at the market, in the gymnasia, in the workshops, busy early and late, talking with youth, with young men, and with old men, on the proper aim and business of life, convincing them of their igno- rance, and wakening up in them the slumbering desires after knowledge. In every human effort, whether directed to the interests of the commonwealth, or to the private individual and the gains of trade, to science or to art, this master of helps to spiritual births could find fit points of contact for the awakening of a true self-knowledge, and a moral and religious consciousness. However often his attempts failed, or were rejected with bitter scorn, or requited with hatred and unthankfulness, yet, led on by the clear conviction that a real improvement in the condition of the state could come only from a proper education of its youth, he remained to the last true to his chosen vocation. Purely Greek in these relations to the rising generation, he designated himself, by preference, as the most ardent lover ; Greek too in this, that with him, notwithstanding these free relations of friend- ship, his own domestic life fell quite into the background. He nowhere shows much regard for his wife and children ; the noto- rious, though altogether too much exaggerated ill-nature of Xan- tippe, leads us to suspect, however, that his domestic relations were not the most happy. As a man, as a practical sage, Socrates is pictured in the brightest colors by all narrators. " He was," says Xenophon, "so pious, that he did nothing without the advice of the gods; so just, that he never injured any one even in the least ; so com- pletely master of himself, that he never chose the agreeable in- stead of the good ; so discerning, that he never failed in distin- guishing the better from the worse ; " in short, he was " just the best and happiest man possible." (Xen. Mem. I. 1, 11. lY. 8, 11.) Still that which lends to his person such a peculiar charm, is the happy blending and harmonious connection of all its char- acteristic traits, the perfection of a beautiful, plastic nature. In SOCRATES. 56 all this universality of his genius, in this force of character, hy which he combined the most contradictory and incongruous ele- ments into a harmonious whole, in this lofty elevation above every human weakness, — in a word, as a perfect model, he is most strik- ingly depicted in the brilliant eulogy of Alcibiades, in the Sym- posium of Plato. In the scantier representation of Xenophon, also, we find everywhere a classic form, a man possessed of the finest social culture, full of Athenian politeness, infinitely removed from every thing like gloomy asceticism, a man as valiant upon the field of battle as in the festive hall, conducting himself with the most unconstrained freedom, and yet with entire sobriety and self-control, a perfect picture of the happiest Athenian time, without the acerbity, the one-sidedness, and contracted reserve of the later moralists, an ideal representation of the genuinely human virtues. 2. Socrates and Aristophanes. — Socrates seems early to have attained universal celebrity through the peculiarities attach- ing to his person and character. Nature had furnished him with a remarkable external physiognomy. His crooked, turned-up nose, his projecting eye, his bald pate, his corpulent body, gave his form a striking similarity to the Silenic, a comparison which is carried out in Xenophon's " Feast," in sprightly jest, and in Plato's Symposium, with as much ingenuity as profoundness. To this was added his miserable dress, his going barefoot, his posture, his often standing still, and rolling his eyes. After all this, one will hardly be surprised that the Athenian comedy took advantage of such a remarkable character. But there was an- other and peculiar motive, which influenced Aristophanes. He was a most ardent admirer of the good old times, an enthusiastic eulogist of the manners and the constitution, under which the fathers had been reared. As it was his great object to waken up anew in his people, and to stimulate a longing after those good old times, his passionate hatred broke out against all modern efforts in politics, art and philosophy, of that increasing mock- wisdom, which went hand in hand with a degenerating democracy. Hence comes his bitter railing at Cleon, the Demagogue (in the 56 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Knights), at Euripides, the sentimental play- writer (in the Erogs) and at Socrates, the Sophist (in the Clouds). The latter, as the representative of a subtle, destructive philosophy, must have ap- peared to him just as corrupt and pernicious, as the party of pro- gress in politics, who trampled without conscience upon every thing which had come down from the past. It is, therefore, the fundamental thought of the Clouds to expose Socrates to public contempt, as the representative of the Sophistic philosophy, a mere semblance of wisdom, at once vain, profitless, corrupting in its influence upon the youth, and undermining all true discipline and morality. Seen in this light, and from a moral stand-point, the motives of Aristophanes may find some excuse, but they can- not be justified ; and his representation of Socrates, into whose character all the characteristic features of the Sophistic philoso- phy are interwoven, even the most contemptible and hateful, yet so that the most unmistakable likeness is still apparent, cannot be admitted on the ground that Socrates did really have the greatest formal resemblance to the Sophists. The Clouds can only be de- signated as a culpable misunderstanding, and as an act of gross injustice brought about by blinded passion; and Hegel, when he attempts to defend the conduct of Aristophanes, forgets, that, while the comic writer may caricature, he must do it without having recourse to public calumniation. In fact all the political and social tendencies of Aristophanes rest on a gross misunder- standing of historical development. The good old times, as he fancies them, are a fiction. It lies j ust as little in the realm of possibility, that a morality without reflection, and a homely in- genuousness, such as mark a nation's childhood, should be forced upon a time in which reflection has utterly eaten out all imme- diateness, and unconscious moral simplicity, as that a grown up man should become a child again in the natural way. Aristo- phanes himself attests the impossibility of such a return, when in a fit of humor, with cynic raillery, he gives up all divine and human authority to ridicule, and thereby, however commendable may have been the patriotic motive prompting him to this eomic extravagance, demonstrates, that he himself no longer stands SOCRATES. 57 upon the basis of the old morality, that he too is the son of his time. 3. The Condemnation of Socrates. — To this same confound- ing of his efforts with those of the Sophists, and the same ten- dency to restore by violent means the old discipline and morality, Socrates, twenty-four years later, fell a victim. After he had lived and labored at Athens for many years in his usual manner> after the storm of the Peloponnesian war had passed by, and this city had experienced the most varied political fortunes, in his seventieth year he was brought to trial and accused of neglecting the gods of the state, of introducing new deities, and also of corrupting the youth. His accusers were Melitus, a young poet, Anytus, a demagogue, and Lycon, an orator, men in every respect insignificant, and acting, as it seems, without motives of personal enmity. The trial resulted in his condemnation. After a fortu- nate accident had enabled him to spend thirty days more with his scholars in his confinement, spurning a flight from prison, he drank the poisoned cup in the year 399 B. C. The first motive to his accusation, as already remarked, was his identification with the Sophists, the actual belief that his doc- trines and activity were marked with the same character of hos- tility to the interests of the state, as those of the Sophists, which had already occasioned so much mischief. The three points in the accusation, though evidently resting on a misunderstanding, alike indicate this ; they are precisely those by which Aristophanes had sought to characterize the Sophist in the person of Socrates. This " corruption of the youth," this bringing in of new customs, and a new mode of culture and education generally, was precisely the charge which was brought against the Sophists ; moreover, in Plato's Menon, Anytus, one of the three accusers, is introduced as the bitter enemy of the Sophists and of their manner of in- struction. So too in respect to the denial of the national gods : before this, Protagoras, accused of denying the god.s, had been obliged to flee, and Prodicus, to drink hemlock, a victim to the same distrust. Even five years after the death of Socrates, Xeno- phon, who was not present at the trial, felt himself called upon 3* 58 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. to write his Memorabilia in defence of liis teacher, so wide-spread and deep-rooted was the prejudice against him. Beside this there was also a second, probably a more decisive reason. As the Sophistic philosophy was, in its very nature, eminently aristocratic, and Socrates, as a supposed Sophist, con- sequently passed for an aristocrat, his entire mode of life could not fail to make him appear like a bad citizen in the eyes of the restored democracy. He had never concerned himself in the affairs of the state, had never but once sustained an official char- acter, and then, as chief of the Prytanes, had disagreed with the will of the people and the rulers. (Plat. Apol. ^ 32. Xen. Mem. I. 1, 18.) In his seventieth year, he mounted the orator's stand for the first time in his life, on the occasion of his own accusation. His whole manner was somewhat cosmopolitan ; he is even said to have remarked, that he was not an Athenian, nor a Greek, but a citizen of the world. We must also take into account, that he found fault with the Athenian democracy upon every occasion, especially with the democratic institution of choice by lot, that he decidedly preferred the Spartan state to the Athenian, and that he excited the distrust of the "democrats by his confidential rela- tions with the former leaders of the oligarchic party. (Xen. Mem. I. 2, 9, sq.) Among others who were of the oligarchic interest, and friendly to the Spartans, Critias in particular, one of the thirty tyrants, had been his scholar ; so too Alcibiades — two men, who had been the cause of much evil to the Athenian people. If now we accept the uniform tradition, that two of his accusers were men of fair standing in the democratic party, and farther, that his judges were men who had fled before the thirty tyrants, and later had overthrown the power of the oligarchy, we find it much more easy to understand how they, in the case before them, should have supposed they were acting wholly in the interest of the democratic party, when they pronounced condemnation upon the accused, especially as enough to all appearance could be brought against him. The hurried trial presents nothing very remarkable, in a generation which had grown up during the Peloponnesian war, and in a people that adopted and repented of their passion- SOCRATES. 59 ato resolves with the like haste. Yea, more, if we consider that Socrates spurned to have recourse to the usual means and forms adopted by those accused of capital crime, and to gain the sym- pathy of the people by lamentations, or their favor by flattery, that he in proud consciousness of his innocence defied his judges, it becomes rather a matter of wonder, that his condemnation was carried by a majority of only three to six votes. And even now he might have escaped the sentence to death, had he been willing to bow to the will of the sovereign people for the sake of a com- mutation of his punishment. But as he spurned to set a value upon himself, by proposing another punishment, a fine, for example, instead of the one moved by his accuser, because this would be the same as to acknowledge himself guilty, his disdain could not fail to exasperate the easily excited Athenians, and no farther ex- planation is needed to show why eighty of his judges who had before voted for his innocence, now voted for his death. Such was the most lamentable result — a result, afterwards most deeply regretted by the Athenians themselves — of an accusation, which at the outset was probably only intended to humble the aristo- cratic philosopher, and to force him to an acknowledgment of the power and the majesty of the people. Hegel's view of the fate of Socrates, that it was the result of the collision of equally just powers — the Tragedy of Athens as he calls it — and that guilt and innocence were shared alike on both sides, cannot be maintained on historical grounds, since Socrates can neither be regarded exclusively as the representative of the modern spirit, the principle of freedom, subjectivity, the concrete personality; nor his judges, as the representatives of the old Athenian unreflecting morality. The first cannot be, since Socrates, if his principle was at variance with the old Greek morality, rested nevertheless so far on the basis of tradition, that the accusations brought against him in this respect were false and groundless ; and the last cannot be, since at that time, after the close of the Peloponnesian war, the old morality and piety had long been wanting to the mass of the people, and given place to the modern culture, and the whole process against Socrates must 60 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. be regarded rather as an attempt to restore by violence, in con nectiou with the old constitution, the old defunct morality. The fault is not therefore the same on both sides, and it must be held, that Socrates fell a victim to a misunderstanding, and to an un- justifiable reaction of public sentiment. 4. The "Genius" (Sai/xovtov) of Socrates. — Those traces of the old religious sentiment, which have been handed down to us from so many different sources, and are certainly not to be explained from a bare accommodation to the popular belief, on the part of the philosopher, and which distinguish him so decidedly from the Sophists, show how little Socrates is really to be regarded as an innovator in discipline and morals. He commends the art of divination, believes in dreams, sacrifices with all proper care, speaks of the gods, of their omniscience, omnipresence, goodness, and complete sufficiency in themselves, even with the greatest reverence, and, at the close of his defence, makes the most solemn asseveration of his belief in their existence. In keeping with his attaching himself in this way to the popular religion, his new principle, though in its results hostile to all external authority, nevertheless assumed the form of the popular belief in " Demonic" signs and symbols. These suggestions of the " Demon " are a knowledge, which is at the same time connected with unconscious- ness. They occupy the middle ground between the bare external of the Greek oracle, and the purely internal of the spirit. That Socrates had the conception of a particular subject, a personal " Demon," or " Genius," is altogether improbable. Just as little can these " Demonic " signs, this inward oracle, whose voice Socrates professed to hear, be regarded after the modern accep- tation, simply as the personification of the conscience, or of the practical instinct, or of the individual tact. The first article in the form of accusation, which evidently refers to this very point, shows that Socrates did not speak barely metaphorically of this voice, to which he professed to owe his prophecies. And it was not solely in reference to those higher questions of decided im- portance, that Socrates had these suggestions, but rather and pre- eminently with respect to matters of mere accident and arbitrary SOCRATES. 61 choice, as for example, whether, and when, his friends should set out on a journey. It is no longer possible to explain the " Demon " or " Genius " of Socrates on psychological grounds ; there may have been something of a magnetic character about it. It is possible that there may be some connection between this and the many other ecstatic or cataleptic states, which are related of Socrates in the Symposium of Plato. 5. The Sources of the Philosophy of Socrates. — Well known is the old controversy, whether the picture of Socrates, drawn by Xenophon or by Plato, is the most complete and true to history, and which of the two men is to be considered as the more reliable source for obtaining a knowledge of his philosophy. This question is being decided more and more in favor of Xeno- phon. Grreat pains has been taken in former as in later times, to bring Xenophon's Memorabilia into disrepute, as a shallow and insufficient source, because their plain, and any thing other than speculative contents, seemed to furnish no satisfactory ground for such a revolution in the world of mind as is attributed to Socrates, or for the splendor which invests his name in history, or for the character which Plato assigns him ; because again the Memorabilia of Xenophon have especially an apologetic aim, and their defence does not relate so much to the philosopher as to the man ; and finally, because they have been supposed to have the appearance of carrying the philosophical over into the unphilo- sophical style of the common understanding. A distinction has therefore been made between an exoteric and an esoteric Socrates, obtaining the first from Xenophon, the latter from Plato. But the preference of Plato to Xenophon has in the first place no historical right in its favor, since Xenophon appears as a pro- per historian and claims historical credibility, while Plato on the other hand never professes to be an historical narrator, save in a few passages, and will by no means have all the rest which he puts in the mouth of Socrates understood as his authentic ex- pressions and discourse. There is, therefore, no historical reason for preferring the representation of Socrates which is given by Plato. In the second place, the under-valuation of Xenophon 62 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. rests, for the most part, on the false notion, that Socrates had a proper philosophy, i. e. a speculative system, and on an unhistorical mistaking of the limits by which the philosophical character of Socrates was conditioned and restricted. There was no proper Socratic doctrine, but a Socratic life ; and, just on this ground, are the different philosophical tendencies of his scholars to be explained. 6. The Universal Cilvracter of the Philosophizx'NG of Socrates. — The philosophizing of Socrates was limited and re- stricted by his opposition, partly to the preceding, and partly to the Sophistic philosophy. Philosophy before the time of Socrates had been in its essen- tial character investigation of nature. But in Socrates, the human mind, for the first time, turned itself in upon itself, upon its own being, and that too in the most immediate manner, by conceiving itself as active, moral spirit. The positive philoso- phizing of Socrates, is exclusively of an ethical character, ex- clusively an inquiry into the nature of virtue, so exclusively, and so onesidedly, that, as is wont to be the case upon the appearance of a new principle, it even expressed a contempt for the striving of the entire previous period, with its natural philosophy, and its mathematics. Setting every thing under the stand-point of im- mediate moral law, Socrates was so far from finding any object iii " irrational" nature worthy of study, that he rather, in a kind of gene- ral teleological manner, conceived it simply in the light of external means for the attainment of external ends ; yea, he would not even go out to walk, as he says in the Phaedrus of Plato, since one can learn nothing from trees and districts of country. Self-knowledge, the Delphic (yyco^t aavrov) appeared to him the only object worthy of a man, as the starting-point of all philosophy. Knowl- edge of every other kind, he pronounced so insignificant and worthless, that he was wont to boast of his ignorance, and to de- clare that he excelled other men in wisdom only in this, t}».at he was conscious of his own ignorance. (Plat. Ap. S. 21, 23.) The other side of the Socratic philosophizing, is its opposition to the philosophy of the time. His object, as is well understood, SOCRATES. 63 could have been only this, to place himself upon the same positior. as that occupied by the philosophy of the Sophists, and overcome it on its own ground, and by its own principles. That Socrates shared in the general position of the Sophists, and even had msLuy features of external resemblance to them — the Socratic irony, for instance — has been remarked above. Many of his assertions, par- ticularly these propositions, that no man knowingly does wrong, and if a man were knowingly to lie, or to do some other wrong act, still he would be better than he who should do the same un- consciously, at first sight bear a purely Sophistic stamp. The great fundamental thought of the Sophistic philosophy, that all moral acting must be a conscious act, was also his. But whilst the Sophists made it their object, through subjective reflection to confuse and to break up all stable convictions, to make all rules re- lating to outward conduct impossible, Socrates had recognized thinking as the activity of the universal principle, free, objective thought as the measure of all things, and, therefore, instead of referring moral duties, and all moral action to the fancy and caprice of the individual, had rather referred all to true knowl- edge, to the essence of spirit. It was this idea of knowledge that led him to seek, by the process of thought, to gain a conceivable objective ground, something real, abiding, absolute, independent of the arbitrary volitions of the subject, and to hold fast to uncon- ditioned moral laws. Hegel expresses the same opinion, when he says that Socrates put morality from ethical grounds, in the place of the morality of custom and habit. Hegel distinguishes morality, as conscious right conduct, resting on reflection and moral principles, from the morality of unsophisticated, half-un- conscious virtue, which rests on the compliance with prevailing custom. The logical condition of this ethical striving of Socrates, was the determining of conceptions, the method of their forma- tion. To search out the " what " of every thing says Xenophon (Mem. TV. 6, 1.) was the uninterrupted care of Socrates, and Aristotle says expressly that a twofold merit must be ascribed to him, viz. : the forming of the method of induction and the giving of strictly logical definitions, — the two elements which constitute 64 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. the basis of science. How these two elements stand connected with the principle of Socrates we shall at once see. 7, The Socratic Method. — We must not regard the Socratic method as we are accustomed to speak of method in our day, i. e. as something which, as such, was distinctly in his consciousness, and which he abstracted from every concrete content, but it rather had its growth in the very mode of his philosophizing, which was not directed to the imparting of a system but to the education of the subject in philosophical thinking and life-. It is only a subjective technicality for his mode of instruction, the peculiar manner of his philosophical, familiar life. The Socratic method has a twofold side, a negative and a pos- itive one. The negative side is the well known Socratic irony. The philosopher takes the attitude of ignorance, and would appa- rently let himself be instructed by those with whom he converses, but through the questions which he puts, the unexpected conse- quences which he deduces, and the contradictions in which he involves the opposite party, he soon leads them to see that their supposed knowledge would only entangle and confuse them. In the embarrassment in which they now find themselves placed, and seeing that they do not know what they supposed, this supposed knowledge completes its own destruction, and the subject who had pretended to wisdom learns to distrust his previous opinions and firmly held notions. "What we knew, has contradicted itself," is the refrain of the most of these conversations. This result of the Socratic method was only to lead the sub- ject to know that he knew nothing, and a great part of the dia- logues of Xenophon and Plato go no farther than to represent ostensibly this negative result. But there is yet another element in his method in which the irony loses its negative appearance. The positive side of the Socratic method is the so-called ob- stetrics or art of intellectual midwifery. Socrates compares him- self with his mother Phaenarete, a midwife, because his position was rather to help others bring forth thoughts than to produce them himself, and because he took upon himself to distinguish the birth of an empty thought from one rich in its content. (Plato SOCRATES. 65 TheatcBtus^ p. 149.) Through this art of midwifery the philoso- pher, by his assiduous questioning, by his interrogatory dissection of the notions of him with whom he might be conversing, knew how to elicit from him a thought of which he had previously been unconscious, and how to help him to the birth of a new thought. A chief means in this operation was the method of induction^ or the leading of the representation to a conception. The philoso- pher, thus, starting from some individual, concrete case, and seiz- ing hold of the most common notions concerning it, and finding illustrations in the most ordinary and trivial occurrences, knew how to remove by his comparisons that which was individual, and by thus separating the accidental and contingent from the essen- tial, could bring up to consciousness a universal truth and a uni- versal determination, — in other words, could form conceptions. In order e. g. to find the conception of justice or valor, he would start from individual examples of them, and from these deduce the universal character or conception of these virtues. From this we see that the direction of the Socratic induction was to gain logical definitions. I define a conception when I develope what it is, its essence, its content. I define the conception of justice when I set up the common property and logical unity of all its different modes of manifestation. Socrates sought to go no far- ther than this. " To seek for the essence of virtue," says an Aristotelian writing {Eth. I. 5), " Socrates regarded as the problem of philosophy, and hence, since he regarded all virtue as a knowing, he sought to determine in respect of justice or valor what they might really be, i. e. he investigated their essence or conception." From this it is very easy to see the connection which his method of definitions or of forming conceptions had with his practical strivings. He went back to the conception of every individual virtue, e. g. justice, only because he was con- vinced that the knowledge of this conception, the knowledge of it for every individual case, was the surest guide for every moral relation. Every moral action, he believed, should start as a con- scious action from the conception. From this we might characterize the Socratic method as the 66 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. skill by whiicli a certain sum of given, homogeneous and individual phenomena was taken, and their logical unity, the universal prin- ciple which lay at their base, inductively found. This method presupposes the recognition that the essence of the objects must be comprehended in the thought, that the conception is the true being of the thing. Hence we see that the Platonic doctrine of ideas is only the objectifying of this method which in Socrates appears no farther than a subjective dexterity. The Platonic ideas are the universal conceptions of Socrates posited as real individual beings. Hence Aristotle [Metaph. XIII. 4) most fit- tingly characterizes the relation between the Socratic method and the Platonic doctrine of ideas with the words, "Socrates posits the universal conceptions not as separate, individual substances, while Plato does this, and names them ideas." 8. The Socratic Doctrine concerning Virtue. — The single, positive doctrinal sentence which has been transmitted us from Socrates is, that virtue is a knowing, — that, consequently, nothing is good which happens without discernment, and nothing bad which is done with discernment, or, what is the same thing, that no man is voluntarily vicious, that the base are such against their will, aye, even he who knowingly does wrong is better than he who does it ignorantly, because in the latter case, morality and true knowledge are both wanting, while in the former — if such a case could happen — morality alone is violated. Socrates could not conceive how a man should know the good and yet not do it ; it was to him a logical contradiction that the man who sought his own well being should at the same time knowingly despise it. Therefore, with him the good action followed as necessarily from the knowledge of the good as a logical conclusion from its pre- mise. The sentence that virtue is a knowing, has for its logical con- sequence the unity of virtue and for its practical consequence the teachableness of it. With these three propositions, in which every thing is embraced which we can properly term the Socratic philosophy, Socrates has laid the first foundation stone for a Bcientific treatment of ethics, a treatment which must be dated THE PARTIAL DISCIPLES OF SOCRATES. 67 first from him. But he laid only the foundation stone, for on the one side he attempted no carrying out of his principle into details, nor any setting up of a concrete doctrine of ethics, but only, after the ancient manner, referred to the laws of states and the unwritten laws of the universal human order, and on the other side, he has not seldom served himself with utilitarian motives to establish his ethical propositions, in other words he has referred to the external advantages and useful conseq[uences of virtue, by which the purity of his ethical point of view became tarnished SECTION XIII. THE PARTIAL DISCIPLES OF SOCRATES. 1. Their relation to the Socratic Philosophy. — The death of Socrates gave to his life an ideal perfection, and this be- came an animating principle which had its working in many directions. The apprehension of him as an ideal type forms the common character of the immediate Socratic schools. The fun- damental thought, that men should have one universal and essen- tially true aim, they all received from Socrates ; but since their master left no complete and systematic doctrine, but only his many-sided life to determine the nature of this aim, every thing would depend upon the subjective apprehension of the personal character of Socrates, and of this we should at the outset naturally expect to find among his different disciples a different estimate. Socrates had numerous scholars, but no school. Among these, three views of his character have found a place in history. That of Antisthenes, or the Cynical, that of Aristippus, or the Cyre- nian, and that of Euclid, or the Megarian — three modes of appre- hending him, each of which contains a true element of the So- cratic character, but all of which separate that which in the master was a harmonious unity, and affirm of the isolated G8 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. elements that which could be truly predicated only of the whole They are therefore, one-sided, and give of Socratee a false pic ture. This, however, was not wholly their fault; but in that Aristippus was forced to go back to the theory of knowledge of Protagoras, and Euclid to the metaphysics of the Eleatics, they rather testify to the subjective character and to the want of method and system of the Socratic philosophy, and exhibit in their defects and one-sidedness, in part, only the original weak- ness which belongs to the doctrine of their master. 2, Antisthenes and the Cynics. — As a strictly literal ad- herent of the doctrine of Socrates, and zealously though grossly, and often with caricature imitating his method, Antisthenes stands nearest his master. In early life a disciple of Grorgias, and him- self a teacher of the Sophistic philosophy, he subsequently became an inseparable attendant of Socrates, after whose death he founded a school in the Cynosarges, whence his scholars and adherents took the name of Cynics, though according to others this name was derived from their mode of life. The doctrine of Antis- thenes is only an abstract expression for the Socratic ideal of virtue. Like Socrates he considered virtue the final cause of men, regarding it also as knowledge or science, and thus as an object of instruction ; but the ideal of virtue as he had beheld it in the person of Socrates was realized in his estimation only in the absence of every need (in his appearance he imitated a beg- gar with staff and scrip) and hence in the disregarding of all former intellectual interests ; virtue with him aims only to avoid evil, and therefore has no need of dialectical demonstrations, but only of Socratic vigor ; the wise man, according to him, is self- sufficient, independent of everything, indifferent in respect of marriage, family, and the public life of society, as also in respect of wealth, honor, and enjoyment. In this ideal of Antisthenes, which is more negative than positive, we miss entirely the genial humanity and the universal susceptibility of his master, and still more a cultivation of those fruitful dialectic elements which the Socratic philosophizing contained. With a more decided con- tempt for all knowledge, and a still greater scorn of all the cus- THE PARTIAL DISCIPLES OF SOCRATES. 69 toms of society, the later Cynicism became frequently a repulsive and sliameful caricature of the Socratic spirit. This was especially the case with Diogenes of Sinope, the only one of his disciples whom Antisthenes suffered to remain with him. In their high estimation of virtue and philosophy these Cynics, who have been suitably styled the Capuchins of the Grecian world, preserved a trace of the original Socratic philosophy, but they sought virtue " in the shortest way," in a life according to nature as they them selves expressed it, that is, in shutting out the outer world, in at- taining a complete independence, and absence of every need, and in renouncing art and science as well as every determinate aim. To the wise man said they nothing should go amiss ; he should be mighty over every need and desire, free from the restraints of civil law and of custom, and of equal privileges with the gods. An easy life, said Diogenes, is assigned by the gods to that man who limits himself to his necessities, and this true philosophy may be attained by every one, through perseverance and the power of self- denial. Philosophy and philosophical interest is there none in this school of beggars. All that is related of Diogenes are anec- dotes and sarcasms. We see here how the ethics of the Cynic school lost itself in entirely negative statements, a consequence naturally resulting from the fact that the original Socratic conception of virtue lacked a concrete positive content, and was not systematically car- ried out. Cynicism is the negative side of the Socratic doctrine. 3. Aristippus and the Cyrenians. — Aristippus of Cyrene, numbered till the death of Socrates among his adherents, is repre- sented by Aristotle as a Sophist, and this with propriety, since he received money for his instructions. He appears in Xenophon as a man devoted to pleasure. The adroitness with which he adapted himself to every circumstance, and the knowledge of human na- ture by Avhich in every condition he knew how to provide means to satisfy his desire for good living and luxury, were well known among the ancients. Brought in contact with the government, he kept himself aloof from its cares lest he should become dependent; he spent most of his time abroad in order to free himself from 70 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. every restraint ; lie made it his rule that circumstances should be dependent upon him, while he should be independent of them. Though such a man seems little worthy of the name of a Socrati- cist, yet has he two points of contact with his master which should not be overlooked, Socrates had called virtue and happiness co- ordinately the highest end of man, i. e. he had indeed asserted most decidedly the idea of a moral action, but because he brought this forward only in an undeveloped and abstract form, he was only able in concrete cases to establish the obligation of the moral law in a utilitarian way, by appealing to the benefit resulting from the practice of virtue. This side of the Socratic principle Aristippus adopted for his own, affirming that pleasure is the ulti- mate end of life, and the highest good. Moreover, this pleasure, as Aristippus regards it, is not happiness as a condition embracing the whole life, nor pleasure reduced to a system, but is only the individual sensation of pleasure which the body receives, and in this all determinations of moral worth entirely disappear ; but in that Aristippus recommends knowledge, self-government, temper- ance, and intellectual culture as means for acquiring and preserv- ing enjoyment, and, therefore, makes a cultivated mind necessary to judge respecting a true satisfaction, he shows that the Socratic spirit was not yet wholly extinguished within him, and that the name of pseudo-Socraticist which Schleiermacher gives him, hardly belongs to him. The other leaders of the Cyrenian school, Hegesias^ Theodo- rus, Anniceris, we can here only name. The farther development of this school is wholly occupied in more closely defining the na- ture of pleasure, i. e. in determining whether it is to be appre- hended as a momentary sensation, or as an enduring condition embracing the whole life ; whether it belonged to the mind or the body, whether an isolated individual could possess it, or whether it is found alone in the social relations of life ; whether we should regard it as positive or negative, (t. e. simply the absence of pain.) 4. Euclid and the Megarians. — The union of the dialecti- cal and the ethical is a common character in all the partial Socratic schools ; the difierence consists only in this, that in the THE PARTIAL DISCIPLES OF SOCRATES. 71 one the ethical is made to do service to the dialectical, and that in the other, the dialectical stands in subjection to the ethical. The former is especially true of the Megarian school, whose essential peculiarity was pointed out by the ancients themselves as a com- bination of the Socratic and Eleatic principles. The idea of the good is on the ethical side the same as the idea of being on the physical ; it was, therefore, only an application to ethics of the Eleatic view and method when Euclid called the good pure being, and the not-good, not-being. "What is farther related of Euclid is obscure, and may here be omitted. The Megarian school was kept up under different leaders after his death, but without living force, and without the independent activity of an organic develop- ment. As hedonism (the philosophical doctrine of the Cyreneans that pleasure is the chief good) led the way to the doctrine of Epicurus, and cynicism was the bridge toward the Stoic, so the later Megaric development formed the transition point to scepti- cism. Directing its attention ever more exclusively towards the culture of the formal and logical method of argument, it left entirely out of view the moral thoughts of Socrates. Its sophis- tries and quiddities which were, for the most part, only plays of word and wit, were widely known and noted among the ancients. 5. Plato, as the complete Socraticist. — The attempts thus far to build upon the foundation pillars of the Socratic doctrine, started without a vigorous germinating principle, and ended fruit- lessly. Plato was the only one of his scholars who has approached and represented the whole Socrates. Starting from the Socratic idea of knowledge he brought into one focus the scattered ele- ments and rays of truth which could be collected from his master or from the philosophers preceding him, and gave to philosophy a systematic completeness. Socrates had affirmed the principle that conception is the true being and the only actual, and had urged to a knowledge according to the conception ; but these positions were no farther developed. His philosophy is not yet a system, but is only the first impulse toward a philosophical development and method. Plato is the first who has approached a systematic rep- 72 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. resentation and development of tlie ideal world of conceptions true in themselves. The Platonic system is Socrates objectified, the blending and reconciling of preceding philosophy. SECTION XIY. PLATO. I. Plato^s Life. 1. His Youth. — Plato, the son of Aristo, of a noble Athenian family, was born in the year 429 B, C. It was the year of the death of Pericles, the second year of the Pelopon- nesian war, so fatal to Athens. Born in the centre of Grecian culture and industry, and descended from an old and noble family, he received a corresponding education, although no farther tidings of this have been transmitted to us, than the insignificant names of his teachers. That the youth growing up under such circum- stances should choose the seclusion of a philosophic life rather than a political career may seem strange, since many and favor- able opportunities for the latter course lay open before him. Critias, one of the thirty tyrants, was the cousin of his mother, and Charmides, who subsequently, under the oligarchic rule at Athens, found his death at Thrasybulus on the same day with Critias, was his uncle. Notwithstanding this, he is never known to have appeared a single time as a public speaker in the assembly of the people. In view of the rising degeneracy and increasing political corruption of his native land, he was too proud to court for himself the favor of the many-headed Demos ; and more at- tached to Doricism than to the democracy and practice of the Attic public life, he chose to make science his chief pursuit, rather than as a patriot to struggle in vain against unavoidable disaster, and become a martyr to his political opinions. He regarded the Athenian state as lost, and to hinder its inevitable ruin he would not bring a useless offering. PLATO. 73 2. His Years of Discipline. — A youth of twenty, Plato came to Socrates, in whose intercourse he spent eight years. Besides a few doubtful anecdotes, nothing is known more particularly of this portion of his history. In Xenophon's Memorabilia (III. 6) Plato is only once cursorily mentioned, but this in a way that indicates an intimate relation between the scholar and his master. Plato himself in his dialogues has transmitted nothing concerning his personal relations to Socrates; only once {Fhced. p. 59) he names himself among the intimate friends of Socrates. But the influence which Socrates exerted upon him, how he recognized in him the complete representation of a wise man, how he found not only in his doctrine but also in his life and action the most fruit- ful philosophic germs, the significance which the personal character of his master as an ideal type had for him — all this we learn with sufficient accuracy from his writings, where he places his own incomparably more developed philosophical system in the mouth of his master, whom he makes the centre of his dialogues and the leader of his discourses 3. His Years of" Travel.— After the death of Socrates 399 B. C, in the thirtieth year of his age, Plato, fearing lest he also should be met by the incoming reaction against philosophy, left, in company with other Socraticists, his native city, and betook himself to Euclid, his former fellow-scholar, the founder of the Megaric school (cf. § XIII. 4) at Megara. Up to this time a pure Socraticist, he became greatly animated and energized by his intercourse with the Megarians, among whom a peculiar philoso- phical direction, a modification of Socraticism, was already asserted. We shall see farther on the influence of this residence at Megara upon the foundation of his philosophy, and especially upon the elaboration and confirmation of his doctrine of Ideas. One whole period of his literary activity and an entire group of his dialogues, can only be satisfactorily explained by the intellectual stimulus gained at this place. From Megara, Plato visited Cyrene, Egypt, Magna-Grecia and Sicily. In Magna-Grecia he became acquainted with the Pythagorean philosophy, which was then in its highest bloom. His abode among the Pythagoreans had a marked effect 4 74 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. upon liim ; as a man it made him more practical, and increased his zest for life and his interest in public life and social inter- course ; as a philosopher it furnished him with a new incitement to science, and new motives to literary labor. The traces of the Pythagoreoan philosophy may be seen through all the last period of his literary life ; especially his aversion to public and political life was greatly softened by his intercourse with the Pythagoreans. While in the Theatsetus, he affirmed most positively the incom- patibility of philosophy with public life, we find in his later dia- logues, especially in the Eepublic and also in the Statesman — upon which Pythagoreanism seems already to have had an influ- ence — a returning favor for the actual world, and the well-known sentence that the ruler must be a philosopher is an expression very characteristic of this change. His visit to Sicily gave him the acquaintance of the elder Dionysius and Dion his brother-in- law, but the philosopher and the tyrant had little in common. Plato is said to have incurred his displeasure to so high a degree, that his life was in danger. After about ten years spent in travel, he returned to Athens in the fortieth year of his age, (389 or 388 B. C.) 4. Plato as Head of the Academy ; His Years of Instruc- tion. — On his return, Plato surrounded himself with a circle of pupils. The place where he taught was known as the academy, a gymnasium outside of Athens where Plato had inherited a garden from his father. Of his school and of his later life, we have only the most meagre accounts. His life passed evenly along, inter- rupted only by a second and third visit to Sicily, where mean- while the younger Dionysius had come to the throne. This second and third residence of Plato at the court of Syracuse abounds in vicissitudes, and shows us the philosopher in a great variety of conditions {cf. Plutarch's Life of Dion) ; but to us, in estimating his philosophical character, it is of interest only for the attempt, which, as seems probable from all accounts, he there made to realize his ideal of a moral state, and by the philosophical educa- tion of the new ruler to unite philosophy and the reins of govern- ment in one and the same hand, or at least in some way by means PLATO. 75 of philosophy to achieve a healthy change in the Sicilian state constitution. His efforts were however fruitless ; the circumstances were not propitious, and the character of the young Dionysius, who was one of those mediocre natures who strive after renown and distinction, hut are capable of nothing profound and earnest, deceived the expectations concerning him which Plato, according to Dion's account, thought he had reason to entertain. When we look at Plato's philosophical labors in the academy, we are struck with the different relations to public life which philosophy already assumes. Instead of carrying philosophy, like Socrates, into the streets and public places and making it there a subject of social conversation with any one who desired it, he lived and labored entirely withdrawn from the movements of the public, satisfied to influence the pupils who surrounded him. In pre- cisely the measure in which philosophy becomes a system and the systematic form is seen to be essential, does it lose its popular character and begin to demand a scientific training, and to become a topic for the school, an esoteric affair. Yet such was the respect for the name of a philosopher, and especially for the name of Plato, that requests were made to him by different states to com- pose for them a book of laws, a work which in some instances it was said was actually performed. Attended by a retinue of de- voted disciples, among whom were even women disguised as men, and receiving reiterated demonstrations of respect, he reached the age of eighty-one years, with his powers of mind unweakened to the latest moment. The close of his life seems to have been clouded by disturb- ances and divisions which arose in his school under the lead of Aristotle. Engaged in writing, or as others state it at a mar- riage feast, death came upon him as a gentle sleep, 348 B. C. His remains were buried in the Ceramicus, not far from the academy. II. The Inner Development of the Platonic Philosophy AND Writings. — That the Platonic philosophy has a real develop- ment, that it should not be apprehended as a perfectly finished system to which the different writings stand related as constitu- 76 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. ent elements, but that these are rather steps of this inner de- velopment, as it -were stages passed over in the philosophical journejings of the philosopher — is a view of the highest import- ance for the true estimate of Plato's literary labors. Plato's philosophical and literary labors may be divided into three periods, which we can characterize in different ways. Look- ing at them in a chronological or biographical respect, we might call them respectively the periods of his years of discipline, of travel, of instruction, or if we view them in reference to the pre- vailing external influence under which they were formed, they might be termed the Socratic, Heraclitic-Eleatic, and the Pytha- gorean ; or if we looked at the content alone, we might term them the Anti-Sophistic-Ethic, the Dialectic or mediating, and the sys- tematic or constructive periods. The First Period — the Socratic — is marked externally by the predominance of the dramatic element, and in reference to its philosophical stand-point, by an adherence to the method and the fundamental principles of the Socratic doctrine. Not yet accurately informed of the results of former inquiries, and rather repelled from the study of the history of philosophy than attract- ed to it by the character of the Socratic philosophizing, Plato confined himself to an analytical treatment of conceptions, partic- ularly of the conception of virtue, and to a reproducing of his master, which, though something more than a mere recital of ver- bal recollections, had yet no philosophical independence. His Socrates exhibits the same view of life and the same scientific stand-point which the historical Socrates of Xenophon had had. His efforts were thus, like those of his contemporary fellow disci- ples, directed prominently toward practical wisdom. His conflicts however, like those of Socrates, had far more weight against the prevailing want of science and the shallow sophisms of the day than for the opposite scientific directions. The whole period bears an eclectic and hortatory character. The highest point in •which the dialogues of this group culminate is the attempt which at the same time is found in the Socratic doctrine to determine PLATO. 77 the certainty of an absolute content (of an objective reality) to the good. The history of the development of the Platonic philosophy would assume a very different form if the view of some modern scholars respecting the date of the Phasdrus were correct. If, as they claim, the Phsedrus were Plato's earliest work, this circum- stance would betray from the outset an entirely different course of culture for him than we could suppose in a mere scholar of Socrates. The doctrine in this dialogue of the pre-existence of souls, and their periodical transmigrations, of the relation of earthly beauty with heavenly truth, of divine inspiration in con- trast to human wisdom, the conception of love, — these and other Pythagorean ingredients are all so distinct from the original So- cratic doctrine that we must transfer the most of that which Plato has creatively produced during his whole philosophical career, to the beginning of his philosophical development. The improba- bility of this, and numerous other grounds of objection, claim a far later composition for this dialogue. Setting aside for the pre- sent the Phasdrus, the Platonic development assumes the follow- ing form : Among the earliest works (if they are genuine) are the small dialogues which treat of Socratic questions and themes in a So- cratic way. Of these e. g. the Charmides discusses temperance, the Lysis friendship, the Laches valor, the lesser Hippias know- ing and wilful wrong-doing, the first Alcibiades, the moral and intellectual qualifications of a statesman, &c. The immaturity and the crudeness of these dialogues, the use of scenic means which have only an external relation to the content, the scanti- ness and want of independence in the content, the indirect man- ner of investigation which lacks a satisfactory and positive result, the formal and analytical treatment of the conceptions discussed — all these features indicate the early character of these minor dialogues. The Protagoras may be taken as a proper type of the Socratic period. Since this dialogue, though directing its whole polemic against the Sophistic philosophy, confined itself almost exclusively ^3 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. to tlic outward manifestation of this system, to its influence on its age and its method of instruction in opposition io that of Soc- rates, without entering into the ground and philosophical charac- ter of the doctrine itself, and, still farther, since, when it comes in a strict sense to philosophize, it confines itself, in an indirect investigation, to the Socratic conception of virtue according to its different sides (virtue as knowing, its unity and its teachableness, cf. ^ XII. 8), — it represents in the clearest manner the tendency, character and want of the first period of Plato's literary life. The Gorgias, written soon after the death of Socrates, repre- sents the third and highest stage of this period. Directed against the Sophistical identification of pleasure and virtue, of the good and of the agreeable, i. e. against the affirmation of an absolute moral relativity, this dialogue maintains the proof that the good, far from owing its origin only to the right of the stronger, and thus to the arbitrariness of the subject, has in itself an indepen- dent reality and objective validity, and, consequently, alone is truly useful, and thus, therefore, the measure of pleasure must follow the higher measure of the good. In this direct and posi- tive polemic against the Sophistic doctrine of pleasure, in its ten- dency to a view of the good as something firm and abiding, and secure against all subjective arbitrariness, consists prominently the advance which the Grorgias makes over the Protagoras. ^ In the first Socratic period the Platonic philosophizing be- came ripe and ready for the reception of Eleatic and Pythagorean categories. To grapple by means of these categories with the higher questions of philosophy, and so to free the Socratic philos- ophy from its so close connection with practical life, was the task of the second period. The Second Period — the dialectic or the Megaric — is marked externally, by a less prominence of form and poetic contempla- tion, and not unfrequently indeed, by obscurity and difficulties of Btyle, and internally, by the attempt to give a satisfactory media- tion for the Eleatic doctrine and a dialectic foundation for the doctrine of ideas. By his exile at Megara, and his journeys to Italy, -Plato be- PLATO. 79 came acquainted Tvith other and opposing philosophical directions, from which he must now separate himself in order to elevate the Socratic doctrine to its true significance. It was now that he first learned to know the philosophic theories of the earlier sages, for whose study the necessary means could not at that period, so wanting in literary publicity, be found at Athens. By his sepa- ration from these varying stand-points, as his older fellow pupils had already striven to do, he attempted striding over tne narrow limits of ethical philosophizing, to reach the final ground of know- ing, and to carry out the art of forming conceptions as brought forward by Socrates, to a science of conceptions, i. e. to the doc- trine of ideas. That all human acting depends upon knowing, and that all thinking depends upon the conception, were results to which Plato might already have attained through the scientific generalization of the Socratic doctrine itself, but now to bring this Socratic wisdom within the circle of speculative thinking, to establish dialectically that the conception in its simple unity is that which abides in the change of phenomena, to disclose the fundamental principles of knowledge which had been evaded by Socrates, to grasp the scientific theories of the opposers direct in their scientific grounds, and follow them out in all their ramifica- tions, — this is the problem which the Megaric family of dialogues attempts to solve. The Theatsetus stands at the head of this group. This is chiefly directed against the Protagorean theory of knowledge, against the identification of the thinking and the sensible percep- tion, or against the claim of an objective relativity of all knowl- edge. As the Grorgias before it had sought to establish the in- dependent being of the ethical, so does the Theatastus ascending from the ethical to the theoretical, endeavor to prove an indepen dent being and objective reality for the logical conceptions which lie at the ground of all representation and thinking, in a word, to prove the objectivity of truth, the fact that there lies a province of thought immanent in the thinking and independent of the per 3eptions of the senses. These conceptions, whose objective reality 80 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. is thus affirmed, are those of a species, likeness and unlikenesa, sameness and difference, &c. The Theatsetus is followed by the trilogy of the Sophist, the Statesman, and the Philosopher, which completes the Megaric group of dialogues. The first of these dialogues examines the conception of appearance, that i? of the not-being, the last (for which the Parmenides may be taken) the conception of being. Both dialogues are especially directed to the Eleatic doctrine. After Plato had recognized the conception in its simple unity as that which abides in the change of phenomena, his attention was naturally turned towards the Eleatics, who in an opposite way had attained the similar result that in unity consists all true substan- tiality, and to multiplicity as such no true being belongs. In order more easily on the one side to carry out this fundamental thought of the Eleatic to its legitimate result, in which the Megarians had already preceded him, he was obliged to give a metaphysical substance to his abstract conceptions of species, i. e. ideas. But on the other side, he could not agree with the inflex- ibility and exclusiveness of the Eleatic unity, unless he would wholly sacrifice the multiplicity of things ; he was rather obliged to attempt to show by a dialectic development of the Eleatic principle that the one must be at the same time a totality, organ- ically connected, and .embracing multiplicity in itself. This double relation to the Eleatic principle is carried out by the Sophist and the Parmenides ; by the former polemically against the Eleatic doctrine, in that it proves the being of the appearance or the not-being, and by the latter pacifically, in that it analyzes the Eleatic one by its own logical consequences into many. The inner progress of the doctrine of Ideas in the Megaric group of dia- logues is therefore this, viz., that the Theatcctus, in opposition to the Heraclitico-Protagorean theory of the absolute becoming, affirms the objective and independent reality of ideas, and the Sophist shows their reciprocal relation and combining qualities, while the Parmenides in fine exhibits their whole dialectic com- pleteness with their relation to the phenomenal world. The Third Period begins with the return of the philosopher PLATO. 81 to his native city. It unites the completeness of form belonging to the first with the profounder characteristical content belonging to the second. The memories of his youthful years seem at this time to have risen anew before the soul of Plato, and to have im- parted again to his literary activity the long lost freshness and fulness of that period, while at the same time his abode in foreign lands, and especially his acquaintance with the Pythagorean phi- losophy, had greatly enriched his mind with a store of images and ideals. This reviving of old memories is seen in the fact that the writings of this group return with fondness to the personality of Socrates, and represent in a certain degree the whole philosophy of Plato as the exaltation of the doctrine and the ideal embodi- ment of the historical character of his early master. In opposi tion to both of the first two periods, the third is marked exter- nally by an excess of the mythical form connected with the grow- ing influence of Pythagoreanism in this period, and internally by the application of the doctrine of ideas to the concrete spheres of psychology, ethics and natural science. That ideas possess objective reality, and are the foundation of all essentiality and truth, while the phenomena of the sensible world are only copies of these, was a theory whose vindication was no longer attempted, but which was presupposed as already proved, and as forming a dialectical basis for the pursuit of the different branches of science. With this was connected a tendency to unite the hitherto separate branches of science into a systematic whole, as well as to mould together the previous philosophical directions, and show the inner application of the Socratic philosophy for ethics, of the Eleatic for dialectics, and the Pythagorean for physics. Upon this stand-point, the Ph^cdrus, Plato's inaugural to his labors in the Academy, together with the Symposium, which is . closely connected with it, attempts to subject the rhetorical theory and practice of their time to a thorough criticism, in order to show in opposition to this theory and practice, that the fixedness and stability of a true scientific principle could only be attained by grounding every thing on the idea. On the same stand-point the Pheedon attempts to prove the immortality of the soul from the 4* 82 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. doctrine of ideas ; the Philebus to bring out the conception ol pleasure and of the highest good ; the Republic to develop the essence of the state, and the Timasus that of nature. Having thus sketched the inner development of the Platonic philosophy, we now turn to a systematic statement of its princi- ples. III. — Classification of the Platonic System. — The phi- losophy of Plato, as left by himself, is without a systematic state- ment, and has no comprehensive principle of classification. He has given us only the history of his thinking, the statement of his philosophical development ; we are therefore limited in reference to his classification of philosophy to simple intimations. Accord- ingly, some have divided the Platonic system into theoretical and practical science, and others into a philosophy of the good, the beautiful and the true. Another classification, which has some support in old records, is more correct. Some of the ancients say that Plato was the first to unite in one whole the scattered philo- sophical elements of the earlier sages, and so to obtain for philoso- phy the three parts, logic, physics, and ethics. The more accurate statement is given by Sextus Umpiricus, that Plato has laid the foundation for this threefold division of philosophy, but that it was first expressly recognized and affirmed by his scholars, Xeno- crates and Aristotle. The Platonic system may, however, with- out difficulty, be divided into these three parts. True, there are many dialogues which mingle together in difierent proportions the logical, the ethical, and the physical element, and though even where Plato treats of some special discipline, the three are suf- fered constantly to interpenetrate each other, still there are some dialogues in which this fundamental scheme can be clearly recog- nized. It cannot be mistaken that the Timseus has predominantly a physical, and the E-epublic as decidedly an ethical element, and if the dialectic is expressly represented in no separate dialogue, yet does the whole Megaric group pursue the common end of bringing out the conception of science and its true object, being, and is, therefore, in its content decidedly dialectical. Plato must have been led to this threefold division by even the earlier de- PLATO. 83 velopment of philosophy, and though Xenocrates does not clearly see it, yet since Aristotle presupposes it as universally admitted, we need not scruple to make it the basis on which to represent he Platonic system. The order which these different parts should take, Plato him- self has not declared. Manifestly, however, dialectics should have the first place as the ground of all philosophy, since Plato uniformly directs that every philosophical investigation should begin with accurately determining the idea (Phced. p. 99. Phcedr. p. 237), while he subsequently examines all the concrete spheres of science on the stand-point of the doctrine of ideas. The relative position of the other two parts is not so clear. Since, however, the physics culminates in the ethics, and the ethics, on the other hand, has for its basis physical investigations into the ensouling power in nature, we may assign to physics the former place of the two. The mathematical sciences Plato has expressly excluded from philosophy. He considers them as helps to philosophical think- ing {Bep. VIL 526), as necessary steps of knowledge, with- out which no one can come to philosophy (lb. VI. 510) ; but mathematics with him is not philosophy, for it assumes its prin- ciples or axioms, without at all accounting for them, as though they were manifest to all, a procedure which is not permitted to pure science ; it also serves itself for its demonstrations, with il- lustrative figures, although it does not treat of these, but of that which they represent to the understanding (lb.). Plato thus places mathematics midway between a correct opinion and sci- ence, clearer than the one, but more obscure than the other. {lb. VII. 533.) IV. The Platonic Dialectics. 1. Conception of Dialec- tics. — The conception of dialectics or of logic, is used by the ancients for the most part in a very wide sense, while Plato em- ploys it in repeated instances interchangeably with philosophy, though on the other hand he treats it also as a separate branch of philosophy. He divides it from physics as the science of the eternal and unchangeable from the science of the changeable, 84 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. which never is, but is only ever becoming ; lie distinguishes also between it and ethics, so far as the latter treats of the good not absolutely, but in its concrete exhibition in morals and in the state ; so that dialectics may be termed philosophy in a higher sense, while physics and ethics follow it as two less exact sciences, or as a not yet perfected philosophy. Plato himself defines dia- lectics, according to the ordinary signification of the word, as the art of developing knowledge by way of dialogue in questions and answers. (Rep. VII. 534). But since the art of communicating correctly in dialogue is according to Plato, at the same time the art of thinking correctly, and as thus thinking and speaking could not be separated by the ancients, but every process of thought was a living dialogue, so Plato would more accurately define dialectics as the science which brings speech to a correct issue, and which combines or separates the species, i. e. the con- ceptions of things correctly with one another. [Soph. p. 253. Phcedr. p. 266). Dialectics with him has two divisions, to know what can and what cannot be connected, and to know how divi- sion or combination can be. But as with Plato these conceptions of species or ideas are the only actual and true existence, so have we, in entire conformity with this, a third definition of dialectics (Pliilehus p. 57), as the science of being, the science of that which is true and unchangeable, the science of all other sciences. We may therefore briefly characterize it as the science of absolute being or of ideas. 2. "What is Science? (1.) As opposed to sensation and the sensuous representation. — The Theatastus is devoted to the dis- cussion of this question in opposition to the Protagorean sensual- ism. That all knowledge consists in perception, and that the two are one and the same thing, was the Protagorean proposition, ifrom this it followed, as Protagoras himself had inferred, that •■hings are, as they appear to me, that the perception or sensation *B infallible. But since perception and sensation are infinitely diversified with different individuals, and even greatly vary in the same individual, it follows farther, that there are no objective determinations and predicates, that we can never affirm what a PLATO. 85 thing is in itself, tliat all conceptions, great, small, light, heavy, to increase, to diminish, &g., have only a relative significance, and consequently, also, the conceptions of species, as combinations of the changeful many, are wholly wanting in constancy and sta- bility. In opposition to this Protagorean thesis, Plato urges the following objections and contradictions. First. The Protago- rean doctrine leads to the most startling consequences. If being and appearance, knowledge and perception are one and the same thing, then is the irrational brute, which is capaole of perception, as fully entitled to be called the measure of all things, as man, and if the representation is infallible, as the expression of my subjective character at a given time, then need there be no more instruction, no more scientific conclusion, no more strife, and no more refutation. Second. The Protagorean doctrine is a logical contradiction ; for according to it Protagoras must yield the question to every one who disputes with him, since, as he himself afiirms, no one is incorrect, but every one judges only according to truth ; the pretended truth of Protagoras is therefore true for no man, not even for himself. Third. Protagoras destroys the knowledge of future events. That which I may regard as profit- able may not therefore certainly prove itself as such in the result. To determine that which is really profitable implies a calculation of the future, but since the ability of men to form such a calcu- lation is very diverse, it follows from this that not man as such, but only the wise man can be the measure of things. Fourth. The theory of Protagoras destroys perception. Perception, ac- cording to him, rests upon a distinction of the perceived object and the perceiving subject, and is the common product of the two. But in his view the objects are in such an uninterrupted flow, that they can neither become fixed in seeing nor in hearing. This condition of constant change renders all knowledge from sense, and hence (the identity of the two being assumed), all knowledge impossible. Fifth. Protagoras overlooks the apriori element in knowledge. It is seen in an analysis of the sense- perception itself, that all knowledge cannot be traced to the activity of the senses, but that there must also be presupposed 86 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY, besides these, intellectual functions, and hence an hidependent province of supersensible knowledge, v We see with the eyes, and hear with the ears, but to group together the perceptions attained through these different organs, and to hold them fast in the unity of self- consciousness, is beyond the power of the activity of the senses. Again, we compare the different sense-perceptions with one another, a function which cannot belong to the senses, since each sense can only furnish its own distinctive perception. Still farther, we bring forward determinations respecting the percep- tions which we manifestly cannot owe to the senses, in that we predicate of these perceptions, being and not-being, likeness and unlikeness, &c. These determinations, to which also belong the beautiful and the odious, good and evil, constitute a peculiar prov- ince of knowledge, which the soul, independently of every sense- perception, brings forward through its own independent activity. The ethical element of this Plato exhibits in his attack upon sensualism, and also in other dialogues. He maintains (in the Sophist), that men holding such opinions must be improved be- fore they can be instructed, and that when made morally better, they will readily recognize the truth of the soul and its moral and rational capacities, and affirm that these are real things, though objects of neither sight nor of feeling. (2.) The Relation of Knowing to Opinion. — Opinion is just as little identical with knowing as is the sense-perception. An in- correct opinion is certainly different from knowing, and a correct one is not the same, for it can be engendered by the art of speech without therefore attaining the validity of true knowledge. The correct opinion, so far as it is true in matter though imperfect in form, stands rather midway between knowing and not-knowing, and participates in both. (3.) The Relation of Science to Thinking. — In opposition to the Protagorean sensualism, we have already referred to an energy of the soul independent of the sensuous perception and sensation, competent in itself to examine the universal, and grasp true being in thought. There is, therefore, a double source of knowledge, sensation and rational thinking. Sensation refers to that which PLATO. 87 is conceived in the constant becoming and perpetual change, to the pure momentary, which is in an incessant transition from the was, through the now, into the shall be (Farm. p. 152) ; it is, therefore, the source of dim, impure, and uncertain knowledge; thinking on the other hand refers to the a,biding, which neither becomes nor departs, but remains ever the same. [Tim. p. 51.) Existence, says the Timasus (p. 27) is of two kinds, " that which ever is but has no becoming, and that which ever becomes but never is. The one kind, which is always in the same state, is comprehended through reflection by the reason, the other, which becomes and departs, but never properly is, may be apprehended by the sensuous perception without the reason." True science, therefore, flows alone from that pure and thoroughly internal ac- tivity of the soul which is free from all corporeal qualities and every sensuous disturbance. (Phced. p. 65.) In this state the soul looks upon things purely as they are {Phced. p. 66) in their eter- nal being and their unchangeable condition. Hence the true state of the philosopher is announced in the Phsedon (p. 64) to be a willingness to die, a longing to fly from the body, as from a hinderance to true knowledge, and become pure spirit. Accord- ing to all this, science is the thinking of true being or of ideas ; the means to discover and to know these ideas, or the organ for their apprehension is the dialectic, as the art of separating and com- bining conceptions; the true objects of dialectics are ideas. 3. The Doctrine of Ideas in its Genesis. — The Platonic doctrine of ideas is the common product of the Socratic method of formiDg conceptions, the Heraclitic doctrine of absolute becom- ing, and the Eleatic doctrine of absolute being. To the first of these Plato owes the idea of a knowing through conceptions, to the second the recognition of the becoming in the field of the sensuous, to the third the position of a field of absolute reality. Elsewhere {in the Philehus) Plato connects the doctrine of ideas with the Pythagorean thought that every thing may be formed from unity and multiplicity, from the limit and the unlimited. The aim of the Theataetus, the Sophist, and the Parmenides is to refute the principles of the Eleatics and Heraclitics ; this refuta- 88 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. tion is effected in the Theatsetus by combating directly the prin- ciple of an absolute becoming, in the Sophist by combating directly the principle of abstract being, and in the Parmenides by taking up the Eleatic one and showing its true relations. We have already spoken of the Theatostus ; we will now look for the development of the doctrine of ideas in the Sophist and Par- menides. The ostensible end of the former of these dialogues is to show that the Sophist is really but a caricature of the philosopher, but its true end is to fix the reality of the appearance, i. e. of the not- being, and to discuss speculatively the relation of being and not- being. The doctrine of the Eleatics ended with the rejection of all sensuous knowledge, declaring that what we receive as the perception of a multiplicity of things or of a becoming is only an appearance. In this the contradiction was clear, the not-being was absolutely denied, and yet its existence was admitted in the notion of men. Plato at once draws attention to this contradic- tion, showing that a delusive opinion, which gives rise to a false image or representation, is not possible, since the whole theory rests upon the assumption that the false, the not -true, i. e. not- being cannot even be thought. This, Plato continues, is the great difficulty in thinking of not-being, that both he who denies and he who affirms its reality is driven to contradict himself For though it is inexpressible and inconceivable either as one or as many, still, when speaking of it, we must attribute to it both being and multiplicity. If we admit that there is such a thing as a false opinion, we assume in this very fact the notion of not-being, for only that opinion can be said to be false which supposes either the not-being to be, or makes that, which is not, to be. In short, if there actually exists a false notion, so does there actually and truly exist a not-being. After Plato had thus fixed the reality of not-being, he discusses the relation of being and not-being, i. e. the relation of conceptions generally in their combinations and difierences. If not-being has no less reality than being, and being no more than not-being, if, therefore, e. g. the not-great is as truly real as the great, then every conception may be apprehended ac- PLATO. 85 cording to its opposite sides as being and not-being at the same time : it is a being in reference to itself, as something identical with itself, but it is not-being in reference to every one of the numberless other conceptions which can be referred to it, and with which, on account of its difference from them, it can have nothing in common. The conception of the same (ravTov) and the different (^arepov) represent the general form of an antithesis. These are the universal formulae of combination for all concep- tions. This reciprocal relation of conceptions as at the same time being and not-being, by virtue of which they can be arranged among themselves, forms now the basis for the art of dialectics, which has to judge what conceptions can and what cannot be joined together. Plato illustrates here by taking the conceptions of being, motion (becoming), and rest (existence), and showing what are the results of the combinations of these ideas. The conceptions of motion and rest cannot well be joined together, though both of them may be joined with that of being, since both arc; the conception of rest is therefore in reference to itself a being, but in reference to the conception of motion a not-being or different. Thus the Platonic doctrine of ideas, after having in the Theataetus attained its general foundation in fixing the objec- tive reality of conceptions, becomes now still farther developed in the Sophist to a doctrine of the agreement and disagreement of conceptions. The category which conditions these reciprocal re- lations is that of not-being or difference. This fundamental thought of the Sophist, that being is not without not-being and not-being is not without being, may be expressed in mo(fern phra- seology thus : negation is not not-being but determinateness, and on the other hand all determinateness and concreteness of concep- tions, or every thing affirmative can be only through negation ; in other words the conception of contradiction is the soul of a philosophical method. The doctrine of ideas appears in the Parmenides as the positive consequence and progressive development of the Eleatic princi- ple. Indeed in thia dialogue, in that Plato makes Parmenides the chief speaker, he seems willing to allow that his doctrine is in 90 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. substance that of the Eleatic sage. True, the fundamental thought of the dialogue — that the one is not conceivable in its complete singleness without the many, nor the many without the one, that each necessarily presupposes and reciprocally conditions the other — stands in the most direct contradiction to Eleaticism. Yet Parmenides himself, by dividing his poem into two parts, and treating in the first of the one and in the second of the many, postulates an inner mediation between these two externally so dis- jointed parts of his philosophy, and in this respect the Platonic theory of ideas might give itself out as the farther elimination, and the true sense of the Parmenidean philosophizing. This dia- lectical mediation between the one and the not-one or the many Plato now attempts in four antinomies, which have ostensibly only a negative result in so far as they show that contradictions arise both whether the one be adopted or rejected. The positive sense of these antinomies, though it can be gained only 'through infer- ences which Plato himself does not expressly utter, but leaves to be drawn by the reader — is as follows. The first antinomy shows that the one is inconceivable as such since it is only apprehended in its abstract opposition to the many ; the second, that in this case also the reality of the many is inconceivable ; the third, that the one or the idea cannot be conceived as not-being, since there can be neither conception nor predicate of the absolute not-being, and since, if not-being is excluded from all fellowship with being, all becoming and departing, all similarity and difi"erence, every representation and explanation concerning it must also be denied ; and lastly, the fourth afiirms that the not-one or the many cannot be conceived without the one or the idea. What now is Plato's aim in this discussion of the dialectic relations between the con- ceptions of the one and the many ? "Would he use the conception of the one only as an example to explain his dialectic method with conceptions, or is the discussion of this conception itself the very object before him ? Manifestly the latter, or the dialogue ends without result and without any inner connection of its two parts. But how came Plato to make such a special investigation of this conception of the one ? If we bear in mind that the PLATO. 91 Eleatics had already perceived the antithesis of the actual and the phenomenal world in the antithesis of the one and the many, and that Plato himself had also regarded his ideas as the unity of the manifold, as the one and the same in the many — since he repeatedly uses " idea" and 'Uhe one" in the same sense, and places (Rep. VII. 537) dialectics in the same rank with the faculty of bringing many to unity — then is it clear that the one which is made an object of investigation in the Parmenides is the idea in its general sense, i. e. in its logical form, and that Plato consequently in the dialectic of the one and the many would repre- sent the dialectic of the idea and the phenomenal world, or in other words would dialectically determine and establish the correct view of the idea as the unity in the manifoldness of the phenomenal. In that it is shown in the Parmenides, on the one side, that the many cannot be conceived without the one, and on the other side, that the one must be something which embraces in itself mani- foldness, so have we the ready inference on the one side, that the phenomenal world, or the many, has a true being only in so far as it has the one or the conception within it, and on the other side, that since the conception is not an abstract one but mani- foldness in unity, it must actually have manifoldness in unity in order to be able to be in the phenomenal world. The indirect result of the Parmenides is that matter as the infinitely divisible and undetermined mass has no actuality, but is in relation to the ideal world a not-being, and though the ideas as the true being gain their appearance in it, yet the idea itself is all that is actual in the appearance or phenomenon ; the phenomenal world derives its whole existence from the ideal world which appears in it, and has a being only so far as it has a conception or idea for its con- tent. 4. Positive Exposition of the Docteine of Ideas. — Ideas may be defined according to the diff'erent sides of their historical connection, as the common in the manifold, the universal in the particular, the one in the many, or the constant and abiding in the changing. Subjectively they are principles of knowing which c ^ot be derived from experience they are the intuitively cer- 92 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. tain and innate regulators of our knowledge. Objectively they are the immutable principles of being and of the phenomenal world, incorporeal and simple unities which have no relation to space, and which may be predicated of every independent thing. The doctrine of ideas grew originally out of the desire to give a definite conception to the inner essence of things, and make the real world conceivable as a harmoniously connected intellectual world. This desire of scientific knowledge Aristotle cites ex- pressly as the motive to the Platonic doctrine of ideas. " Plato," he says {MetapJi. XIII. 4), " came to the doctrine of ideas be- cause he was convinced of the truth of the Heraclitic view which regarded the sensible world as a ceaseless flowing and changing. His conclusion from this was, that if there be a science of any thing there must be, besides the sensible, other substances which have a permanence, for there can be no science of the fleeting." It is, therefore, the idea of science which demands the reality of ideas, a demand which cannot be granted unless an idea or con- ception is also the ground of all being. This is the case with Plato. According to him there can be neither a true knowing nor a true being without ideas and conceptions which have an independent reality. What now does Plato mean by idea ? From what has already been said it is clear that he means something more than ideal con- ceptions of the beautiful and the good. An idea is found, as the name itself (et^o?) indicates, wherever a universal conception of a species or kind is found. Hence Plato speaks of the idea of a bed, table, strength, health, voice, color, ideas of simple relations and properties, ideas of mathematical figures, and even ideas of not-being, and of that, which in its essence only contradicts the idea, baseness and vice. In a word, we may put an idea wherever many things may be characterized by a common name {Bep. X. 596) : or as Aristotle expresses it (Met. XII. 3). Plato places an idea to every class of being. In this sense Plato himself speaks in the beginning of the Parmenides. Parmenides asks the young Socrates what he calls ideas. Socrates answers by naming unconditionally the moral ideas, the ideas of the true, the beauti- PLATO. 93 fill, the good, and then after a little delay he mentions some physi- cal ones, as the ideas of man, of fire, of water ; he will not allow ideas to be predicated of that which is only a formless mass, or which is a part of something else, as hair, mud and clay, hut in this he is answered by Parmenides, that if he would be fully im- bued with philosophy, he must not consider such things as these to be wholly despicable, but should look upon them as truly though remotely participating in the idea. Here at least the claim is asserted that no province of being is excluded from the idea, that even that which appears most accidental and irrational is yet a part of rational knowledge, in fact that every thing ex- isting may be brought within a rational conception. 5. The relation of Ideas to the Phenomenal World. Analogous to the different definitions of idea are the different names which Plato gives to the sensible and phenomenal world. He calls it the many, the divisible, the unbounded, the undeter- mined and measureless, the becoming, the relative, great and small, not-being. The relation now in which these two worlds of sense and of ideas stand to each other is a question which Plato has answered neither fully nor consistently with himself. His most common way is to characterize the relation of things to concep- tions as a participant, or to call things the copies and adumbra- tions, while ideas are the archetypes. Yet this is so indefinite that Aristotle properly says that to talk in this way is only to use poetical metaphors. The great difficulty of the docti'ine of ideas is not solved but only increased by these figurative repre- sentations. The difficulty lies in tlie contradiction which grows out of the fact that while Plato admits the reality of the becom- ing and of the province of the becoming, he still affirms that ideas which are substances ever at rest and ever the same are the only actual. Now in this Plato is formally consistent with himself, while he characterizes the materiel of matter not as a positive substratum but as not-being, and guards himself with the express affirmation that he does not consider the sensible as being, but only as something similar to being. (Rep. X. 597.) The position laid down in the Parmenides is also consistent with this, that a 94 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. perfect philosopliy should look upon the idea as the cognizable in the phenomenal world, and should follow it out in the smallest particulars until every part of being should be known and all dualism removed. In fine, Plato in many of his expressions seems to regard the world of sensation only as a subjective ap- pearance, as a product of the subjective notion, as the result of a confused way of representing ideas. In this sense the phenomena are entirely dependent on ideas ; they are nothing but the ideas themselves in the form of not being ; the phenomenal world de- rives its whole existence from the ideal world which appears in it. But yet when Plato calls the sensible a mingling of the same with the different or the not-being {Tim. p. 35), when he charac- terizes the ideas as vowels which go through every thing like a chain [Soph. p. 253), when he himself conceives the possibility that matter might ofi"er opposition to the formative energy of ideas {Tim. p. 66), when he speaks of an evil soul of the world {de Leg. X. 896), and gives intimations of the presence in the world of a principle in nature hostile to God [Polit. p. 268), when he in the Phsedon treats of the relation between body and soul as one wholly discordant and malignant, — in all this there is evidence enough, even after allowing for the mythical form of the Timaeus, and the rhetorical composition which prevails in the Phgedon, to substantiate the contradiction mentioned above. This is most clear in the Timasus. Plato in this dialogue makes the sensible world to be formed by a Creator after the pattern of an idea, but in this he lays down as a condition that this Demi- urge or Creator should find at hand a something which should be apt to receive and exhibit this ideal image. This something Plato compares to the matter which is fashioned by the artisan (whence the later name hyle). He characterizes it as wholly un- determined and formless, but possessing in itself an aptitude for every variety of forms, an invisible and shapeless thing, a some- thing which it is dijfficult to characterize, and which Plato even does not seem inclined very closely to describe. In this the actuality of matter is denied ; while Plato makes it equivalent to space it is only the place, the negative condition of the sensible j PLATO, 95 while it possesses a being only as it receives in itself the ideal form. Still matter remains the objective and phenomenal form of the idea : the visible world arises only through the mingling of ideas with this substratum, and if matter be metaphysically expressed as " the different," then does it follow with logical ne- cessity in a dialectical discussion that it is just as truly being as not-being. Plato does not conceal from himself this difficulty, and therefore attempts to represent with comparisons and images this presupposition of a hyle which he finds it as impossible to do without as to express in a conceivable form. If he would do without it he must rise to the conception of an absolute creation, or consider matter as an ultimate emanation from the absolute spirit, or else explain it as appearance only. Thus the Platonic system is only a fruitless struggle against dualism. 6. The idea of the Good and the Deity. If the true and the real is exhibited in general conceptions which are so related to each other that every higher conception embraces and combines under it several lower, so that any one starting from a single idea may eventually discover all {Meno. p. 81), -then must the sum of ideas form a connected organism and succession in which the lower idea appears as a stepping-stone and presupposition to a higher. This succession must have its end in an idea which needs no higher idea or presupposition to sustain it. This highest idea, the ultimate limit of all knowledge, and itself the independent ground of all other ideas, Plato calls the idea of the good, i. e. not of the moral but of the metaphysical good. (Bep. YII. 517.) What this good is in itself, Plato undertakes to show only in images. " In the same manner as the sun," he says in the Repub- lic (VI. 506), " is the cause of sight, and the cause not merely that objects are visible but also that they grow and are produced, so the good is of such power and beauty, that it is not merely the cause of science to the soul, but is also the cause of being and reality to whatever is the object of science, and as the sun is not itself sight or the object of sight but presides over both, so the good is not science and truth but is superior to both, they being not the good itself but of a goodly nature." The good has uncon- 96 A inSTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. ditioned wortli, and gives to every other thing all the value it possesses. The idea of the good excludes all presupposition. It is the ultimate ground at the same time of knowing and of being, of the perceiver and the perceived, of the subjective and the ob- jective, of the ideal and the real, though exalted itself above such a division. [Rep. YI. 508-517.) Plato, however, has not attempt- ed a derivation of the remaining ideas from the idea of the good ; his course here is wholly an empirical one ; a certain class of objects are taken, and having referred these to their common essence this is given out as their idea. He has treated the indi- vidual conceptions so independently, and has made each one so complete in itself, that it is impossible to find a proper division or establish an immanent continuation of one into another. It is difficult to say precisely what relation this idea of the good bore to the Deity in the Platonic view. Taking every thing together it seems clear that Plato regarded the two as identical, but whether he conceived this highest cause to be a personal being or not is a question which hardly admits of a definite answer. The logical result of his system would exclude the personality of Grod. If only the universal (the idea) is the true being, then can the only absolute idea, the Deity, be only the absolute universal ; but that Plato was himself conscious of this logical conclusion we can hardly affirm, any more than we can say on the other hand that he was clearly a theist. For whenever in a mythical or popular statement he speaks of innumerable gods, this only indicates that he is speaking in the language of the popular religion, and when he speaks in an accurate philosophical sense, he only makes the relation of the personal deity with the idea a very uncertain one. Most probable, therefore, is it that this whole question concerning the personality of Grod was not yet definitely before him, that he took up the religious idea of Grod and defended it in ethical interest against the anthropomorphism of the mythic poets, that be sought to establish it by arguments drawn from the evidences of design in nature, and the universal prevalence of a belief in a God, while as a philosopher he made no use of it. V. The Platonic Physics. 1. Nature. — The connection PLATO. 97 ^etween the Physics and the Dialectics of Plato lies principally m two points — the conception of becoming, which forms the chief property of nature, and that of real being, which is at once the all sufficient and good, and the true end of all becoming. Because nature belongs to the province of irrational sensation we cannot look for the same accuracy in the treatment of it, as is furnished in dialectics. Plato therefore applied himself with much less zest to physical investigations than to those of an ethical or dialectical character, and indeed only attended to them in his later years. Only in one dialogue, the Timaeus, do we find any extended evo- lution of physical doctrines, and even here Plato seems to have gone to his work with much less independence than his wont, this dialogue being more strongly tinctured with Pythagoreanism than any other of his writings. The difficulty of the Timaeus is in- creased by the mythical form on which the old commentators themselves have stumbled. If we take the first impression that it gives us, we have, before the creation of the world, a Creator as a moving and a reflecting principle, with on the one side the ideal world existing immovable as the eternal archetype, and on the other side, a chaotic, formless, irregular, fluctuating mass, which holds in itself the germ of the material world, but has no deter- mined character nor substance. With these two elements the Creator now blends the world-soul which he distributes according to the relation of numbers, and sets it in definite and harmonious motion. In this way the material world, which has become actual through the arrangement of the chaotic mass into the four ele- ments, finds its external frame, and the process thus begun is completed in its external structure by the formation of the organic world. It is difficult to separate the mythical and the philosophical elements in this cosmogony of the Timaeus, especially difficult to determine how far the historical construction, which gives a suc- cession in time to the acts of creation, is only a formal one, and also how far the affirmation that matter is absolutely a not-being can be harmonized with the general tenor of Plato's statements. The significance of the world-soul is clearer. Since the soul in 5 98 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. the Platonic system is the mean between spirit and body, and as in the same way mathematical relations, in their most universal expression as numbers, are the mean between mere sensuous ex- istence and the pure idea (between the one and the many as Plato expresses it), it would seem clear that the world-soul, construed according to the relation of numbers, must express the relation of the world of ideas to that of sense, in other words, that it denotes the sensible world as a thought represented in the form of material existence. The Platonic view of nature, in opposition to the mechanical attempts to explain it of the earlier philosophers, is entirely teleological, and based upon the conception of the good, or, on the moral idea. Plato conceives the world as the image of the good, as the work of the divine munificence. As it is the image of the perfect it is therefore only one, corresponding to the idea of the single all-embracing substance, for an infinite number of worlds is not to be conceived as actual. For the same reason the world is spherical, after the most perfect and uniform struc- ture, which embraces in itself all other forms ; its movement is in a circle, because this, by returning into itself, is most like the movement of reason. The particular points of the Timaeus, the derivation of the four elements, the separation of the seven planets according to the musical scale, the opinion that the stars were im- mortal and heavenly substances, the affirmation that the earth holds an abiding position in the middle of the world, a view which subsequently became elaborated to the Ptolemaic system, the re- ference of all material figures to the triangle as the simplest plane figure, the division of inanimate nature, according to the four ele- ments, into creatures of earth, water, and air, his discussions re- specting organic nature, and especially respecting the construction of the human body — all these we need here only mention. Their philosophical worth consists not so much in their material content, but rather in their fundamental idea, that the world should be conceived as the image and the work of reason, as an organism of order, harmony, and beauty, as the good actualizing itself 2. The Soul. — The doctrine of the soul, considering it simply as the basis of a moral action, and leaving out of view all ques- PLATO. 99 tions of concrete ethics, forms a constituent element in the Pla- tonic physics. Since the soul is united to the body, it participates in the motions and changes of the body, and is, in this respect, related to the perishable. But in so far as it participates in the knowledge of the eternal, i. e. in so far as it knows ideas, does there live within it a divine principle — reason. Accordingly, Plato distinguishes two components of the soul — the divine and the mortal, the rational and the irrational. These two are united by an intermediate link, which Plato calls -^v/xos or spirit, and which, though allied to reason is not reason itself, since it is often exhibi- ted in children and also in brutes, and since even men are often car- ried away by it without reflection. This threefol dness, here exhibited psychologically, is found, in different applications, through all the last general period of Plato's literary life. Based upon the anthro- pological triplicate of reason, soul and body, it corresponds also to the division of theoretical knowledge into science (or thinking), correct opinions (or sense-perception), and ignorance, to the triple ladder of eroticism in the Symposium and the mythological repre- sentation connected with this of Poros, Eros, and Penia ; to the metaphysical triplicate of the ideal world, mathematical relations and the sensible world ; and furnishes ground for deriving the ethical division of virtue and the political division of ranks. So far as the soul is a mean between the spiritual and cor- poreal, may we connect the Phaedon's proofs of its immortality with the psychological view now before us. The common thought of these arguments is that the soul, in its capacity for thinking, participates in the reason, and being thus of an opposite nature to, and uncontrolled by the corporeal, it may have an independent existence. The arguments are wholly analytical, and possess no valid and universal proof ; they proceed entirely upon a petitio princijoii, they are derived partly from mythical philosophemes, and manifest not only an obscure conception of the soul, but of its relations to the body and the reason, and, so far as the relation of the soul to the ideal world is in view, they furnish in the best case only some proof for the immortality of him who has raised his soul to a pure spirit, i. e. the immortality of the philosopher. Plato 100 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. was not himself deceived as to the theoretical insufficiency of his arguments. Their number would show this, and, besides, he ex- pressly calls them proofs which amount to only human probability, and furnish practical postulates alone. With this view he intro- duces at the close of his arguments the myth of the lower world, and the state of departed souls, in order, by complying with the religious notions, and traditions of his countrymen, to gain a pos- itive support for belief in the soul's immortality. Elsewhere Plato also speaks of the lower world, and of the future rewards and punishments of the good and the evil, in accordance with the popular notions, as though he saw the elements of a divine revela- tion therein ; he tells of purifying punishment in Hades, analo- gous to a purgatory ; he avails himself of the common notion to affirm that shades still subject to the corporeal principle will hover after death over their graves, seeking to recover their life- less bodies, and at times he dilates upon the migration of the soul to various human and brute forms. On the whole, we find in Plato's proofs of immortality, as in his psychology generally, that dualism, which here expresses itself as hatred to the corporeal, and is connected with the tendency to seek the ultimate ground of evil in the nature of the " different" and the sensible world. VI. The Platonic Ethics. — The ground idea of the good, which in physics served only as an inventive conception, finds now, in the ethics, its true exhibition. Plato has developed it prominently according to three sides, as good, as individual virtue, and as ethical world in the state. The conception of duty re- mains in the background with him as with the older philosophers. 1. Good and Pleasure. — That the highest good can be noth- ing other than the idea of the good itself, has already been shown in the dialectics, where this idea was suffered to appear as the ulti- mate end of all our striving. But since the dialectics represent the supreme good as unattainable by human reason, and only cog nizable in its different modes of manifestation, we can, therefore only follow these different manifestations of the highest gooa, which represent not the good itself, but the good in becoming, where it appears as science, truth, beauty, virtue, &c. We are PLATO. 101 thus not required to be equal to God, but only like him (ThecEi.) It is this point of view which lies at the basis of the graduated table of good, given in the Philebus. In seeking the highest good, the conception of pleasure must be investigated. The Platonic stand-point here is the attempt to strike a balance between Hedonism, (the Cyrenian theory that pleasure is the highest good, cf. ^ XIII. 3), and Cynicism. While he will not admit with Aristippus that pleasure is the true good, neither will he find it as the Cynics maintain, simply in the nega- tion of its contrary, pain, and thus deny that it belongs to the good things of human life. He finds his refutation of Hedonism in the indeterminateness and relativity of all pleasure, since that which at one time may seem as pleasure, under other circum- stances may appear as pain ; and since he who chooses pleasure without distinction, will find impure pleasures always combined in his life with more or less of pain ; his refutation of Cynicism he establishes by showing the necessary connection between virtue and true pleasure, showing that there is a true and enduring plea- sure, the pleasure of reason, found in the possession of truth and of goodness, while a rational condition separate from all pleasure, cannot be the highest good of a finite being. It is most promi- nently by this distinction of a true and false, of a pure and im- pure pleasure, that Plato adjusts the controversy of the two Socratic schools. — A detailed exhibition of the Philebus we must here omit. — On the whole, in the Platonic apprehension of plea- sure, we cannot but notice that same vacillation with which Plato every where treats of the relation between the corporeal and the spiritual, at one time considering the former as a hindrance to the latter, and at another as its serving instrument ; now, regarding it as a concurring cause to the good, and then, as the ground of all evil ; here, as something purely negative, and there, as a positive substratum which supports all the higher intellectual develop- ments; and in conformity with this, pleasure is also considered at one time as something equivalent to a moral act, and to knowl- edge, and at another as the means and accidental consequence of the good. 102 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 2. Virtue. — In Ms theory of virtue, Plato is wholly Socratic. He holds fast to the opinion that it is science {Protagoras), and therefore, teachable (Meno), and as to its unity, it follows from the dialectical principle that the one can be manifold, or the man- ifold one, that, therefore, virtue must both be regarded as one, and also in a different respect, as many. Plato thus brings out prominently the union and connection of all virtues, and is fond of painting, especially in the introductory dialogues, some single virtue as comprising in itself the sum of. all the rest. Plato fol- lows for the most part the fourfold division of virtues, as popu- larly made; and first, in the Republic (TV. 441), he attempts a scientific derivation of them, by referring to each of the three parts of the soul its appropriate virtue The virtue of the reason he calls prudence or wisdom, the directing or measuring virtue, without whose activity valor would sink to brute impulse, and calm endurance to stupid indifference; the virtue of spirit is valor, the help-meet of reason, or spirit (S-v}x6y the phenomenal world ; but at the same time the theoretical Ego contains the two sides within itself, for if, on the one side, empiricism may be justified upon the ground that the material and only field of all our knowledge is furnished by experience, so on the other side, rationalism may be justified on the ground that there is an apriori factor and basis to our knowledge, for in experience itself we make use of concep- tions which are not furnished by experience, but are contained apriori in our understanding. In order, now, that we may bring the very elaborate frame- work of the Kantian philosophy into a clearer outline, let us briefly glance at its fundamental conceptions, and notice its chief principles and results. Kant subjected the activity of the hu- man mind in knowing, and the origin of our experience, to his critical investigation. Hence his philosophy is called critical philosophy, or criticism, because it aims to be essentially an ex- amination of our faculty of knowledge ; it is also called transcen- dental philosophy, since Kant calls the reflection of the reason upon its relation to the objective world, a transcendental reflec- tion (transcendental must not be confounded with transcendent), or, in other words, a transcendental knowledge is one " which does not relate so much to objects of knowledge, as to our way of knowing them, so far as this is apriori possible." The exami- nation of the faculty of knowledge, which Kant attempts in his " Critich of Pure Beason.j''' shows the following results. All knowledge is a product of two factors, the knowing subject and the external world. Of these two factors, the latter furnishes our knowledge with experience, as the matter, and the former with the conceptions of the understanding, as the form, through TRANSITION TO KANT. 231 which a connected knowledge, or a synthesis of our perceptions in a whole of experience first becomes possible. If there were no external world, then would there be no phenomena ; if there were no understanding, then these phenomena, or perceptions, which are infinitely manifold, would never be brought into the unity of a notion, and thus no experience were possible. Thus, while intuitions without conceptions are blind, and conceptions without intuitions are empty, knowledge is a union of the two, since it re(][uires that the form of conception should be filled with the matter of experience, and that the matter of experience should be apprehended in the net of the understanding's concep- tions. Nevertheless, we do not know things as they are in them- selves. Firsts because the categories, or the forms of our under- standing prevent. Ey bringing that which is given as the mate- rial of knowledge into our own conceptions as the form, there is manifestly a change in respect of the objects, which become thought of not as they are, but only as we apprehend them ; they appear to us only as they are transmuted into categories. But besides this subjective addition, there is yet another. Secondly^ we do not know things as they are in themselves, because even the intuitions which we bring within the form of the understand- ing's conceptions, are not pure and uncolored, but are already penetrated by a subjective medium, namely, by the universal form of all objects of sense, space and time. Space and time are also subjective additions, forms of sensuous intuition, which are just as originally present in our minds as the fundamental conceptions or categories of our understanding. That which we would repre- sent intuitively to ourselves we must place in space and time, for without these no intuition is possible. From this it follows that it is only phenomena which we know, and not things in themselves separate from space and time. A superficial apprehension of these Kantian principles might lead one to suppose that Kant's criticism did not essentially go beyond the standpoint of Locke's empiricism. But such a sup- position disappears upon a careful scrutiny. Kant was obliged to recognize with Hume that the conceptions, cause and efiect, sub- 232 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Etance and attribute, and the other conceptions which the human understanding sees itself necessitated to think in the phenomena, and in which every one of its thoughts must be found, do not arise from any experience of the sense. For instance, when we become afTected through different senses, and perceive a white color, a sweet taste, a rough surface, &c., and predicate all these of one thing, as a piece of sugar, there come from without only the plu- rality of sensations, while the conception of unity cannot come through sensation, but is a category^ or conception borne over to the sensations from the mind itself. But instead of denying, for this reason, the reality of these conceptions of the understanding, Kant took a step in advance, assigning a peculiar provinn uses the trick of bringing forth as a new argument an old one with a changed dress, that it might seem to have the power of summoning two witnesses. (c.) The Physico-theological proof. — If thus neither concep- tion nor experience can furnish a proof for the divine existence, there still remains a third attempt, viz., to start from a determi- nate experienc, and endeavor to see whether the existence of a supreme being can not be inferred from the arrangement and condition of things in the world. Such is the physico-theological proof, which starts from the evidences of design in nature, and directs its argument as follows : there is evidently design in the universe \ this is extraneous to the things of the world, and ad- KANT. 251 heres to them only contingently ; there exists therefore a neces- sary cause of this design which works with wisdom and intelli- gence ; this necessary cause must be the most real being ; the most real being has therefore necessary existence. — To this Kant answers : The physico-theological proof is the oldest, clearest, and most conformable to the common reason. But it is not demon- stration (apodictic). It infers, from the form of the world, a pro- portionate and sufficient cause of this form; but in this way we onl^ attain an originator of the form of the world, and not an originator of its matter, a world-builder, and not a world-creator. To help out with this difficulty the cosmological proof is brought in, and the originator of the form becomes conceived as the necessary being lying at the ground of the content. Thus we have an ab- solute being whose perfection corresponds to that of the world. But in the world there is no absolute perfection ; we have there- fore only a very perfect being ; to get the most perfect, we must revert again to the ontological proof. Thus the teleological proof rests upon the cosmological, while this in turn has its basis in the ontological, and from this circle the metaphysical modes of proof cannot escape. From these considerations, it would follow that the ideal of a supreme being is nothing other than a regulative principle of the reason, by which it looks upon every connection in the world as if it sprang from an all-sufficient and necessary cause ; in order that, in explaining this connection, it may establish the rule of a systematic and necessary unity, it being also true that in this pro- cess the reason through a transcendental subreption cannot avoid representing to itself this formal principle as constitutive, and this unity as personal. But in truth this supreme being remains for the simply speculative use of the reason, a mere but faultless ideal, a conception which is the summit and the crown of the whole human knowledge, whose objective reality, though it cannot be proved with apodictic certainty, can just as little be dis- proved. With this critick of the ideas of the reason there is still an- other qi^estion. If these ideas have no objective significance, why 252 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. are they found within us ? Since they are necessary, they will doubtless have some good purpose to subserve. What this pur- pose is, has already been indicated in speaking of the theological idea. Though not constitutive, yet are they regulative principles. "VVe cannot better order the faculties of our soul, than by acting " as i]/" there were a soul. The cosmological idea leads us to consider the world "asi/" the series of causes were infinite, without, however, excluding an intelligent cause. The theologi- cal idea enables us to look upon the world in all its complexity, as a regulated unity. Thus, while these ideas of the reason are not constitutive principles, by means of which our knowledge could be widened beyond experience, they are regulative princi- ples, by means of which our experience may be ordered, and brought under certain hypothetical unities. These three ideas, therefore, the psychological, the cosmological, and the theological, do not form an organon for the discovery of truth, but only a ca- non for the simplification and systematizing of our experiences. Besides their regulative significance, these ideas of the reason have also a practical importance. There is a sufficient certainty, not objective, but subjective, which is especially of a practical nature, and is called belief or confidence. If the freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the existence of a God, are three cardinal principles, which, though not in afiy way contribu- ting to our knowledge, are yet pressed continually upon us by the reason, this difficulty is removed in the practical field where these ideas have their peculiar significance for the moral confidence. This confidence is not logical, but moral certainty. Since it rests wholly upon subjective grounds, upon the moral character, I can- not say it is morally certain that there is a Grod, but only I am morally certain, &c. That is, the belief in a Grod and in another world is so interwoven with my moral character, that I am in just as much danger of losing this character as of being deprived of this belief. "We are thus brought to the basis of the Practical Reason. II. Critick of the Practical Reason. — With the Critick of the Practical Reason, we enter a wholly different world, where KANT. 253 the reason richly recovers that of which it was deprived in tha theoretical province. The essential problem of the Critick of the Practical Keason is almost diametrically different from that of the critick of the theoretical reason. The object of investigation in the critick of the speculative reason, was, — how can the pure reason know objects apriori; in the practical reason it is, — how can the pure reason determine apriori the will in respect of ob- jects. The critick of the speculative reason inquired after the cognizableness of objects apriori : the practical reason has nothing to do with the cognizableness of objects, but only with the de- termination of the will. Hence, in the latter critick, we have an order directly the reverse of that which we find in the former. As the original determinations of our theoretical knowledge are intuitions, so the original determinations of our will are principles and conceptions. The critick of the practical reason must, there- fore, start from moral principles, and only after these are firmly fixed, may we inquire concerning the relation in which the prac- tical reason stands to the sensory. Freedom, says Kant, is given to us apriori as an inner fact, it is a fact of the inner experience. While, therefore, the reason in the theoretical field had only a negative result, because, when it would attain to a true thing in itself it became transcendent, yet now in the practical province it becomes positive through the idea of freedom, because with the fact of freedom we have no need to go out beyond ourselves, but possess a principle immanent to the reason. But why then give a critick of practical reason ? In order to determine the relation of freedom to the sensory. Since the free will works through its acts upon the sensory, there must be a point of contact between the two. This is found in the sen- suous motives of the will, which exist implanted in it by nature, in the impulses and inclinations which, as the principle of the empiric in opposition to the free or pure will, bear in themselves the char- acter of a want of freedom. Since, then, freedom cannot be touched, a critick of the practical reason can only relate to these smpirical motives, in the sense of divesting these from the claim of being exclusively the motives by which the will is determined 254 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. While, therefore, in the theoretical reason the empirical element was immanent, and the intelligible transcendent, the reverse is the case in the practical reason, since here the empirical is trans- cendent, and the intelligible immanent. It is the object of the Analytic to show the relation of these two momenta of the will, and the highest moral principle which springs therefrom, while it belongs to the Dialectic to solve the antinomies which result from the contradiction of the pure and empiric will. (1.) The Analytic. — Freedom, as the one constituent element which shows itself in the activity of our will, is the simple form of our actions. The universal law binding the will, is that it should determine itself purely from itself, independently of every external incitement. This capacity of self-lawgiving, or self-de- termining, Kant calls the autonomy of the will. The free auton- omic will says to man : thou oughtest ! and since this moral ought commands to an unconditioned obedience, the moral imperative is a categorical imperative. What is it now which is categorically commanded by the practical reason ? To answer this question, we must first consider the empirical will, i. e. the nature-side of man. The empirical, as the other constituent element of our will, first produces a definite deed when it has filled the empty form of action with the matter of action. The matter of the will is furnished by the sensory in the desire of pleasure and the dread of pain. Since this second principle of our actions does not find its seat in the freedom of the will as the higher faculty of desire, but in the sensory, as the lower faculty of desire, and a foreign law is thus laid upon the will, — Kant calls it, in opposition to the autonomy of the reason, the Jieteronomy of the will. The categorical imperative is the necessary law of freedom binding upon all men, and is distinguished from material motives, in that the latter have no fixed character. For men are at variance in respect of pleasure and pain, since that which is disagreeable to one may seem pleasant to another, and if they ever agree, this is simply accidental. Consequently^ these material motivea can never act the part of laws bindiog upon every being, but each KANT. 255 subject may find his end in a difierent motive. Such rules of act- ing, Kant calls maxims of the will. He also censures those moralists who have exalted such maxims as universal principles of morality. Nevertheless, these maxims, though not the highest principles of morality, are yet necessary to the autonomy of the will, he- cause they alone furnish for it a content. It is only by uniting the two sides, that we gain the true principle of morality. To this end the maxims of acting must be freed from their limitation, and widened to the form of universal laws of the reason. Only those maxims should be chosen as motives of action which are capable of becoming universal laws of the reason. The highest jjrincijple of moraliiy will therefore be this : act so that the maxims of thy will can at the same time be valid as the principle of a uni- versal lawgiving, i. e. that no contradiction shall arise in the attempt to conceive the maxims of thy acting as a law universally obeyed. Through this formal moral principle all material moral principles which can only be of a heteronomic nature, are ex- cluded. The question next arises — what impels the will to act con- formably to this highest moral law ? Kant answers : the moral law itself, apprehended and revered, must be the only moving- spring of the human will. If an act which in itself might be conformable to the moral law, be done only through some impulse to hippiness arising simply from an inclination of the sense, if it be not done purely for the sake of the law, then have we simply legality and not morality. That which is included in every in- clination of the sense is self-love and self-conceit, and of these the former is restricted by the moral law, and the latter wholly stricken down. But that which. strikes down our self-conceit and humbles us must appear to us in the highest degree worthy of es- teem. But this is done by the moral law. Consequently the positive feeling which we shall cherish in respect of the moral law will be reverence. This reverence, though a feeling, is neither sensuous nor pathological, for it stands opposed to these ; but is rather an intellectual feeling^ since it arises from the notion 256 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. of the practical law of the reason. On the one side as subor- dination to law, the reverence includes pain; on the other side, since the coercion can only be exercised through the proper reason, it includes pleasure. Reverence is the single sensation befitting man in reference to the moral law. Man, as creature of sense, cannot rest on any inner inclination to the moral law, for he has ever inclinations within him which resist the law ; love to the law can only be considered as something ideal. — Thus the moral purism of Kant, or his effort to separate every impulse of \he sense from the motives to action, merges into rigorism, or the dark view that duty can never be done except with resistance. A similar exaggeration belongs to the well-known epigram of Schiller, who answers the following scruple of conscience — The friends whom I love I gladly Avould serve, But to this inclination incites me ; And so I am forced from virtue to swerve Since my act, through aflfection, delights me — with the following decision : The friends whom thou lov'st, thou must first seek to scorn, For to no other way can I guide thee : 'Tis alone with disgust thou canst rightly perform The acts to which duty would lead thee. (2.) The Dialectic. — The pure reason has always its dialectics, since it belongs to the nature of the reason to demand the uncon- ditioned for the given conditioned. Hence also the practical rea- son seeks an unconditioned highest good for that conditioned good after which man strives. What is this highest good ? If we understand by the highest good the fundamental condition of all other goods, then it is virtue. But virtue is not the perfect good, since the finite reason as sensitive stands in need also of happi- ness. Hence the highest good is only perfect when the highest happiness is joined to the highest virtue. The question now arises : what is the relation of these two elements of the highest good to each other ? Are they analytically or synthetically con- KANT. 257 nected together ? The former would be affirmed by most of the ancients, especially by the Greek moral philosophers. We might allow with the Stoics, that happiness is contained as an accidental element in virtue, or, with the Epicureans, that virtue is con- tained as an accidental element in happiness. The Stoics said : to be conscious of one's virtue is happiness ; the Epicureans said : to be conscious of the maxims leading one to happiness is virtue. But, says Kant, an analytic connection between these two con- ceptions is not possible, since they are wholly different in kind. Consequently there can be between them only a synthetic unity, and this unity more closely scanned is seen to be a causal one, so that the one element is cause, and the other effect. Such a rela- tion must be regarded as its highest good by the practical reason, whose thesis must therefore be : virtue and happiness must be bound together in a correspondent degree as cause and effect. But this thesis is all thwarted by the actual fact. Neither of the two is the direct cause of the other. Neither is the striving after happiness a moving spring to virtue, nor is virtue the efficient cause of happiness. Hence the antithesis : virtue and happiness do not necessarily correspond, and are not universally connected as cause and effect. The critical solution of this anti- nomy Kant finds in distinguishing between the sensible and the intelligible world. In the world of sense, virtue and happiness do not, it is true, correspond ; but the reason as noumenon is also a citizen of a supersensible world, where the counter-strife be- tween virtue and happiness has no place. In this supersensible world virtue is always adequate to happiness, and when man passes over into this he may look for the actualization of the high- est good. But the highest good has, as already remarked, two elements, (1) highest virtue, (2) highest happiness. The actual- ization demanded for the first of these elements postulates the immortality of the soul, and for the second, the existence of God. {a.) To the highest good belongs in the first place perfect virtue or holiness. But no creature of sense can be holy : reason united to sense can only approximate holiness as an ideal in an 258 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. endless progression. But sucli an endless progress is only pos- sible in an endless continuance of personal existence. If, there- fore, the highest good shall ever be actualized, the immortality of the soul must be presupposed. (5.) To the highest good belongs, in the second place, perfect happiness. Happiness is that condition of a rational creature in the world, to whom every thing goes according to his desire and will. This can only occur when all nature is in accord with his ends. But this is not the case ; as acting beings we are not the cause of nature, and there is not the slightest ground in the moral law for connecting morality and happiness. Notwith- standing this, we ought to endeavor to secure the highest good. It must therefore be possible. There is thus postulated the necessary connection of these tv^o elements, i. e. the existence of a cause of nature distinct from nature, and which contains the ground of this connection. There must be a being as the com- mon cause of the natural and moral world, a being who knows our characters of intelligence, and who, according to this intelli- gence imparts to us happiness. Such a being is God. Thus from the practical reason there issue the ideas of im- mortality and of God, as we have already seen to be the case with the idea of freedom. The reality of the idea of freedom is derived from the possibility of a moral law ; that of the idea of immortality is borrowed from the possibility of a ^perfect virtue ; that of the idea of a God follows from the necessary demand of a perfect happiness. These three ideas, therefore, which the speculative reason has treated as problems that could not be solved, gain a firm basis in the province of the practical reason. Still they are not yet theoretical dogmas, but as Kant calls them practical postulates, necessary premises of moral action. My theoretical knowledge is not enlarged by them : I only know now that there are objects corresponding to these ideas, but of these objects I can know no more. Of God, for instance, we pos- sess and know no more than this very conception; and if we should attempt to establish the theory of the supersensible grounded upon such categories, this would be to make theology KANT. 25£ like a magic lantern, with its pliantasmagorical representations. Yet Las the practical reason acquired for us a certainty respecting the objective reality of these ideas, which the theoretical reason had been obliged to leave undecided, and in this respect the prac- tical reason has the primacy. This relation of the two faculties of knowledge is wisely established in relation to the destiny of men. Since the ideas of God and immortality are theoretically obscure to us, they do not defile our moral motives by fear and hope, but leave us free space to act through reverence for the moral law. Thus far Kant's Critick of the Practical Reason. In con- nection with this we may here mention his vieivs of religion as they appear in his treatise upon " Religion within the Bounds of Pure Beasony The chief idea of this treatise is the referring of religion to morality. Between morality and religion there may be the twofold relation, that either morality is founded upon religion, or else religion upon morality. If the first relation were real, it would give us fear and hope as principles of moral action ; but this cannot be, and we are therefore left alone to the second. Morality leads necessarily to religion, because the high- est good is a necessary ideal of the reason, and this can only be realized through a God ; but in no way may religion first incite us to virtue, for the idea of God may never become a moral mo- tive. Religion, according to Kant, is the recognition of all our duties as divine commands. It is revealed religion when I find in it the divine command, and thus learn my duty ; it is natural religion when I find in it my duty, and thus learn the divine com- mand. The Church is an ethical community, which has for its end the fulfilment and the most perfect exhibition of moral com- mands, — a union of those who with united energies purpose to resist evil and advance morality. The Church, in so far as it is no object of a possible experience, is called the invisible Church, which, as such, is a simple idea of the union of all the righteous under the divine moral government of the world. The visible Church, on the other hand, is that which presents the kingdom of God upon earth, so far as this can be attained through men. The 260 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. requisites, and hence also the characteristics of the true visible Church (which are divided according to the table of the cate- gories since this Church is given in experience) are the following : (a) In respect of quantity the Church must be total or unive?'- sal ; and though it may be divided in accidental opinions, yet must it be instituted upon such principles as will necessarily lead to a universal union in one single church. (5) The quality of the true visible Church is purity ^ as a union under no other than moral motives, since it is at the same time purified from the stupidness of superstition and the madness of fanaticism, (c) The relation of the members of the Church to each other rests upon the principle of freedom. The Church is, therefore, a free state, neither a hierarchy nor a democracy, but a voluntary, uni- versal, and enduring union of heart, {d) In respect of modality the Church demands that its constitution should not be changed. The laws themselves may not change, though one may reserve to himself the privilege of changing some accidental arrangements which relate simply to the administration. — That alone which can establish a universal Church is the moral faith of the reason, for this alone can be shared by the convictions of every man. But, because of the peculiar weakness of human nature, we can never reckon enough on this pure faith to build a Church on it alone, for men are not easily convinced that the striving after virtue and an irreproachable life is every thing which God demands : they always suppose that they must offer to God a special service prescribed by tradition, in which it only comes to this — that he is served. To establish a Church, we must therefore have a statutory faith historically grounded upon facts. This is the so-called faith of the Church. In every Church there are therefore two elements — the purely moral, or the faith of reason, and the his- torico-statutory, or the faith of the Church. It depends now upon the relation of the two elements whether a Church shall have any worth or not. The statutory element should ever be only the vehicle of the moral. Just so soon as this element becomes in itself an independent end, claiming an independent validity, will KANT. 261 the Church become corrupt and irrational, and -whenever tht Church passes over to the pure faith of reason, does it approx- imate to the kingdom of God. Upon this principle we may dis- tinguish the true from the spurious service of the kingdom of God, religion from priestcraft. A dogma has worth alone in so far as it has a moral content. The apostle Paul himself would with difficulty have given credit to the dicta of the faith of the Church without this moral faith. From the doctrine of the Trinity, e. g. taken literally, nothing actually practical can be derived. Whether we have to reverence in the Godhead three persons or ten makes no difference, if in both cases we have the same rules for our conduct of life. The Bible also, with its in- terpretation, must be considered in a moral point of view. The records of revelation must be interpreted in a sense which will harmonize with the universal rules of the religion of reason. Reason is in religious things the highest interpreter of the Bible. This interpretation in reference to some texts may seem forced, yet it must be preferred to any such literal interpretation as would contain nothing for morality, or perhaps go against every moral motive. That such a moral signification may always be found without ever entirely repudiating the literal sense, results from the fact that the foundation for a moral religion lay origi- nally in the human reason. We need only to divest the repre- sentations of the Bible of their mythical dress (an attempt which Kant has himself made^ by moral explanation of some of the weightiest doctrines), in order to attain a rational sense which shall be universally valid. The historical element of the sacred books is in itself of no account. The maturer the reason be- comes, the more it can hold fast for itself the moral sense, so much the more unnecessary will be the statutory institutions of the faith of the Church. The transition of the faith of the Church to the pure faith of reason is the approximation to the kingdom of God, to which, however, we can only approach nearer and nearer in an infinite progress. The actual realization of the kingdom of God is the end of the world, the cessation of history. 262 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. III. Critick of the Faculty of Judgment. — The con- ception of this science Kant gives in the following manner. The two faculties of the human mind hitherto considered were the faculty of knowledge and that of desire. It was proved in the Critick of pure Keason, that the understanding only as faculty of knowledge included constitutive principles apriori ; and it was shown in the Critick of Practical Reason, that the reason pos- sesses constitutive principles apriori, simply in reference to the faculty of desire. Whether now the faculty of judgment^ as the middle link between understanding and reason, can take its object — the feeling of pleasure and pain as the middle link be- tween the faculty of knowledge and that of desire — and furnish it apriori with principles which shall be for themselves consti- tutive and not simply regulative : this is the point upon which the Critick of the Faculty of Judgment has to turn. The faculty of judgment is the middle link between the un- derstanding as the faculty of conceptions, and the reason as the faculty of principles. In this position it has the following func- tions : The speculative reason had taught us to consider the world only according to natural laws ; the practical reason had inferred for us a moral world, in which every thing is determined through freedom. There was thus a gulf between the kingdom of nature and that of freedom, which could not be passed unless the faculty of judgment should furnish a conception which should unite the two sides. That it is entitled to do this lies in the very concep- tion of the faculty of judgment. Since it is the faculty of con- ceiving the particular as contained under the universal, it thus refers the empirical manifoldness of nature to a supersensible, transcendental principle, which embraces in itself the ground for the unity of the manifold. The object of the faculty of judg- ment is, therefore, the conception of design in nature ; for the evidence of this points to that supersensible unity which contains the ground for the actuality of an object. And since all design and every actualization of an end is connected with pleasure, we may farther explain the faculty of judgment by saying, that it contains the laws for the feeling of pleasure and pain. KANT. 263 The evidence of design in nature can be represented eithei subjectively or objectively. In the first case I perceive pleasure a,nd pain, immediately through the representation of an object, before I have formed a conception of it ; my delight, in this in- s^nce, can only be referred to a designed harmony of relation, between the form of an object, and my faculty of beholding. The faculty of judgment viewed thus subjectively, is called the cEsthetic faculty^ In the second case, I form to myself at the outset, a conception of the object, and then judge whether the form of the object corresponds to this conception. In order to find a flower that is beautiful to my beholding, I do not need to have a conception of the flower ; but, if I would see a design in it, then a conception is necessary. The faculty of judgment, viewed as capacity to judge of these objective designs, is called the teleological faculty. 1. Critick of the Esthetic Faculty of Judgment. (1.) Analytic. — The analytic of the aesthetic faculty of judgment is divided into two parts, the analytic of the beautiful^ and the an- alytic of the sublime. In order to discover what is required in naming an object beautiful^ we must analyze the judgment of taste, as the faculty for deciding upon the beautiful, {a) In respect of quality, the beautiful is the object of a pure, uninterested satisfaction. This disinterestedness enables us to distinguish between the satisfac- tion in the beautiful, and the satisfaction in the agreeable and the good. In the agreeable and the good I am interested ; my satis- faction in the agreeable is connected with a sensation of desire ; my satisfaction in the good is, at the same time, a motive for my will to actualize it. My satisfaction in the beautiful alone is without interest, {b) In respect of quantity, the beautiful is that which universally pleases. In respect of the agreeable, every one decides that his satisfaction in it is only a personal one ; but if any one should affirm of a picture, that it is beautiful, he would expect that not only he, but every other one, would also find it so. Nevertheless, this judgment of the taste does not arise from conceptions ; its universal validity is therefore purely 264 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. subjective. I do not judge that all the objects of a species are beautiful, but only that a certain specific object will appear beau- tiful to every beholder. All the judgments of taste are indi- vidual judgments, (c) In respect of relation, that is beautiful in which we find the form of design, without representing to our- selves any specific design, (d) In respect of modality, that is beautiful which is recognized without a conception, as the object of a necessary satisfaction. Of every representation, it is at least possible, that it may awaken pleasure. The representation of the agreeable awakens actual pleasure. The representation of the beautiful, on the other hand, awakens pleasure necessarily. The necessity which is conceived in an aesthetic judgment, is a neces- sity for determining every thing by a judgment, which can be viewed as an example of a universal rule, though the rule itself cannot be stated. The subjective principle which lies at the basis of the judgment of taste, is therefore a common sense, which de- termines what is pleasing, and what displeasing, only through feeling, and not through conception. The sublime is that which is absolutely, or beyond all com- parison, great, compared with which every thing else is small. But now in nature there is nothing which has no greater. The absolutely great is only the infinite, and the infinite is only to be met with in ourselves, as idea. The sublime, therefore, is not properly found in nature, but is only carried over to nature from our own minds. We call that sublime in nature, which awakens within us the idea of the infinite. As in the beautiful there is prominent reference to quality, so, in the sublime, the most im- portant element of all, is quantity ; and this quantity is either greatness of extension (the mathematically sublime), or greatness of power (the dynamically sublime). In the sublime there is a greater satisfaction in the formless, than in the form. The sub- lime excites a vigorous movement Of the heart, and awakens pleasure only through pain, i. e. through the feeling that the energies of life are for the moment restrained. The satisfaction in the sublime is hence not so much a positive pleasure, but rather an amazement and awe, which may be called a negative pleasure. KANT. 265 The elements for an aesthetic judgment of the sublime are the same as in the feeling of the beautiful, (a) In respect of quan- tity, that is sublime which is absolutely great, in comparison with which every thing else is small. The aesthetic estimate of great- ness does not lie, however, in numeration, but in the simple in- tuition of the subject. The greatness of an object of nature, which the imagination attempts in vain to comprehend, leads to a supersensible substratum, which is great beyond all the measures of the sense, and which has reference properly to the feeling of the sublime. It is not the object itself, as the surging sea, which is sublime, but rather the subject's frame of mind, in the estima- tion of this object, (b) In respect of quality, the sublime does not awaken pure pleasure, like the beautiful, but first pain, and through this, pleasure. The feeling of the insufficiency of our imagination, in the aesthetic estimate of greatness, gives rise to pain ; but, on the other side, the consciousness of our independ- ent reason, for which the faculty of imagination is inadequate, awakens pleasure. In this respect, therefore, that is sublime which immediately pleases us, through its opposition to the in- terest of the sense, (c) In respect of relation, the sublime suf- fers nature to appear as a power, indeed, but in reference to which, we have the consciousness of superiority, (d) In respect of modality, the judgments concerning the sublime are as neces- sarily valid, as those for the beautiful ; only with this difference, that our judgment of the sublime finds an entrance to some minds, with greater difficulty than our judgment of the beautiful, since to perceive the sublime, culture, and developed moral ideas, are necessary. (2.) Dialectic. — A dialectic of the aesthetic faculty of judg- ment, like every dialectic, is only possible where we can meet with judgments which lay claim to universality apriori. For dia- lectics consists in the opposition of such judgments. The anti- nomy of the principles of taste rests upon the two opposite ele- ments of the judgment of taste, that it is purely subjective, and at the same time, lays claim to universal validity. Hence, the two common-place sayings : " there is no disputing about taste," 12 266 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. and " there is a contest of taste." From these, we have the fol- lowing antinomy, (a) Thesis : the judgment of taste cannot be grounded on conception, else might we dispute it. (b) Antithe- sis : the judgment of taste must be grounded on conception, else, notwithstanding its diversity, there could be no contest respecting it. — This antinomy, says Kant, is, however, only an apparent one, and disappears as soon as the two propositions are more accu- rately apprehended. The thesis should be : the judgment of taste is not grounded upon a definite conception, and is not strictly demonstrable ; the antithesis should be : this judgment is grounded upon a conception, though an indefinite one, viz., upon the conception of a supersensible substratum for the phenomenal. Thus apprehended, there is no longer any contradiction between the two propositions. In the conclusion of the aesthetic faculty of judgment, we can now answer the question, whether the fitness of things to our faculty of judgment (their beauty and sublimity), lies in the things themselves, or in us ? The assthetic realism claims that the supreme cause of nature designed to produce things which should affect our imagination, as beautiful and sublime, and the organic forms of nature strongly support this view. But on the other hand, nature exhibits even in her merely mechanical forms, such a tendency to the beautiful, that we might believe that she could produce also the most beautiful organic forms through me- chanism alone ; and that thus the design would lie not in nature, but in our soul. This is the standpoint of idealism, upon which it becomes explicable how we can determine any thing apriori concerning beauty and sublimity. But the highest view of the gesthetical, is to use it as a symbol of the moral good. Thus Kant makes the theory of taste, like religion, to be a corollary of morality. 2. Cpjtick of the Teleological Faculty of Judgment. — In the foregoing, we have considered the subjective sssthetical design in the objects of nature. But the objects of nature have also a relation of design to each other. The teleological faculty of judgment has also to consider this faculty of design. KANT. 267 (1.) Analytic of the Teleological Faculty of Judgment. — The analytic has to determine the kinds of objective design. Objec- tive, material design, is of two kinds, external, and internal. The external design is only relative, since it simply indicates a useful- ness of one thing for another. Sand, for instance, which borders the sea shore, is of use in bearing pine forests. In order that animals can live upon the earth, the earth must produce nourish- ment for them, etc. These examples of external design, show that here the design never belongs to the means in itself, but only accidentally. We should never get a conception of the sand by saying that it is a means for pine forests ; it is conceivable for it- self, without any reference to the conception of design. The earth does not produce nourishment, because it is necessary that men should dwell upon it. In brief, this external or relative de- sign may be conceived from the mechanism of nature alone. Not so the inner design of nature, which shows itself prominently in the organic products of nature. In an organic product of na- ture, every one of its parts is end, and every one, means or in- strument. In the process of generation, the natural product ap- pears as species, in growth it appears as individual, and in the process of complete formation, every part of the individual shows itself. This natural organism cannot be explained from mechani- cal causes, but only through final causes, or teleologically. (2.) Dialectic. — The dialectic of the teleological faculty of judgment, has to adjust this opposition between this mechanism of nature and teleology. On the one side we have the thesis : every production of material things must be judged as possible, according to simple mechanical laws. On the other side we have the antithesis : certain products of material nature cannot be judged as possible, according to simple mechanical laws, but de- mand the conception of design for their explanation. If these two maxims are posited as constitutive (objective) principles for the possibility of the objects themselves, then do they contradict each other, but as simply regulative (subjective) principles for the investigation of nature, they are not contradictory. Earlier systems treated the conception of design in nature dogmatically, 268 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. and either affirmed or denied its essential existence in nature. But we, convinced that teleology is only a regulative principle, have nothing to do with the question whether an inner design be- longs essentially to nature or not, but we only affirm that our faculty of judgment must look upon nature as designed. We envisage the conception of design in nature, but leave it wholly undecided whether to another understanding, which does not think discursively like ours, nature may not be understood, with- out at all needing to bring in this conception of design. Our un- derstanding thinks discursively : it proceeds frcm the parts, and comprehends the whole as the product of its parts ; it cannot, therefore, conceive the organic products of nature, where the whole is the ground and the prius of the parts, except from the point of view of the conception of design. If there were, on the other hand, an intuitive understanding, which could know the particular and the parts as co- determined in the universal and the whole ; such an understanding might conceive the whole of nature out of one principle, and would not need the conception of end. If Kant had thoroughly carried out this conception of an in- tuitive understanding as well as the conception of an immanent design in nature, he would have overcome, in principle, the stand- point of subjective idealism, which he made numerous attempts, in his critick of the faculty of judgment, to break through ; but these ideas he only propounded, and left them to be positively carried out by his successors. SECTION XXXIX. TRANSITION TO THE POST-KANTIAN PHILOSOPHY. The Kantian philosophy soon gained in Germany an almost undisputed rule. The imposing boldness of its standpoint, the novelty of its results, the applicability of its principles, the moral TRANSITION TO THE POST-KANTIAN PHILOSOPHY. 269 severity of its view of the world, and above all, the spirit of free- dom and moral autonomy which appeared in it, and which was so directly counter to the efforts of that age, gained for it an assent as enthusiastic as it was extended. It aroused among all culti- vated classes a wider interest and participation in philosophic pursuits, than had ever appeared in an equal degree among any people. In a short time it had drawn to itself a very numerous school : there were soon few German universities in which it had not had its talented representatives, while in every department of science and literature, especially in theology (it is the parent of theological rationalism), and in natural rights, as also in helles- lettres [Schiller) ^ it began to exert its influence. Yet most of the writers who appeared in the Kantian school, confined themselves to an exposition or popular application of the doctrine as Kant had given it, and even the most talented and independent amon^ the defenders and improvers of the critical philosophy [e. g Reinhold, 1758-1823 ; Bardili, 1761-1808 ; Scliulze, Beck, Fries, Krug, Bouterwech), only attempted to give a firmer basis to the Kantian philosophy as they had received it, to obviate some of its wants and deficiencies, and to carry out the standpoint of transcendental idealism more purely and consistently. Among those who carried out the Kantian philosophy, only two men, FicTite and Herhart, can be named, who made by their actual advance an epoch in philosophy ; and among its opposers [e. g. Hamann, Herder), only one, Jacohi, is of philosophic importance. These three philosophers are hence the first objects for us to con- sider. In order to a more accurate development of their princi- ples, we preface a brief and general characteristic of their relation to the Kantian philosophy. 1. Dogmatism had been critically annihilated by Kant ; his Critick of pure Reason had for its result the theoretical inde- monstrableness of the three ideas of the reason, Grod, freedom, and immortality. True, these ideas which, from the standpoint of theoretical knowledge, had been thrust out, Kant had introduced again as postulates of the practical reason ; but as postulates, as only practical premises, they possess no theoretic certainty, and 270 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. remain exposed to doubt. In order to do away with this uncer- tainty, and this despairing of knowledge which had seemed to he the end of the Kantian philosophy, Jacohi, a younger cotempo- rary of Kant, placed himself upon the standpoint of the faith philosophy in opposition to the standpoint of criticism. Though these highest ideas of the reason, the eternal and the divine, can- not be reached and proved by means of demonstration, yet is it the very essence of the divine that it is indemonstrable and unat- tainable for the understanding. In order to be certain of the highest, of that which lies beyond the understanding, there is only one organ, viz., feeling. In feeling, therefore, in immediate know- ledge, in faith, Jacobi thought he had found that certainty which Kant had sought in vain on the basis of discursive thinking. 2. While Jacobi stood in an antithetic relation to the Kan- tian philosophy, Fichte appears as its immediate consequence. Fichte carried out to its consequence the Kantian dualism, ac- cording to which the Ego, as theoretic, is subjected to the external world, while as practical, it is its master, or, in other words, ac- cording to which the Ego stands related to the objective world, now receptively and again spontaneously. He allowed the reason to be exclusively practical, as will alone, and spontaneity alone, and apprehended its theoretical and receptive relation to the ob- jective world as only a cu'cumscribed activity, as a limitation prescribed to itself by the reason. But for the reason, so far as it is practical, there is nothing objective except as it is produced. The will knows no being but only an ought. Hence the objec- tive being of truth is universally denied, and the thing which is essentially unknown must fall away of itself as an empty shadow. Every thing which is, is the Ego," is the principle of the Fichtian system, and represents at the same time the subjective idealism in its consequence and completion. 3. While the subjective idealism of Fichte was carried out in the objective idealism of Schelling, and the absolute idealism of Hegel, there arose cotemporaneously with these systems a third offshoot of the Kantian criticism, viz., the philosophy of Herhart. It had its subjective origin in the Kantian philosophy, but its ob- JACOBI. 271 jective and historic connection with Kant is slight. It breaks up all historic continuity, and holds an isolated position in the histo- ry of philosophy. Its general basis is Kantian, in so far as it makes for its problem a critical investigation of the subjective experience. We place it between Fichte and Schelling. SECTION XL. JACOBI. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi was born at Diisseldorf in 1743. His father destined him for a merchant. After he had studied in Geneva and become interested in philosophy, he entered his father's mercantile establishment, but afterwards abandoned this business, having been made chancellor of the exchequer and customs commissioner for Cleves and Berg, and also privy councillor at Diisseldorf. In this city, or at his neighboring estate of Pempelfort, he spent a great part of his life devoted to philosophy and his friends. In the year 1804 he was called to the newly-formed Academy of Sciences in Munich. In 1807 he was chosen president of this institution, a post which he filled till his death in 1819. Jacobi had a rich intellect and an amiable character. Besides being a philosopher, he was also a poet and citizen of the world ; and hence we find in his philosophizing an absence of strict logical arrangement and precise expression of thought. His writings are no systematic whole, but are occasional treatises written " rhapsodically and in grasshopper gait," for the most part in the form of letters, dialogues, and romances. " It was never my purpose," he says himself, " to set up a system for the schools. My writings have sprung from my innermost life, and were the result of that which had taken place within me. In a certain sense I did not make them voluntarily, but the;y were drawn out of me by a higher power irresistible to myself This want of an inner principle of classification and of a syste 272 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. matic arrangement, renders a development of J acobi's philosophy not easy. It may best be represented under the following three points of view : — 1. Jacobi's polemic against mediate knowledge. 2. His principle of immediate knowledge. 3. His relation to the cotemporaneous philosophy, especially to the Kantian criticism. 1. Spinoza was the negative starting point of Jacobi's phi- losophizing. In his work " On the Doctrine of Spinoza, in letters to Moses Mendelssohn'''' (1785), he directed public attention again to the almost wholly forgotten philosophy of Spinoza. The correspondence originated thus : Jacobi made the discovery that Lessing was a Spinozist, and announces this to Mendelssohn. The latter will not believe it, and thence grew the farther his- torical and philosophical examination. The positive philosophic views which Jacobi exhibits in this treatise can be reduced to the following three principles : (1) Spinozism is fatalism and atheism. (2) Every path of philosophic demonstration leads to fatalism and atheism. (3) In order that we may not fall into these, we must set a limit to demonstrating, and recognize faith as the element of all metaphysic knowledge. (1.) Spinozism is atheism, because, according to it, the cause of the world is no person — is no being working for an end, and endowed with reason and will — and hence is no God. It is fatal- ism, for, according to it, the human will regards itself only falsely as free. (2.) This atheism and fatalism is, however, only the necessary consequence of all strictly demonstrative philosophizing. To conceive a thing, says Jacobi, is to refer a thing to its nearest cause ; it is to find a possible for an actual, the condition for a conditioned, the mediation for an immediate. We conceive only that which we can explain out of another. Hence our conceiving moves in a chain of conditioned conditions, and this connection forms a mechanism of nature, in whose investigation our under- standing has its immeasurable field. However far we may carry conception and demonstration, we must hold, in reference to every object, to a still higher one which conditions it ; where this chain of the conditioned ceases, there do conception and demonstration JACOBI. 273 also cease ; till we give up demonstrating we can reach no infinite. If philosophy determines to apprehend the infinite with the finite understanding, then must it bring down the divine to the finite ; and here is where every preceding philosophy has been entangled, while it is obviously an absurd undertaking to attempt to discover the conditions of the unconditioned, and make the absolutely necessary a possible, in order that we may be able to construct it, A Grod who could be proved is no God, for the ground of proof is ever above that which is to be proved ; the latter has its whole reality from the former. If the existence of God should be proved, then God would be derived from a ground which were before and above him. Hence the paradox of Jacobi ; it is foi the interest of science that there be no God, no supernatural and no extra or supramundane being. Only upon the condition that nature alone is, and is therefore independent and all in all, can science hope to gain its goal of perfection, and become, like its object itself, all in all. Hence the result which Jacobi derives from the " Drama of the history of philosophy " is this : — " There is no other philosophy than that of Spinoza. He who considers all the works and acts of men to be the effect of natural mechan- ism, and who believes that intelligence is but an accompanying consciousness, which has only to act the part of a looker-on, cannot be contended with and cannot be helped till we set him free from his philosophy. No philosophical conclusion can reach him, for what he denies cannot be philosophically proved, and what he proves cannot be philosophically denied." Whence then is help to come ? " The understanding, taken by itself, is ma- terialistic and irrational ; it denies spirit and God. The reason taken by itself is idealistic, and has nothing to do with the under- standing; it denies nature and makes itself God." (3.) Hence we must seek another way of knowing the supersen- sible, which is faith. Jacobi calls this flight from cognition through conception to faith, the salto mortale of the human reason. Every certainty through a conception demands another certainty, but in faith we are led to an immediate certainty which needs no ground nor proof, and which is in fact absolutely exclusive of all proof. 12* 274 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Such a confidence which does not arise from arguments, is called faith. We know the sensible as well as the supersensible only through faith. All human knowledge springs from revelation and faith. These principles which Jacobi brought out in his letters con- cerning Spinoza, did not fail to arouse a universal opposition in the German philosophical world. It was charged upon him that he was an enemy of reason, a preacher of blind faith, a despiser of science and of philosophy, a fanatic and a papist. To rebut these attacks, and to justify his standpoint, he wrote in 1787, a year and a half after the first appearance of the work already named, his dialogue entitled " David Hume^ or Faith, Idealism, and Realism,'''' in which he developes more extensively and defi- nitely his principle of faith or immediate knowledge. 2. J acobi distinguished his faith at the outset from a blind credence in authority. A blind faith is that which supports it- self on a foreign view, instead of on the grounds of reason. But this is not the case with his faith, which rather rests upon the innermost necessity of the subject itself. Still farther : his faith is not an arbitrary imagination : we can imagine to our- selves every thing possible, but in order to regard a thing as actual, there must be an inexplicable necessity of our feeling, which we cannot otherwise name than faith. J acobi was not con- stant in his terminology, and hence did not always express him- self alike in respect of the relation in which faith stood to the dilferent sides of the human faculty of knowledge. In his earlier terminology he placed faith (or as he also called it, the power of faith), on the side of the sense or the receptivity, and let it stand opposed to the understanding and the reason, taking these two terms as equivalent expressions for the finite and immediate know- ledge of previous philosophy ; afterwards he followed Kant, and, distinguishing between the reason and the understanding, he called that reason which he had previously named sense and faith. According to him now, the faith or intuition of the reason is the organ for perceiving the supersensible. As such, it stands op- posed to the understanding. There must be a higher faculty JACOBI. 275 which can learn, in a way inconceivable to sense and the under- standing, that which is true in and above the phenomena. Over against the explaining understanding stands the reason, or the natural faith of the reason, which does not explain, but positively reveals and unconditionally decides. As there is an intuition of the sense, so is there a rational intuition through the reason, and a demonstration has no more validity in respect of the latter thaD in respect of the former. Jacobi justifies his use of the term, in- tuition of the reason, from the want of any other suitable designa- tion. Language has no other expression to indicate the way in which that, which is unattainable to the sense, becomes appre- hended in the transcendental feeling. If any one affirms that he knows any thing, he may properly be required to state the origin of his knowledge, and in doing this, he must of necessity go back either to sensation or to feeling; the latter stands above the former as high as the human species above the brute. So 1 affirm, then, without hesitation, says Jacobi, that my philosophy/ starts from pure feeling, and declares the authority of this to be supreme. The faculty of feeling is the highest in man, and that alone which specifically distinguishes him from the brute. This faculty is one and the same with reason ; or, reason may be said to find in it its single and only starting point. Jacobi had the clearest consciousness of the opposition in which he stood, with this principle of immediate knowledge, to previous philosophy. In his introduction to his complete works, he says : " There had arisen since the time of Aristotle an in- creasing effort in philosophical schools, to subject the immediate knowledge to the mediate, to make that faculty of perception which originally establishes every thing, dependent on the faculty of re-- flection, which is conditioned through abstraction ; to subordinate the archetype to the copy, the essence to the word, the reason to the understanding, and, in fact, to make the former wholly disap- pear in the latter. Nothing is allowed to be true which is not capable of a .double demonstration, in the intuition and in the conception, in the thing and in its image or word ; the thing it- self, it is said, must truly lie and actually be known only in the 276 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. word." But every philosophy which allows only the reflecting reason, must lose itself at length in an utter ignorance. Its end is nihilism. 3. From what has been already said, the position of Jacobi with his principle of faith, in relation to the Kantian philosophy, can, partly at least, be seen. Jacobi had separated himself from this philosophy, partly in the above-named dialogue " David Hume," (especially in an appendix to this, in which he discussed the transcendental Idealism), and partly in his essay " On the attempt of criticism to hring the reason to the understanding " (1801). His relation to it may be reduced to the following three general points : (1.) Jacobi does not agree with Kant's theory of sensuous knowledge. In opposition to this theory he defends the stand- point of empiricism, affirms the truthfulness of the sense-percep- tion, and denies the apriority of space and time, for which Kant con- tends in order to prove that objects as well as their relations are simply determinations of our own self, and do not at all exist ex- ternally to us. For, however much it may be affirmed that there is something corresponding to our notions as their cause, yet does it remain concealed what this something is. According to Kant, the laws of our beholding and thinking are without objective validity, our knowledge has no objective significance. But it is wrong to claim that in the phenomena there is nothing revealed of the hidden truth which lies behind them. With such a claim, it were far better to give up completely the unknown thing-in- itself, and carry out to its results the consequent idealism. " Logi- cally, Kant is at fault, when he presupposes objects which make impressions on our soul. He is bound to teach the strictest idealism. (2.) Yet Jacobi essentially agrees with Kant's critick of the un- derstanding. Jacobi affirmed, as Kant had done, that the under- standing is insufficient to know the supersensible, and that the highest ideas of the reason could be apprehended only in faith. Jacobi places Kant's great merit in having cleared away the ideas, which were simply the products of reflection and logical phan- JACOBI. 277 tasms. " It is very easy for the understanding, when producing one notion from another, and thus gradually mounting up to ideas, to imagine that, hy virtue of these, which, though they carry it beyond the intuitions of the sense, are nothing but logi- cal phantasms, it has not only the faculty but the most decided determination to fly truly above the world of sense, and to gain by its flight a higher science independent of the intuition, a sci- ence of the supersensible. Kant discovers and destroys this er- ror and self-deception. Thus there is gained, at least, a clear place for a genuine rationalism. This is Kant's truly great deed, his immortal merit. But the sound sense of our sage did not al- low him to hide from himself that this clear place must disappear in a gulf, which would swallow up in itself all knowledge of the true, unless a God should interpose to hinder it. Here Kant's doctrine and mine meet." (8.) But Jacobi does not fully agree with Kant, in wholly denying to the theoretical reason the faculty of objective knowl- edge. He blames Kant for complaining that the human reason cannot theoretically prove the reality of its ideas. He affirm? that Kant is thus still entangled in the delusion, that the onl} reason why these ideas cannot be proved, is found in the nature of the ideas themselves, and not in the deficient nature of our knowledge. Kant therefore attempts to seek, in a practical way, a kind of scientific proof; a roundabout way, which, to every profound seeker, must seem folly, since every proof is as impossi- ble as it is unnecessary. Jacobi agreed better with Kant, than with the post-Kantian philosophy. The atheistic tendency of the latter was especially repulsive to him. " To Kant, that profound thinker and upright philosopher, the words God, freedom, immortality, and religion, signified the same as they have ever done to the sound human understanding ; he in no way treats them as nothing but decep- tion. He created offence by irresistibly showing the insufficiency of all proofs of speculative philosophy for these ideas. That which was wanting in the theoretical proof, he made up by the necessary postulates of a pure practical reason. With these, ac- 278 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. cording to Kant's assurance, philosopliy was fully helped out of her difficulty, and the goal, which had been always missed, actu- ally reached. But the first daughter of the critical philosophy (Fichte's system) makes the living and working moral order it- self to be God, a God expressly declared to be without conscious- ness and self-existence. These frank words, spoken publicly and without restraint, roused some attention, but the fear soon sub- sided. Presently astonishment ceased wholly, for the second daughter of the critical philosophy (Schelling's system) gave up entirely the distinction which the first had allowed to remain be- tween natural and moral philosophy, necessity and freedom, and without any further ado affirmed that the only existence is na- ture, and that there is nothing above ; this second daughter is Spinozism transfigured and reversed, an ideal materialism." This latter allusion to Schelling, connected as it was with other and harder thrusts in the same essay, called out from this philosopher the well-known answer : " Schelling''s Monument to the Treatise on Divine Things^ 1812." If we now take a critical survey of the philosophical stand- point of Jacobi, we shall find its peculiarity to consist in the ab- stract separation of understanding and feeling. These two Ja- cobi could not bring into harmony. " There is light in my heart," he says, " but it goes out whenever I attempt to bring it into the understanding. Which is the true luminary of these two ? That of the understanding, which, though it reveals fixed forms, shows behind them only a baseless gulf ? Or that of the heart, which points its light promisingly upwards, though deter- minate knowledge escapes it ? Can the human spirit grasp the truth unless it possesses these two luminaries united in one light ? And is this union conceivable except through a miracle V " If now, in order to escape in a certain degree this contradiction be- tween understanding and feeling, Jacobi gave to immediate knowledge the place of mediate as finite knowledge, this was a self-deception. Even that knowledge, which is supposed to be immediate, and which Jacobi regards as the peculiar organ for knowing the supersensible, is also mediate, obliged to go through FICHTE. 279 a course of subjective mediations, and can only give itself out as immediate when it wholly forgets its own origin. SECTION XLI. FICHTE JoHANN Gottlieb Fichte was born at Eammenau, in Upper Lusatia, 1762. A nobleman of Silesia became interested in the boy, and having committed him first to the instruction of a clergyman, he afterwards placed him at the high school at Schulp- forte. In his eighteenth year, at Michaelmas, 1780, Fichte entered the university at Jena to study theology. He soon found himself attracted to philosophy, and became powerfully afi"ected by the study of Spinoza. His pecuniary circumstances were straitened, but this only served to harden his will and his energy. In 1784 he became employed as a teacher in a certain family, and spent some time in this occupation with different families in Saxony. In 1787 he sought a place as country clergyman, but was refused on account of his religious opinions. He was now obliged to leave his fatherland, to which he clung with his whole soul. He repaired to Zurich, where, in 1788, he took a post as private tutor, and where also he became acquainted with his future wife, a sister's daughter of Klopstock. At Easter, 1790, he returned to Saxony and taught privately at Leipsic, where he became acquainted with the Kantian philosophy, by means of lessons which he was obliged to give to a student. In the spring of 1791 we find him as private tutor at Warsaw, and soon after in Konigsberg, where he resorted, that he might become personally acquainted with the Kant he had learned to revere. Instead of a letter of recommendation he presented him his " Gritich of all Bevelation,^'' a treatise which Fichte composed in eight days. In this he attempted to deduce, from the practical reason, the possibility of a revelation. This is not seen purely apriori, but 280 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. only under an empirical condition ; we must consider humanity to be in a moral ruin so complete, that the moral law has lost all its influence upon the will and all morality is extinguished. In such a case we may expect that God, as moral governor of the world, would give man, through the sense, some pure moral im- pulses, and reveal himself as lawgiver to them through a special manifestation determined for this end, in the world of sense. In such a case a particular revelation were a postulate of the practi- cal reason. Fichte sought also to determine apriori the possible content of such a revelation. Since we need to know nothing but God, freedom, and immortality, the revelation will contain naught but these, and these it must contain in a comprehensible form, yet so that the symbolical dress may lay no claim to un- limitsd veneration. This treatise, which appeared anonymously in 1792, at once attracted the greatest attention, and was at first universally regarded as a work of Kant. It procured for its author, soon after, a call to the chair of philosophy at Jena, to succeed Reinhold, who then went to Kiel. Fichte received this appointment in 1793 at Zurich, where he had gone to consummate his marriage. At the same time he wrote and published, also anonymously, his " Aids to correct views of the French Revolu- tion an essay which the governments never looked upon with favor. At Easter, 1794, he entered upon his new office, and soon saw his public call confirmed. Taking now a new standpoint, which transcended Kant, he sought to establish this, and carry it out in a series of writings (the Wissenschaftslehre appeared in 1794, the Naturrecht in 1796, and the Sittenlehre in 1798), by which he exerted a powerful influence upon the scientific move- ment in Germany, aided as he was in this by the fact that Jena was then one of the most flourishing of the German universi- ties, and the resort of every vigorous head. With Goethe, Schiller, the brothers Schlegel, William von Humboldt, and Hufeland, Fichte was in close fellowship, though this was unfortu- nately broken after a few years. In 1795 he became associate editor of the ^^Philosophical Journal^'' which had been established by Niethammer. A fellow-laborer, Rector Forberg, at Saalfeld, FICHTE. 281 offered for publication in this journal an article " to determine the conception of religion." Fichte advised the author not to publish it, but at length inserted it in the journal, prefacing it, however, with an introduction of his own " On the ground of our faith in a divine government of the world,^^ in which he en- deavored to remove, or at least soften, the views in the article which might give offence. Both the essays raised a great cry of atheism. The elector of Saxony confiscated the journal in his territory, and sent a requisition to the dukes Ernest, who held in common the university of Jena, to summon the author to trial and punishment. Fichte answered the edict of confiscation and attempted to justify himself to the public (1799), by his " Appeal to the Public. An essay which it is reqicested may be read before it is confiscated while he defended his course to the government by an article entitled " The Publishers of the Phi- losophical Journal justified from the charge of Atheism^ The government of Weimar, being as anxious to spare him as it was to please the elector of Saxony, delayed its decision. But as Fichte, either with or without reason, had privately learned that the whole matter was to be settled by reprimanding the accused parties for their want of caution ; and, desiring either a civil acquittal or an open and proper satisfaction, he wrote a private letter to a member of the government, in which he desired his dismission in case of a reprimand, and which he closed with the intimation that many of his friends would leave the university with him, in order to establish together a new one in G-ermany. The government regarded this letter as an application for his dis- charge, indirectly declaring that the reprimand was unavoidable. Fichte, now an object of suspicion, both on account of his religious and political views, looked about him in vain for a place of refuge. The prince of Rudolstadt, to whom he turned, denied him his protection, and his arrival in Berlin (1799) attracted great notice. In Berlin, where he had much intercourse with Frederick Schlegel, and also with Schleiermacher and Novalis, his views became gradually modified ; the catastrophe at Jena had led him from the exclusive moral standpoint which he, resting upon Kant, had 282 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. hitherto held, to the sphere of religion ; he now sought to recon cile religion with his standpoint of the Wissenshaftshhre, and turned himself to a certain mysticism (the second form of the Fichtian theory). After he had privately taught a number of years in Berlin, and had also held philosophical lectures for men of culture, he was recommended (1806) by Beyme and Altenstein, chancellor of state of Hardenberg, to a professorship of philo- sophy in Erlangen, an appointment which he received together with a permit to return to Berlin in the winter, and hold there his philosophical lectures before the public. Thus, in the winter of 1807-8, while a French marshal was governor of Berlin, and while his voice was often drowned by the hostile tumults of the enemy through the streets, he delivered his famous Addresses to the German nation.'''' Fichte labored most assiduously for the foundation of the Berlin university, for only by wholly trans- forming the common education did he believe the regeneration of Germany could be secured. As the new university was opened 1809, he was made in the first year dean of the philosophical faculty, and in the second was invested with the dignity of rector. In the " war of liberation," then breaking out, Fichte took the liveliest participation byword and deed. His wife had contracted a nervous fever by her care of the sick and wounded, and though she recovered, he fell a victim to the same disease. He died Jan. 28, 1814, not having yet completed his fifty-second year. In the following exposition of Fichte's philosophy, we distin- guish between the two internally different periods of his philosophi- zing, that of J ena and that of Berlin. The first division will include two parts — Fichte's theory of science and his practical philosophy. I. The Fichtian Philosophy in its Original Form. 1. The Theoretical Philosophy of Fichte, his Wissenschafts- LEHRE, OR Theory of Science. — It has already been shown (^ 39) that the thoroughly-going subjective idealism of Fichte was only the logical consequence of the Kantian standpoint. It was wholly unavoidable that Fichte should entirely reject the Kantian essen- tially thing {thing in itself)^ which Kant had himself declared to be unrecognizable though real, and that he should posit as a FICHTE. 283 proper act. of the mind, that external influence which Kant had referred to the essentially thing. That the Ego alone is, and that which we regard as a limitation of the Ego by external objects, is rather the proper self-limitation of the Ego ; this is the grand feature of the Fichtian as of every idealism. Fichte himself supported the standpoint of this Theory of Science as follows : In every experience there is conjointly an Ego and a thing, the intelligence and its object. Which of these two sides must now be reduced to the other ? If the philosophei abstracts the Ego, he has remaining an essentially thing, and must then apprehend his representations or sensations as the products of this object ; if he abstracts the object, he has remaining an es- sentially Ego (an Ego in itself). The former is dogmatism, the latter idealism. Both are irreconcilable with each other, and there is no third way possible. We must therefore choose be- tween the two. In order to decide between the two systems, we must note the following: (1) That the Ego appears in conscious- ness, wherefore the essentially thing is a pure invention, since in consciousness we have only that which is perceived ; (2.) Dog- matism must account for the origin of its representation through some essentially object, it must start from something which does not lie in the consciousness. But the effect of being is only being, and not representation. Hence idealism alone can be correct which does not start from being, but from intelligence. Accord- ing to idealism, intelligence is only active, not passive, because it is a first and absolute : and on this account there belongs to it no being, but simply an acting. The forms of this acting, the system of the necessary mode in which intelligence acts, must be found from the essence of intelligence. If we should take the laws of intelligence from experience, as Kant did his categories, we fail in two respects: (1) We do not see why intelligence must so act, nor whether these laws are immanent laws of intelligence ; (2) We do not see how the object itself originates. Hence the fundamental principles of intelligence, as well as the objective world, must be derived from the Ego itself. Fichte supposed that in these results he only expressed the 284 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. true sense of the Kantian philosopliy. " Whatever my system may properly be, whether the genuine criticism thoroughly car ried out, as I believe it is, or howsoever it be named, is of no ac- count." His system, Fichte affirms, had the same view of the matter as Kant's, while the numerous followers of this philosopher had wholly mistaken and misunderstood their master's idealism. In the second introduction to the Theory of Science (1797), Fichte grants to these expounders of the Critick of pure Eeason that it contains some passages where Kant would affirm that sen- sations must be given to the subject from without as the material conditions of objective reality ; but shows that the innumerably repeated declarations of the Critick, that there could be no influ- ence upon us of a real transcendental object outside of us, cannot at all be reconciled with these passages, if any thing other than a simple thought be understood as the ground of the sensations. " So long," adds Fichte, " as Kant does not expressly declare that he derives sensations from an impression of some essentially thing, or, to use his terminology, that sensation must be explained from a transcendental object existing externally to us : so long will I not believe what these expounders tell us of Kant. But if he should give such an explanation, I should sooner regard the Crit- ick of Pure Keason to be a work of chance than of design." For such an explanation the aged Kant did not suffer him long to wait. In the IntelligenzhlaU der Allgemeinen Litter atur 2 eitung (1799), he formally, and with much emphasis, rejects the Fichtian improvement of his system, and protests against every interpreta- tion of his writings according to the conceit of any mind, while he maintains the literal interpretation of his theory as laid down in the Critick of Reason. Reinhold remarks upon all this : " Since the well known and public explanation of Kant respecting Fichte's philosophy, there can be no longer a doubt that Kant himself would represent his own system, and desire to have it represented by his readers, entirely otherwise than Fichte had represented and interpreted it. But from this it irresistibly follows, that Kant himself did not regard his system as illogical because it presup- posed something external to the subjectivity. Nevertheless, it FICHTE. 285 does not at all follow that Fichte erred when he declared that this system, with such a presupposition, must be illogical." So much for Reinhold. That Kant himself did not fail to see this incon- clusiveness, is evident from the changes he introduced into the second edition of the Critick of Pure Reason, where he suffered the idealistic side of his system to fall back decidedly behind the empirical. From what has been said, we can see the universal standpoint of the Theory of Science; the Ego is made a principle, and from the Ego every thing else is sought to be derived. It hardly needs to be remarked, that by this Ego we are to understand, not any individual, but the universal Ego, the universal rationality. The Ego and the individual, the pure and the empirical Ego, are wholly different conceptions. We have still the following preface to make concerning the form of the Theory of Science. A theory of science, according to Fichte, must posit some supreme principle, from which every other must be derived. This supreme principle must be absolute- ly, and through itself, certain. If our human knowledge should be any thing but fragmentary, there must be such a supreme principle. But now, since such a principle does not admit of proof, every thing depends upon giving it a trial. Its test and demonstration can only be thus gained, viz., if we find a principle to which all science may be referred, then is this shown to be a fundamental principle. But besides the first fundamental princi- ple, there are yet two others to be considered, the one of which is unconditioned as to its content, but as to its form, conditioned through and derived from the first fundamental principle ; the other the reverse. The relation of these three principles to each other is, in fine, this, viz., that the second stands opposed to the first, while a third is the product of the two. Hence, according to this plan, the first absolute principle starts from the Ego, the second opposes to the Ego a thing or a non-Ego, and the third brings forward the Ego again in reaction against the thing or the non-Ego. This method of Fichte (thesis, — antithesis, — synthesis) is the same as Hegel subsequently adopted, and applied to the 286 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. whole system of philosophy, a union of the synthetical and ana- lytical methods. We start with a fundamental synthesis, which we analyze to produce its antitheses, in order to unite these anti- theses again through a second synthesis. But in making this second synthesis, our analysis discovers still farther antitheses, which obliges us therefore to find another synthesis, and so on- ward in the process, till we come at length to antitheses which can no longer he perfectly but only approximately connected. We stand now upon the threshold of the Theory of Science. It is divided into three parts. (1) General principles of a theory of science. (2) Principles of theoretical knowledge. (3) Prin- ciples of practical science. As has already been said, there are three supreme fundamen- tal principles, one absolutely unconditioned, and two relatively unconditioned. (1.) The absolutely first and absolutely unconditioned funda- mental principle ought to express that act of the mind which lies at the basis of all consciousness, and alone makes consciousness possible. Such is the principle of identity, A=A. This princi- ple remains, and cannot be thought away, though every empirical determination be removed. It is a fact of consciousness, and must, therefore, be universally admitted : but at the same time it is by no means conditioned, like every other empirical fact, but unconditioned, because it is a free act. By affirming that this principle is certain without any farther ground, we ascribe to our- selves the faculty of positing something absolutely. We do not, therefore, affirm that A is, but only that if A is, then it is equal to A. It is no matter now about the content of the principle, we need only regard its form. The principle A=A is, therefore, conditioned (hypothetically) as to its content, and unconditioned only as to its form and its connection. If we would now have a principle unconditioned in its content as well as in its connection, we put Ego in the place of A, as we are fully entitled to do, since the connection of subject and predicate contained in the judgment A=A is posited in the Ego and through the Ego. Hence A=A becomes transformed into Ego=Ego. This principle is uncondi- FICHTE. 287 tioned not only as to its connection, but also as to its content. While we could not, instead of A=A, say that A is, yet we can instead of Ego=Ego, say that Ego is. All the facts of the em- pirical consciousness find their ground of explanation in this, viz., that before any thing else is posited in the Ego, the Ego itself is there. This fact, that the Ego is absolutely posited and grounded on itself, is the basis of all acting in the human mind, and shows the pure character of activity in itself. The Ego is, because it posits itself, and it only is, because this simple positing of itself is wholly by itself. The being of the Ego is thus seen in the posi- ting of the Ego, and on the other hand, the Ego is enabled to posit simply by virtue of its being. It is at the same time the acting, and the product of the action. I am, is the expression of the only possible deed. Logically considered we have, in the first principle of a Theory of Science, A=A, the logical law of identity. From the proposition A==A, we arrive at the proposi- tion Ego=Ego. The latter proposition, however, does not derive its validity from the former, but contrarywise. The prius of all judgments is the Ego, which posits the connection of subject and predicate. The logical law of identity arises, therefore, from Ego = Ego. Metaphysically considered, we have in this same first principle of a Theory of Science, the category of reality. We obtain this category by abstracting every thing from the content, and reflecting simply upon the mode of acting of the human mind. From the Ego, as the absolute subject, every category is derived (2.) The second fundamental principle y conditioned in its con- tent, and only unconditioned in its form, which is just as incapable as the first of demonstration or derivation, is also a fact of the empirical consciousness : it is the proposition non-A is not=A. This sentence is unconditioned in its form, because it is free act like the first, from which it cannot be derived ; but in its content, as to its matter it is conditioned, because if a non-A is posited, there must have previously been posited an A. Let us examine this principle more closely. In the first principle, A=A, the form of the act was a positing, while in this second principle it is an oppositing. There is an absolute opposition, and this opposi- 288 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. tioD, in its simple form, is an act absolutely possible, standing un- der no condition, limited by no higher ground. But as to its matter, the opposition presupposes a position; the non-A cannot be posited without the A. What non-A is, I do not through that yet know : I only know concerning non-A that it is the opposite of A : hence I only know what non-A is under the condition that I know A. But now A is posited through the Ego ; there is originally nothing posited but the Ego, and nothing but this abso- lutely posited. Hence there can be an absolute opposition only to the Ego. That which is opposed to the Ego is the non-Ego. A non-Ego is absolutely opposed to the Ego, and this is the second fact of the empirical consciousness. In every thing ascribed to the Ego, the contrary, by virtue of this simple opposition, must be ascribed to the non Ego. — As we obtained from the first prin- ciple Ego==Ego, the logical law of identity, so now we have, from the second sentence Ego is not = non-Ego, the logical law of con- tradiction. And metaphysically, — since we wholly abstract the definite act of judgment, and, simply in the form of sequence, con- clude not-being from opposite being, — -we possess from this second principle the category of negation. (3.) The third principle^ conditioned in its form, is almost capable of proof, since it is determined by two others. At every step we approach the province where every thing can be proved. This third principle is conditioned in its form, and unconditioned only in its content : i. e. the problem, but not the solution of the act to be established through it, has been given through the two preceding principles. The solution is afi'orded unconditionally and absolutely by a decisive word of the reason. The problem to be solved by this third principle is this, viz., to adjust the con- tradiction contained in the two former ones. On the one side, the Ego is wholly suppressed by the non-Ego : there can be no positing of the Ego so far as the non-Ego is posited. On the other side, the non-Ego is only an Ego posited in the conscious- ness, and hence the Ego is not suppressed by the non- Ego. The Ego appearing on the one side to be suppressed, is not really sup- pressed. Such a result would be non-A=A. In order to remove FICHTE. 289 this contradiction, wbicli threatens to destroy the identity of our consciousness, and the only absolute foundation of our knowledge, we must find in x that which will justify both of the first two principles, and leave the identity of our consciousness undisturbed. The two opposites, the Ego and the non-Ego, should be united in the consciousness, should be alike posited without either excluding the other ; they should be received in the identity of the proper consciousness. How shall being and not-being, reality and nega- tion, be conceived together without destroying each other ? They will reciprocally limit each other. Hence the unknown quantity whose terms we are seeking, stands for these limits : limitation is the sought-for act of the Ego, and as category in the thought, we have thus the category of determination or limitation. But in limitation, there is also given the category of quantity^ for when we say that any thing is limited, wc mean that its reality is through negation, not wholly^ but only j[>artially suppressed. Thus the conception of limit contains also the conception of divisi- bility, besides the conceptions of reality and negation. Through the act of limitation, the Ego as well as the non-Ego, is posited as divisible. Still farther, we see how a logical law follows from the third fundamental principle as well as from the first two. If we abstract the definite content, the Ego and the non-Ego, and leave remaining the simple form of the union of opposites through the conception of divisibility, we have then the logical principle of the ground^ or foundation, which may be expressed in the formula : A in part = non-A, non-A in part = A. Wherever two oppo- sites are alike in one characteristic, we consider the ground as a ground of relation, and wherever two similar things are opposite in one characteristic, we consider the ground as a ground of dis- tinction. — With these three principles we have now exhausted the measure of that which is unconditioned and absolutely certain. We can embrace the three in the following formula : / posit in the Ego a divisible non Ego over against the divisible Ego. No philosophy can go beyond this cognition, and every fundamental philosophy should go back to this. Just so far as it does this, it becomes science (Wissenschaftslehre). 13 290 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Every thing which can appear in a system of knowledge, as well as a farther division of the Theory of Science itself, must be de- rived from this. The proposition that the Ego and the non-Ego reciprocally limit each other, may be divided into the following two : (1) the Ego posits itself as limited through the non-Ego {i. e. the Ego is in a cognitive (or passive) relation ) ; (2) the Ego posits the non-Ego as limited through the Ego {i. e. the Ego is in an active relation). The former proposition is the basis of the theoretical, and the latter of the practical part of the Theory of Science. The latter part cannot, at the outset, be brought upon the stage; for the non-Ego, which should be limited by the acting Ego, does not at the outset exist, and we must wait and see whether it will find, in the theoretical part, a reality. The groundwork of theoretical knowledge advances through an uninterrupted series of antitheses and syntheses. The funda- mental synthesis of the theoretical Theory of Science is the pro- position : the Ego posits itself as determined (limited) hy the non-Ego. If we analyze this sentence, we find in it two subordi- nate sentences which are reciprocally opposite. (1) The non- Ego as active determines the Ego, which thus far is passive ; but since all activity must start from the Ego, so (2) the Ego deter- mines itself through an absolute activity. Herein is a contradic- tion, that the Ego should be at the same time active and passive. Since this contradiction would destroy the above proposition, and also suppress the unity of consciousness, we are forced to seek some point, some new synthesis, in which these given antitheses may be united. This synthesis is attained when we find that the conceptions of action and passion, which are contained under the categories of reality and negation, find their compensation and due adjustment in the conception of divisibility. The propo- sitions : " the Ego determines," and " the Ego is determined," are reconciled in the proposition : " the Ego determines itself in part, and is determined in part." Both, however, should be con- sidered as one and the same. Hence more accurately : as many parts of reality as the Ego posits in itself, so many parts of nega- tion does it posit in the non-Ego ; and as many parts of reality FICHTE. 291 as tlie Ego posits in tlie non-Ego, so many parts of negation does it posit in itself. This determination is reciprocal determination, or reciprocal action. Thus Fichte deduces the last of the three categories under Kant's general category of relation. In a simi- lar way (viz., by finding a synthesis for apparent contradictions), he deduces the two other categories of this class, viz., that of cause, and that of substance. The process is thus : So far as the Ego is determined, and therefore passive, has the non-Ego reali- ty. The category of reciprocal determination, to which we may ascribe indifferently either of the two sides, reality or negation, may, more strictly taken, imply that the Ego is passive, and the non-Ego active. The notion which expresses this relation is that of causality. That, to which activity is ascribed, is called cause (primal reality), and that to which passiveness is ascribed, is called effect; both, conceived in connection, may be termed a working. On the other side, the Ego determines itself. Here- in is a contradiction ; ( 1 ) the Ego determines itself ; it is there- fore that which determines, and is thus active ; (2) it determines itself; it is therefore that which becomes determined, and is thus passive. Thus in one respect and in one action both reality and negation are ascribed to it. To resolve this contradiction, we must find a mode of action which is activity and passiveness in one ; the Ego must determine its passiveness through activity, and its activity through passiveness. This solution is attained by aid of the conception of quantity. In the E'go all reality is first of all posited as absolute quantum, as absolute totality, and thus far the Ego may be compared to a greatest circle which contains all the rest. A definite quantum of activity, or a limited sphere within this greatest circle of activity, is indeed a reality ; but when compared with the totality of activity, is it also a negation of the totality or passiveness. Here we have found the media- tion sought for ; it lies in the notion of substance. In so far as the Ego is considered as the whole circle, embracing the totality of all realities, is it substance ; but so far as it becomes posited in a determinate sphere of this circle, is it accidental. No acci- dence is conceivable without substance ; for, in order to know 292 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. that any thing is a definite reality, it must first be referred to reality in general, or to substance. In every change we think of substance in the universal ; accidence is something specific (de- terminate), which changes with every changing cause. There is originally hid one substance, the Ego ; in this one substance all possible accidents, and therefore all possible realities, are posited. The Ego alone is the absolutely infinite. The Ego, as thinking and as acting, indicates a limitation. The Fichtian theory is ac- cordingly Spinozism, only (as Jacobi strikingly called it) a re- versed and idealistic Spinozism. Let us look back a moment. The objectivity which Kant had allowed to exist Fichte has destroyed. There is only the Ego. But the Ego presupposes a non-Ego, and therefore a kind of object. How the Ego comes to posit such an object, must the theoretical Theory of Science now proceed to show. There are two extreme views respecting the relation of the Ego to the non-Ego, according as we start from the conception of cause, or that of substance. (1) Starting from the concep- tion of cause, we have posited through the passiveness of the Ego an activity of the non-Ego. This passiveness of the Ego must have some ground. This cannot lie in the Ego, which in itself posits only activity. Consequently it lies in the non-Ego. Here the distinction between action and passion is apprehended, not simply as quantitative (i. e., viewing the passiveness as a di- minished activity), but the passion is in quality opposed to the action ; a presupposed activity of the non-Ego is, therefore, a real ground of the passiveness in the Ego. (2) Starting from the conception of substance, we have posited a passiveness of the Ego through its own activity. Here the passiveness in respect of quality is the same as activity, it being only a diminished ac- tivity. While, therefore, according to the first view, the passive Ego has a ground distinct in quality from the Ego, and thus a real ground, yet here its ground is only a diminished activity of the Ego, distinct only in quantity from the Ego, and is thus an ideal ground. The former view is dogmatic realism, the latter is dogmatic idealism. The latter aflirms : all reality of the non- FICHTE. 203 Ego is only a reality given it from tlie Ego ; the former declares : nothing can be given, unless there be something to receive, unless an independent reality of the non-Ego, as thing in itself, be pre- supposed. Both views present thus a contradiction, which can only be removed by a new synthesis. Fichte attempted this syn- thesis of idealism and realism, by bringing out a mediating sys- tem of critical idealism. For this purpose he sought to show that the ideal ground and the real ground are one and the same. Neither is the simple activity of the Ego a ground for the reality of the non-Ego, nor is the simple activity of the non-Ego a ground for the passiveness in the Ego. Both must be conceived together in this way, viz., the activity of the Ego meets a hin- drance^ which is set up against it, not without some assistance of the Ego, and which circumscribes and reflects in itself this activ- ity of the Ego, The hindrance is found when the subjective can be no farther extended, and the expanding activity of the Ego is driven back into itself, producing as its result self-limita- tion. What we call objects are nothing other than the different impinging of the activity of the Ego on some inconceivable hin- drance, and these determinations of the Ego, we carry over to something external to ourselves, and represent them to ourselves as space filling matter. That which Fichte calls a hindrance through the non-Ego, is thus in fact the same as Kant calls thing essentially, the only difference being that with Fichte it is made subjective. From this point Fichte then deduces the subjective activities of the Ego, which mediate, or seek to mediate, theoret- ically, the Ego with the non-Ego — as imagination, representation sensation, intuition, feeling), understanding, faculty of judgment, reason ; and in connection with this he brought out the subjective projections of the intuition, space, and time. We have now reached the third part of the Theory of Sci- ence, viz., the foundation of the practical. We have seen that the Ego represents. But that it may represent does not depend upon the Ego alone, but is determined by something external to it. We could in no way conceive of a representation, except through the presupposition that the Ego finds some hindrance to 294 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. its undetermined and unlimited activity. Accordingly the Ego, as intelligence, is universally dependent upon an indefinite, and hitherto wholly indefinable non-Ego, and only through and by means of such non-Ego, is it intelligence. A finite being is only finite as intelligence. These limits, however, we shall break through. The practical law which unites the finite Ego with the infinite, can depend upon nothing external to ourselves. The Ego, according to all its determinations, should be posited abso- lutely through itself, and hence should be wholly independent of every possible non-Ego. Consequently, the absolute Ego and the intelligent Ego, both of which should constitute but one, are opposed to each other. This contradiction is obviated, when we see that because the absolute Ego is capable of no passiveness, but is absolute activity, therefore the Ego determines, through it- self, that hitherto unknown non-Ego, to which the hindrance has been ascribed. The limits which the Ego, as theoretic, has set over against itself in the non-Ego, it must, as practical, seek to destroy, and absorb again the non-Ego in itself (or conceive it as the self-limitation of the Ego). The Kantian primacy of the practical reason is here made a truth. The transition of the theoretical part into the practical, the necessity of advancing from the one to the other, Fichte represents more closely thus : — The theoretical Theory of Science had to do with the mediation of the Ego, and the non-Ego. For this end it introduced one connecting link after another, without ever attaining its end. Then enters the reason with the absolute and decisive word : " there ought to be no non-Ego, since the non-Ego can in no way be united with the Ego ; " and with this the knot is cut, though not untied. Thus it is the incongruity between the absolute /practical) Ego, and the finite (intelligent) Ego, which is carried over beyond the theoretical province into the practical. True, this incongruity does not wholly disappear, even in the practical province, where the act is only an infinite striving to surpass the limits of the non-Ego. The Ego, so far as it is practical, has, indeed, the tendency to pass beyond the actual world, and estab- lish an ideal world, as it would be were every reality posited by nCHTE. 295 the absolute Ego ; but this striving is always confined to the finite partly through itself, because it goes out towards objects, and objects are finite, and partly through the resistance of the sensible world. We ought to seek to reach the infinite, but we cannot do it ; this striving and inability is the impress of our des- tiny for eternity. Thus — and in these words Fichte brings together the result of the Theory of Science — the whole being of finite rational natures is comprehended and exhausted : an original idea of our abso- lute being ; an effort to reflect upon our^^elves, in order to gain this idea ; a limitation, not of this striving, but of our own exist- ence, which first becomes actual through this limitation, or through an opposite principle, a non-Ego, or our finiteness ; a self- consciousness, and especially a consciousness of our practical strivings ; a determination accordingly of our representations, and through these of our actions ; a constant widening of our limits into the infinite. 2. Fichte's Practical Philosophy. — The principles which Fichte had developed in his Theory of Science he applied to practical life, especially to the theory of rights and morals. He sought to deduce here every thing with methodical rigidness, without admitting any thing which could not be proved from experience. Thus, in the theory of rights and of morals, he will not presuppose a plurality of persons, but first deduces this : even that the man has a body is first demonstrated, though, to be sure, not stringently. The Theory of Bights (the rights of nature) Fichte founds upon the conception of the individual. First, he deduces the conception of rights, and as follows : — A finite rational being can- not posit itself without ascribing to itself a free activity. Through this positing of its faculties to a free activity, this rational being posits an external world of sense, for it can ascribe to itself no activity till it has posited an object towards which this activity may be directed. Still farther, this free activity of a rational be- ing presupposes other rational beings, for without these it would never be conscious that it was free. We have therefore a plu- 296 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. rality of free individuals, each one of whom has a sphere of free activity. This co-existence of free individuals is not possible without a relation of rights. Since no one with freedom passes beyond his sphere, and each one therefore limits himself, they recog- nize each other as rational and free. This relation of a reciprocal acting through intelligence and freedom between rational beings, according to which each one has his freedom limited by the con- ception of the possibility of the other's freedom, under the con- dition also that this other limits his own freedom also through that of the first, is called a relation of rights. The supreme maxim of a theory of rights is therefore this : limit thy freedom through the conception of the freedom of every other person with whom thou canst be connected. After Fichte has attempted the application of this conception of rights, and ior this end has de- duced the corporeity, the anthropological side of man, he passes over to a proper theory of rights. The theory of rights may be divided into three parts. (1) Rights which belong to the simple conception of person are called original rights. The original right is the absolute right of the person to be only a cause in the sensible world, though he may be absolutely (in other relations than to the sense) an effect. In this are contained, (a) the right of personal (bodily) freedom, and (h) the right of property. But every relation of rights between individual persons is conditioned through each one's recognition of the rights of the other. Each one must limit the quantum of his free acts for the sake of the freedom of the other, and only so far as the other has respect to my freedom need I have regard to his. In case, therefore, the other does not respect my original rights, some mechanical neces- sity must be sought in order to secure the rights of person, and this involves (2) the Fdght of Coercion. The laws of punishment have their end in securing that the opposite of that which is in- tended shall follow every unrighteous aim, that every vicious pur- pose shall be destroyed, and the right in its integrity be estab- lished. To establish such a law of coercion, and to secure a uni- versal coercive power, the free individuals must enter into cove- nant among themselves. Such a covenant is only possible on the FICHTE. 297 ground of a common nature. Natural right, i. e. the rightful rela- tion between man and man, presupposes thus (3) a civil right, viz., (a) a free covenant, a compact of citizens by which the free individ- uals guarantee to each other their reciprocal rights ; {h) positive laws, a civil legislation, through which the common will of all be- comes law ; (c) an executive force, a civil power which executes the common will, and in which, therefore, the private will and the common will are synthetically united. The particular view of Fichte's theory of rights is this : on the one side there is the state as reason demands (philosophical theory of rights), and on the other side the state as it actually is (theory of positive rights and of the state). But now comes up the problem, to make the actual state ever more and more conformable to the state of reason. The science which has this approximation for its aim, is polity. We can demand of no actual state a perfect conformity to the idea of a state. Every state constitution is according to right, if it only leaves possible an advancement to a better state, and the only constitution wholly contrary to right is that whose end is to hold every thing just as it is. The absolute Ego of the Theory of Science is separated in the Theory of Rights into an infinite number of persons with rights : to bring it out again in its unity is the problem of Ethics. Right and morals are essentially different. Right is the external neces- sity to omit or to do something in order not to infringe upon the freedom of another ; the inner necessity to do or omit some- thing wholly independent of external ends, constitutes the moral nature of man. And as the theory of rights arose from the conflict of the impulse of freedom in one subject with the impulse of free- dom in another subject, so does the theory of morals or ethics arise from such a conflict, which, in the present case, is not external but internal, between two impulses in one and the same person. (1) The rational being is impelled towards absolute independence, and strives after freedom for the sake of freedom. This fundamental impulse may be called the pure impulse, and it furnishes the formal principle of ethics, the principle of absolute autonomy, of absolute indeterminableness through anything external to the Ego. 13* 298 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. But (2) as the rational being is actually empirical and finite, as it by nature posits over against itself a non-Ego and posits itself as corporeal, so there is found beside the pure impulse another, the impulse of nature, which makes for its end not freedom but enjoy- ment. This impulse of nature furnishes the material, utilitarian (eudoemoniacal) principle of striving after a connected enjoyment. Both impulses, which from a transcendental standpoint are one and the same original impulse of the human being, strive after unity, and furnish a third impulse which is a mingling of the two. The pure impulse gives the form, and the natural impulse the content of an action. It is true that sensuous objects will be chosen, but by virtue of the pure impulse these are modified so as to conform to the absolute Ego. This mingled impulse is now the moral impulse. It mediates the pure and the natural impulse. But since these two lie infinitely apart, the approximation of the natural to the pure impulse is an infinite progression. The intent in an action is directed towards a complete freeing from nature, and it is only the result of our limitation that the act should re- main still conformable to the natural impulse. Since the Ego can never be independent so long as it is Ego, the final aim of the rational being lies in infinity. There must be a course in whose progress the Ego can conceive itself as approximating towards ab- solute independence. This course is determined in infinity in the idea ; there is, therefore, no possible case in which it is not deter- mined what the pure impulse should demand. We might name this course the moral determination (destiny) of the finite rational being. The principle of ethics is, therefore : Alivays fulfil thy destiny ! That which is in every moment conformable to our moral destiny, is at the same time demanded by our natural im- pulse, though it does not follow that every thing which the latter demands agrees therefore with the former. I ought to act only when conscious that something is duty, and I ought to discharge the duty for its own sake. The blind motives of sympathy, love of mankind, &c., have not, as mere impulses of nature, morality. The moral impulse has causality as having none, for it demands be free ! Through the conception of the absolute ought, is the FICHTE. 299 rational being absolutely independent, and is represented thus only when acting from duty. The formal condition of the mo- rality of our actions, is : act always according to the best con- viction of thy duty ; or, act according to thy conscience. The absolute criterion of the correctness of our conviction of duty is a feeling of truth and certainty. This immediate feeling never deceives, for it only exists with the perfect harmony of our em- pirical Ego with that which is pure and original. From this point Fichte developes his particular ethics, or theory of duties, which, however, we must here pass by. Fichte's theory of religion is developed in the above men- tioned treatise : " On the ground of our faith in a divine gov- ernjnent of the world^'' and in the writings which he subsequently put forth in its defence. The moral government of the world, says Fichte, we assume to be the divine. This divine government becomes living and actual in us through right-doing : it is pre- supposed in every one of our actions which are only performed in the presupposition that the moral end is attainable in the world of sense. The faith in such an order of the world comprises the whole of faith, for this living and active moral order is God ; we need no other God, and can comprehend no other. There is no ground in the reason to go out of this moral order of the world, and by concluding from design to a designer, affirm a separate being as its cause. Is, then, this order an accidental one ? It is the absolute First of all objective knowledge. But now if you should be allowed to draw the conclusion that there is a God as a separate being, what have you gained by this ? This being should be dis- tinct from you and the world, it should work in the latter accord- ing to conceptions ; it should, therefore, be capable of conceptions, and possess personality and consciousness. But what do you call personality and consciousness ? Certainly that which you have found in yourself, which you have learned to know in yourself, and which you have characterized with such a name. But that you cannot conceive of this without limitation and finiteness, you might see by the slightest attention to the construction of this conception. By attaching, therefore, such a predicate to this be- 300 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. ing, you bring it down to a finite, and make it a being like your- self; you have not conceived God as you intended to do, but have only multiplied yourself in thought. The conception of God, as a separate substance, is impossible and contradictory. God has essential existence only as such a moral order of the world. Every belief in a divine being, which contains any thing more than the conception of the moral order of the world, is an abomination to me, and in the highest degree unworthy of a rational being. — Re- ligion and morality are, on this standpoint, as on that of Kant, naturally one ; both are an apprehending of the supersensible, the former through action and the latter through faith. This " Reli- gion of joyous right- doing," Fichte farther carried out in the writings which he put forth to rebut the charge of atheism. He affirms that nothing but the principles of the new philosophy could restore the degenerate religious sense among men, and bring to light the inner essence of the Christian doctrine. Especially he seeks to show this in his Appeal " to the public. In this he says : to furnish an answer to the questions : what is good ? what is true ? is the aim of my philosophical system. "We must start with the affirmation that there is something absolutely true and good ; that there is something which can hold and bind the free flight of thought. There is a voice in man which cannot be silenced, which affirms that there is a duty, and that it must be done simply for its own sake. Resting on this basis, there is opened to us an entirely new world in our being ; we attain a higher existence, which is independent of all nature, and is grounded simply in ourselves. I would call this absolute self-sat- isfaction of the reason, this perfect freedom from all dependence, blessedness. As the single but unerring means of blessedness, my conscience points me to the fulfilment of duty. I am, therefore, impressed by the unshaken conviction, that there is a rule and fixed order, according to which the purely moral disposition neces- sarily makes blessed. It is absolutely necessary, and it is the essential element in religion, that the man who maintains the dig- nity of his reason, will repose on the faith in this order of a moral world, will regard each one of his duties as an enactment of this FICHTE. 301 order, and will joyfully submit himself to, and find bliss in, every consequence of his duty. Thou shalt know God if I can only beget in thee a dutiful character, and though to others of us thou mayest seem to be still in the world of sense, yet for thyself art thou already a partaker of eternal life. II. The later form of Fichte's Philosophy. — Every thing of importance which Fichte accomplished as a speculative philoso- pher, is contained in the Theory of Science as above considered. Subsequently, after his departure from Jena, his system gradually became modified, and from difi"erent causes. Partly, because it was difficult to maintain the rigid idealism cf the Theory of Science ; partly, because Schelling's natural philosophy, which now appeared, was not without an influence upon Fichte's think- ing, though the latter denied this and became involved in a bitter controversy with Schelling; and, partly, his outward relations, which were far from being happy, contributed to modify his view of the world. Fichte's writings, in this second period, are for the most part popular, and intended for a mixed class of readers- They all bear the impress of his acute mind, and of his exalted manly character, but lack the originality and the scientific sequence of his earlier productions. Those of them which are scientific do not satisfy the demands which he himself had previously laid down with so much strictness, both for himself and others, in respect of genetic construction and philosophical method. His doctrine at this time seems rather as a web, of his old subjective idealistic conceptions and the newly added objective idealism, so loosely connected that Schelling might call it the completest syncretism aud eclecticism. His new standpoint is chiefly distin- guished from his old by his attempt to merge his subjective ideal- ism into an objective pantheism (in accordance with the new Platonism), to transmute the Ego of his earlier philosophy into the absolute, or the thought of God. God, whose conception he had formerly placed only at the end of his system, in the doubt- ful form of a moral order of the world, becomes to him now the absolute beginning, and single element of his philosophy. This gave to his philosophy an entirely new color. The moral severity 302 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. gives place to a religious mildness ; instead of the Ego and the Ought, life and love are now the chief features of his philosophy ; in place of the exact dialectic of the Theory of Science, he now makes choice of mystical and metaphorical modes of expression. This second period of Fichte's philosophy is especially charac- terized by its inclination to religion and Christianity, as exhibited most prominently in the essay " Direction to a Blessed Life^ Fichte here affirms that his new doctrine is exactly that of Chris- tianity, and especially of the Gospel according to John. He would make this gospel alone the clear foundation of Christian truth, since the other apostles remained half Jews after their con- version, and adhered to the fundamental error of Judaism, that the world had a creation in time. Fichte lays great weight upon the first part of John's prologue, where the formation of the world out of nothing is confuted, and a true view laid down of a revela- tion co-eternal with Grod, and necessarily given with his being. That which this prologue says of the incarnation of the Logos in the person of Jesus, has, according to Fichte, only a historic validity. The absolute and eternally true standpoint is, that at all times, and in every one, without exception, who is vitally sen- sible of his union with God, and who actually and in fact yields up his whole individual life to the divine life within him, — the eternal word becomes flesh in the same way as in Jesus Christ and holds a personal, sensible, and human existence. The whole communion of believers, the first-born alike with the later born, coincides in the Godhead, the common source of life for all. And so then, Christianity having gained its end, disappears again in the eternal truth, and affirms that every man should come to a union with God. So long as man desires to be himself any thing whatsoever, God does not come to him, for no man can become God. But just so soon as he purely, wholly, and radically gives up himself, God alone remains, and is all and in all. The man himself can beget no God, but he can give up himself as a proper negation, and thus he disappears in God. The result of his advanced philosophizing, Fichte has briefly HERBART. 303 and clearly comprehended in the following lines, which we extract from two posthumous sonnets : The Eternal One Lives in my life and sees in my beholding. Nought is but God, and God is nought but life. Clearly the vail of things rises before thee ; It is thyself, what though the mortal die And hence there lives but God in thine endeavors , If thou -wilt look through that which lives beyond this death, The vail of things shall seem to thee as vail, And imveiled thou shalt look upon the life divine. SECTION XLII. HERBAKT. A peculiar, and in many respects noticeable, carrying out of the Kantian philosophy, was attempted by JoJiann Friedrich Herhart^ who was born at Oldenburg in 1776, chosen professor of philosophy in Grottingen in 1805 ; made Kant's successor at Konigsberg in 1808, and recalled to Gottingen in 1838, where he died in 18-il. His philosophy, instead of making, like most other systems, for its principle, an idea of the reason, followed the direc- tion of Kant, and expended itself mainly in a critical examina- tion of the subjective experience. It is essentially a criticism, but with results which are peculiar, and which differ wholly from those of Kant. Its fundamental position in the history of phi- losophy is an isolated one ; instead of regarding antecedent sys- tems as elements 'of a true philosophy, it looks upon almost all of them as failures. It is especially hostile to the post-Kantian Ger- man philosophy, and most of all to Schelling's philosophy of na- ture, in which it could only behold a phantom and a delusion ; sooner than come in contact with this, it would join Hegelianism, of which it is the opposite pole. We will give a brief exposition f its prominent thoughts. 304 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 1. The Basis and Starting-point of Philosophy is, accord ing to Herbart, the common view of things, or a knowledge which shall accord with experience. A philosophical system is in reali- ty nothing but an attempt by which a thinker strives to solve cer- tain questions which present themselves before him. Every ques- tion brought up in philosophy should refer itself singly and solely to that which is given, and must arise from this source alone, be- cause there is no other original field of certainty, for men, than experience alone. Every philosophy should begin with it. The thinking should yield itself to experience, which should lead it, and not be led by it. Experience, therefore, is the only object and basis of philosophy ; that which is not given cannot be an ob- ject of thought, and it is impossible to establish any knowledge which transcends the limits of experience. 2. The first act of Philosophy. — Though the material fur- nished by experience is the basis of philosophy, yet, since it is furnished, it stands outside of philosophy. The question arises, what is the first act or beginning of philosophy ? The thinking should first separate itself from experience, that it may clearly see the difi&culties of its undertaking. The beginning of philoso- phy, where the thinking rises above that which is given, is ac- cordingly doubt or scepticism. Scepticism is twofold, a lower and a higher. The lower scepticism simply doubts that things are so constituted as they appear to us to be ; the higher scepti- cism passes beyond the form of tbe phenomenon, and inquires whether in reality any thing there exists. It doubts e. g. the suc- cession in time ; it asks in reference to the forms of the objects of nature which exhibit design, whether the design is perceived, or only attached to them in the thought, &c. Thus the problems which form the content of metaphysics, are gradually brought out. The result of scepticism is therefore not negative, but posi- tive. Doubt is nothing but the thinking upon those conceptions of experience which are the material of philosophy. Through this reflection, scepticism leads us to the knowledge that these con- ceptions of experience, though they refer to something given, yet contain no conceivable content free from logical incongruities. HERBART. 305 3. Remodelling of the conceptions of experience. — Me- taphysics, according to Herbart, is the science of that which is conceivable in experience. Our view thus far has been a twofold one. On the one side we hold fast to the opinion that the single basis of philosophy is experience, and on the other side, scepticism has shaken the credibility of experience. The point now is to transform this scepticism into a definite knowledge of metaphysical problems. Conceptions from experience crowd upon us, which cannot be thoughts, i. e. they may indeed be thought by the ordinary understanding, but this thinking is obscure and con- fused, and does not separate nor compare opposing characteristics. But an acute process of thought, a logical analysis, will find in the conceptions of experience (e.g. space, time, becoming, motion, &c.) contradictions and characteristics, which are totally inconsistent with each other. What now is to be done ? We may not reject these conceptions, for they are given, and beyond the given we cannot step ; we cannot retain them, for they are inconceivable and cannot logically be established. The only way of escape which remains to us is to remodel them. To remodel the conceptions of experience, to eliminate their contradictions, is the proper act of speculation. Scepticism has brought to light the more definite problems which involve a contradiction, and whose solution it therefore belongs to metaphysics to attempt ; the most important of these are the problems of inherence, change, and the Ego. The relation between Herbart and Hegel is very clear at this point. Both are agreed respecting the contradictory nature of the determinations of thought, and the conceptions of experience. But from this point they separate. It is the nature of these con- ceptions as of every thing, says Hegel, to be an inner contradic- tion ; becoming, for instance, is essentially the unity of being, and not being, &c. This is impossible, says Herbart, on the other side, so long as the principle of contradiction is valid ; if the con- ceptions of experience contain inner contradictions, this is not the fault of the objective world, but of the representing subject who must rectify his false apprehension by remodelling these concep- tions, and eliminating the contradiction. Herbart thus charges the 306 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. philosophy of Hegel with empiricism, because it receives from ex- perience these contradictory conceptions unchanged, and not only regards these as established, but even goes so far as to metamor- phose logic on their account, and this simply because they are given in experience, though their contradictory nature is clearly seen. Hegel and Herbart stand related to each other as Hera- clitus and Parmenides {cf. ^ ^ Yl. and VII.) 4. Herbart's Reals. — From this point Herbart reaches his " reals " (Bealen) as follows : To discover the contradictions, he says, in all our conceptions of experience, might lead us to abso- lute scepticism, and to despair of the truth. But here we re- member that if the existence of every thing real be denied, then the appearance, sensation, representation, and thought itself would bo destroyed. We perceive, therefore, just as strong an indication of being as of appearance. We cannot, indeed, as- cribe to the given any true and essential being per se, it is not per se alone, but only on, or in, or through something other. The truly being is an absolute being, which as such excludes every thing relative and dependent ; it is absolute positio7i, which it is not for us first to posit, but only to recognize. In so far as this being is attributed to any thing, this latter possesses reality. The truly being is, therefore, ever a quale, a something which is considered as being. In order now that this posited may correspond to the conditions which lie in the conception of absolute position, the what of the real must be thought (a) as absolutely positive or affirmative, i. e. without any negation or limitation, which might destroy again the absoluteness ; (J) as ab- solutely simple, i. e. in no way, as a multiplicity or admitting of inner antitheses ; (c) as indeterminate by any conceptions of great- ness, i. e. not as a quantum which may be divided and extended in time and space ; hence, also, not as a constant greatness or con- tinuity. But we must never forget that this being or this absolute reality is not simply something thought, but is something inde- pendent and resting on itself, and hence it is simply to be recog- nized by the thinking. The conception of this thinking lies at the basis of all Herbart's metaphysics. Take an example of this HERBART. 307 The first problem to he solved in metaphysics is the problem of inhercneej or the thing with its characteristics. Every percepti- ble thing represents itself to the senses as a complex of several characteristics. But all the attributes of a thing which are given in perception are relative. We say e. g. that souni is a property of a certain body. It sounds — but it cannot do this without air ; what now becomes of this property in a space without air ? Again, we say that a body is heavy, but it is only so on the earth. Or again, that a body is colored, but light is necessary for this ; what now becomes of such a property in darkness ? Still farther, a multiplicity of properties is incompatible with the unity of an object. If you ask ivhat is this thing, you are an- swered with the sum of its characteristics ; it is soft, white, full- sounding, heavy, — but your question was of one, not of many. The answer only affirms what the thing has, not what it is. Moreover, the list of characteristics is always incomplete. The what of a thing can therefore lie neither in the individual given properties, nor in their unity. In determining what a thing is, we have only this answer remaining, viz., the thing is that un- known, which we must posit before we can posit any thing as ly- ing in the given properties ; in a word, it is the substance. For if, in order to see what the thing purely and essentially is, we take away the characteristics which it may have, we find that nothing more remains, and we perceive that what we considered as the real thing was only a complex of characteristics, and the union of these in one whole. But since every appearance indi- cates a definite reality, and thus since there must be as much re- ality as there is appearance, we have to consider the reality, which lies at the basis of the thing, with its characteristics, as a complex of many simple substances or monads, and whose quality is different in different instances. When our experience has led us to a repeated grouping together of these monads, we call the group a thing. Let us now briefly look at the formation of those fundamental conceptions of metaphysics, which involve the same thoughts through the fundamental conception of being. First, there is the conception of causality, which cannot be maintained 308 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. in its ordinary form. All that we can perceive in the act is sue* cession in time, and not the necessary connection of cause with effect. The cause in itself can be neither transcendent nor im- manent ; it cannot be transcendent, because a real influence of one real thing u-poB. another, contradicts the conception of the absolute reality ; nor immanent, for then the substance must be thought as one with its characteristics, which contradicts the in- vestigations concerning a thing with its characteristics. We can just as little find in the conception of the real an answer to the question, how one determinate being can be brought into contact with another, for the real is the absolute unchangeable. We can therefore only explain the conception of causality on the ground that the different reals which lie at the basis of the characteris- tics are conceived, each one for itself, as cause of the phenome- non, there being just as many causes as there are phenomena. The problem of change, is intimately connected with the concep- tion of cause. Since, however, according to Herbart, there is no inner change, no self-determination, no becoming and no life ; since the monads are, and remain in themselves unchangeable, they do not therefore become different in respect of quality, but they are originally different one from another, and each one exhibits its equality without ever any change. The problem of change can thus only be solved through the theory of the disturbance and self-preservation of these essences. But if that which we call not simply an apparent but an actual event, in the essence of the monads, may be reduced to a " self-preservation," as the last gleam of an activity and life, still we have the question ever re- maining, how to explain the appearance of change. For this it is necessary to bring in two auxiliary conceptions ; first, that of accidental views, and second, that of intellectual spaces. The accidental views, an expression taken from mathematics, signify, in reference to the problem before us this much, viz., one and the same conception may often be considered in very different rela- tions to some other essence, without the slightest change in its own essence, e. g. a straight line may be considered as radius or as tangent, and a tone as harmonious or discordant. By help of HERBART. 309 these accidental views, we may now regard that which actually results in the monad, when other monads, opposite in quality, come in contact with it, as on the one side an actual occurrence, though on the other side, no actual change can be imputed to the original condition of the monads (a gray color, e. g. seems com- paratively white by the side of black, and comparatively black by the side of white, without changing at all its quality). A further auxiliary conception is that of intellectual space, which arises when we must consider these essences as at the same time together and not together. By means of this conception we can eliminate the contradictions from the conception of movement. Lastly, it can be seen that the conception of matter and that of the Ego (in psychologically explaining which, the rest of the metaphysics is occupied) are, like the preceding ones, no less con- tradictory in themselves than they are irreconcilable with the fundamental conception of the real ; for neither can an extended being, like matter, be formed out of spaceless monads — and with matter, therefore, fall also the ordinary conceptions of space and time — nor can we admit, without transformation, the conception of the Ego, since it exhibits the contradictory conception of a thing with many and changing characteristics (conditions, pow- ers, faculties, &c.) We are reminded by Herbart's " reals " of the atomic theory of the atomists (cf. § IX. 2), of the Eleatic theory of the one be- ing {cf. ^ YI.), and of Leibnitz's monadology. His reals however are distinguished from the atoms by not possessing impenetrability. The monads of Herbart may be just as well represented in the same space as a mathematical point may be conceived as accurate- ly coexisting with another in the same place. In this respect the " real " of Herbart has a far greater similarity to the " one " of the Eleatics. Both are simple, and to be conceived in intellectual spa>ces, but the essential difference is, that Herbart's substances ex- ist in numbers distinct from one another, and even from opposites among themselves. Herbart's simple quantities have already been compared to the monads of Leibnitz, but these latter have essen- tially a power of representation ; they are essences with inner cir- 310 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. cumstances, while, according to Herbart, representation, just as lit« tie as every otlier circumstance, belongs to tbe essence itself. 5. Psychology is connected with metaphysics. The Ego is primarily a metaphysical problem, and comes in this respect under the category of the thing with its characteristics. It is a real with many properties changing circumstances, powers, faculties, activi- ties, &c., and thus is not without contradictions. But then the Ego is a psychological principle, and here those contradictions may be considered which lie in the ideality of subject and object. The subject posits itself and is therefore itself object. But this posited object is nothing other than the positing subject. Thus the Ego is, as Fichte says, subject-object, and, as such, full of the hardest contradictions, for subject and object will never be affirmed as one and the same without contradiction. But now if the Ego is given it cannot be thrown away, but must be purified from its contradictions. This occurs whenever the Ego is conceived as that which represents, and the different sensations, thoughts, &c. are embraced under the common conception of changing appear- ance. The solution of this problem is similar to that of inher- ence. As in the latter problem the thing was apprehended as a complex of as many reals as it has characteristics, just so here the Ego ; but with the Ego inner circumstances and representations correspond to the characteristics. Thus that which we are accus- tomed to name Ego is nothing other than the soul. The soul as a monad, as absolutely being, is therefore simple, eternal, indis- soluble, from which we may conclude its eternal existence. From this standpoint Herbart combats the ordinary course of psychology which ascribes certain powers and faculties to the soul. That which stands out in the soul is nothing other than self-preserva- tion, which can only be manifold and changing in opposition to other reals. The causes of changing circumstances are therefore these other reals, which come variously in conflict with the soul- monad, and thus produce that apparently infinite manifoldness of sensations, representations, and afiections. This theory of self, preservation lies at the basis of all Herbart's psychology. That which psychology ordinarily calls feeling, thinking, representing, HERBART. 311 &c., are only specific differences in the self-preservation of the soul ; they indicate no proper condition of the inner real essence itself, hut only relations between the reals, relations, which, coming up together at the same time from different sides, are partly sup- pressed, partly forwarded, and partly modified Consciousness is the sum of those relations in which the soul stands to other essences. But the relations to the objects, and hence to the represen- tations corresponding to these, are not all equally strong ; one presses, restricts, and obscures another, a relation of equilibrium which can be calculated according to the doctrine of statics. But the suppressed representations do not wholly disappear, but wait- ing on the threshold of consciousness for the favorable moment when they shall be permitted again to arise, they join themselves with kindred representations, and press forward with united ener- gies. This movement of the representations (sketched in a master- ly manner by Herbart) may be calculated according to the rules of mathematics, and this is Herbart's well known application of mathematics to the empirical theory of the soul. The represen- tations which were pressed back, which wait on the threshold of con- sciousness and only work in the darkness, and of which we are on- ly half conscious, are feelings. They express themselves as desires, according as their struggle forward is more or less successful. Desire becomes will when united with the hope of success. The will is no separate faculty of the mind, but consists only in the relation of the dominant representations to the others. The power of deciding and the character of a man, prominently depend upon the constant presence in the consciousness of a certain num- ber of representations, while other representations are weakened, or denied an entrance over the threshold of consciousness. 6. The Importance of Herbart's Philosophy. — Herbart's philosophy is important mainly for its metaphysics and psychology. In the other spheres and activities of the human mind, e. g. rights, morality, the state, art, religion, his philosophy is mostly barren of results, and though there are not wanting here striking observa- tions, yet these have no connection with the speculative principles of the system. Herbart fundamentally isolates the different phil- 312 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. osopliical sciences, distinguishing especially and in the strictest manner between theoretical and practical philosophy. He charges the effort after unity in philosophy, with occasioning the greatest errors ; for logical, metaphysical, and aesthetic forms are entirely diverse. Ethics and aesthetics have to do with objects in which an immediate evidence appears, but this is foreign to the whole nature of metaphysics, which can only gain its knowledge as errors have been removed. Esthetic judgments on which practical philoso- phy rests, are independent of the reality of any object, and appear with immediate certainty in the midst of the strongest metaphysi- cal doubts. Moral elements, says Herbart, are pleasing and dis- pleasing relations of the will. He thus grounds the whole practical philosophy upon aesthetic judgments. The aesthetic judgment is an involuntary and immediate judgment, which attaches to certain objects, without proof, the predicates of goodness and badness. — Here is seen the greatest difference between Her- bart and Kant. We may characterize, on the whole, the philosophy of Her- bart as a carrying out of the monadology of Leibnitz, full of en- during acuteness, but without any inner fruitfulness or capacity of development. SECTION XLIII. SCHELLING. Schelling sprang from Fichte. We may pass on to an expo- sition of his philosophy without any farther introduction, since that which it contains from Fichte forms a part of its historical development, and will therefore be treated of as this is un- folded. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling was born at Leonberg, in W rtemberg, January 27th, 1775. With a very precocious development, he entered the theological seminary at Tubingen in SCHELLING. 313 his fifteenth year, and devoted himself partly to philology and mythology, but especially to Kant's philosophy. During his course as a student, he was in personal connection with Holder- lin and Hegel. Schelling came before the world as an author very early. In 1792 appeared his graduating treatise on the third chapter of Genesis, in which he gave an interesting philoso- phical signification to the Mosaic account of the fall. In the fol- lowing year, 1793, he published in Paulus' Memorabilia an essay of a kindred nature ^' On the Myths and Philosophemes of the Ancient Worlds To the last year of his abode at Tilbingen belong the two philosophical writings : " Ori the Possibility of a Form for Philosophy,'''' and " On the Ego as a Principle of Philosophy, or on the Unconditioned in Human Knowledge.''^ After completing his university studies, Schelling went to Leipsic as tutor to the Baron von Kiedesel, but soon afterwards repaired to Jena, where he became the pupil and co-laborer of Fichte. After Fichte's departure from Jena, he became himself, 1798, teacher of philosophy there, and now began, removing himself from Fichte's standpoint, to develope more and more his own pe- culiar views. He published in Jena the Journal of Specidative Physics, and also in company with Hegel, the Critical Journal. In the year 1803 he went to Wvirzburg as professor ordinarius of philosophy. In 1807 he repaired to Munich as member ordi- narius of the newly established academy of sciences there. The year after he became general secretary of the Academy of the plastic arts, and subsequently, when the university professorship was established at Munich, he became its incumbent. After the death of Jacobi, he was chosen president of the Munich Academy. In 1841 he removed to Berlin, where he has sometimes held lec- tures. For the last ten years Schelling has Avritten nothing of importance, although he has repeatedly promised an exposition of his present system. By far the greater portion of his writings belongs to his early life. Schelling's philosophy is no completed system of which his separate works are the constituent elements ; but, like Plato's, it has a historical development, a course of formative steps which the philosopher has passed through in his 14 314 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. own life. Instead of systematically elaborating tlie separate sciences from the standpoint of his principle, Schelling has gone back repeatedly to the beginning again, seeking ever for new foundations and new standpoints, connecting these for the most part (like Plato) with some antecedent philosophemes, (Fichte, Spi- noza, New Platonism, Leibnitz, Jacob Boehme, Gnosticism,) which in their order he attempted to interweave with his system. We must modify accordingly our exposition of Schelling's Philosophy, and take up its different periods, separated according to the dif- ferent groups of his writings.* I. First Period. Schelling's Procession from Fichte. Schelling's starting point was Fichte, whom he decidedly fol- lowed in his earliest writings. In his essay, " On the Possibility of a Form of Philosophy,''^ he shows the necessity of that supreme principle which Fichte had first propounded. In his essay, " On the ^^o," Schelling shows that the ultimate ground of our knowl- edge can only lie in the Ego, and hence that every true philosophy must be idealism. If our knowledge shall possess reality, there must be one point in which ideality and reality, thought and be- ing, can identically coincide ; and if outside of our knowledge, there were something higher which conditioned it, if itself were not the highest, then it could not be absolute. Fichte regarded this essay as a commentary on his Theory of Science ; yet it con- tains already indications of Schelling's subsequent standpoint, in its expressly affirming the unity of all knowledge, the necessity that in the end all the different sciences shall become merged into one. In the Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,^'' 1795, Schelling combatted the notions of those Kantians who had left the critical and idealistic standpoint of their master, and fallen back again into the old dogmatism. It was also on the stand- point of Fichte that Schelling published in Niethammer's and Fichte's Journal, 1797-98, a series of articles, in which he gave a survey of the recent philosophical literature. Here he begins * Schelling died August 20th, 1854, at Ragaz, Switzerland, whither he had gone for the benefit of his health, which had long been declining. — Translator. SCHELLING. 315 to turn his attention towards a philosophical deduction of nature, though he still remains on the standpoint of Fichte when he de- duces nature wholly from the essence of the Ego. In the essay which was composed soon after, and entitled Ideas for a philos- ophy of Nature,^'' 1797, and the one " On the World-soul, 1798, he gradually unfolded more clearly his views. The chief points which are brought out in the two last named essays are the fol- lowing : The first origin of the conception of matter springs from nature and the intuition of the human mind. The mind is the union of an unlimited and a limiting energy. If there were no limit to the mind, consciousness would he just as impossible as if the mind were totally and absolutely limited. Feeling, percep- tion and knowledge are only conceivable, as the energy which strives for the unlimited becomes limited through its opposite, and as this latter becomes itself freed from its limitations. The ac- tual mind or heart consists only in the antagonism of these two energies, and hence only in their ever approximate or relative unity. Just so is it in nature. Matter as such is not the first, for the forces of which it is the unity are before it. Matter is only to be apprehended as the ever becoming product of attrac- tion and repulsion ; it is not, therefore, a mere inert grossness, as we are apt to represent it, but these forces are its original. But force in the material is like something immaterial. Force in nature is that which we may compare to mind. Since now the mind or heart exhibits precisely the same conflict, as matter, of opposite forces, we must unite the two in a higher identity. But the organ of the mind for apprehending nature is the intuition which takes, as object of the external sense, the space which has been filled and limited by the attracting and repelling forces. Thus Schelliug was led to the conclusion that the same absolute appears in nature as in mind, and that the harmony of these is somethiug more than a thought in reference to them. " Or if you affirm that we only carry over such an idea to nature, then have you utterly failed to apprehend the only nature which there can be to us. For onr view of nature is not that it accidentally meets the laws of our mind — (perhaps through the mediation of a third) — but that it 316 A HISTORY OP PHILOSOPHY. necessarily and originally not only expresses, but itself realizes, the laws of our mind, and that it is nature, and is called such only in so far as it does this." " Nature should be the visible mind, and mind invisible nature. Here, therefore, in the absolute ideality of the mind within us, and nature wiihout us, must we eolve the problem how it is possible for a nature outside of us to be." This thought, that nature or matter is just as much the ac- tual unity of an attracting and a repelling force, as the mind or heart is the unity of an unlimited and a limiting tendency, and that the repelling force in matter corresponds to the positive or unlimited activity of the mind, while the attracting force corres- ponds to the mind's negative or limiting activity — this identical deduction of matter from the essence of the Ego, is very promi- nent in all that Schelling wrote upon natural philosophy during this period. Nature thus appears as a copy (Doppelhild) of the mind, which the mind itself produces, in order to return, by its means, to pure self-intuition, to self-consciousness. Hence we have the successive stages of nature, in which all the stations of the mind in its way to self- consciousness are externally established. It is especially in the organic world that the mind can behold its own self-production. Hence, in every thing organic, there is something symbolical, every plant bears some feature of the soul. The chief characteristics of an organic formation, — the self-form- ing process from within outwards, the conformity to some end, the change of interpenetration of form and matter — are equally chief features of the mind. Since now there exists in our mind an end- less striving to organize itself, so there must also be manifested in the external world a universal tendency to organization. The whole universe may thus be called a kind of organization which has formed itself from a centre, rising ever from a lower to a higher stage. From such a point of view, the natural philosopher will make it his chief effort to bring to a unity in his contempla- tions that life of nature, which by many researches into physical science had been separated into numberless different powers. "It is a needless trouble which many have given themselves, to show how very different is the working of fire and electricity, for ever^; SCHELLING. 317 one tnows this who has ever seen or heard of the two. But oui mind strives after unity in the system of its knowledge; it will not endure that there should be pressed upon it a separate princi- ple for every single phenomenon, and it will only believe that it sees nature where it can discover the greatest simplicity of laws in the greatest multiplicity of phenomena, and the highest frugality of means in the highest prodigality of effects. Therefore, every thought, even that which is now rough and crude, merits attention so soon as it tends towards the simplifying of principles, and if it serves no other end, it at least strengthens the impulse to inves- tigate and trace out the hidden process of nature." The special tendency of the scientific investigation of nature which prevailed at that time, was to make a duality of forces the predominant ele- ment in the life of nature. In mechanics, the Kantian theory of the opposition of attraction and repulsion was adopted ; in chem- istry, by apprehending electricity as positive and negative, its phenomenon was brought near that of magnetism ; in physiology there was the opposition of irritability and sensibility, &c. In opposition to these dualities, Schelling now insisted upon the unity of every thing opposite, the unity of all dualities, and this not simply as an abstract unity, but as a concrete identity, as the har- monious coworking of the heterogeneous. The world is the actual unity of a positive and a negative principle, " and these two con- flicting forces taken together, or represented in their conflict, lead to the idea of an organizing principle which makes of the world a system, in other words, to the idea of a world-soul." In his above-cited essay on " ilie tvorld-soulj'' Schelling took the great step forward of apprehending nature as entirely auto- nomic. In the world-soul nature has a peculiar principle which dwells within it, and works according to conception. In this way the objective world was recognized as the independent life of na- ture in a manner which the logical idealism of Fichte would not permit. Schelling proceeeded still farther in this direction, and distinguished definitely, as the two sides of philosophy, the philos- ophy of nature and a transcendental philosophy. By placing a philosophy of nature by the side of idealism, Schelling passed de- 318 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. cidedly beyond the standpoint of science, and we thus enter a second stadium of his philosophizing, though his method still re- mained that of Fichte, and he continued to believe that he was speculating in the spirit of the Theory of Science. II. Second Period. Standpoint of the distinguishing be- tween THE Philosophy of Nature and of Mind. This standpoint of Schelling is chiefly carried out in the fol- lowing works : — " First Draft of a System of Natural Philoso- phy 1799; an introduction to this, 1799; articles in the Journal of Speculative Physics,'''' 1800, 1801; System of Transcendental Idealism,^ 1800. Schelling thus distinguishes the two sides of philosophy. All knowledge rests upon the har- mony of a subject with an object. That which is simply objective is natural, and that which is simply subjective is the Ego or intel- ligence. There are two possible ways of uniting these two sides : we may either make nature first, and inquire how it is that intel- ligence is associated with it (natural philosophy) ; or we may make the subject first, and inquire how do objects proceed from the subject (transcendental philosophy). The end of all philosophy must be to make either an intelligence out of nature, or a nature out of intelligence. As the transcendental philosophy has to sub- ject the real to the ideal, so must natural philosophy attempt to explain the ideal from the real. Both, however, are only the two poles of one and the same knowledge which reciprocally attract each other ; hence, if we start from either pole, we are necessa- rily drawn towards the other. 1. Natural Philosophy. — To philosophize concerning nature is, in a certain sense, to create nature — to raise it from the dead mechanism in which it had seemed confined, to inspire it with free- dom, and transpose it into a properly free development. And what, then, is matter, other than mind which has become extinct? Ac- cording to this view, since nature is only the visible organism of our understanding, it can produce nothing but what is conforma- ble to a rule and an end. But you radically destroy every idea of nature just so soon as you allow its design to have come to it from without, by passing over from the understanding of any SCHELLING. 319 1)eiDg. The complete exhibition of the intellectual world in the laws and forms of the phenomenal world, and, on the other hand the complete conception of these laws and forms from the intel- lectual world, and therefore the exhibition of the ideality of na- ture with the ideal world, is the work of natural philosophy. Immediate experience is indeed its starting point ; we know originally nothing except through experience ; but just as soon as I gain an insight into the inner necessity of a principle of ex- perience, it becomes a principle apriori. Natural philosophy is empiricism extended until it becomes absolute. Schelling expresses himself as follows, concerning the jhief principles of a philosophy of nature. Nature is a suspension (Schivehen) between productivity and product, which Is always passing over into definite forms and products, just as it is always productively passing beyond these. This suspension indicates a duality of principles, through which nature is held in a constant activity, and hindered from exhausting itself in its products. A universal duality is thus the principle of every explanation of nature ; it is the first principle of a philosophic theory of nature, to end in all nature with polarity and dualism. On the other hand, the final cause of all our contemplation of nature is to know that absolute unity which comprehends the whole, and which suf- fers only one side of itself to be known in nature. Nature is, as it were, the instrument of this absolute unity, through which it eternally executes and actualizes that which is prefigured in the absolute understanding. The whole absolute is therefore cogni- zable in nature, though phenomenal nature only exhibits in a suc- cession, and produces in an endless development, that which the true or real nature eternally possesses. Schelling treats of natu- ral philosophy in three sections : (1) the proof that nature, in its original products, is organic ; (2) the conditions of an inorganic nature ; (3) the reciprocal determination of organic and inorganic nature. (1.) Organic nature Schelling thus deduces: Nature abso- lutely apprehended is nothing other than infinite activity, infinite productivity. If this were unhindered in expressing itself, it 320 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. would at once, with infinite celerity, produce an absolute product^ wliicli would allow no explanation for empirical nature. If this latter may be explained — if there may be finite products, we must consider the productive activity of nature as restrained by an opposite, a retarding activity, which lies in nature itself. Thus arises a series of finite products. But since the absolute produc- tivity of nature tends towards an absolute product, these indi- vidual products are only apparent ones, beyond each one of which nature herself advances, in order to satisfy the absoluteness of her inner productivity through an infinite series of individual products. In this eternal producing of finite products, nature shows itself as a living antagonism of two opposite forces, a pro- ductive and a retarding tendency. And, indeed, the working of this latter is infinitely manifold ; the original productive impulse of nature has not only to combat a simple restraint, but it must struggle with an infinity of reactions, which may be called original qualities. Hence every organic being is the permanent expression for a conflict of reciprocally destroying and limiting actions of nature. And from this, viz., from the original limitation and in- finite restraint of the formative impulse of nature, we see the reason why every organization, instead of attaining to an absolute product, only reproduces itself ad infinitum. Upon this rests the special significance for the organic world, of the distinction of sex. The distinction of sex fixes the organic products of nature, it restrains them within their own processes of development, and sufi"ers them only to produce the same again. But in this produc- tion nature has no regard for the individual, but only for the species. The individual is contrary to nature; nature desires the absolute, and its constant effort is to represent this. Indi- vidual products, therefore, in which the activity of nature is brought to a stand, can only be regarded as abortive attempts to represent the absolute. Hence the individual must be the means, and the species the end of nature. Just so soon as the species is secured, nature abandons the individuals and labors for their de- struction. Schelling divides the dynamic scale of organic nature according to the three grand functions of the organic world: 8CHELLING. 321 (a) Formative impulse (reproductive energy) ; (h) Irritability ; (c) Sensibility. Highest in rank are those organisms in which sensibility has the preponderance over irritability ; a lower rank is held by those where irritability preponderates, and lower still are those where reproduction first comes out in its entire perfec- tion, while sensibility and irritability are almost extinct. Yet these three powers are interwoven together in all nature, and hence there is but one organization, descending through all nature from man to the plant. (2.) Inorganic nature offers the antithesis to organic. The existence and essence of inorganic nature are conditioned through the existence and essence of organic nature. While the powers of organic nature are productive, those of inorganic nature are not productive. While organic nature aims only to establish the species, inorganic nature regards only the individual, and offers no reproduction of the species through the individual. It pos- sesses a great multitude of materials, but can only use these ma- terials in the way of conjoining or separating. In a word, inor- ganic nature is simply a mass held together by some external cause as gravity. Yet it, like organic nature, has its gradations. The power of reproduction in the latter has its counterpart in the chemical process in the former ; that which in the one case is irritability, in the other is electricity ; and sensibility, which is the highest stage of organic life, corresponds to the universal magnetism, the highest stage of the inorganic. (3.) The reciprocal determination of the organic and inor- ganic ivorld, is made clear by what has already been said. The result to which every genuine philosophy of nature must come, is that the distinction between organic and inorganic nature is only in nature as object, and that nature, as originally productive, waves over both. If the functions of an organism are only pos- sible on the condition that there is a definite external world, and an organic world, then must the external world and the organic world have a common origin. This can only be explained on the ground that inorganic nature presupposes in order to its existence a higher dynamical order of things, to which it is subject. There 322 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. must be a third, which can unite again organic and inorganio nature ; which can be a medium, holding the continuity between the two. Both must be identified in some ultimate cause, through which, as through one common soul of nature (world-soul), both the organic and inorganic, i. e. universal nature, is inspired ; in Bome common principle, which, fluctuating between inorganic and' or- ganic nature, and maintaining the continuity of the two, contains the first cause of all changes in the one, and the ultimate ground of all activity in the other. We have here the idea of a univer- sal organism. That it is one and the same organization which unites in one the organic and inorganic world, would appear from what has already been said of the parallel gradations of the two worlds. That which in universal nature is the cause of magnet- ism, is in organic nature the cause of sensibility, and the latter is only a higher potency of the former. Just as in the organic world through sensibility, so in universal nature through magnet- ism, there arises a duality from the ideality. In this way or- ganic nature appears only as a higher stage of the inorganic ; the very same dualism which is seen in magnetic polarity, electrical phenomena, and chemical differences, displays itself also in the organic world. 2. Transcendental Philosophy. — Transcendental philoso- phy is the philosophy of nature become subjective. The whole succession of objects thus far described, becomes now repeated as a su«cessive development of the beholding subject. It is the pe- culiarity of transcendental idealism, that so soon as it is once ad- mitted, it requires that the origin of all knowledge shall be sought for anew ; that the truth which has long been considered as estab- lished, should be subjected to a new examination, and that this examination should proceed under at least an entirely new form. All parts of philosophy must be exhibited in one continuity, and the whole of philosophy must be regarded as that which it is, viz., the advancing history of consciousness, which can use only as monuments or documents that which is laid down in experience. (Schelling's transcendental idealism is, in this respect, the fore- runner to Hegel's Phcenomenology ^ which pursues a similar 6CHELLING. 328 course). The exhibition of this connection is properly a succes- sion of intuitions through which the Ego raises itself to conscious- ness in the highest potency. Neither transcendental philosophy nor the philosophy of nature, can alone rej)resent the parallelism between nature and intelligence; but, in order to this, both sciences must be united, the former being considered as a neces- sary counterpart to the other. The division of transcendental philosophy follows from its problem, to seek anew the origin of all knowledge, and to subject to a new examination every pre- vious judgment which had been held to be established truth. The pre-judgments of the common understanding are principally two : (1) That a world of objects exist independent of, and outside of, ourselves, and are represented to us just as they are. To explain this pre-judgment, is the problem of the first part of the transcen- dental philosophy {theoretical philosophy). (2) That we can produce an effect upon the objective world according to represen- tations which arise freely within us. The solution of this prob- lem is practical philosophy. But, with these two problems we find ourselves entangled, (3) in a contradiction. How is it possi- ble that our thought should ever rule over the world of sense, if the representation is conditional in its origin by the objective? The solution of this problem, which is the highest of transcenden- tal philosophy, is the answer to the question : how can the repre- sentations be conceived as directing themselves according to the objects, and at the same time the objects be conceived as direct- ing themselves according to the representations ? This is only conceivable on the ground that the activity through which the objective world is produced, is originally identical with that which utters itself in the will. To show this identity of conscious and unconscious activity, is the problem of the third part of transcendental philosophy, or the science of ends in nature and of art. The three parts of the transcendental philosophy corre- spond thus entirely to the three criticks of Kant. (1.) The theoretical philosophy starts from the highest prin- ciple of knowledge, the self-consciousness, and from this point developes the history of self-consciousness, according to its most 324 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHT. prominent epochs and stations, viz., sensation, intuition, produc- tive intuition (which produces matter) — outer and inner intuition (from which space and time, and all Kant's categories may be derived), abstraction (by which the intelligence distinguishes itself from its products) — absolute abstraction, or absolute act of will. With the act of the will there is spread before us, (2). The Field of Practical Philosophy. — In practical philos- ophy the Ego is no longer beholding, i. e. consciousless, but is consciously producing, i. e. realizing. As a whole, nature de- velopes itself from the original act of self-consciousness, so from the second act, or the act of free self-determination, there is pro- duced a second nature, to find the origin for which is the object of practical philosophy. In his exposition of the practical phi- losophy, Schelling follows almost wholly the theory of Fichte, but closes this section with some remarkable expressions respect- ing the philosophy of history. History, as a whole, is, according to him, a gradual and self-disclosing revelation of the absolute, a progressing demonstration of the existence of a God. The his- tory of this revelation may be divided into three periods. The first is that in which the overruling power was apprehended only as destiny, i. e. as a blind power, cold and consciousless, which brings the greatest and most glorious things of earth to ruin ; it is marked by the decay of the magnificence and wonders of the ancient world, and the fall of the noblest manhood that has ever bloomed. The second period of history is that in which this des- tiny manifests itself as nature, and the hidden law seems changed into a manifest law of nature, which compels freedom and every choice to submit to and serve a plan of nature. This period seems to begin with the spread of the great Roman republic. The third period will be that where what has previously been re- garded as destiny and nature, will develope itself as Providence. When this period shall begin, we cannot say ; we can only affirm that if it be, then God will be seen also to be. (3.) Philosophy of Art. — The problem of transcendental philosophy is to harmonize the subjective and the objective. In history, with which practical philosophy closes, the identity of SCHELLING. 325 the two is not exhibited, but only approximated in an infinite progress. But now the Ego must attain a position where it can actually look upon this identity, which constitutes its inner es- sence. If now all conscious activity exhibits design, then a con- scious and consciousless activity can only coincide in a product, which, though it exhibits design, was yet produced without de- sign. Such a product is nature ; we have here the principle of all teleology^ in which alone the solution of the given problem can be sought. The peculiarity of nature is this, viz., that though it exhibits itself as nothing but a blind mechanism, it yet displays design, and represents an identity of the conscious sub- jective, and the consciousless objective activity ; in it the Ego beholds its own most peculiar essence, which consists alone in this identity. But in nature the Ego beholds this identity, not as something objective, which has a being only outside of it, but also as that whose principle lies within the Ego itself. This be- holding is the art-intuition. As the production of nature is con- sciousless, though similar to that which is conscious, so the aes- thetic production of the artist is a conscious production, similar to that which is consciousless. Esthetics must therefore be joined to teleology. That contradiction between the conscious and the consciousless, which moves forward untiringly in history, and which is unconsciously reconciled in nature, finds its con- scious reconciliation in a work of art. In a work of art, the in- telligence attains a perfect intuition of itself. The feeling which accompanies this intuition, is the feeling of an endless satisfac- tion ; all contradictions being resolved, and every riddle ex- plained. The unknown, which unexpectedly harmonizes the ob- jective and the conscious activity, is nothing other than that ab- solute and unchangeable identity, to which every existence must be referred. In the artist it lays aside the veil, which elsewhere surrounds it, and irresistibly impels him to complete his work. Thus there is no other eternal revelation but art, and this is also the miracle which should convince us of the reality of that su- preme, which is never itself objective, but is the cause of all ob- jective. Hence art holds a higher rank than philosophy, for only 826 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. in art has the intellectual intuition objectivity. There is noth- ing, therefore, higher to the philosopher than art, because this opens before him, as it were, the holy of holies, where that which is separate in nature and history, and which in _ife and action, as in thought, must ever diverge, burns, as it were, in one flame, in an eternal and original union. From this we see also both the fact and the reason for it, that philosophy, as philosophy, can never be universally valid. Art is that alone to which is given an absolute objectivity, and it is through this alone that nature, consciously productive, concludes and completes itself within itself. The " Transcendental Idealism " is the last work which Schelling wrote after the method of Fichte. In its principle he goes decidedly beyond the standpoint of Fichte. That which was with Fichte the inconceivable limit of the Ego, Schelling derives as a necessary duality, from the simple essence of the Ego. While Fichte had regarded the union of subject and ob- ject, only as an infinite progression towards that which ought to be, Schelling looked upon it as actually accomplished in a work of art. With Fichte God was apprehended only as the object of a moral faith, but with Schelling he was looked upon as the im- mediate object of the aesthetic intuition. This difference between the two could not long be concealed from Schelling. He was obliged to see that he no longer stood upon the basis of subjec- tive idealism, but that his real position was that of objective ideal- ism. If he had already gone beyond Fichte in setting the phi- losophy of nature and transcendental philosophy opposite to each other, it was perfectly consistent for him now to go one step far- ther, and, placing himself on the point of indifierence between the two, make the identity of the ideal and the real, of thought and being, as his principle. This principle Spinoza had already possessed before him. To this philosophy of identity Schelling now found himself peculiarly attracted. Instead of following Fichte's method, he now availed himself of that of Spinoza, the mathematical, to which he ascribed the greatest evidence of proof. III. Third Period : Period of Spinozism, or the Indif- ference OF THE Ideal and the Real. SCHELLING. 327 The principal writings of this period are : — " Exposiiion of my System of Philosophy " (Journal for Speculative Physics, ii. 2) ; the second edition, with additions, of the " Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature y'' 1803; the dialogue, Bruno, or concerning the Di vine and the Natural Principle of Things,''^ 1802; ^''Lectures on the Method of Academical Study, ''^ 1803; three numbers of a " New Journal for Speculative Physics,''"' 1802-3. The charac- teristic of the new standpoint of Schelling, to which we now arrive, is perfectly exhibited in the definition of reason, which he places at the head of the first of the above-named writings ; I give to reason the name absolute, or the reason in so far as it is con- ceived as the total indifference of the subjective and the objec- tive. To think of reason is demanded of every man ; to think of it as absolute, and thus to reach the standpoint which I require, every thing must be abstracted from the thinking subject. To him who makes this abstraction, reason immediately ceases to be something subjective, as most men represent it ; neither can it be conceived as something objective, since an objective, or that which is thought, is only possible in opposition to that which thinks. AYe thus rise through this abstraction to the reality of things {zum ivahren an-sich), which reality is precisely in the indifference point of the subjective and the objective. The stand- point of philosophy is the standpoint of reason ; its knowledge is a knowledge of things as they are in themselves, i. e. as they are in the reason. It is the nature of philosophy to destroy every distinc- tion which the imagination has mingled with the thinking, and to see in things only that through which they express the absolute reason, not regarding in them that which is simply an object for that reflection which expends itself on the laws of mechanism and in time. Besides reason there is nothings and in it is every thing. Keason is the absolute. All objections to this principle can only arise from the fact, that men are in the habit of looking at things not as they are in reason, but as they appear. Every thing which is, is in essence like the reason, and is one with it» It is not the reason which posits something external to itself, but only the false use of reason, which is connected with the 328 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. incapacity of forgetting the subjective in itself. The reason is absolutely one and like itself. The highest law for the being of reason, and since there is nothing besides reason, the high- est law for all being, is the law of identity. Between subject and object therefore — since it is one and the same absolute identity which displays itself in both — there can be no differ- ence except a quantitative difference (a difference of more or less), so that nothing is either simple object or simple subject, but in all things subject and object are united, this union being in different proportions, so that sometimes the subject and sometimes the object has the preponderance. But since the absolute is pure identity of subject and object, there can be no quantitative differ- ence except outside of the identity, i. e. in the finite. As the fundamental form of the infinite is A=A, so the scheme of the finite is A=B (i. e. the union of a subjective with another objec- tive in a different proportion). But, in reality, nothing is finite, because the identity is the only reality. So far as there is differ- ence in individual things, the identity exists in the form of indif- ference. If we could see together every thing which is, we should find in all the pure identity, because we should find in all a perfect quantitative equilibrium of subjectivity and objectivity. True, we find, in looking at individual objects, that sometimes the pre- ponderance is on one side and sometimes on the other, but in the whole this is compensated. The absolute identity is the absolute totality, the universe itself. There is in reality (an-sicli) no indi- vidual being or thing. There is in reality nothing beyond the totality ; and if any thing beyond this is beheld, this can only happen by virtue of an arbitrary separation of the individual from the whole, which is done through reflection, and is the source of every error. The absolute identity is essentially the same in every part of the universe. Hence the universe may be conceived under the figure of a line, in the centre of which is the A=A, while at the end on one side is A=B, i. e. a transcendence of the subjective", and at the end on the other side is A=B, i. e. a trans- cendence of the objective, though this must be conceived so that a SCHELLING. 329 relative identity may exist even in these extremes. The one side is the real or nature, the other side is the ideal. The real side develoj^es itself according to three potences (a potence, or power, indicates a definite quantitative difference of subjectivity and ob- jectivity). (1) The first potence is matter and weight — the greatest preponderance of the object. (2) The second potence is light (A^), an inner — as weight is an outer — intuition of nature. The light is a higher rising of the subjective. It is the absolute identity itself. (3) The third potence is organism (A^), the common product of light and weight. Organism is just as original as matter. Inorganic nature, as such, does not exist : it is actually organized, and is, as it were, the universal germ out of which organization proceeds. The organization of every globe is but the inner evolution of the globe itself ; the earth itself, by its own evolving, becomes animal and plant. The organic world has not formed itself out of the inorganic, but has been at least poten- tially present in it from the beginning. That matter which lies before us, apparently inorganic, is the residuum of organic meta- morphoses, which could not become organic. The human brain is the highest bloom of the whole organic metamorphosis of the earth. From the above, Schelling adds, it must be per- ceived that we affirm an inner identity of all things, and a poten- tial presence of every thing in every other, and therefore even the so-called dead matter may be viewed only as a sleeping-world of animals and plants, which, in some period, the absolute identity may animate and raise to life. At this point Schelling stops sud- denly, without developing further the three potences of the ideal series, corresponding to those of the real. Elsewhere he com- pletes the work by setting up the following three potences of the ideal series : (1) Knowledge, the potence of reflection ; (2) Action, the potence of subsumption ; (3) the Reason as the unity of re- flection and subsumptioa. These three potences represent them- selves : (1) as the true, the imprinting of the matter in the form; (2) as the good, or the imprinting of the form in the matter ; (3) as the beautiful, or the work of art, the absolute blending to- gether of form and matter. 330 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHT. Schelling sought also to furnish himself with a new method for knowing the absolute identity. Neither the analytic nor the synthetical method seems to him suitable for this, since both are only a finite knowledge. Gradually, also, he abandoned the mathematical method. The logical forms of the ordinary method of knowledge, and even the ordinary metaphysical categories, were now insufficient for him. Schelling now places the intellectual intuition as the starting point of true knowledge. Intuition, in general, is an equal positing of thought and being. When I be- hold an object, the being of the object and my thought of the object is for me absolutely the same. But in the ordinary intui- tion, some separate sensible being is posited as one with the thought. But in the intellectual or rational intuition, being in general, and every being is made identical with the thought, and the absolute suhj ect-ohj ect is beheld. The intellectual intuition is absolute knowledge, and as such it can only be conceived as that in which thought and being are not opposed to each other. It is the beginning and the first step towards philosophy to behold, immediately and intellectually within thyself, that same indifi'er- ence of the ideal and the real which thou beholdest projected as it were from thyself in space and time. This absolutely absolute mode of knowledge is wholly and entirely in the absolute itself. That it can never become taught is clear. It cannot, moreover, be seen why philosophy is bound to have special regard to the unattainable. It seems much more fitting to make so complete a separation on every side between the entrance to philosophy and the common knowledge, that no road nor track shall lead from the latter to the former. The absolute mode of knowledge, like the truth which it contains, has no true opposition outside of itself, and as it cannot be demonstrated by any intelligent being, so nothing can be set up in opposition to it by any. — Schelling has attempted to bring the intellectual intuition into a method, and has named this method construction. The possibility and the necessity of the constructive method is based upon the fact that the absolute is in all, and that all is the absolute. Construction is nothing other than the proving that the whole is absolutely ex- SCHELLING. 331 pressed in every particular relation and object. To construe an object, pbilosophically, is to prove that in this object the whole inner structure of the absolute repeats itself. In SchelliDg's Lectures on the 3Iethod of Academical Study''"' (delivered in 1802, and published in 1803), he sought to treat encyclopaediacally, every philosophical discipline from the given standpoint of identity or indifference. They furnish a con- nected and popular exposition of the outlines of his philosophy, in the form of a critical modelling of the studies of the university course. The most noticeable feature in them is Schelling's attempt at a historical construction of Christianity. The incarnation of God is an incarnation from eternity. The eternal Son of God, born from the essence of the father of all things, is the finite itself, as it is in the eternal intuition of God. Christ is only the his- torical and phenomenal pinnacle of the incarnation ; as an indi- vidual, he is a person wholly conceivable from the circumstances of the age in which he appeared. Since God is eternally outside of all time, it is inconceivable that he should have assumed a human nature at any definite moment of time. The temporal form of Christianity, the exoteric Christianity does not correspond to its idea, and has its perfection yet to be hoped for. A chief hindrance to the perfection of Christianity, was, and is the so- called Bible, which, moreover, is far inferior to other religious writings, in a genuine religious content. The future must bring a new birth of the esoteric Christianity, or a new and higher form of religion, in which philosophy, religion and poesy shall melt together in unity. — This latter remark contains already an intima- tion of the " Philosophy of Bevelation,^^ a work subsequently written by Schelling, and which exhibited many of the principles current in the age of the apostle J ohn. In the work we are now considering, there are also many other points which correspond to this later standpoint of Schelling. Thus he places at the summit of history a kind of golden age. It is inconceivable, he says, that man as he now appears, should have raised himself through him- self from instinct to consciousness, from animality to rationality. Another human race, must, therefore, have preceded the present, 382 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. which the old saga have immortalized under the form of gods and heroes. The first origin of religion and culture is only conceiva- ble through the instruction of higher natures. I hold the condi- tion of culture as the first condition of the human race, and con- siderer the first foundation of states, sciences, religion and arts as cotemporary, or rather as one thing : so that all these were not truly separate, but in the completest interpenetration, as it will be again in the final consummation. Schelling is no more than con- sistent when he accordingly apprehends the symbols of mythology which we meet with at the beginning of history, as disclosures of the highest wisdom. There is here also a step towards his sub- sequent " Philosophy of Mythologyy The mystical element revealed in these expressions of Schelling gained continually a greater prominence with him. Its growth^ was partly connected with his fruitless search after an absolute method, and a fitting form in which he might have satisfactorily expressed his philosophic intuitions. All noble mysticism rests on the incapacity of adequately expressing an infinite content in the form of a conception. So Schelling, after he had been rest- lessly tossed about in every method, soon gave up also his method of construction, and abandoned himself wholly to the unlimited current of his fancy. But though this was partly the cause of his mysticism, it is also true that his philosophical standpoint was gradually undergoing a change. From the speculative science of nature, he was gradually passing over more and more into the philosophy of mind, by which the determination of the absolute in his conception became changed. While he had previously de- termined the absolute as the indifierence of the ideal and the real^ he now gives a preponderance to the ideal over the real, and makeb ideality the fundamental determination of the absolute. The first is the ideal ; secondly, the ideal determines itself in itself to the real, and the real as such is the third. The earlier harmony of mind and matter is dissolved : matter appears now as the nega- tive of mind. Since Schelling in this way distinguishes the uni- verse from the absolute as its counterpart, we see that he leaves SCHELLING. 333 decidedly the basis of Spinozism on which he had previously stood, and places himself on a new standpoint. lY. Fourth Pemod : the Direction of Schelling's Phi- losophy AS Mystical and allied to New-Platonism. The writings of this period are : — " Philosophy and JReligion,^^ 1804. " Exposition of the true relation of the Philosophy of Nature to the improved Theory of Fichte,^^ 1806 ; " Medical Annual " (published in company with Marcus) 1805-1808. — As has already been said, the absolute and the universe were, on the standpoint of indilference, identical. Nature and history were immediate manifestations of the absolute. But now Schelling lays stress upon the difference between the two, and the independence of the world. This he expresses in a striking way in the first of the above named writings, by placing the origin of the world wholly after the manner of New-Platonism, in a breaking away or a fall- ing off from the absolute. From the absolute to the actual, there is no abiding transition ; the origin of the sensible world is only conceivable as a complete breaking off per saltum from the abso- lute. The absolute is the only real, finite things are not real ; they can, therefore, have their ground in no reality imparted to them from the absolute, but only in a separation and complete falling away from the absolute. The reconciliation of this fall, and the manifestation of God made complete, is the final cause of history. With this idea there are also connected other represen- tations borrowed from New-Platonism, which Schelling briugs out in the same work. He speaks in it of the descent of the soul from intellectuality, to the world of sense, and like the Platonic myth he allows this fall of souls to be a punishment for their self- hood (pride) ; he speaks also in connection with this of a regenera- tion, or transmigration of souls, by which they either -begin a higher life on a better sphere, or intoxicated with matter, they are driven down to a still lower abode, according as they have in the present life laid aside more or less of their selfhood, and become purified in a greater or less degree, to an identity with the infi- nite ; but we are especially reminded of New-Platonism by the high place and the mystical and symbolical significance, which Schelling 334 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. gives in this work to the Greek mysteries (as did Bruno), and the view that if religion would be held in its pure ideality, it can only exist as exoteric, or in the form of mysteries. — This notion of a higher blending together of religion and philosophy goes through all the writings of this period. All true experience, says Schel- ling in the " Medical Annual,'''' is religious. The existence of God is an empirical truth, and the ground of all experience. True, religion is not philosophy, but the philosophy which does not unite in sacred harmony, religion with science, were unworthy of the name. True, I know something higher than science. And if science has only these two ways open before it to knowledge, viz., that of analysis or abstraction, and that of synthetic deriva- tion, then we deny all science of the absolute. Speculation is every thing, i. e. a beholding, a contemplation of that which is in God. Science itself has worth only so far as it is speculative, i. e. only so far as it is a contemplation of God as he is. But the time will come when the sciences shall more and more cease, and immediate knowledge take their place. The mortal eye closes only in the highest science, where it is no longer the man who sees, but the eternal beholding which has now become seeing in him. With this theosophic view of the world, Schelling was led to pay attention to the earlier mystics. He began to study their writings. He answered the charge of mysticism in his controversy with Fichte as follows : — Among the learned of the last century, there was a tacit agreement never to go beyond a certain height, and, therefore, the genuine spirit of science was given up to the unlearned. These, because they were uneducated and had drawn upon themselves the jealousy of the learned, were called fanat- ics. But many a philosopher by profession might well have ex- changed all his rhetoric for the fulness of mind and heart which abound in the writings of such fanatics. Therefore I am not ashamed of the name of such a fanatic. I will even seek to make this reproach true ; if I have not hitherto studied the writings of these men correctly, it has been owing to negligence. Schelling did not omit to verify these words. There were some special mental affinities between himself and Jacob BoeJime, SCHELLING. 335 with whom he now became more and more closely joined. A study of his writings is indeed indicated in Schelling's works of the present period. One of the most famous of Schelling's writ- ings, his theory of freedom, which appeared after this (" Fhiloso- phiscJie Untersuchungen itber das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit,^^ 1809), is composed entirely in the spirit of Jacob Boehme. We begin with it a new period of Schelling's philoso- phizing, where the ivill is affirmed as the essence of God, and we have thus a new definition of the absolute differing from every previous one. V. Fifth Period : — Attempt at a Theggony and Cosmogo- ny AFTER THE MaNNER OF JaCOB BoEHME. Schelling had much in common with Jacob Boehme. Both con- sidered the speculative cognition as a kind of immediate intuition. Both made use of forms which mingled the abstract and the sen- suous, and interpenetrated the definiteness of logic with the coloring of fancy. Both, in fine, were speculatively in close contact. The self-duplication of the absolute was a fundamental thought of Boehme. He started with the principle, that the divine essence was the indeterminable, infinite, and inconceivable, the absence of ground ( TJngrund). This absence of ground now projects itself in a proper feeling of its abstract and infinite essence, into the finite, i. e. into a ground, or the centre of nature, in the dark womb of which qualities are produced, from whose harsh collision the light- ning streams forth, which, as mind or principle of light, is des- tined to rule and explain the struggling powers of nature, so that the God who has been raised from the absence of ground through a ground to the light of the mind, may henceforth move in an eternal kingdom of joy. This theogony of Jacob Boehme is in striking accord with the present standpoint of Schelling. As Boehme had apprehended the absolute as the indeterminable ab- sence of ground, so had Schelling in his earlier writings appre- hended it as indifierence. As Boehme had distinguished this ab- sence of ground from a ground, or from nature and from God, as the light of minds, so had Schelling, in the writings of the last period, apprehended the absolute as a self-renunciation, and a re- 336 A HISTOEY OF PHILOSOPHY. turn back from this renunciation into a higher unity with itself. We have here the three chief elements of that history of God, around which Schelling's essay on freedom turns: (1) God as indifference, or the absence of ground ; (2) God as duplication into ground and existence, real and ideal ; (3) Reconciliation of this duplication, and elevation of the original indifference to iden- tity. The first element of the divine life is that of pure indiffer- ence, or indistinguishableness. This, which precedes every thing existing, may be called the original ground, or the absence of ground. The absence of ground is not a product of opposites, nor are they contained implicite in it, but it is a proper essence separate from every opposite, and having no predicate but that of predicatelessness. Real and ideal, darkness and light, can never be predicated of the absence of ground as opposites ; they can only be affirmed of it as not-opposites in a neither-nor. From this indifference now rises the duality : the absence of ground separates into two co-eternal beginnings, so that ground and ex- istence may become one through love, and the indeterminable and lifeless indifference may rise to a determinate and living identity. Since nothing is before or external to God, he must have the ground of his existence in himself. But this ground is not sim- ply logical, as conception, but real, as something which is actual- ly to be distinguished in God from existence ; it is nature in God, an essence inseparable indeed from him, but yet distinct. Hence we cannot assign to this ground understanding and will, but only desire after this ; it is the longing to produce itself. But in that this ground moves in its longing according to obscure and un- certain laws like a swelling sea, there is, self-begotten in God, another and reflexive motion, an inner representation by which he beholds himself in his image. This representation is the eternal word in God, which rises as light in the darkness of the ground, and endows its blind longing with understanding. This under- standing, united with the ground, becomes pre-creating will. Its work is to give order to nature, and to regulate the hitherto un- regulated ground ; and from this explanation of the real through the ideal, comes the creation of the world. The development of SCHELLING. 337 the world has two stadia : ( 1 ) the travail of light, or the pro- gressive development of nature to man ; (2) the travail of mind, or the development of mind in history. (1.) The progressive development of nature proceeds from a conflict of the ground with the understanding. The ground originally sought to produce every thing solely from itself, but its products had no consistence without the understanding, and went again to the ground, a creation which we see exhibited in the extinct classes of animals and plants of the pre- Adamite world. But consecutively and gradually, the ground admitted the work of the understanding, and every such step towards light is indicated by a new class of nature's beings. In every creature of nature we must, therefore, distinguish two principles : first, the obscure principle through which the creatures of nature are separate from God, and have a particular will ; second, the divine principle of the understanding, of the universal will. With irra- tional creatures of nature, however, these two principles are not yet brought to unity ; but the particular will is simple seeking and desire, while the universal will, without the individual will, reigns as an external power of nature, as controlling instinct. (2.) The two principles, the particular and the universal will, are first united in man as they are in the absolute : but in God they are united inseparably, and in man separably, for otherwise God could not reveal himself in man. It is even this separable- ness of the universal will, and the particular will, which makes good and evil possible. The good is the subjection of the par- ticular will to the universal will, and the reverse of this right relation is evil. Human freedom consists in this possibility of good and evil. The empirical man, however, is not free, but his whole empirical condition is posited by a previous act of intelli- gence. The man must act just as he does, but is nevertheless free, because he has from eternity freely made himself that which he now necessarily is. The history of the human race is founded for the most part on the struggle of the individual will with the universal will, as the history of nature is founded on the struggle of the ground with the understanding. The difi'erent stages 15 338 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. through which evil, as a historical power, takes its way in conflict with love, constitute the periods of the world's history. Chris- tianity is the centre of history : in Christ, the principle of love came in personal contact with incarnate evil : Christ was the mediator to reconcile on the highest stage the creation with God ; for that which is personal can alone redeem the personal. The end of history is the reconciliation of the particular will and love, the prevalence of the universal will, so that God shall be all in all. The original indifference is thus elevated to identity. Schelling has given a farther justification of this his idea of God, in his controversial pamphlet against Jacobi, (1812). The charge of naturalism which Jacobi made against him, he sought to refute by showing how the true idea of God was a union of naturalism and theism. Naturalism seeks to conceive of God as ground of the world (immanent), while theism would view him as the world's cause (transcendent) : the true course is to unite both determinations. God is at the same time ground and cause. It no way contradicts the conception of God to afiirm that, so far as he reveals himself, he developes himself from himself, advancing from the imperfect to the perfect : the imperfect is in fact the perfect itself, only in a state of becoming. It is necessary that this becoming should be by stages, in order that the fulness of the perfect may appear on all sides. If there were no obscure ground, no nature, no negative principle in God, we could not speak of a consciousness of God. So long as the God of modern theism remains the simple essence which ought to be purely essential, but which in fact is without essence, so long as an actual twofold- ness is not recognized in God, and a limiting and denying energy (a nature, a negative principle) is not placed in opposition to the extending and affirming energy in God, so long will science be entitled to make its denial of a personal God. It is universally and essentially impossible to conceive of a being with conscious- ness, which has not been brought into limit by some denying energy within himself — as universally and essentially impossible as to conceive of a circle without a centre. VI. Since the essay against Jacobi, which in its philosophical TRANSITION TO HEGEL. 339 content accords mainly with his theory of freedom, Schelling has not made public any thing of importance. He has often announced a work entitled " Die Weltalter,^^ which should contain a com- plete and elaborate exposition of his philosophy, but has always withdrawn it before its appearance. Paiilus has surreptitiously brought his later Berlin lectures before the public in a manner for which he has been greatly blamed : but since this publication is not recognized by Schelling himself, it cannot be used as ai: authentic source of knowledge of his philosophy. During this long period, Schelling has published only two articles of a philo- sophical content : " On the Deities of Samothracos,^^ 1815, and a " Critical Preface''^ to Becker'' s translation of a preface of Cousin J 1834. Both articles are very characteristic of the pre- sent standpoint of Schelling's philosophizing — he himself calls his present philosophy Positive Philosophy, or the Philosophy of My- thology and Revelation, — but as they give only intimations of this, and do not reach a complete exposition, they do not admit of being used for our purpose. SECTION XLIV. TRANSITION TO HEGEL. The great want of Schelling's philosophizing, was its inability to furnish a suitable form for the philosophic content. Schelling went through the list of all methods, and at last abandoned all. But this absence of method into which he ultimately sank, contra- dicted the very principle of his philosophizing. If thought and being are identical, yet form and content cannot be indifferent in respect to each other. On the standpoint of absolute knowledge, there must be found for the absolute content an absolute form, which shall be identical with the content. This is the position assumed by Hegel. Hegel has fused the content of Schelling's philosophy by means of the absolute method. 340 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. Hegel sprang as truly from Ficlite as from Schelling ; the origin of his system is found in both. His method is essentially that of Fichte, but his general philosophical standpoint is Schell- ing's. He has combined both Fichte and SchelliEg. Hegel has himself, in his " Phenomenology^'''' the first work in which he appeared as a philosopher on his own hook, having pre- viously been considered as an adherent of Schelling — clearly ex- pressed his difference from Schelling, which he comprehensively affirms in the following three hits (Schlagworte): — In Schelling's philosophy, the absolute is, as it were, shot out of a pistol ; it is only the night in which every cow looks black ; when it is widened to a system, it is like the course of a painter, who has on his palette but two colors, red and green, and who would cover a surface with the former when a historical piece was demanded, and with the latter when a landscape was required. The first of these charges refers to the mode of attaining the idea of the abso- lute, viz., immediately, through intellectual intuition ; this leap Hegel changes, in his Phenomenology, to a regular transit, proceed- ing step by step. The second charge relates to the way in which the absolute thus gained is conceived and expressed, viz., simply as the absence of all finite distinctions, and not as the immanent positing of a system of distinctions within itself. Hegel declares that every thing depends upon apprehending and expressing the true not as substance {i. e. as negation of determinateness), but as subject (as a positing and producing of finite distinction). The third charge has to do with Schelling's manner of carrying out his principle through the concrete content of the facts given in the natural and intellectual worlds, viz., by the application of a ready- made schema (the opposition of the ideal and the real) to the objects, instead of suffering them to unfold and separate them- selves from themselves. The school of Schelling was especially given to this schematizing formalism, and that which Hegel re- marks, in the introduction to his Phenomenology, may very well be applied to it : " If the formalism of a philosophy of nature should happen to teach that the understanding is electricity, or that the animate is nitrogen, the inexperienced might look upon such in- TRANSITION TO HEGEL. 341 structions with deep amazement, and perhaps revere them as dis- playing the marks of profound genius. But the trick of such a wisdom is as readily learned as it is easily practised ; its repetition is as insufferable as the repetition of a discovered feat of legerde- main. This method of affixing to every thiiig heavenly and earthly, to all natural and intellectual forms, the two determina- tions of the universal scheme, makes the universe like a grocer's shop, in which a row of closed jars stand Avith their labels pasted on them. ^ The point, therefore, of greatest difference between Scbelling and Hegel is their philosophical method, and this at the same time forms the bond of close connection which unites Hegel with Ficbte. Thesis, antithesis, synthesis — this was the method by which Fichte had sought to deduce all being from the Ego, and in precisely the same way Hegel deduces all being — the intellec- tual and natural universe — from the thought, only with this dif- ference, that with him that which was idealistically deduced had at the same time an objective reality. While the practical ideal- ism of Fichte stood related to the objective world as a producer, and the ordinary empiricism as a beholder, yet with Hegel the speculative (conceiving) reason is at the same time productive and beholding. I produce (for myself) that which is (in itself) without my producing. The result of philosophy, says Hegel, is the thought which is by itself, and which comprehends in itself the universe, and changes it into an intelligent world. To raise all being to being in the consciousness, to knowledge, is the problem and the goal of philozophizing, and this goal is reached when the mind has become able to beget the whole objective world from itself. In his first great work, the " Phenomenology of the Mind,^^ Hegel sought to establish the standpoint of absolute knowledge or absolute idealism. He furnishes in this work a history of the phenomenal consciousness (whence its title), a development of the formative epochs of the consciousness in its progress to philo- sophical knowledge. The inner development of consciousness consists in this, viz., that the peculiar condition in which it finds 342 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. itself becomes objectified (or conscious), and through this know- ledge of its own being the consciousness rises ever a new step to a higher condition. The " Phenomenology " seeks to show how, and out of wha.t necessity the consciousness advances from step to step, from reality to being per se [vom AnsicJi zum Farsich), from being to knowledge. The author begins with the immediate consciousness as the lowest step. He entitled this section : " The Sensuous Certainty, or the This and the Mine^ At this stage the question is asked the Ego : what is this, or what is here ? and it answers, e. g. the tree ; and to the question, what is now ? it answers now is the night. But if we turn ourselves around, here is not a tree but a house ; and if we write down the second answer, and look at it again after a little time, we find that now is no longer night but mid-day. The this becomes, therefore, a not- this, i. e. a universal. And very naturally ; for if I say : this piece of paper, yet each and every paper is a this piece of paper, and I have only said the universal. By such inner dialectics the whole field of the immediate certainty of the sense in perception is gone over. In this way — ^since every formative step (every form) of the consciousness of the philosophizing subject is in- volved in contradictions, and is carried by this immanent dialec- tics to a higher form of consciousness — this process of develop- ment goes on till the contradiction is destroyed, i. e. till all strangeness between subject and object disappears, and the mind rises to a perfect self-knowledge and self-certainty. To charac- terize briefly the different steps of this process, we might say that the consciousness is first found as a certainty of the sense, or as the this and the mine ; next as perception, which apprehends the objective as a thing with its properties ; and then as understand- ing, i. e. apprehending the objects as being reflected in itself, or distinguishing between power and expression, being and manifes- tation, outer and inner. From this point the consciousness, which has only recognized itself, its own pure being in its objects and their determinations, and for which therefore every other thing than itself has, as such, no significance, becomes the self-like Ego, and rises to the truth and certainty of itself to self-consciousness. HEGEL. 348 The self-consciousness become universal, or as reason, now tra- verses also a series of development-steps, until it manifests itself as spirit, as the reason which, in accord with all rationality, and satisfied with the rational world without, extends itself over the natural and intellectual universe as its kingdom, in which it finds itself at home. Mind now passes through its stages of uncon- strained morality, culture and refinement, ethics and the ethical view of the world to religion ; and religion itself in its perfection, as revealed religion becomes absolute knowledge. At this last stage being and thought are no more separate, being is no longer an object for the thought, but the thought itself is the object of the thought. Science is nothing other than the true knowledge of the mind concerning itself. In the conclusion of the " Phe- nomenology,^^ Hegel casts the following retrospect on the course which he has laid down : " The goal which is to be reached, viz., absolute knowledge, or the mind knowing itself as mind, requires us to take notice of minds as they are in themselves, and the organization of their kingdom. These elements are preserved, and furnished to us either by history, where we look at the side of the mind's free existence as it accidentally appears, or by the science of phenomenal knowledge, where we look at the side of the mind's ideal organization. These two sources taken together, as the ideal history, give us the real history and the true being of the absolute spirit, the actuality, truth, and certainty of his throne, without which he were lifeless and alone ; only ' from the cup of this kingdom of minds does there stream forth for him his infinity.' " SECTION XLV. HEGEL. George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was born at Stuttgart, the 27th of August, 1770. In his eighteenth year he entered the university of Tubingen, in order to devote himself to the study 344 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. of theology. During his course of study here, he attracted no marked attention; Schelling, who was his junior in years, shone far beyond all his cotemporaries. After leaving Tubingen, he took a situation as private tutor, first in Switzerland, and after- wards in Frankfort-on-the-Main till 1801, when he settled down at Jena. At first he was regarded as a disciple, and defender of Schelling's philosophy, and as such he wrote in 1801 his first minor treatise on the " Difference hetiveen Fichte and Scliellingy Soon afterwards he became associated with Schelling in publish- ing the <' CriticalJournal of Philosophy,''^ 1802-8, for which he furnished a number of important articles. His labors as an aca- demical teacher met at first with but little encouragement ; he gave his first lecture to only four hearers. Yet in 1806 he became professor in the university, though the political catastro- phe in which the country was soon afterwards involved, deprived him again of the place. Amid the cannon's thunder of the battle of Jena, he finished " the Phenomenology of the Mindj'^ his first great and independent work, the crown of his Jena labors. He was subsequently in the habit of calling this book which appeared in 1807, his " voyage of discovery." From Jena, Hegel for want of the means of subsistence went to Bamberg, where for two years he was editor of a political journal published there. In the fall. of 1808, he became rector of the gymnasium at Nuremberg. In this situation he wrote his Logic, 1812-16. All his works were produced slowly, and he first properly began his literary ac- tivity as Schelling finished his. In 1816, he received a call to a professorship of philosophy at Heidelberg, where in 1817 he pub- lished his " Encyclopcedia of the philosophical sciences,^'' in which for the first time he showed the whole circuit of his system. But his peculiar fame, and his far-reaching activity, dates first from his call to Berlin in 1818. It was at Berlin that he surrounded himself with an extensive and very actively scientific school, and where through his connection with the Prussian government he gained a political influence and acquired a reputation for his phi- losophy, as the philosophy of the State, though this neither speaks favorably for its inner purity, nor its moral credit Yet in his HEGEL. 345 '^Philosophy of Bights,^^ whicli appeared in 1821 (a time, to be Bure, when the Prussian State had not yet shown any decidedly anti-constitutional tendency), Hegel does not deny the political demands of the present age ; he declares in favor of popular re presentation, freedom of the press, and publicity of judicial pro ceedings, trial by jury, and an administrative independence of corporations. In Berlin, Hegel gave lectures upon almost every branch of philosophy, and these have been published by his disciples and friends after his death. His manner as a lecturer was stammer- ing, clumsy, and unadorned, but was still not without a peculiar attraction as the immediate expression of profound thoughtfulness. His social intercourse was more with the uncultivated than with the learned ; he was not fond of shining as a genius in social cir- cles. In 1829 he became rector of the university, an office which he administered in a more practical manner than Fichte had done. Hegel died with the cholera, Nov. 14th, 1831, the day also of Leibnitz's death. He rests in the same churchyard with Solger and Fichte, near by the latter, and not far from the former. His writings and lectures form seventeen volumes which have ap- peared since 1832: Vol. I. Minor Articles; II. Phenomenology; III-Y. Logic; YL-YII. Encyclopedia; VIII. Philosphy of Rights; IX. Philosophy of History; X. Esthetics; XI.-XIL Phi- losophy of Religion ; XIII.-XY. History of Philosophy ; XYI- XYII. Miscellanies. His life has been written by Rosenkranz. Hegel's system may be divided in a number of ways. The best mode is by connecting it with Schelling. Schellings's abso- lute was the identity or the indifference point of the ideal and the real. From this Hegel's threefold division immediately follows. (1) The exposition of the indifference point, the development of the pure conceptions or determinations in thought, which lie at the basis of all natural and intellectual life; in other words, the logi- cal unfolding of the absolute, — the science of logic. (2) The development of the real world or of nature — natural philosophy. (3) The development of the ideal world, or of mind as it shows itself concretely in right, morals, the state, art, religion, and 15* 346 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. science. — Philosophy of Mind. These three parts of the system represent the three elements of the absolute method, thesis, anti- thesis, synthesis. The absolute is at first pure, and immaterial thought ; secondly, it is differentiation (Andersseyn) of the pure thought or its diremption(verzerrw?2<7) in space and time — nature ; thirdly, it returns from this self-estrangement to itself, destroys the differentiation of nature, and thus becomes actual self-know- ing thought or mind. I. Science of Logic. — The Hegelian logic is the scientific exposition and development of the pure conceptions of reason, those conceptions or categories which lie at the basis of all thought and being, and which determine the subjective knowledge as truly as they form the indwelling soul of the objective reality; in a word, those ideas in which the ideal and the real have their point of coincidence. The domain of logic, says Hegel, is the truth, as it is -per se in its native character. It is as Hegel him- self figuratively expresses it, the representation of Grod as he is in his eternal being, before the creation of the world or a finite mind. In this respect it is, to be sure, a domain of shad- ows ; but these shadows are, on the other hand, those simple essences freed from all sensuous matters, in whose diamond net the whole universe is constructed. Different philosophers had already made a thankworthy be- ginning towards collecting and examining the pure conceptions of the reason, as Aristotle in his categories, Wolff in his ontology, and Kant in his transcendental analytics. But they had neither completely collected, nor critically sifted, nor (Kant excepted) derived them from one principle, but had only taken them up em- pirically, and treated them lexicologically. But in opposition to this course, Hegel attempted, (1) to completely collect the pure art-conceptions ; (2) to critically sift them (^. e. to exclude every thing but pure thought) ; and (3) — which is the most character- istic peculiarity of the Hegelian logic — to derive these dialecti- cally from one another, and carry them out to an internally con- nected system of pure reason. Hegel starts with the view, that in every conception of the reason, every other is contained impH- HEGEL. 347 citey and may be dialectically developed from it. Fichte had al- ready claimed that the reason must deduce the whole system of knowledge purely from itself, without any thing taken for granted ; that some principle must he sought which should be of itself cer- tain, and need no farther proof, and from which every thing else could be derived. Hegel holds fast to this thought. Starting from the simplest conception of reason, that of pure being, which needs no farther establishing, he seeks from this, by advancing from one conception ever to another and a richer one, to deduce the whole system of the pure knowledge of reason. The lever of this development is the dialectical method. Hegel's dialectical method is partly taken from Plato, and partly from Fichte. The conception of negation is Platonic. All negation, says Hegel, is position, ajQ&rmation. If a conception is negated, the result is not the pure nothing — a pure negative, but a concrete positive ; there results a new conception which extends around the negation of the preceding one. The negation of the one e. g. is the conception of the many. In this way Hegel makes nega- tion a vehicle for dialectical progress. Every pre-supposed concep- tion is denied, and from its negation a higher and richer conception is gained. This is connected with the method of Fichte, which posits a fundamental synthesis ; and by analyzing this, seeks its antitheses, and then unites again these antitheses through a second synthesis, — e. g, being, nothing, becoming, quality, quantity, measure, &c. This method, which is at the same time analytical and synthetical, Hegel has carried through the whole system of science. We now proceed to a brief survey of the Hegelian Logic. It is divided into three parts ; the doctrine of heing^ the doctrine of essence^ and the doctrine of conception. 1. The Doctrine OF Being. (1.) Quality. --^oiencQhegmsYfiih. the immediate and indeterminate conception of being. This, in its want of content and emptiness, is nothing more than a pure negation, a nothing. These two conceptions are thus as absolutely identical as they are absolutely opposed; each of the two disappears immediate- ly in its contrary. This oscillation of the two is the pure becoming^ 348 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. which, if it be a transition from nothing to being, we call arising. or, in the reverse case, we call it a departing. The still and sim- ple precipitate of this process of arising and departing, is exist- ence (Daseyn). Existence is being with a determinateness, or it is quality ; more closely, it is reality or limited existence. Lim- ited existence excludes every other from itself. This reference to itself, which is seen through its negative relation to every other, we call being per se {FdrsicTiseyn). Being per se which refers itself only to itself, and repels every other from itself, is the one. But, by means of this repelling, the one posits immediately many ones. But the many ones are not distinguished from each other. One is what the other is. The many are therefore one. But the one is just as truly the manifold. For its exclusion is the posit- ing of its contrary, or it posits itself thereby as manifold. By this dialectic of attraction and repulsion, quality passes over into quantity : for indifference in respect of distinction or qualitative determinateness is quantity. (2. ) Quantity. — Quantity is determination of greatness, which, as such, is indifferent in respect of quality. In so far as the greatness contains many ones distinguishably within itself, it is a discrete, or has the element of discretion ; but on the other hand, in so far as the many ones are similar, and the greatness is thus indistinguishable, it is continuous, or has the element of con- tinuity. Each of these two determinations is at the same time identical with the other ; discretion cannot be conceived without continuity, nor continuity without discretion. The existence of quantity, or the limited quantity, is the quantum. The quan- tum has also manifoldness and unity in itself ;. it is the enumera- tion of the unities, i.. e. number. Corresponding to the quantum **' or the extensive greatness, is the intensive greatness or the degree. With the conception of degree, so far as degree is simple deter- minateness, quantity approaches quality again. The unity of quantity and quality is the measure. (3.) The measure is a qualitative quantum, a quantum on which the quality is dependent. An example of quantity deter- mining the quality of a definite object is found in the temperature HEGEL. 349 of water, which decides whether the water shall remain water or turn to ice or steam. Here the quantum of heat actually consti- tutes the quality of the water. Quality and quantity are, there- fore, ideal determinations, perpetually turning around on one being, on a third, which is distinguished from the immediate what and how much (quality and quantity) of a thing. This third is the essence, which is the negation of every thing immediate, or quality independent of the immediate being. Essence is being in se, being divided in itself, a self-separation of being. Hence the twofoldness of all determinations of essence. 2. The Doctrine of Essence. (1.) The Essence as such. The essence as reflected being is the reference to itself only as it is a reference to something other. We apply to this being the term reflected analogously with the reflection of light, which, when it falls on a mirror, is thrown back by it. As now the reflected light is, through its reference to another object, something mediated or posited, so the reflected being is that which is shown to be mediat- ed or grounded through another. From the fact that philosophy makes its problem to know the essence of things, the immediate being of things is represented as a covering or curtain behind which the essence is concealed. If, therefore, we speak of the essence of an object, the immediate being standing over against the essence (for without this the essence cannot be conceived), is set down to a mere negative, to an appearance. The being ap- pears in the essence. The essence is, therefore, the being as appearance in itself. The essence when conceived in distinction from the appearance, gives the conception of the essential, and that which only appears in the essence, is the essenceless, or the unessential. But since the essential has a being only in distinc- tion from the unessential, it follows that the latter is essential to the former, which needs its unessential just as much as the unes- sential needs it. Each of the two, therefore, appears in the other, or there takes place between them a reciprocal reference which we call reflection. We have, therefore, to do in this whole sphere with determinations of reflection, with determinations, each one of which refers to the other, and cannot be conceived without it 350 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHT. ^ (e. g. positive and negative, ground and sequence, thing and pro- perties, content and form, power and expression). We have, therefore, in the development of the essence, those same deter- minations which we found in the development of being, only no longer in an immediate, but in a reflected form. Instead of being and nothing, we have now the forms of the positive and negative ; instead of the there-existent {Daseyn), we now have existence. Essence is reflected being, a reference to itself, which, how- ever, is mediated through a reference to something other which appears in it. This reflected reference to itself we call identity (which is unsatisfactorily and abstractly expressed in the so-called first principle of thought, that A=A). This identity, as a nega- tivity referring itself to itself, as a repulsion of its own from Itself, contains essentially the determination of distinction. The imme- diate and external distinction is the difference. The essential dis- tinction, the distinction in itself, is the antithesis {positive and negative). The self-opposition of the essence is the contradiction. The antithesis of identity and distinction is put in agreement in the conception of the ground. Since now the essence distinguishes itself from itself, there is the essence as identical with itself or the ground^ and the essence as distinguished from itself or the sequence. In the category of ground and sequence the same thing, i. e. the essence, is twice posited ; the grounded and the ground are one and the same content, which makes it difficult to define the ground except through the sequence, or the sequence except through the ground. The two can, therefore, be divided only by a powerful abstraction ; but because the two are identi- cal, it is peculiarly a formalism to apply this category. If reflec- tion would inquire after a ground, it is because it would see the thing as it were in a twofold relation, once in its immediateness, and then as posited through a ground. (2.) Essence and Phenomenon. — The phenomenon is the ap- pearance which the essence fills, and which is hence no longer essenceless. There is no appearance without essence, and no essence which may not enter into phenomenon. It is one and the same content which at one time is taken as essence, and at another HEGEL. 351 as phenomenon. In the phenomenal essence we recognize the positive element which has hitherto been called ground, but which we now name content, and the negative element which we call the form. Every essence is a unity of content and form, i. e. it exists. In distinction from immediate being, we call that being which has proceeded from some ground, existence, i. e. grounded being. When we view the essence as existing, we call it thing. In the relation of a thing to its properties we have a repetition of the re- lation of form and content. The properties show us the thing in respect of its form, but it is thing in respect of its content. The reflation between the thing and its properties is commonly indica- ted by the verb to have (e. g. the thing has properties), in order to distinguish between the two. The essence as a negative refer- ence to itself, and as repelling itself from itself in order to a reflection in an alterum, is power and expression. In this category, like all the other categories of essence, one and the same content is posited twice. The power can only be explained from the ex- pression, and the expression only from the power ; consequently every explanation of which this category avails itself, is tautolo- gical. To regard power as uncognizable, is only a self-deception of the understanding respecting its own doing. — A higher expres- sion for the category of power and expression is the category of inner and outer. The latter category stands higher than the former, because power needs some solicitation to express itself, but the inner is the essence spontaneously manifesting itself. Both of these, the inner and the outer, are also identical ; neither is without the other. That, e. g. which the man is internally in respect of his character, is he also externally in his action. The truth of this relation will be, therefore, the identity of inner and outer, of essence and phenomenon, viz. : (3.) Actuality. — Actuality must be added as a third to being and existence. In the actuality, the phenomenon is a complete and adequate manifestation of the essence. The true actuality is, therefore (in opposition to possibility and contingency), a necessary being, a rational necessity. The well-known Hegelian sentence that every thing is rational, and every thing rational is 352 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. actual, is seen in this apprehension of " actuality " to be a simple tautology. The necessary, when posited as its own ground, iden- tical with itself, is substance. The phenomenal side, the unessen- tial in the substance, and the contingent in the necessary, are acci- deuces. These are no longer related to the substance, as the phenomenon to the essence, or the outer to the inner, i. e. as an adequate manifestation ; they are only transitory affections of the substance, accidentally changing phenomenal forms, like sea waves on the water of the sea. They are not produced by the substance, but are rather destroyed in it. The relation of substance leads to the relation of cause. In the relation of cause there is one and the same thing posited on the one side as cause, and on the other side as effect. The cause of warmth is warmth, and its effect is again warmth. The effect is a higher conception than the acci- dence, since it actually stands over against the cause, and the cause itself passes over into effect. So far, however, as each side in the relation of cause presupposes the other, we shall find the true relation one in which each side is at the same time cause and effect, i. e. reciprocal action. Reciprocal action is a higher relation than causality, because these is no pure causality. There is no effect without counteraction. "We leave the province of essence with the category of reciprocal action. All the categories of essence had shown themselves as a duplex of two sides, but when we come to the category of reciprocal action, the opposition be- tween cause and effect is destroyed, and they meet together ; unity thus takes again the place of duplicity. We have, therefore, again a being which coincides with mediate being. This unity of being and essence, this inner or realized necessity, is the conception. 8. The Doctrine of the Coxceptiox. — A conception is a rational necessity. We can only have a conception of that whose true necessity we have recognized. The conception is, therefore, the truly actual, the peculiar essence ; because it states as well that which is actual as that which should be. (1.) The subjective conception contains the elements of uni- versality (the conception of species), particularity (ground of classification, logical difference), and individuality (species — logi- HEGEL. 353 cal difference). The conception is therefore a unity of that which is distinct. The self-separation of the conception is the judgment. In the judgment, the conception appears as self-excluding dual- ity. The twofoldness is seen in the difiference between subject and predicate, and the unity in the copula. Progress in the dif- ferent forms of judgment, consists in this, viz., that the copula fills itself more and more with the conception. But thus the judgment passes over into the conclusion or inference, i. e. to the conception which is identical with itself through the conception. In the inference one conception is concluded with a third through a second. The different figures of the conclusion are the differ- erent steps in the self-mediation of the conception. The concep- tion is when it mediates itself with itself and the conclusion is no longer subjective ; it is no longer my act, but an objective rela- tion is fulfilled in it. (2.) Ohjectivity is a reality only of the conception. The ob- jective conception has* three steps, — Mechanism^ or the indifferent relation of objects to each other ; Chemism, or the interpenetra- tion of objects and their neutralization ; Teleology, or the inner design of objects. The end accomplishing itself or the self-end is, (8.) The idea. — The idea is the highest logical definition of the absolute. The immediate existence of the idea, we call life, or process of life. Every thing living is self-end immanent-end. The idea posited in its difference as a relation of objective and subjective, is the true and good. The true is the objective ration- ality subjectively posited; the good is the subjective rationality carried into the objectivity. Both conceptions together consti- tute the absolute idea, which is just as truly as it should be, i. e. the good is just as truly actualized as the true is living and self-realizing. The absolute and full idea is in space, because it discharges itself from itself, as its reflection ; this its being in space is Nature. II. The Science op Nature. — Nature is the idea in the form of differentiation. It is the idea externalizing itself; it is the mind estranged from itself. The unity of the conception 354 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. is therefore concealed in nature, and since philosopliy makes it ita problem to seek out the intelligence which is hidden in nature, and to pursue the process by which nature loses its own charac- ter and becomes mind, it should not forget that the essence of nature consists in being which has externalized itself, and that the products of nature neither have a reference to themselves, nor correspond to the conception, but grow up in unrestrained and unbridled contingency. Nature is a bacchanalian god who nei- ther bridles nor checks himself. It therefore represents no ideal succession, rising ever in regular order, but, on the contrary, it every where obliterates all essential limits by its doubtful struc- tures, which always defy every fixed classification. Because it is impossible to throw the determinations of the conception over nature, natural philosophy is forced at every point, as it were, to capitulate between the world of concrete individual structures, and the regulative of the speculative idea. Natural philosophy has its beginning, its course, and its end. It begins with the first or immediate determination of nature, with the abstract universality of its being extra se, space and matter ; its end is the dissevering of the mind from nature in the form of a rational and self-conscious individuality — man ; the problem which it has to solve is, to show the intermediate link between these two extremes, and to follow out successively the in- creasingly successful struggles of nature to raise itself to self-con- sciousness, to man. In this process, nature passes through three principal stages. 1. Mechanics, or matter and an ideal system of matter. Mat- ter is the being extra se [AussersicTiseyn) of nature, in its most universal form. Yet it shows at the outset that tendency to being per se which forms the guiding thread of natural philos- ophy — gravity. Gravity is the being in se (Insichseyn) of mat- ter ; it is the desire of matter to come to itself, and shows the first trace of subjectivity. The centre of gravity of a body is the one which it seeks. This same tendency of bringing all the manifold unto being jper se lies at the basis of the solar system and of uni- versal gravitation. The centrality which is the fundamental con- HEGEL. 355 ception of gravity, becomes here a system, whicli is in fact a rational system so far as the form of the orbit, the rapidity of motion, or the time of revolution may be referred to mathematical laws. 2. Physics. — But matter possesses no individuality. Even in astronomy it is not the bodies themselves, but only their geo- metrical relations which interest us. We have here at the outset to treat of quantitative and not yet of qualitative determinations. Yet in the solar system, matter has found its centre, itself. Its abstract and hollow being in se has resolved itself into form. Matter now, as possessing a quality, is an object of physics. In physics we have to do with matter which has particularized itself in a body, in an individuality. To this province belongs inor- ganic nature, its forms and reciprocal references. 3. Organics. — Inorganic nature, which was the object of phys- ics, destroys itself in the chemical process. In the chemical pro- cess, the inorganic body loses all its properties (cohesion, color, shining, sound, transparency, &c.), and thus shows the evanes- cence of its existence and that relativity which is its being. This chemical process is overcome by the organic, the living process of nature. True, the living body is ever on the point of passing over to the chemical process ; oxygen, hydrogen and salt, are always entering into a living organism, but their chemical action is always overcome ; the living body resists the chemical process till it dies. Life is self-preservation, self-end. While therefore nature in physics had risen to individuality, in organics, it pro- gresses to subjectivity. The idea, as life, represents itself in three stages. (1.) The general image of life in geological organism, or tho mineral kingdom. Yet the mineral kingdom is the result, and the residuum of a process of life and formation already passed. The primitive rock is the stiffened crystal of life, and the geologi- cal earth is a giant corpse. The present life which produces itself eternally anew, breaks forth as the first moving of subjectivity, (2.) In the organism ofj)lants or the vegetable kingdom. The plant rises indeed to a formative process, to a process of assimila- 356 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. tion, and to a process of species. But it is not yet a totality per' ^ fectly organized in itself. Each part of the plant is the whole in- dividual, each twig is the whole tree. The parts are related in- differently to each other ; the crown can become a root, and the root a crown. The plant, therefore, does not yet attain a true being in se of individuality ; for, in order that this may be attained, an absolute unity of the individual is necessary. This unity, which constitutes an individual and concrete subjectivity, is first seen in (8.) The animal organism, the animal kingdom. An unin- terrupted intus-susception, free motion and sensation, are first found in the animal organism. In its higher forms we find an inner warmth and a voice. In its highest form, man, nature, or rather the spirit, which works through nature, apprehends itself as conscious individuality, as Ego. The spirit thus become a free and rational self, has now completed its self-emancipation from nature. III. Philosophy of Mind. — 1. The Subjective Mind. — The mind \s> the truth of nature ; it is being removed from its estrangement, and become identical with itself. Its formal es- sence, therefore, is freedom, the possibility of abstracting itself from every thing else ; its material essence is the capacity of manifesting itself as mind, as a conscious rationality, — of positing the intellectual universe as its kingdom, and of building a struc- ture of objective rationality. In order, however, to know itself, and every thing rational, — in order to posit nature more and more negatively, the mind, like nature, must pass through a series of stages or emancipative acts. As it comes from nature and rises from its externality to being, per se, it is at first soul or spirit of nature, and as such, it is an object of anthropology in a strict sense. As this spirit of nature, it sympathizes with the general planetary life of the earth, and is in this respect subject to diver- sity of climate, and change of seasons and days ; it sympathizes with the geographical portion of the world which it occupies, i. e., it is related to a diversity of race ; still farther, it bears a na- tional type, and is moreover determined by mode of life, forma- tion of the body, &c., while these natural conditions work also HEGEL. 357 upon its intelligent and moral character. Lastly, we must here take notice of the way in which nature has determined the indi- vidual subject, i. e. his natural temperament, character, idiosyn- crasy, &c. To this belong the natural changes of life, age, sex- ual relation, sleep, aod waking. In all this the mind is still buried in nature, and this middle condition between being ^er se and the sleep of nature, is sensation, the hollow forming of the mind in its unconscious and unenlightened (verstandlos) individ- uality. A higher stage of sensation is feeling, i. e. sensation in se, where being per se appears ; feeling in its completed form is self- feeling. Since the subject, in self-feeling, is buried in the pecu- liarity of his sensations, but at the same time concludes himself with himself, as a subjective one, the self-feeling is seen to be the preliminary step to consciousness. The Ego now appears as the shaft in which all these sensations, representations, cognitions and thoughts are preserved, which is with them all, and constitutes the centre in which they all come together. The mind as con- scious, as a conscious being per se, as Ego, is the object of the phenomenology of consciousness. The mind was individual, so long as it was interwoven with nature ; it is consciousness or Ego when it has divested itself of nature. When distinguishing itself from nature, the mind with- draws itself into itself, and that with which it was formerly inter- woven, and which gave it a peculiar (earthly, national, &c.) de- termination, stands now distinct from it, as its external world (earth, people, &c). The awaking of the Ego is thus the act by which the objective world, as such, is created ; while on the other hand, the Ego awakens to a conscious subjectivity only in the ob- jective world, and in distinction from it. The Ego, over against the objective world, is consciousness in the strict sense of the word. Consciousness becomes self-consciousness by passing through the stages of immediate sensuous consciousness, percep- tion, and understanding, and convincing itself in this its formative history, that it has only to do with itself, while it believed that it had to do with something objective. Again, self-consciousness becomes universal or rational self-consciousness, as follows : In 368 A mSTORY OP PHILOSOPHY. its strivings to stamp the impress of the Ego upon the objective^ and thus make the objective subjective, it falls in conflict with other self-consciousnesses, and begins a war of extermination against them, but rises from this helium omnium contra omnes, as common consciousness, as the finding of the proper mean between command and obedience, i. e. as truly universal, i. e. rational self consciousness. The rational self-consciousness is actually free because, when related to another, it is really related to itself, and in all is still with itself ; it has emancipated itself from nature. We have now mind as mind, divested of its naturalness and sub- jectivity, and as such, it is an object of Pneumatology. Mind is at first theoretical mind, or intelligence, and then practical mind, or will. It is theoretical in that it has to do with the rational as something given, and now posits it as its own ; it is practical in that it immediately wills the subjective content (truth), which it has as its own, to be freed from its one-sided subjective form, and transformed into an objective. The practi- cal mind is, so far, the truth of the theoretical. The theoretical mind, in its way to the practical, passes through the stages of in- tuition, representation, and thought ; and the will on its side forms itself into a free will through impulse, desire, and inclina- tion. The free will, as having a being in space {Daseyn), is the objective mind, right, and the state. In right, morals and the state, the freedom and rationality, which are chosen by the will, take on an objective form. Every natural determination and im- pulse now becomes moralized, and comes up to view again as ethi- cal institute, as right and duty (the sexual impulse now appears as marriage, and the impulse of revenge as civil punishment, &c.) 2. The Objective Mind. — (1.) The immediate objective being (Daseyn) of the free will is the right. The individual, so far as he is capable of rights, so far as he has rights and exercises them, is a person. The maxim of right is, therefore, be a person and have respect to other persons. The person allows himself an ex- ternal sphere for his freedom, a substratum in which he can exer- cise his will : as property, possession. As person I have the right of possession, the absolute right of appropriation, the right to cast HEGEL. 359 my will over every thing, which thereby becomes mine. But there exist other persons besides myself. My right is, therefore, limited through the right of others. There thus arises a conflict between will and will, which is settled in a compact, in a common will. The relation of compact is the first step towards the state, but only the ^^rs^ step, for if we should define the state as a com- pact of all with all, this would sink it in the category of private rights and private property. It does not depend upon the will of the individual whether he will live in the state or not. The relation of compact refers to private property. In a compact, therefore, two wills merge themselves in a common will, which as such becomes a right. But just here lies also the possibility of a conflict between the individual will and the right or the universal will. The separation of the two is a wrong (civil wrong, fraud, crime). This separation demands a reconciliation, a restoration of the right or the universal will from its momentary suppression or negation by the particular will. The right restoring itself in respect of the particular will, and establishing a negation of the wrong, is punishment. Those theories, which found the right of punishment in some end of warning or improvement, mistake the essence of punishment. Threatening, warning, &c., are finite ends, i. e. means, and moreover uncertain means : but an act of righteousness should not be made a means ; righteousness is not exercised in order that any thing other than itself shall be gained. The fulfilment and self-manifestation of righteousness is absolute end, self-end. The particular views we have mentioned, can only be considered in reference to the mode of punishment. The pun- ishment which is inflicted on a criminal, is his right, his ration- ality, his law, beneath which he should be subsumed. His act comes back upon himself. Hegel also defends capital punishment whose abolition seemed to him as an untimely sentimentalism. (2.) The removal of the opposition of the universal and par- ticular will in the subject constitutes morality. In morality the freedom of the will is carried forward to a self-determination of the subjectivity, and the abstract right becomes duty and virtue. The moral standpoint is the standpoint of conscience, it is the 360 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. right of the subjective will, the right of a free ethical decision. In the consideration of strict right, it is no inquiry what my prin- ciple or my view might be, but in morality the question is at once directed towards the purpose and moving spring of the will. Hegel calls this standpoint of moral reflection and dutiful action for a reason — morality, in distinction from a substantial, uncondi- tioned and unreflecting ethics. This standpoint has three ele- ments; (1) the element of resolution {vorsatz), where we consider the inner determination of the acting subject, that which allows an act to be ascribed only to me, and the blame of it to rest only on my will (imputation) ; (2) the element of purpose, where the completed act is regarded not according to its consequences, but according to its relative worth in reference to myself. The reso- lution was still internal ; but now the act is completed, and I must suffer myself to judge according to the constituents of the act, be- cause I must have known the circumstances under which I acted ; (8) the element of the good, where the act is judged according to its universal worth. The good is peculiarly the reconciliation of the particular subjective will with the universal will, or with the conception of the will ; in other words, to will the rational is good. Opposed to this is evil, or the elevation of the subjective will against the universal, the attempt to set up the peculiar and indi- vidual choice as absolute ; in other words, to will the irrational is evil. (3.) In morality we had conscience and the abstract good (the good which ought to be) standing over against each other. The concrete identity of the two, the union of subjective and objective good, is ethics. In the ethical the good has become actualized in an existing world, and a nature of self-consciousness. The ethical mind is seen at first immediately, or in a natural form, as marriage and the family. Three elements meet together in marriage, which should not be separated, and which are so often and so wrongly isolated. Marriage is (1) a sexual relation, and is founded upon a difference of sex ; it is, therefore, something other than Platonic love or monkish asceticism ; (2) it is a civil con- tract ; (3) it is love. Yet Hegel lays no great stress upon this HEGEL. 361 subjective element in concluding upon marriage, for a reciprocal affection will spring up in tlie married life. It is more ethical when a determination to marry is first, and a definite personal affection follows afterwards, for marriage is most prominently duty Hegel would, therefore, place the greatest obstacles in the way of a dissolution of marriage. He has also developed and described in other respects the family state with a profound ethical feeling. Since the family becomes separated into a multitude of fami- lies, it is a civil society, in which the members, though still inde- pendent individuals, are bound in unity by their wants, by the constitution of rights as a means of security for person and pro- perty, and by an outward administrative arrangement. Hegel distinguished the civil society from the state in opposition to most modern theorists upon the subject, who, regarding it as the great end of the state to give security of property and of personal free- dom, reduced' the state to a civil society. But on such a stand- point which would make the state wholly of wants and of rights, it is impossible, e. g. to conceive of war. On the ground of civil society each one stands for himself, is independent, and makes himself as end, while every thing else is a means for him. But the state, on the contrary, knows no independent individuals, each one of whom may regard and pursue only his own well-being ; but in the state, the whole is the end, and the individual is the means. — For the administration of justice, Hegel, in opposition to those of our time who deny the right of legislation, would have written and intelligible laws, which should be within reach of every one ; still farther, justice should be administered by a public trial by jury. — In respect of the organization of civil society, Hegel ex- presses a great preference for a corporation. Sanctity of mar- riage, he says, and honor in corporations, are the two elements around which the disorganization of civil society ttlTns. Civil society passes over into the state since the interest of the mdividual loses itself in the idea of an ethical whole. The state ts the ethical idea actualized, it is the ethical mind as it rules over the action and knowledge of the individuals conceived in it. Finally the states themselves, since they appear as individuals in 16 362 A HISTORY OP PHILOSOPHr. an attracting or repelling relation to each other; represent, in their destiny, in their rise and fall, the process of the iuorld''s history. In his apprehension of the state, Hegel approached very near the ancient notion, which merged the individual and the right of individuality, wholly in the will of the state. He held fast to the omnipotence of the state in the ancient sense. Hence his resist- ance to modern liberalism, which would allow individuals to pos- tulate, to criticize, and to will according to their improved knowl- edge. The state is with Hegel the rational and ethical substance in which the individual has to live, it is the existing reason to which the individual has to submit himself with a free view. He regarded a limited monarchy as the best form of government, after the manner of the English constitution, to which Hegel was especially inclined, and in reference to which he uttered his well- known saying that the king was but the dot upon the i. There must be an individual, Hegel supposes, who can affirm for the state, who can prefix an " I will " to the resolves of the state, and who can be the head of a formal decision. The personality of a state, he says, " is only actual as a person, as monarch." Hence Hegel defends hereditary monarchy, but he places the nobility by its side as a mediating element between people and prince — not indeed to control or limit the government, nor to maintain the rights of the people, but only that the people may experience that there is a good rule, that the consciousness of the people may be with the government and that the state may enter into the sub- jective consciousness of the people. States and the minds of individual races pour their currents into the stream of the world's history. The strife, the victory, and the subjection of the spirits of individual races, and the pass- ing over of the world spirit from one people to another, is the con- tent of the world's history. The development of the world's his- tory is generally connected with some ruling race, which carries in itself the world spirit in its present stage of development, and in distinction from which the spirits of other races have no rights. Thus these race-spirits stand around the throne of the absolute HEGEL. 363 spirit, as the executors of its actualization, as the witnesses and adornment of its glory. 3. The Absolute Mind. — (1.) JEsihetics. The absolute mind is immediately present to the sensuous intuition as the beautiful or as art. The beautiful is the appearance of the idea through a sensible medium (a crystal, color, tone, poetry) ; it is the idea actualized in the form of a limited phenomenon. To the beautiful (and to its subordinate kinds, the simply beautiful, the sublime, and the comical) two factors always belong, thought and matter ; but both these are inseparable from each other ; the matter is the outer phenomenon of the thought, and should express nothing but the thought which inspires it and shines through it. The different ways in which matter and form are connected, furnish the differ- ent forms of art. In the symbolic form of art the matter prepon- derates ; the thought presses through it, and brings out the ideal only with difficulty. In the classic form of art, the ideal has at- tained its adequate existence in the matter ; content and form are absolutely befitting each other. Lastly, in romantic art, the mind preponderates, and the matter is a mere appearance and sign through which the mind every where breaks out, and struggles up above the material. The system of particular arts is connected with the different forms of art ; but the distinction of one par- ticular art from another, depends especially upon the difference of the material. (a.) The beginning of art is Architecture. It belongs essen- tially to the symbolic form of art, since in it the sensible matter far preponderates, and it first seeks the true conformity between content and form. Its material is stone, which it fashions ac- cording to the laws of gravity. Hence it has the character of magnitude, of silent earnestness, of oriental sublimity. (6.) Sculpture. — The material of this art is also stone, but it advances from the inorganic to the organic. It gives the stone a bodily form, and makes it only a serving vehicle of the thought. In sculpture, the material, the stone, since it represents the body, that building of the soul, in its clearness and beauty, disappears 364 A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. wholly in the ideal ; there is nothing left of the material which does not serve the idea. (c.) Fainting. — This is pre-eminently a romantic art. It represents, as sculpture cannot do, the life of the soul, the look, the disposition, the heart. Its medium is no longer a coarse material substratum, hut the colored surface, and the soul-like play of light ; it gives the appearance only of complete spacial dimen- sion. Hence it is able to represent in a complete dramatic movement the whole scale of feelings, conditions of heart, and actions. {d.) Music. — This leaves out all relation of space. Its mate- rial is sound, the vibration of a sonorous body. It leaves, there- fore, the field of sensuous intuition, and works exclusively upon the sensation. Its basis is the breast of the sensitive soul. Music is the most subjective art. {e.) Lastly in Poetry, or the speaking art, is the tongue of art loosed ; poetry can represent every thing. Its material is not the mere sound, but the sound as word, as the sign of a representa- tion, as the expression of reason. But this material cannot be formed at random, but only in verse according to certain rhythmi- cal and musical laws. In poetry, all other arts return again ; as epic, representing in a pleasing and extended narrative the figura- tive history of races, it corresponds to the plastic arts ; as lyric, expressing some inner condition of soul, it corresponds to music ; as dramatic poetry, exhibiting the struggles between characters acting out of directly opposite interests, it is the union of both these arts. (2.) Philosophy of Religion. — Poetry forms the transition from art to religion. In art the idea was present for the intui- tion, in religion it is present for the representation. The content of every religion is the reconciliation of the finite with the infi- nite, of the subject with God. All religions seek a union of the divine and the human. This was done in the crudest form by (a.) The natural religions of the oriental world. God is, with them, but a power of nature, a substance of nature, in comparison with which the finite and the individual disappear as nothing. HEGEL. 365 (5.) A higher idea of God is attained by the religions of spir- itual individuality, in which the divine is looked upon as subject, — ■ as an exalted subjectivity, full of power and wisdom in Judaism, the religion of sublimity ; as a circle of plastic divine forms in the Grecian religion, the religion of beauty ; as an absolute end of the state in the Roman religion, the religion of the understand- ing or of design. (c.) The revealed or Christian religion first establishes a posi- tive reconciliation between God and the world, by beholding the actual unity of the divine and the human in the person of Christ, the God-man, and apprehending God as triune, i. e. as Himself, as incarnate, and as returning from this incarnation to Himself. The intellectual content of revealed religion, or of Christianity, is thus the same as that of speculative philosophy; the only difference being, that in the one case the content is represented in the form of the representation, in the form of a history ; while, in the other, it appears in the form of the conception. Stripped of its form of religious representation, we have now the standpoint of (3.) The Absolute Philosophy, or the thought knowing itself as all truth, and reproducing the whole natural and intellectual universe from itself, having the system of philosophy for its de- velopment — a closed circle of circles. With Hegel closes the history of philosophy. The philosophi- cal developments which have succeeded him, and which are part- ly a carrying out of his system, and partly the attempt to lay a new basis for philosophy, belong to the present, and not yet to history. THE END. D. APPLET ON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. ENGLISH LANGUAGE Hand-Book of tlie English Language. By G. R. Latham, M.D., F.R.S. 12mo, 398 pages. The ethnological relations of the English Language, its history and ana- lysis, its spelUng and pronunciation, etymology and syntax, are here treated with a completeness, learning, and grasp of intellect, that will be vainly sought elsewhere. The elements of our tongue, the successive changes by which it has been modified, the origin of its pecuUar expressions, and other subjects of like importance and interest, receive due attention of the author, who ranks among the most accomplished scholars of England. Whether for private study, or as a manual for college and high-school classes. Dr. Latham's Hand-Book will be found one of the most useful works extant in the depart- ment of belles-lettres. Graham^s English Synonymes, Classified and explained ; with practical exercises, designed for schools and private tuition ; with an introduction and illustrative authorities. By Henry Reed, LL.D. 12mo, 344 pages. This treatise is intended to teach the right use of words. It explains the principal synonymes of the language, classified and arranged in pairs, and illustrates their use at different eras with passages from Shakespeare, Milton, and Wordsworth. Exercises are appended, which require the pupil to fill blanks by the insertion of the words compared, selecting in each case the one that is adapted to the context. Thus practically impressed on the pupil's mind, their distinctive meanings will not soon be forgotten. The attention of teachers is particularly invited to this v/ork, as one of the most useful that can be found for imparting a thorough acquaintance with our tongue. Besides teaching the student how to avoid common inaccu- racies of expression, and training him to that precision which is essential to a good style, it wiU be found highly -serviceable in disciplining his mind by accustommg it to a critical appreciation of nice distmctions. Wherever it has been introduced into academic or coUegiate institutions, it has awakened great interest in the study of words, and proved a valuable auxiUary te ■ curses of grammar and rhetoric. B. APPLETON c£- CO:S PUBLICATIONS. History of English Literature. By WILLIAM SPALDING, A.M., Professor of Logic, Rhetoric, and Metaphysics, in the University of St. Andrews. 12mo, 413 pages. The above work is ofifered as a Text-book for the use of advanced Schools and Academies. It traces the literary progress of the nation from Anglo- Saxon times to the present day, and furnishes a comprehensive outline of the origin and growth of our language. Those literary monuments of early date which are thought most worthy of attention, are described with con- siderable fulness and in an attractive manner. Constant effort is made to arouse reflection, both by occasional remarks on the relations between in- tellectual culture and the world of reality and action, and by hints as to the laws on which criticism is founded. The characteristics of the most cele- brated modern works are analyzed at length. The style of the author is remarkably clear and interesting, compelling the reader to linger over his pages with unwearied attention. Manual of Grecian and Roman Antiquities. By Dr. E. F. BOJESEN, with Notes and Questions by Rev. THOMAS K. ARNOLD. 12mo, 209 pages. The present Manuals of Greek and Roman Antiquities are far superior to any thing on the same topics as yet offered to the American public. A leading Review of Germany says of the Roman Manual : — " Small as the compass of it is, we may confidently affirm that it is a great improvement on all preceding works of the kind. We no longer meet with the wretched old method, in which subjects essentially distinct are herded together, and connected subjects disconnected, but have a simple, systematic arrangement, by which the reader readily receives a clear representation of Roman life. We no longer stumble against countless errors in detail, which, though long ago assailed and extirpated by Niebuhr and others, have found their last place of refuge in our manuals. The recent investigations of philologists and jurists have been extensively, but carefully and circumspectly used." D. APPLETON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. Elements of Logic. With an Introductory view of Philosophy in general, and a Preliminary View of the Reason. By Henry W. Tappan. 12mo, 467 pages. Not considering Logic as an abstraction, Prof. Tappan assigns it its proper place among kindred sciences, and takes the student over the whole field of Philosophy, that the connection of its various parts may be distinctly perceived. He presents the subject, not merely as a method of obtaining inferences from truths, but also as a method of estabhshing those first truths and general principles that must precede all deduction. The great starting- points of theory, the sources to which we must look for premises in every department of science, are viewed in connection \dih. Logic ; the relations between the two are examined ; and the proper understanding of both is thus greatly facilitated. This is new ground ; yet it is what the profound thinker and all who would master the subject have long needed. In carrying out this plan, the author begins with Philosophy in general ; shows the distinction between the Phenomenal and the Metaphenomenal, the Objective and the Subjective, the Sensual and the Transcendental ; defines Ideas and the laws of their development ; and then proceeds to treat of the divisions of General Philosophy, Metaphysics, and homology — ia the latter of which, with Ethics, ^Esthetics, and Somatology, Logic is included. The interesting questions incidentally opened up, such as the Criteria of a True Philosophy, receive attention, and then, after a brief preliminary view of the Reason and its functions, we are introduced to Logic Proper. The evolution of Ideas, in all their variety, is first set set forth at length ; and numerous important points, now for the first time found in a system of Logic, such as the relation between matter and spirit, right and wrong, free- dom and responsibihty, are discussed in a manner which proves the author a practical adept in the science he would teach. Inductive and Deductive Logic follow; the latter of which embraces all the rules, principles, and formulte to be found in the text-books of former dialecticians, and to v/hich, for the most part, they confine themselves. The work closes with a masterly dissertation on the nature of proof, its different kinds, degrees of evidence, circumstantial evidence, reasoning from experience and analogy, and the calculation of chances. Important as these subjects are, and intimately as they are connected with the work of the dialectician, they have heretofore had no place in treatises on Logic ; Mr. Tappen is the first to unfold their connection with this science, and the clearness and comprehensiveness with which he has treated them leave nothing to be desired. D. APPLET ON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. An Elementary Treatise on Logic : Including, Part I. Analysis of Formulge ; Part II. Method. With an Appendix of Examples for Analysis and Criticism, and a copious Index of Terms and Subjects. By W. D. Wilson, D.D., Trinity Pro- fessor of Christian Ethics and Logic in Hobart Free College. 12mo, 425 pages. The peculiar merits of Dr. Wilson's Elementary Treatise on Logic can become known only by a thorough examination of the book itself, or daily use in the class-room. But a few of its distinguishing features can be here enumerated. In the first place, it is eminently clear in its arrangement, language, and illustrations. Its definitions are terse and precise ; its advance from step to step is natural and gradual ; every technicahty is thoroughly explained, and every difficulty removed. Secondly, it covers the whole ground, leaving nothing unsaid, nothing unexplained, nothing for the scholar to ask, nothing for the teacher to supply from other sources. Again, it is claimed that in this work many errors inherent in the old systems, and per- petuated by writer after writer, from Aristotle down, have been corrected, and that important new ground has been covered. The subject of Method^ by some omitted altogether, receives special attention at the hands of the author ; who, to all that is valuable in the works of others, has added the results of his own careful study. If the for- mulae of Logic are worth any thing, of course the method of their application is important ; in fact, on this method depends much of their value. In the application of his rules and precepts, Dr. Wilson is peculiarly happy. He never allows the pupil to lose sight of the practical phase of the questions he successively treats. The First Part of the Elementary Treatise relates to the Analysis of Formulae. A new and superior classification of syllogisms has been adopted, and the different classes are defined and illustrated in such a way as to in- sure their prompt recognition. The Second Part of the work, in which the original labors of the author are everywhere apparent, considers in turn the Methods of Investigation, of Proof and Refutation, of Instruction and Criti- cism. An Appendix furnishes copious examples for the exercise of the student. The publishers are convinced that the clearness, completeness, and prac- tical character of this work wiU greatly facilitate the study of Logic in schools and colleges. They invite the severest test of the claims here made in its behalf. L. APPLETON & C0:8 PUBLICATIONS. Elements of Moral Philosopliy : Analytical, Synthetical, and Practical. By Hubbard "Winslow. 12mo, 480 pages. This work is an original and thorough examination of the fundamental laws of Moral Science, and of their relations to Christianity and to practical life. It has already taken a firm stand among our highest works of literatmre and science. From the numerous commendations of it by our most learned and competent men, we have room for only the following brief extracts : From Eev. TnosiAS H. Sktnnee, D.D., of the Union Theol. Soc, Y. "It is a work of tmcommon merit, on a subject very difficult to be treated well. His analysis is complete. He has sbunned no question whicli his purpose required him to answer, and he has met no adversary which he has not overcome." From Kev. L. P. Hickok, Vice-President of Union College. " I deem the book well adapted to the ends proposed in the preface. The style is cle^, the thoughts perspicuous. I think it calculated to do good, to promote tho truth, to diffuse light, and impart instruction to the community, in a department of study of the deepest interest to mankind." From Eev. James "Walker, D.D., President of Harvard University, " Having carefully examined the more critical parts, to which my attention has been especially directed, I am free to express my conviction of the great clearness, discrimi- nation, and accuracy of the work, and of its admirable adaptation to its object." From Eev. E ay Palmee, D.D., of Albany. " I have examined this work with great pleasure, and do not hesitate to say that in my judgment it is greatly superior to any treatise I have seen, in all the essential requisites of a good text-book." From Peof. Eosseatt D. HrrcHCOCK, D.D., of the Union Theol. Soc, N. Y. " The task of mediating between science and the popular mind, is one that requires a peculiar gift of perspicuity, both in thought and style ; and this, I think, the author possesses in an eminent degree. I am pleased with its comprehensiveness, its plainness, and its fidelity to the Chi-istian stand-point." From Peof. Henet B. Smith, D.D,, of the Union Theol. Soc, N. Y. " It commends itself by its clear arrangement of the topics, its perspicuity of lan- guage, and its constant practical bearings. I am particularly pleased with its views of conscience. Its frequent and pertinent illustrations, and the Scriptural character of its explanations of the particular duties, will make the work both attractive and valuable as a text-book, in imparting instruction upon this vital part of philosophy." From "W. D. 'Wixson, D.D., Professor of Intellectual and Moral Philosophy in Hob art Free College. " I have examined the work with care, and have adopted it as a text-book in the study of Moral Science. I consider it not only sound in doctrine, but clear and system- atic in method, and withal pervaded with a prevailing healthy tone of sentiment, which cannot fail to leave behind, in addition to the truths it inculcates, aa impression in favor of those truths. I esteem this one of the greatest merits of the book. In this respect it has no equal, so far as I know ; and I do not hesitate to speak of it as being preferable to any other work yet published, for use in all institutions where Moral Philosophy forms a department in the course of instruction." D. APPLETON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. A History of Philosophy : An Epitome. By Dr. Albert Schtvtegler. Translated from the c rigi- nal German, by Julius H. Seelte, 12mo, 365 pages. This translation is designed to supply a want long felt by both teachers and students in our American colleges. We have valuable histories of Philosophy in English, but no manual on this subject so clear, concise, and comprehensive as the one now presented. Schwegler's work bears the marks of great learning, and is evidently written by one who has not only studied the original sources for such a history, but has thought out for him. self the systems of which he treats. He has thus seized upon the real germ of each system, and traced its process of development with great clearness and accuracy. The whole history of speculation, from Thales to the present time, is presented in its consecutive order. This rich and important field of study, hitherto so greatly neglected, will, it is hoped, receive a new im- pulse among American students through Mr. Seelye's translation. It is a Dook, moreover, invaluable for reference, and should be in the possession of every pubUc and private library. From L. P. Hickok, Vice-President of Union College. " I have had opportunity to hear a large part of Mr. Seelye's translation of Schweg- ler's History of Philosophy read from manuscript, and I do not hesitate to say that it is a faithful, clear, and remarkably precise English rendering of this invaluable Epitome of the History of Philosophy. It is exceedingly desirable that it should be given to American students of philosophy in the English language, and I have no expectation of its more favorable and successful accomplishment than in this present attempt. I should immediately introduce it as a text-book in the graduate's department under my own instruction, if it be favorably published, and cannot doubt that other teachers will rejoice to avail themselves of the like assistance from it." From Hekky B. Smith, Professor of Christian Theology, Union Theological Seminary, JSf. T. "It will well reward diligent study, and is one of the best works for a text -book in our colleges upon this neglected branch of scientific investigation." From N. Poetee, Professor of Intellectual Philosophy in Yale College. " It is the only book translated from the German which professes to give an account of the recent German systems which seems adap'ied to give any intelligible informa- tion on the subject to a novice." From Geo. P. Fishee, Professor of Divinity in Yale College. " It is really the best Epitome of the History of Philosophy now accessible to the English stndent." From Joseph Havek, Professor of Mental Philosophy in Amherst College. "As a manual and brief summary of the whole range of speculative inquiry, I know of no work which stikes me more favorably." D. APPLET ON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. Lectures on the True, tlie Beautiful, and the Good. By M. VICTOR COUSIX. Translated by 0. W. WIGHT. 1 vol., 8vo, 391 pages. Cousin is confessedly the soundest of modern philosophers. The founder and head of the Eclectic School, his teachings by the intrinsic force of truth have, with all earnest thinkers, superseded the insufficient systems that pro- ceded it. The theory on which they are based may justly be called a high- toned spu-itualism, whose tendency is to subordinate the sensual and to ennoble mankind. It teaches the spirituahty of the soul, the freedom and responsibility of human action, the dignity of justice, and the beauty of charity. It sustains rehgious sentiment, seconds art, supports the right, and purifies society. Such is the general character of Cousin's philosophy. In these Lectures, the latest production of his great mind, it is presented in a condensed, striking, and attractive form. After taking a brief view of the philosophy of the nineteenth centuiy, and the relation which his theory sustains to other systems, the author enters at once upon his subject. Under the head of "the True," he considers the existence, origin, and value of Universal and Necessary Principles ; God, the principle of principles ; and mysticism of sentiment and philosophy. Under "the Beautiful," he treats of Beauty in nature and art, and adds a valuable chapter on French art in the seventeenth century. Under the head of "the Good," he surveys the whole field of Ethics, reviews the theory of Expediency and other defective systems, and finally brings us to Deity as the grand embodiment of aU that is good in the universe. No one can master the system of Ethics here set forth by Cousin, without feeling that it has made him wiser, nobler, and better. History of Modern Philosophy. By M. VICTOR COUSIN. Translated by 0. W. WIGHT. 2 vols., 8vo, 801 pages. Philosophy of Sir William Hamilton. Edited by 0. W. WIGHT. 8vo, 530 pages. D. APPLETON c£- C0:8 PUBLICATIONIS. Course of Ancient Geography : Arranged with Special Reference to Convenience of Recitation. By Prof. H. I. SCHMIDT, D.D., of Columbia CoUege. 12mo, 328 pages. The object of this work is to facilitate study. With nothing new to teach in the department of Ancient Geography, there is much necessity of breaking up the great masses of knowledge accumulated on the subject by classical scholars, and rendering the subject itself, its general features, and principal parts, more easily accessible to the student. Nothing is introduced into the book but what the student in reading is constantly required to know. The best authorities have been consulted, carefully compared, and freely used throughout. No pains have been spared to render the work as correct as our knowledge of the ancient world will permit. The volume opens with a short account of the Geography known to the ancients at diflPerent periods, and of the gradual extension of their knowledge. Then the author begins with the Ancient Geography of Europe — Greece is de- scribed in ample detail, and Italy in the same manner. Then follows all that is known of Asia Minor. This constitutes what maj be termed Classi- cal Geography — that portion of Ancient Geography which the student most constantly needs in the study of classical authors. To present this properly is the main design of the work. After this the author returns to Europe — again to Asia — and lastly, treats the Ancient Geography of Africa. This order seemed the most natural in a work of the kind, as it is based upon the relative importance, iu classical authors, of those countries ; the author also took upon this point the advice of a number of distinguished instructors. All the matter presented is broken up into short paragraphs, and these are numbered ; and questions which refer to the facts given in these para- graphs, and marked respectively with the corresponding numbers, are given in the lower margin. This at once assists the pupil and the teacher. In this work every material division of the ancient world is noted, and the name of every sea, lake, river, or to\vn is given ; in many instances, the derivation and etymology of the names are added. The book is sufficiently fuU for every practical purpose, not only of the school-room, but for refer- ence in general reading of ancient authors. It has a copious Index that much enhances its value in this respect. From the Becorder. "This very satisfactory work makes a valuable addition to the library of the classical student, and also to the series of test-books to be used during the course of o^adomical and collegiate study," D. APPLETON & C0:8 PUBLICATIONS. Historical and Miscellaneous Questions. From the Eighty-Fourth London Edition. With large additions : Em* bracing the Elements of Mythology, Astronomy, Architecture Heraldry, etc., adapted for Schools in the United States, by Mrr Julia Lawrence. EmbelHshed witk Nui-jnerous Engra\ings oi Wood. Fourth American Edition, Revised and Corrected, with $ Chapter on the American Constitution by RICHMAL MANGNALL 12mo, 396 pages. Mangnairs Questions has attained an enviable reputation on both sides of the Atlan tic as a condensed abstract of history, art, science, and general information. It is ir the form of question and answer, and is adapted to the higher classes in common school? and academies. The variety of subjects embraced, the difficulty of obtaining suitable text-books relating to many of them, much more of iinding any single work that con- tains them all, and the judgment displayed by the author in selecting what is important and presenting great facts and leading principles in a striking manner that impressef them on the mind, have gained for this work an extensive and well-deserved circula tion. A careful revision and the introduction of much that is important to the American student, enhance the value of the present edition. An idea may be formed of the extensive and important ground it eovers from the following table of CONTENTS. A short View of Scripture History, from the Creation to the Eeturn of the Jews. Questions from the Early Ages to the time of Julius Caesar. Miscellaneous Questions in Grecian History. Miscellaneous Questions in General History — chiefly Ancient. Questions containing a Sketch of the most remarkable Events from the Chris- tian Era to the close of the Eighteenth Centiiry. Miscellaneous Questions in Eoman His- tory. Questions in English History, from the Invasion of Ctesar to the Eeformation. Continuation of Questions in English History, from the Eeformation to the Present Time. Abstract of Early British History. Abstract of English Eeigns from the Conquest. Abstract of the Scottish Eeigns. Abstract of the French Eeigns, from Pharamond to Philip I. Continuation of the French Eeigns, from Louis VI. to Louis Philippe. Questions relating to the History of America, from its Discovery to the Pres- ent Time. Abstract of Eoman Kings and most dis- tinguished Heroes. Abstract of the most celebrated Grecians. Of Heathen Mythology in General. Abstract of the Heathen Mythology. The Elements of Astronomy. Explanation of a few Astronomical Terms. List of Constellations. Questions on Common Subjects, Questions on Architecture. Questions on Heraldry. Explanation of such Latin Words and Phrases as are seldom Englished. Questions on the History of the Middle Ages. B. APPLETON 6: CO:S PV PLICATIONS. The Child's First History of Rome. By Miss E. M. SEWELL. 18mo, 255 pages. In the preparation of this work for the use of children, the authoress has drawn her material from the most reliable sources, and incorporated them into a narrative at once imostentatious, perspicuous, and graphic, ahnmg to be understood by those for whom she writes, and to impress deeply and permanently on their minds the facts successively presented. The entire work is clothed in a style at once pleasing and intelligible to the juvenile mind ; and the introduction of interesting episodes tends to rivet the atten- tion and relieve the difficulty of memorizing dry details. Small as this volume is, it covers the whole ground, from the founding of the city to its destruction by the Xorthem barbarians. A condensed sketch of the manners and mode of life of the ancient Romans is appended ; as, also, are Questions, for the convenience of those who desire them. A First History of Greece. By Miss E. M. SEWELL. 18mo, 358 pages. This work is designed to give the young a clearer idea of Grecian History than is to be obtained from any of the numerous works on the subject that have been accumulating during the present century. By culluig out promi- aent characters and events, presenting them in a striking light, and not making their perusal irksome by a mass of minor details, the authoress has rendered an important service to the youth of our country. With the view of removing the difficulty often encountered in the study of Grecian History, in consequence of its involving events connected with numerous places, the names of which are new and the position of which is unknown, a list of the Grecian States and their chief cities is presented in a preliminary chapter. k. Chronological Table of the contemporary events of Grecian and Jewish History is appended, which will be of use to the Bible student as well as the general reader. Few books wiU be found more acceptable in the school- room than this. D. APPLET ON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. History of Rome. By Dr. THOMAS ARNOLD. Three Yolumes in One. 8vo, 670 pages. Arnold's History of Rome is a well-known standard, no less full and accurate than the works of Niebuhr and Schmitz, while it far surpasses them in interest. The style is such as the subject requires, — easy, perspicuous, dignified, and eloquent. Every page glows with that truth-loving spirit for which Dr. Arnold was distinguished. With him nothing is taken for granted ; every statement is verified by reference to the old historians. The clear-sighted judgment of the author and his profound acquirements as a philologist and critic, preeminently quaUfy him for deahng with ancient records, in which truth and fable are so blended that it is often exceedingly difficult to distinguish them. No proper opportunity is lost of introducing sage reflections on morals and poUtics, and suggesting themes of useful thought to the intelligent mind. As this history is destined to remain a standard for years, it should have a place in every private and public hbrary. Its adaptation to the wants of high-schools and colleges will be apparent on the most cursory examination. Lectures on Modern History. By Dr. THOilAS ARNOLD. Large 12mo, 428 pages. In these Lectures, Dr. Arnold, confessedly one of the best of modem historians, has presented his views on the subject of history and its uses ; the difficulties a student is likely to encounter, and the best mode of sur- mounting them. His object is to awaken an interest in historical studies, and furnish the learner with such general information as will enable him to pursue his course to the best advantage. The present is a reprint of the second London edition. It is accompa- nied with a Preface and Notes by Henry Reed, M.A., Professor of English Literature in the University of Pennsylvania, who has had in view its use, not only for general reading, but also as a text-book for collegiate classes. jPVowl the Courier and Enquirer. " Professor Eeed has added ^eatly to the worth and interest of the volume, by ap- pending to each Lecture such extracts from Dr. Arnold's other -n-ritings as would more fully illustrate its prominent points. The jSTotes and Appendix -which he has thus furnished are exceedingly valuable. No student or literary man who has the least regard for the philosophy of history should be without this book. So far as our knowledge extends, there is no other before the public which can be compared to it for Interest and permanent worth." D. AFFLETON & CO:S FUBLICATIONS. PUTZ'S GEOGEAPHIOAL AND HISTOEIGAL SEEIES. I. Ancient Geography and History. ISmo, 396 pages. This work was originally prepared by Wilhelm Piitz, an eminent German scholar, translated and edited in England by the Rev. T, K. Arnold, and is now revised and introduced to the American pubHc in a well-written preface, by Mr. George W. Greene, Teacher of Modern Languages in Brown Uni- versity. As a Text-Book on Ancient History for colleges and advanced academies, this volume is believed to be one of the best compends published. II. Mediaeval Geography and History. Translated by Rev. R. B. PAUL, M.A. 12mo, 211 pages. The characteristics of this volume are precision, condensation, and luminous arrangement. It is precisely what it pretends to be — a manual, a sure and conscientious guide for the student through the crooks and tangles of Mediaeval History. All the great principles of this extensive period are carefully laid down, and the most important facts skilfully grouped around them. III. Manual of Modern Geography and History. Translated by Rev. R. B. PAUL, M.A. 12mo, 836 pages. This volume completes the Series of the author's works on Geography and History. Every important fact of the period, comprehensive as it is both in Geography and History, is presented in a concise, yet clear and connected manner, so as to be of value, not only as a text-book for students, but to the general reader for reference. Although the facts are greatly condensed, as of necessity they must be, yet they are presented with so much distinctness as to produce a fixed impression on the mind. It is also reliable as the work of an indefatigable German scholar, for correct infor- mation relating to the progress and changes of States and nations, literature, the sciences and the arts, and all that combines in modern civilization. D. AFPLETON iSc CO: 8 PUBLICATIONS. Manual of Ancient and Modern History. By W. C. Taylor, LL. D., M. R. A. S. Revised by C. S. Henry. D. D. 1 vol., 8vo, 8V0 pages. ANCIENT HISTOET, Separately, 858 pages. Containing the Political History, Geographical Position, and Social State of the principal Nations of Antiquity, carefully digested from the ancient writers, and illustrated by the discoveries of modern scholars and travellers. MODEEN HISTOET, Sepakatelt, 812 pages. Containing the Rise and Progress of the principal European Nations, their Political History, and the changes in their Social Condition ; with a History of the Colonies founded by Europeans. Inquiry is often made by those who have not the time or opportunity for an extended course of historical reading, for a work that embraces within reasonable compass the leading events of Ancient and Modern History, and will give them a correct idea of its leading features stripped of unimport- ant details. Such a work will be found in this compilation of Dr. Taylor. With the view of bringing a general knowledge of the past within the reach of all classes of readers, he has selected the great facts connected with the rise and progress of nations, their customs, religion, and pohtical institutions, and carefully digested them in a clear and comprehensive summary. For the purposes for which it is designed, it is believed that this work has no equal. It is this conviction on the part of those who have examined it, that has led to its extensive introduction as a text-book into the academies and collegies of our land. Some of its distinguishing features are mentioned below. In presenting facts, the author has not overlooked the philosophy of history, but has traced events to their causes, and directed attention to the progress of civilization and its eflPects on society. Thus exhibited in their connection, as parts of the great plan of Providence in the government of the world, events are understood as well as remembered, and the reader receives a no less valuable lesson in philosophy than in history. A knowledge of its cHmate, natural features, towns and cities, is often essential to the proper understanding of a country's history. To meet this want, a brief geographical outline is in every case prefixed. The accentu- ation of proper names, -as they occur, is another feature of great practical value. Dryness is generally characteristic of condensed historical outlines ; in the present case it is avoided by the vigorous style of the author, and the introduction of interesting anecdotes and episodes that serve to relieve the mind, and bring out in clear light the pecuHarities of individual or national character. The American edition has been revised throughout by Dr. Henry, and enlarged by the introduction of an admirable chapter on American Historv. D. APPLET ON & CO:S PUBLICATIONS. A Digest of the Laws, Customs, Manners, and Institutions of the Ancient and Modern Nations. By Thomas Dew, late President of the College of William and Mary. 8yo, 662 pages. On examination, it will be found that more than ordinary labor has been expended upon this work, and that the author has proceeded upon higher principles and has had higher aims in view than historical compilers ordi- narily propose to themselves. Instead of being a mere catalogue of events, chronologically arranged, it is a careful, laborious, and instructive digest of the laws, customs, manners, institutions, and civilization of Ancient and Modern Nations. That it is thus enabled to give a clearer and fairer idea of the past and its relations to the present, does not admit of a moment's doubt. No pains have been spared by the author to secure accuracy in facts and figures ; and in doubtful cases references are given in parentheses, so that the student can readily satisfy himself by going to original sources. The department of Modern History, too often neglected in works of this kind, has received special care and attention. From John J. Owen, Professor in New York Free Academy. " I have examined, with much pleasure, Prof. Dew's Digest of the Laws, Manners, Customs, &c., of Ancient and Modern Nations. It furnishes a desideratum in the study of history which I have long desired to see. The manner in which history is generally studied in our institutions of learning is, in my judgment, very defective. The great central points or epochs of history are not made to stand out with sufficient prominence. Events of minor importance are made to embarrass the memory by the confused method of their presentation to the mind. History is studied by pages, and not by subjects. In the wilderness of events through which the student is groping his way, he soon becomes lost and perplexed. The past is as obscure as the future. His lesson soon becomes an irksome task. The memory is wearied with the monotonous task of striving to retain the multitudinous events of each daily lesson. "This evil appears to be remedied in a great degree by Prof. Dew's admirable arrangement. Around the great points of history he has grouped those of subordinate Importance. Each section is introduced by a caption, in which the subject is briefly stated, and so as to be easily remembered. Thus the student having mastered the leading events, will find little or no difficulty in treasuring up the minor points in their order and connection. I trust the book will be adopted in our higher institutions of learning. I greatly prefer it to any history for the use of schools which I have seen."