t^f^mmyz-'^^^'^m^ Pass 'B F 1 3 ' Book__ GoipghtN?. coEHUGHr DEjraste Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from The Library of Congress http://www.archive.org/details/empiricalrationaOOschu EMPIKICai^ AiNiJ KATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY n^. '^030 J^ Embracing Cognitions, Feelings, and Volitions BY A. SCHUYLER, LL. D. President of Baldwin University. Author of Principles of Logic, and a Series of Mathematical Works "How charming is divine Philosophy/ Not harsh and crabbed, as dull fools suppose, But musical as is Apollo's lute, And a perpetual Feast of nectared sweets, Where no crude surfeit reigns.'" VA]^ ANTWEEP, BEAGG & CO. Cincinnati Kew York /ft.... i\r Eclectic Educational Series. Dr. Schuyler's Works. . Schuyler'' s Principles of Logic \0 n ^n^ Schuyler^ s Psychology. ^ '^ Schuyler^ s Complete Algebra. Schuyler^ s Elements of Geometry. Schuyler'' s Trigonometry and Mensuration (Pay^s Series). Schuyler^ s Surveying and Navigation [Pay^s Series). Descriptive List and Prices on Application. Copyright 1882.. : . Van Antwerp, Bragg & Co. (ii) PEEFAOE. Psychology treats directly of Cognition, Feeling, and Volition, and indirectly of Intellect, Sensibility, and Will. Greater prominence is thus given to the phenomena of the soul, with their conditions and laws, than to the faculties implied by these phenomena. Though much light has, no doubt, been thrown upon Psychology by the investigations of Physiologists, — light which the Psychologist should heartily welcome,— yet to know any phenomenon, as it is in itself, we must study it as revealed in consciousness. This is especially true of the higher processes of thought. Thus, to understand the nature of the reasoning process, it will not suffice to examine the structure and functions of the nerves, the ganglia, the brain, and the organs of sense, but we must analyze the reasoning process itself as a known fact of conscious experience. The discussion of the Intuitions is introduced at an early stage, since they afford the fundamental principles for subsequent investigations. To defer the consideration of fundamental principles to the last pages, as is com- monly done, would embarass all preceding discussions. AVhat would be thought of a writer on Geometry, who should put his axioms on the last page of his book? The difficulty of discussing fundamental princij^les is no justification for such an arrangement, since any mind mature enough to undertake the study of Psychology, is certainly prepared to understand a clear presentation of its first piinciples. (ill) iv PREFACE. The elements involved in the act of Perception have been discriminated with much care, and an attempt has been made to exhibit clearly and correctly the nature of this act. That a correct explanation of perception has been given, will, it is believed, be admitted by those who will carefully study this process in itself,- as revealed by their own consciousness, and as developed in the chap- ters pertaining to this subject. The interesting phenomena of Eepresentation, embra- cing Memory, Imagination, and Phantasy have been con- cisely and clearly exhibited. Light has been thrown on the Law of Association, especially in regard to the transi- tion from one series of representations to another. The processes of Elaboration have been fully and care- fully treated. These phenomena can be understood only by actually exhibiting them, and developing their laws. No vague discourse about the logical processes will suffice to make known their principles and laws, or to unfold their philosophy. The Aristotelian Logic will, perhaps, never be super- seded; but, as is needful, it will be supplemented by Modern Logic, which supplies the defects of the ancient, while the ancient affords the necessary basis for the modern. Each may, therefore, be regarded as the com- plement or indispensable counterpart of the other. The brief space of a few pages only has been given to the subjects of Mood, Figure, and Eeduction. These sub- jects, though not essential to Logic itself, are interesting in themselves, and in their historical associations. There is a growing demand, by progresssive teachers, to have Logic presented in connection with Psychology. To meet this demand, the third division of Part I. is made a course of Logic. It is even more and better than this, since it presents, not only the logical pro- cesses themselves, but their philosophy, and the relation PREFACE. V of elaborated thought to the elementary phenomena of the mind. To those students who have not studied Logic, this division will prove an ample course; and to those who have, it will be a thorough review, giving broader views of thought, and deeper insight into the abstruse pro- cesses of the intellectual powers. The phenomena of Feeling and Yolition, with their corresponding faculties of Sensibility and Will, have, in the second and third parts, been as fully discussed as the limits of the book w^otild permit. It is believed that these parts, though necessarily concise, will be not only interesting, but clear and thorough. The value of philosophic studies can scarcely be over- estimated, and it has been maintained by philosophers of opposing schools. John Stuart Mill, in his Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy, Vol. I, page 10, says, ^'That a true Psychology is the indispensable scientific basis of morals, of politics, of the science and art of education; that the difficulties of Metaphysics lie at the root of all science; that these difficulties can only be quieted by be- ing resolved ; and that until they are resolved, positively if possible, but at any rate negatively, we are never as- sured that any human knowledge, even physical, stands on solid foundations." Sir Wm. Hamilton, Metaphysics^ Lecture 11.^ says: ''In the compass of our experience, we distinguish two series of facts, — the facts of the external or material world, and the facts of the internal world, or world of intelli- gence. . . . The phenomena of the material world are subjected to immutable laws, and are produced and re- produced in the same invariable succession, and manifest only the blind force of a mechanical necessity. '' The phenomena of man are, in part, subjected to the laws of the external universe. As dependent upon a vi PREFACE. bodily organization, as actuated by sensual propensities and animal wants, he belongs to matter; and in this re- spect, he is the slave of necessity. Eut what man holds of matter does not make up his personality. They are his, not he; man is not an organism, — he is an intelligence served by organs. For, in man, there are tendencies, — there is a law, — which continually urge him to prove that he is more powerful than the nature by which he is surrounded and jDcnetrated. He is conscious to him- self of faculties not comprised in the chain of physical necessity; his intelligence reveals prescriptive principles of action, absolute and universal, in the law of duty, and a liberty capable of carrying that law into effect, in opposition to the solicitations, the impulses of his mate- rial nature ^'Now, the study of Philosophy operates in three ways to establish that assurance of human liberty which is necessary for a rational belief in our moral nature in a moral world, and in a moral Euler of that world. "In the first place, an attentive consideration of the phenomena of mind is requisite in order to a luminous and distinct apprehension of liberty as a fact or datum of the intelligence. For though, without philosophy, a natural conviction of free agency lives and works in the recesses of every human mind, it requires a process of philosophical thought to bring this conviction to clear consciousness and scientific certainty '' In the second place, a profound philosophy is neces- sary to obviate the difilculties which meet us whenever we attempt to explain the possibility of this fact, and to prove that the datum of liberty is not a mere illu- sion " In the third place, the study of mind is necessary to counterbalance and correct the influence of the study of matter; and this utility of Metaj)hysics rises in propor- FREFA CE. vii tion to the progress of the natural sciences, and to the greater attention which they engross." Psychology, including Logic, constitutes the essential basis of a philosophic course. However valuable a work on Metaphysics, as that of Ferrier's or Bowne's may be, it requires, as the indispensable condition of its profita- ble perusal, a preliminary knowl^edge of the phenomena and laws of mind. A few words in reference to the time and method of study may not be amiss. In case the school year is divided into three terms, as is now usually the case, Psychology ought to be studied by the senior class of the Public Schools, or by the junior or senior class of the Colleges, the first and second terms, and the History of Philosophy the third term; but if the teacher prefers. Psychology can be taken the first term by itself, and, in connection with the History of Philosophy, the second and third terms. For valuable critical suggestions, thanks are due to B. A. Hinsdale^ late President of Hiram College, now Superintendent of Public Instruction, Cleveland, Ohio, who kindly consented to read the manuscript. This work is presented to the public with the hope that it will be profitable, not only to the student, but to the general reader who may desire to understand the facts and laws of mind; that it will prove especially in- teresting to those who may wish to revive their knowl- edge of Philosophy; and that thus the time and labor and thought bestowed in its preparation may not be wanting in good results. CO^'TENTS. PAGE Introduction 11 PAKT I,— COGNITION AND THE INTELLECT. DIVISION I.— ACQUISITION. CHAPTER I. — Consciousness 19 -IL— Eeflection , '.29 III. — Rational Intuition — General View 39 IV. — Intuitions Continued — Non-Dynamical Conditions. . 46 V. — Intuitions Continued — Dynamical Conditions. ... 59 VI. — Intuitions Continued — The Ego and Personal Identity. 75 VII. -Sensation 89 VIII. — Perception — General View 98 IX — Perception through Smell and Taste 102 X. — Perception through Touch and Hearing . . . . . 107 XL — Perception through Sight 113 XII. — Acquired Perception 129 XIII. — Development and Product of Perception 139 XIV. — Errors in Perception ... 145 XV. — Passivity and Activity and Conditions 152 XVI. — Theories of Perception — Ancient, Medieval, Cartesian. 156 XVII. — Theories of Perception Continued — Locke, Berkeley, Hume ... 165 XVIII. — Theories of Perception Continued — Kant, Reid, Ham- ilton 174 XIX. — Theories of Perception Concluded — Mill and Porter . 184 (viii) CONTENTS. ix DIVISION II.- REPRESENTATION. CHAPTER PAGE I. — General View of Kepresentation 195 II. — Laws of Kepresentadon 202 III. — Peculiarities of Roif^esentation 210 IV.— Memory . . ./. 218 V. — Imagination m 228 VI.— Phantasy 232 DIVISION III.— ELABORATION. I. — Elaboration — General View 241 II. — Classification and Conception — Preliminary Discus- sion 245 III. — Classification and Conception — General Discussion . 252 IV. — Classification and Conception— Names, Classes, Concepts 261 V. — Classification and Conception — Order of Procedure in Classification 268 VI. — Quantity of Concepts . 275 VII.— Quality of Concepts ....'. 282 VIII.— Relation of Concepts .291 IX. — Judgment — General View 299 X. — Categorical Judgments — Classification and Relation . 305 XL — Categorical Judgments — Distribution and Conversion 312 XII. — Conditional Judgments 318 XIII. — Deductive Reasoning — Immediate Arguments. . . . 322 XIV. — Deductive Reasoning — Mediate Arguments .... 325 XV. — Deductive Reasoning — Categorical Syllogisms . . . . 332 XVI. — Deductive Reasoning— Conditional Syllogisms . . . 338 XVII. — Deductive Reasoning — Formal Fallacies 347 XVIII. — Deductive Reasoning — Material Fallacies 357 XIX. — Deductive Reasoning — Mood of Syllogisms .... 365 XX. — Deductive Reasoning — Figure of the Syllogism. . . 369 XXL — Deductive Reasoning — Reduction to the First Figure . 379 XX 1 1. — Inductive Reasoning — Mathematical Induction. . . 382 XXIII. — Inductive Reasoning — Logical Induction — Subsidia- ries 388 XXIV. — Inductive Reasoning — Logical Induction 394 XXV. — Inductive Reasoning — The Ground of Induction . . 402 XX VL— Modern Logic . 409 CONTENTS, PAET II.— FEELING AND THE SENSIBILITY. CHAPTER PAGE I. — Physical Feelings 417 IL— Vital Feelings 427 HI. — Psychical Feelings — Emotions 432 IV. — Psychical Feelings — Affections 441 V. — Psychical Feelings — Desire and Aversion ..... 455 PAET III.— VOLITION AND THE WILL. I. — General View of Volition 463 IL— Freedom of the Will 469 III. — Moral Eesponsibility ............ 477 PSYCHOLOGY. INTRODUCTION. Psychology is the science which treats of the phe- nomena and the faculties of the human soul. It treats directly of phenomena and indirectly of faculties, since faculties are known only through phenomena. The aim of psychology is to ascertain the phenomena of the human soul, to analyze and classify these phe- nomena, and to determine their conditions and laws. The utility of psychology is evident from the fact that it supplies the fundamental principles for all the sciences pertaining to man as an intellectual, moral, social, and religious being; that it cultivates the mind loj calling its faculties into vigorous exercise, thus contributing to our perfection and consequently to our happiness; and that it checks the evils resulting from too exclusive pursuit of physical science, by directing our attention to our spiritual nature, moral dignity, and probable destiny. The means for psychological study may be divided into two classes — principal and collateral. The principal means for psychological study are con- sciousness, reflection, and rational intuition. Consciousness is the immediate knowledge which the soul has of its phenomena. It is the primary means of (11) 12 PSYCHOLOGY. collecting the facts pertaining to the operations of the various faculties of the soul. Reflection is the turning back of the thoughts to the consideration of psychical phenomena. It is the means by which the phenomena of the soul are analyzed, com- pared, identified or discriminated, and classified. Thus, by reflection, psychical phenomena are found to be redu- cible to three classes — cognitions, or acts of knowledge; feelings, or sensations, instincts, appe'tites, emotions, af- fections, and desires; and volitions, or choices. Rational intuition is the immediate apprehension of necessary truth. It is the means by which the soul ap- prehends the necessity of the conditions and laws of its phenomena. Thus, by rational intuition, the phenomena of the soul are referred to causes capable of producing them; for, these phenomena, beginning in time, are not eternal. They can not bring themselves into existence, since they can not act before they exist. A faculty of the soul is its capability of doing a cer- tain act, or its susceptibility of being in a certain state. Hence, the faculties of the soul, its powers and sus- ceptibilities, are, as inferred from its phenomena, like- wise reducible to three classes — the Intellect^ or faculty of cognition; the Sensibility, or susceptibility of feeling; and the Will, or power of volition. It is, therefore, evident that the intimate relation of the psychical phenomena, the cognitions, feelings, and volitions, implies the intimate relation of the faculties, the intellect, the sensibility, and the will, and the unity of the soul, their common origin; that these phenomena, though fleeting, imply, from their continued succession and spiritual character, a permanent spiritual subject, variously called the soul, spirit, mind, I, self, or ego, en- dowed with the faculties of intellect, sensibility, and will. The collateral means for psychological studj^ are the INTR OD UCTION, 13 sciences of Biology, Anthropology, Sociology, Anatomy, and Physiology. Biology is the science of life. It treats of the phenom- ena manifested by the living beings of the two organic kingdoms, vegetable and animal. As a science, Biology is fundamental and comprehensive. It throws great light on all the other sciences pertaining to living beings. Anthropology is the science which treats of man ac- cording to the methods of Natural History. It consid- ers him as a complex being, consisting of body, animal life, and soul or spirit. It views man in a general way, as to race, sex, age, heredity, and the reciprocal influ- ence of body and soul. It studies him as affected by climate, education, religion, government, employment, and accidental circumstances, leaving the more profound and scientific study of the physical and spiritual natures of man to distinct and special sciences. Sociology is the science of society. It treats of man in social organizations — the family, society, the church, or the state. Man's capabilities are known by his man- ifestations .and achievements. In war, he has exhibited ambition and patriotism, courage and cruelty, genius and rapacity. In peace, he has cultivated science, liter- ature, and art; he has engaged in agriculture, in the mechanic arts, and in commerce; he has founded gov- ernments, organized religions, and developed the learned professions. Anatomy and Physiology are related sciences which treat of the structure and functions of man's physical organism. A knowledge of these sciences is a valuable preparation for the study of mind; since the body, es- pecially the nervous system, sustains vital relations to the phenomena of the soul. In the perception of exter- nal objects, the mind uses the organs of the five senses. In executing its volitions, it employs the body as its in- 14 PSYCHOLOGY. strument; but in the higher operations of thought, it seems to act independently of all material organs, exhib- iting phenomena totally unlike the properties of matter. In endeavoring to ascertain the relations existing be- tween the body and soul, the approved methods of science — observation, experiment, induction, and deduc- tion — are to be employed; and though nothing is to be assumed without evidence, yet it may be allowed, in the course of an investigation, to form an hypothesis, with the understanding that it is merely provisional, and that it must stand or fall according as it is confirmed or re- futed by subsequent investigations. It is legitimate to endeavor to ascertain what physi- cal conditions, if any, are the invariable antecedents or consequents, as the case may be, of certain psychical states; but it is not legitimate to assume, without proof, except provisionally, that every psychical phenomenon must have fixed physical antecedents or consequents. Though our knowledge of the body has already en- larged our knowledge of the conditions of the phenom- ena of the soul, and may be expected to do so more and more as our investigations are continued, yet it is to be remembered that we can understand neither per- ception, nor representation, nor elaboration, by examin- ing the nerves with the Physiologist, nor by feeling the head after the manner of the Phrenologist, but only by studying these processes themselves, in the light of con- sciousness, by the aid of reflection and rational intuition. The Rules for Investigation are the following: 1. Employ the principal and collateral means of study. 2. Take, as fundamental facts, the psychical phenomena given in consciousness, all the phenomena, and nothing but the phenomena. 3. Carefully observe, analyze, compare, and classify the phenomena. INTR OD UCTION. 15 4. Determine the conditions and laws of the phenomena. 5. Eefer phenomena essentially alike to the same fac- ulty, and those essentially unlike to different faculties. 6. Make an accurate register of the results. In order to present a bird's-eye view of the subject, we subjoin a summary classification of the phenomena of the human soul, also a classification of the faculties implied by these phenomena. These classifications give an outline of the subject, and they will be useful for reference, as we pursue our investigations. It will be observed that certain phenomena and the corresponding faculties have the same names, a defect unavoidable on account of the imperfection of language. The word JReason is used to denote the reasoning power. It is sometimes used to denote the logical power in gen- eral, also the power of rational intuition. Cognition CLASSIFICATION OF PSYCHICAL PHENOMENA. c^ 1-. ^- I Consciousness. Subjective { ^^^^^^^^^^^_ Rational — Intuition. Obj ective— Perception. Memory. Feeling Volition. Acquisition Representation Elaboration Physical feeling - Vital feeling Psychical feeling Imagination. Phantasy. Conceiving. Judging. Reasoning. Sensation. Instinct. Appetite. Of rest or fatigue. Of vigor or languor. Of health or sickness. Emotions. AffectionSo Desires. Solicitation— the antecedent of volition. Volition — the choice or decision. Execution — the consequent of volition. 16 PSYCHOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION OF THE PSYCHICAL FACULTIES. Subjective ( Consciousness. Intellect Acquisitive faculties Representative faculties Sensibility ^ Logical faculties Physical sensibility Vital sensibility Psychical sensibility \ Reflection. Rational— Intuition. Objective— Perception. Memory. Imagination. Phantasy. Conception. Judgment. Reason. Sensation. Instinct. Appetite. Of rest or fatigue. Of vigor or languor. Of health or sickness. Susceptibility of emotion. Susceptibility of affection. Susceptibility of desire. Will Passive susceptibility— as solicited by motive. Elective power— ability to choose or decide. Executive energy — as exerted in execution. Eeview. — Eeproduceon blackboard, expand 6 and 7, and elucidate. 1. Definition. 2. Aim Introduction 3. Utility 4. Means of study 1st. Principal 2d. Collateral 1st. 2d. 5. Rules for investigation -i. ^^^ 5th. 6th. 6. Classification of psychical phenomena. 7. Classification of psychical faculties. PART I. COaNITION AND THE INTELLECT. Psy.-2. (17) DIVISION I. ACQUISITION AND THE ACQUISITIVE FACULTIES. CHAPTEE I. CONSCIOUSNESS. 1. Consciousness as an act defined and character- ized.— Consciousness is tlie immediate knowledge which the soul has of its phenomena. It is empirical^ since it apprehends its object as contingent, and not as nec- essary. It is intuitive^ since it reaches its object di- rectly, and not through any medium, as the senses, the memory, or the reasoning processes. It is, therefore, empirical intuition. 2. Consciousness implied by all psychical phenom- ena. — Cognition implies consciousness ; for if I know, I know that I know, since if I do not know that I know, I do not know\ In like manner, it can be proved that feeling implies consciousness, and that volition implies consciousness. Hence the absurdity of the opinion that consciousness is impossible, as held by M. Comte, who says in reference to the consciousness of intellectual ac- tivity, ^'In order to observe, your intellect must pause from its activity; yet it is this very activity you want to observe. If you can not effect the pause, you can not observe ; if you do effect it, there is nothing to ob- serve." Comte's Positive Philosophy, by H. Martineau, page 33. But instead of its being impossible to be conscious of knowing, it is impossible to know without being con- (19) 20 PSYCHOLOGY, scions of knowing. Consciousness is involved in know- ing, as an essential element. 3. Consciousness an intellectual act. — Though con- sciousness is implied by all psychical phenomena, whether cognitions, feelings, or volitions, yet it is itself an act of the intellect. The etymology of the Avord conscious- ness^ from con and sciOj indicates its meaning — that along with knowing an object, I know also the know- ing. In case the object of consciousness is a phenome- non of the sensibility, the consciousness of the feeling is scarcely distinguishable from the feeling. Thus, if to be conscious of pain is not identical w^ith the feeling of pain, it is to be aware of the feeling. The faculties of the soul are so intimately related, that they do not act independ- ently of one another. Knowledge affords the condition of desire and affection; and both knowledge and feeling precede and accompany volition. 4. Consciousness as a faculty defined and considered. — Consciousness is the capability of knowing our psychical acts or states. If the soul is conscious of its cognitions, feelings, and volitions, it has the faculty of being con- scious of these phenomena, and this faculty is called consciousness. The term consciousness., then, is used to denote both an act and the faculty to which the act is referred. As an act, it is the immediate cognizance which the soul takes of its phenomena, and is implied, as a necessary condition, by the phenomena of cognition-, feeling, or volition. As a faculty, it is the capability of immediately knowing psychical phenomena, and is im- plied by the act of consciousness, as a necessary condition. 5. Objects of consciousness psychical phenomena.— The objects of consciousness are psychical phenomena, actual and present. The soul is conscious of all its phe- nomena — all appearances; for, if there is an appearance, tliat appearance is known or realized, otherwise it is not CONSCIOUSNESS. 21 an appearance; but a realization of the appearance is consciousness. The object of consciousness is nothing else than a psy- chical phenomenon. In the first place, we are not con- scious of an external object, as a house. If we perceive a house, we are conscious of the perception, but not of the house. Consciousness is immediate knowledge; but the knowledge of an external object is mediate, since it is derived from the sensation w^iich the object causes. In the second place, we are not conscious of the soul, nor of the soul as knowing, feeling, or willing, but of the knowing, feeling, and willing, as phenomena. The necessity of the soul, as the subject of these phenomena, is apprehended by rational intuition, as will be more fully shown hereafter. 6. Processes which are not objects of consciousness. — In saying that the soul is conscious of all its phenomena, we do not affirm that it is conscious of all its processes. Phenomena are processes that appear. The soul is con- scious of these processes, otherwise they could not be phenomena, that is, could not appear. There are, however, other processes that are not phe- nomena; and since these do not appear, their existence is not an object of consciousness, but a matter of infer- ence. This is ultimately true of consciousness itself, which, though an act, is not a distinct phenomenon, but an element of a phenomenon. For, if the act of conscious- ness is a distinct phenomenon, it appears, and is, there- fore, an object of consciousness. That is, in being con- scious of a phenomenon, we should, on this supposition, be conscious of the consciousness, and in like manner, we should be conscious of this second consciousness, and so on, which involves an infinite series of acts of con- sciousness, an impossibility in finite time. Granting that, by special efi'ort, an indefinite number of acts of con- 22 PSYCHOLOGY, sciousness might thus take place, yet, in general, the phenomenon is the object of attention, but not the con- sciousness of it, much less the consciousness of the con- sciousness of it, and so on. There are other psychical processes, inferred from their effects, which are unknown to consciousness. These pro- cesses have, by certain philosophers, been inconsistently called latent modifications of consciousness, and by others, unconscious cerebrations. They are latent processes, whether purely psychological, physiological, or mixed. 7. Idea and ideation. — The j)henomenon which is an object of consciousness develops and crystallizes into an idea of the phenomenon. The development of the idea is called ideation. The idea may afterwards be recalled in the memory, but not the original phenomenon. The idea when recalled is an object of consciousness. 8. Consciousness simultaneous with its object. — In the first place, the consciousness of a phenomenon can not be antecedent to that phenomenon, since we should, in that case, be conscious of that which has no existence, *which is impossible. In the next place, the consciousness of a phenomenon can not be subsequent to that phenomenon, since, before the consciousness, the supposed j)lienomenon could not appear, and hence would not be a phenome- non ; that is, consciousness is essential to the phenome- i^on, and is, therefore, not subsequent to it. The formula of consciousness, I know that I know, does not imply that I first know, then, after that, know that I know; for, if I first know, without being conscious that I know, then, at the first instant of knowing, before the con- sciousness of the knowledge, I know, without knowing that I know, which is absurd. The view that the consciousness of a psychical phe- nomenon is subsequent to that phenomenon, makes con- sciousness depend on memory. But if we are not con- CONSCIO USNESS. 23 scions of a phenomenon at the instant of its occurrence, we should know nothing of it at that instant, and, there- fore, have nothing to remember; hence, memory itself would be impossible, and consciousness, thus depending on memor}^, would also be impossible; but as both mem- ory and consciousness are facts, the theory that con- sciousness is subsequent to its object, which annihilates both memory and consciousness, can not be true. We have now found that consciousness of a phenom- enon is neither antecedent to that phenomenon nor sub- sequent to it; hence, the consciousness of a phenomenon is simultaneous Avith that phenomenon. 9. Consciousness a logical consequent of its object. — Though consciousness of a phenomenon is simultaneous with the phenomenon, yet the phenomenon involves the consciousness as its logical consequent, otherwise it could not be a ^^li^nomenon, that is, could not appear; and the consciousness implies the phenomenon as its logical antecedent, otherwise there would be nothing of which to be conscious. That a logical consequent may be chronologically sim- ultaneous with its logical antecedent, may be illustrated by the equation. y=f(x). This equation is read, y is equal to a function of x^ and signifies that the value of y depends on that of x, so that, if X changes, changing the value of /Or), y changes, so as always to be equal to f{xy Now, let X change, the change in x changing the value of /(x). The change in f{x) is simultaneous with the change in :r, otherwise f{x) has the same value while x has different values, which is impossible. As x changes, the change in x is followed by a change in y ; but the word foUoiced is used in a logical^ not in a chronological sense; for the change in y is simultaneous 24 PSYCHOLOGY, with the change in x, since if y could remain, with- out change, a moment after the change in x^ then, for that moment, y would not be equal to /(x), which is contrary to the sup230sition that y is always equal to f(x). Hence, the change in y, though logically conse- quent to the change in x, is chronologically simultane- ous with that change. This will serve to illustrate the possibility of the fact that logically consciousness may be the consequent of a phenomenon, while chronologically the phenomenon and the consciousness of it may be simultaneous. 10. Kinds of consciousness — natural, ethical, and ab- normal. — 1st. Natural consciousness is that ordinary form of consciousness which is common to all healthy minds. It is simply immediate knowledge of psychical phenom- ena, whether cognitions, feelings, or volitions. 2d. Ethical consciousness is that form of conscious- ness which is induced by those who practice self-inspec- tion in view of ascertaining their moral condition. It indicates the controlling influence of conscience, and a sensitiveness with regard to right and wrong. The de- velopment of this form of consciousness is mainly due to the influence of moral and religious systems. Ethical consciousness is, strictly speaking, reflection applied to moral states. 3d. Abnormal consciousness is that form of consciousness which is exhibited by bashful persons, who imagine that others are noticing their awkwardness. They are said to be self-conscious. 11. Varying intensity of consciousness. — Consciousness may vary in intensity from obscurity and indistinctness, through all the intermediate degrees, to clearness and dis- tinctness. The degree of intensity de]3ends largely upon the condition of the body, the character of the mind, age, culture, and the concentration of attention. CONSCIO USNESS, 25 12. General conditions of consciousness. — These are a living subject, a faculty of consciousness, and psychical phenomena. 1st. A living subject is a condition of consciousness; for consciousness implies a being who is conscious. 2d. A faculty of consciousness is a condition of the act of consciousness; for without the faculty, or capability of being conscious, the act would be impossible. 3d. A psychical phenomenon is a condition of conscious- ness; for psychical phenomena are the only objects of consciousness ; hence, in the absence of these phenomena, there can be no consciousness, since there would bo nothing of which to be conscious. 13. Conditions of vivid consciousness.^ These are the general conditions, above named, also varying psychical phenomena, abstraction, attention, and cultivation. 1st. The general conditions of consciousness are condi- tions of vivid consciousness; for whatever is essential to consciousness itself, is essential to any degree of con- sciousness, and hence, to vivid consciousness. 2d. Varying psychical pjhenomena are conditions of vivid consciousness; for a continuance in a state the same in kind throughout, would be attended by a decreasing de- gree of intensity of consciousness, tending to total un- consciousness. Thus, the miller is scarcely conscious of hearing the noise of the mill, though if it made an un- usual noise, he w^ould at once be clearly conscious of the chan, are congruents. Both are true, if b is less than a; both false, if b is equal to a; one true and the other false, if 6 is greater than a. Consec[uence. From mere congruence, the truth or NON-DYNAMTCAL CONDITIONS. 53 falsity of either of two propositions can not be inferred from either the truth or the falsity of the other. (3) The law of conflictives. Two conflictive propositions can not both he true. For, whether contraries or contra- dictories, they are incompatible ; hence, if both were true, the truth of each would involve the falsity of the other, and both would be false ; then each is both true and false, or a truth is. a falsity, which contradicts the negative part of the law of indentity — that a thing is not any thing else than itself. Thus, the propositions, this tree is an oak, and the same tree is a walnut, are con- flictives, and both can not be true. Consequences. 1) If one of two conflictives is true, the other is false. 2) Two true propositions can not be conflictive. 3) All truths exist in harmony. 4) A prop- osition is false, if it involves the conflictive of a truth. The law of conflictives is commonly called the law of contradiction. It follows as a corollary from the nega- tive part of the law of identity. As a law of the genus conflictives^ it is applicable to both species, contraries and contradictories, w^hich also have special laws. (4) The law of contraries. Two contrary propositions can not both he true, hut may both he false. For since they are conflictives, both can not be true; and since they are contraries, they are not universally inclusive; hence, other cases are possible, and both may be false. Thus, the propositions, a is equal to h, and a is greater than 6, are contraries; both can not be true, but both may be false, since a may be less than h. Consequences. 1) The truth of either of two contra- ries involves the falsity of the other. 2) The falsity of either of two contraries does not involve the truth of the other. (5) The law of contradictories. Two contradictory prop- ositions can not both be true, nor both false. For, since 54 PSYCHOLOGY, they are conflictives, both can not be true; and since they are contradictories, they are universally inclusive; hence, no other cases are possible, and both can not be false. Thus, the propositions, a and 6, are equal, and a and h are unequal, are contradictories; both can not be true, nor both false. Consequences. 1) One of two contradictories is true and the other false. 2) The truth of either of two contradictories involves the falsity of the other. 3) The falsity of either of two contradictories involves the truth of the other. The law of contradictories is commonly called the law of excluded middle, since any middle supposition is ex- cluded. This law has a special application to the two proposi- tions, one affirming that an object of a genus belongs to one of the two contradictory species of a genus, and the other affirming that it belongs to the other species. Thus, let A be a genus divided into the two contradic- tory species, B and (7, and let D be an object in A. Then, the propositions, D is ^, and D is 6\ are contra- dictories; hence, D is either B or C; if it is one, it is not the other; and if it is not one, it is the other. Thus, since the genus propositions may be divided into the contradictory species, true propositions and false propo- sitions, any proposition is either true or false; if it is true, it is not false; and if it is false, it is not true. What is involved in a true proposition is also true; but what is involved in a false proposition may be either trne or false. The truth of the laws of harmony has been denied by certain philosophers, notably by Heraclitus and Hegel. Thus, Ferrier, in his History of Greek Philosophy, says, in his article on Heraclitus: ''Opposite determinations are not only compatible in the same object, but they are J. NON-DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 55 even necessary to the constitution of every object. . . . How does a thing get out of one state into another? Because, says Heraclitus, in being in the state in which it is, it is already out of it. Being in it is being out of it; and being out of it is being in another The two moments, the moment of being in it, and the moment of being out of it, are one, and constitute one indivisible conception of becoming " Suppose the changing states of an object to be rep- resented by A^ B, (7, D, etc. The state A appears, and in appearing disappears. A's disappearance is the ap- pearance of Bj which, in like manner, disappears in the very act of appearing; but B's disappearance is the ap- pearance of (7, which no sooner appears than it vanishes into D, and so on. Kow, here the moments of being and not being are inseparable. A's being is A's not- being; A's not-being is B's being; B's being is ^'s not- being; B's not-being is C's being, and so on. "Let us try the other alternative — A's being is not A's not-being, because, on this supposition being and not-being are held asunder as separate conceptions; and neither is A's not-being, or disappearance, B's being, or appearance. Our supposition is, that appearance, or be- ing, and disappearance, or not-being, are separate con- cepts, and, therefore, we must not suppose that the dis- appearance of A is the appearance of B What, then, happens ? This happens, that there is an interval between the appearance or being of A and the appear- ance or being of B, in which the thing is in no state at all And this is the ridiculous and contradictor v conclusion to which we are driven, if we suppose change to take place by leaps, and that being and not-being, in- stead of being mere elements of one indivisible concep- tion, are themselves distinct and completed conceptions." This view arises from a misconception of what the 56 PSYCHOLOGY, laws of harmony require. Absolute being and absolute not-being are certainly incompatible; so also are the being of A^ and, at the same instant, the not-being of A; but the not-being of A is not incompatible with the being of B^ though not identical with it, since in place of the being of B^ there might be the being of (7, or of D, or of E^ etc. There is truth in the view of Ileraclitus that things do not remain for a definite time in a fixed state, and then change by a sudden leap. The change is continu- ous, though the rate of change may be variable. But it is not true that a thing is in a state and not in that state precisely at the same instant. The thing, however, does not rest in that state, but passes through it. It is easy to reduce the Heraclitean view to an ab- surdity. Thus, to take a case chosen by Ferrier himself, let the temperature of water, at the successive moments, as it is raised from the freezing to the boiling point, be denoted by A, B, 0, D Then, according to Ferrier, "^1'5 being is A's not-being; A's not-being is B's being; B's being is B's not-being; B's not-being is C's being, and so on." Also, according to this view, the water in the state A is already out of it. " The two moments, the moment of being in it, and the moment of being out of it, are one;" and since "being out of it is , being in an- other," the water is in the states A and B at the same moment. For like reasons, it is, at the very same mo- ment, in the states B and C, and, at precisely the same moment, in the states D, BJ, etc., to the boiling jDoint. Hence, the water is freezing and boiling at the very same moment, and at the same time has all intermediate temperatures ! This consequence is fairly deduced from the premises; whereas the absurdity, that a body is, for a time, in no state at all, was deduced by Ferrier on the false assump- NON-D YNA MFC A L CON I) I TIONS. 57 tion that the law of identity requires us to hold that not- A is incompatible with B. The laws relating- to the sequence of thouglit, called the laws of Reason and Consequent^ are the following: (1) No judgment is warranted icithont a sufficient reason. We know by intuition that a reason is necessary to war- rant a judgment, but not what the reason is, unless the judgment is intuitive. (2) To affirm the reason is to affirm the consequent. Thus, to affirm that A has the fever is to affirm that he is sick. (3) To deny the consequent is to deny the reason. Thus, to deny that A is sick is to deny that he has the fever. " (4) To'deny a particular reason is not to deny the conse- quent^ but to deny every reason is to deny the consequent. Thus, to deny that A has the fever is not to deny that he is sick, since he may have some other disease; but to deny every disease is to deny that he is sick. (5) To affirm the consequent is not- to affirm a specified reason, but it is to affirm some reason. Thus, to affirm that A is sick is not to affirm that he has the fever, but it is to affirm that he has some disease. The reason may be simply the reason of knowing — ratio cognoscendi, or it m^j also be the reason of being — • 7^atio essendi ; but the laws of sequence are concerned only with the reason, as the reason of knowing, and not with the reason, as the reason of being, or the cause, which is a dynamical condition. 2d. The special axioms of the various sciences may be illustrated by those of Geometry, the fundamental axiom of which is the following : Either of two magnitudes identical in any respect is, in that respect, a substitute for the other. By remembering that similar magnitudes are identical in form, that equivalent magnitudes are identical in ex- tent, and that equal magnitudes are identical in both 58 PSYCHOLOGY. form and extent, this fundamental axiom can be expli- cated into three special axioms. (1) The axiom of similarity. Either of two similar magni- tudes is, in respect to form, a substitute for the other. (2) The axiom of equivalencij. Either of two equivalent magnitudes is, in respect to extent, a substitute for the other. (3) The axiom of equality. Either of tico equal magni- tudes is, in respect to both form and extent, a substitute for the other. The ordinary so-called axioms of Geometry may be deduced from the above as corollaries, [See Schuyler s Geometry, Art. 23.] The act of substituting one thing for another, renders an advance in thought possible; and substitution, ac- cording to the axiom, is always legitimate when the two magnitudes are identical in respect to the attributes under consideration. The special axioms may also be illustrated by the fundamental axiom of Ethics — Benevolence is the primal duty. The necessity of benevolence as the condition of the performance of duty is a rational intuition. CHAPTER V. INTUITIONS CONTINUED. 1. Substance. — Substance is the substratum or under- lying power which manifests conjoined properties or qualities. Attributes are the conjoined properties or qualities which are manifested by a substance. Attributes are known by experience. Substance itself does not appear — it is not a phenomenon; but on the condition of the manifestation of its attributes, its ne- cessity is a2:)prehended by rational intuition. Attributes imply substance as their ground or source; and sub- stance involves attributes as the modes of its existence. Attributes are not the manifestations of nothing, but of underlying power capable of manifesting them. The fact that attributes are conjoined in groups is explained by their dependence on a common substance, but is otherwise inexplicable. A substance must have attri- butes, though not necessarily a specified attribute; for, if it exist at all, it must exist in some way, and the modes of its existence are its attributes. A substance, through the action of other substances, may change its manifes- tations ; but the substance of the material universe can not be augmented or diminished, except, ab extra, by supernatural agency, and the manifestation of attributes, without substance, is impossible. A tJwig is a substance with its conjoined attributes. It is contained in space, and has date and duration in (59) 60 PSYCHOLOOY, time. The general attributes of things are quantity, quality, relation, and modality. A thing has quantity involving unitijj when regarded as one whole; plurality ^ when regarded as a substance with a multiplicity of attributes; totality ^ when regarded as the sum of the substance and conjoined attributes. A thing has quality involving existence and identity. Existence as opposed to non-existence involves reality as opposed to non-reality^ something as opposed to nothimj^ or entity the negation of non-entity. It is not possible for a thing to be and, at the same time, not to be. Identity, or the fact that a thing is itself and nothing else, involves peculiarity, or the positive attributes char- acteristic of the thing, and particularity, or the negative of the positive characteristics peculiar to other things, though it may have other attributes in common with those things. A thing has relation, involving the inherence of its attributes in the substance in j^erjoetual time; causality, when it is the cause of an effect, or the effect of a cause in successive time; reciprocity, when acting or reacting in simultaneous time. Modality is the view of a thing tiUven by the mind as influenced by the evidence relating to its reality. It embraces the following couples: Necessity, when the thing must be, or contingency, when the thing is actual or possible, but not necessary; probability, when the ev- idence of its reality overbalances the evidence of its unreality, or inqjrob ability, when the evidence of its un- reality overbalances the evidence of its reality; possibility, when the evidence does not absolutely exclude its real- ity, or impossibility, when the evidence absolutely ex- cludes its reality; certainty, wlien the evidence excludes doubt, or uncertainty, when the evidence does not ex- clude doubt. DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, 01 Substance is divided into matter and spirit. Mailer is an extended substance. It occupies space, and is contained in space, and continues in time. As occupy- ing space, it has magnitude, and form, and ultimate in- compressibility. As contained in space, it has location and mobility. As continuing through a period of time, it has date and duration. Sjnrit is that sul)stance which is endowed with intellect, sensibility, or will. If a spirit does not occupy space, it is nevertheless contained in space, and has locality and mobility. As contained in time, a spirit has date and duration. It follows, from the fundamental laws of thought, that two congruent attributes may both be present in the same thing, or both absent, or either may be present and the other absent, and that the presence or absence of either does not involve either the presence or the absence of the other; that two conflictive attributes can not both be present in the same thing, and that if either is present, the other is absent; that two contrary attributes can not both be present, but may both be ab- sent, that the presence of either involves the absence of the other, but tliat the absence of either does not involve the presence of the other; that two contradictory at- tributes can not both be present in the same thing, nor both absent, that the presence of either involves the absence of the other, and that the absence of either in- volves the presence of the other. 2. Cause. — A cause is that which produces an event. An event is that which comes to pass or takes place. It is a change either in the elements of a thing or in its relations to other things. An effect is an event pro- duced by a cause. 1st. Kinds of causes. Aristotle distinguishes four kinds of causes — formal, material, etiicient, and final. The formal cause of a thing is the essential character- 62 PSYCHOLOGY, istic which distinguishes it from other things. Thus, the plan of a house is its formal cause, since it distin- guishes it from other objects. The material cause is the matter out of whicih a thing is made. Thus, iron is the material cause of a stove. The efficient cause is the force, energy, or exertion of power which produces a thing, or changes its place or state. Thus, a blow from a bat is an efficient cause which will change the direction of a moving ball. The final cause is the end or purpose which the thing la designed to subserve. Thus, vision is the final cause of the eye. A cause is said to be imminent when it exists and operates within the thing itself It is identical with the formal cause. A cause is transcendent^ or transeunt^ when it goes beyond that in which it inheres and acts upon other things, ab extra. It is identical with the efficient cause. The word cause is sometimes used to denote simply an immediate and invariable antecedent, exclusive of the idea of efficiency. This view improperly identifies cause with a non-dynamical condition, and resolves the rela- tion of cause and effect into that of antecedence and consequence, that is, into a law of sequence. Thus, a law of nature is a general fact embracing a multitude of particular facts. A law when known enables us to predict the particular fact. It is not a cause of the facts, but a cause of our knowing them — not a ratio essendi, but a ratio cognoscendi. The word cause is also used improperly in the sense of instrument, as when it is said, a pistol was the cause of the man's death. The pistol was the instrument, while the one who fired it was the cause. The signification of the word cause is sometimes en- larged so as to embrace, not only that which is efficient DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, 63 in producing the event, but also all antecedent condi- tions, wliether dynamical or non-dynamical; in short, whatever is necessary to the occurrence of the event. Thus, Mill says: "The cause, philosophically speaking, is the sum total of the conditions, positive and negative, taken together; the whole of the contingencies of every description, which, being realized, the consequent invari- ably follows." It is best, however, to restrict the application of the word cause to those dynamical conditions which conspire to produce an event, and to employ the word conditions to signify all necessary antecedents, both negative and positive, includiag the cause. According to this view, a cause is a condition, that is, it is indispensable to the event; but a condition is not necessarily a cause. Thus space is a condition but not a cause of motion. The relation of cause to condition is that of species to its genus. Cause is that dynamical condition which produces an event. Of the various senses of the word cause, the efficient cause is the one which corresponds to the popular notion, and this is the sense in wdnch the word is here used. By using the w^ord condition to denote any necessary ante- cedent, positive or negative, dynamical or non -dynamical, and the word cause to denote the sum total of the d}"- namical conditions, the philosophical and popular signifi- cations of these terms are brought into harmony, which is a result greatly to be desired. Causes are to be distinguished from reasons, which as intellectual, moral, or spiritual influences, are either the grounds of inference or the motives for volition. As grounds of inference, reasons influence the judg- ment, and, according to their strength, warrant the con- clusion as probable or certain. As motives of volition, reasons, though causes of 64 PSYCHOLOGY, desires, are conditions but not causes of volition. They solicit, but do not compel volition. The cause of volition is the will itself When several forces, as causes of mo- tion, act upon a body, the eifect is the resultant of the combination of causes; but when different ]notives solicit action in different directions, the will, in deciding to act in accordance with the solicitations of one of these motives, sets aside the others. Volition is, therefore, not the resultant of motives, but is the act of the will in view of motives. Effects, as events, are known by experience. An event being known by experience, the conditional necessity of a cause as that which produced the event, is known by rational intuition. That there is a cause is known by intuition; what the cause is, is known by investigation. An event being given, its cause is necessary; but the supposed event not being a reality, either the cause or some other antecedent is not only not necessary, but not actual; for if all the antecedent conditions, including the cause, were actual, the event would be necessitated. The cause is, therefore, not absolutely, but conditionally necessary — it is necessary on the condition that there is an event. An event, as known by experience, is regarded as contingent; but the cause and all other antecedent con- ditions being given, the event is necessary; that is, the character of the cause and other conditions determines the nature of the effect; but since the cause is not abso- lutely necessary, the event is not absolutely necessary. 2d. Laws of causality. These are the following: (1) Every event must have a cause. (2) The eff'ect is always complex, (3) The cause is always complex. (4) The complexity of the cause is proportionate to the complexity of the effect. DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, C5 (5) Like causes and conditions are followed by like effects. The first of these laws is, Every event must have a eause; that is, every event is an effect. This law is sometimes stated. Every effect must have a cause; but this state- ment is tautological; for, by definition, an effect is that which is produced by a cause; hence, the statement. Every effect has a cause, is equivalent to the statement, Every thing which is produced by a cause is produced by a cause. But an event is that which comes to pass or takes place; and though it is true that every event has a cause, yet this is not implied in the word itself. The theories concerning the origin of the first law, re- garded as a causal judgment, are the following: 1) This judgment has its origin in the perception of cause. The first objection to this theory is that we have no such perception. This is now generally admitted. AVe perceive an event, but not the energy which produces the event. The second objection is that, if we had such a percep- tion, it could not, as a matter of experience, relating only to particular cases, account for the universality and necessity found in the judgment of causality — that every event must have a cause. 2) The casual judgment has its origin in a consciousness of causal efficiency. It is true, for example, that we are conscious of the volition to move the hand ; that we are conscious of making an effort to move it; and that we are conscious of perceiving the hand move ; but we are not conscious of the mode in which the effort produces the effect. AYe know not what intermediate ai^encies there may be between the effort and the effect. In the consciousness of effort, we find that there is something more in cause than mere antecedence. Here, perhaps, Ave have consciousness, not of cause or iiower Psy.-(}. eQ PSYCHOLOGY. itself, but of the exertion of the power in a partieular case, though not of the mode of its producing the effect. But this does not account for the universality aud ne- cessity found in the judgment of causality. 3) TTie judgment of causality is attained by induct io7i. According to this theory we find that events have causes in particular cases, and hence infer that they have causes in all cases. But as we do not perceive causes in particular cases, as we have before seen, but only succession, we have no facts to warrant the induction, unless we resolve the relation of cause and effect, as Hume has done, into that of antecedent and consequent. But should we do so, the fact would be, that, so far as observed, every event has an antecedent, or every event is a consequent; hence, by induction, it is inferred that all events, observed or unobserved, have antecedents. But such inductions give us probability only, not neces- sity. Hence, the causal judgment is not derived from induction, since this judgment affirms, as we shall see, the necessity of an efficient cause, not the probability of an antecedent. 4) The principle of causality is derived from association or custom. If this theory be true, the conviction is a growth, and should have degrees; but the conviction is as strong when the law is first apprehended as ever afterwards. Association, custom, or habit can not ac- count for a necessary principle. 5) The principle of causality is the product of a special faculty. There is no necessity of referring the causal judgment to a special faculty whose only office is to affirm this judgment ; for rational intuition, which affirms the necessity of other a priori truths, is competent to affirm this also. 6) The principle of causality is derived from the expec- tation of the uniformity of nature. But this expectation DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 67 gives only the probable, not the necessary; and does not, therefore, give us the causal judgment. 7) The principle of causality is derived from the law of contradiction. This is impossible; for, though under this law, more properly called the law of conflictives, we can reason from affirmation to denial, yet we can not reason from denial to affirmation. 8) The principle of causality is derived from the law of the conditioned. This is the opinion of Hamilton, who derives the principle of causality, not from a potency^ but from an impotency of mind. "It is the inability we experience of annihilating, in thought, an existence in time past, in other words, our utter impotence of conceiving its absolute commencement, that constitutes and explains the whole phenomenon of causality." Bow- en's Hamilton's Metaphysics, page 554. It will be observed that Hamilton rejects an absolute commencement on account of its inconceivability; but if an absolute commencement is rejected, a cause for every event must be admitted ; hence, there never was a time when there was absolutely nothing, since, on that supposition, there must have been an absolute commencement. Eter- nal existence is, therefore, a reality ; but eternal exist- ence is inconceivable. The mind is impotent to conceive the eternal. Now, if we derive a principle from this impotence, according to Hamilton's method, and reject the fact of eternal existence, because it is inconceivable, we must admit its contradictory — that there must have been an absolute commencement. If an absolute com- mencement can be rejected on the ground of its incon- ceivability, and its contradictory affirmed — that every event must have a cause, and hence that there must have been eternal existence, then, certainly, we are au- thorized to reject eternal existence on the ground of its inconceivability^ and to affirm its contradictory — an abso- 08 PSY(JirOL()(JV. lute commoricemont; hut this «(3t8 aside the hiw of enn- sulity, whieh is, therefore, hy Haniilton's owd method, shown not to be rieeessary. This method must, therefore, he eharaeterized as "impotent," since it fails to account for the necessity of the law of causality, as we are at liberty to choose hetween the two inconceivahle alter- natives. The universal rejection hy mankind of one of these inconceivahle alternatives, and the acceptance of the other, |)rov(^s that the ground of the rejection is not its inconceiva})ility. l)j Tlic inipossihllity of an ahHolutc conimenceynent is krurwn hij rational intuition^ and hence the necessity of its contradict or ij — t/uit encrfj event must /taoe a, cause. It is true that we can not conceive the eternal. The imag- ination is not competent to deal with the infinite. In- tuition ordy has this j)Ower. Though the imagination can not grasp the eternal, it is yet ahle to see that there is no past date, however I'cmote, ])efore which there mir, fjrfore a thing is, it can not act, and can not, therefore, bring itself into existence ; if it does act, it already is, and hence does not bring itself into existence. The propositions. There is an absolute commencement, and Every event must have a cause, are virtually contradic- tories, as has hefore heen shown ; but the falsity of either of two contradictories, is logically identical with the truth of the other; hence, the impossibility of an abso- lute commc^ncement, that is, that an event can take place without a cause, is the necessity that every event must have a cause. In estahlishing the law of causality, we do not employ th(; law of conflictives, or, as it is commonly called, the DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 69 law of contradiction ; for, under this law, tlioiii^h wc can pasH from tlic affii'rnation of cither of two confiictivcB to the denial of the other, yet we can not pass from the denial of either, to the affirmation of the other; but this we can do under tiie law of contradictories, com- monly called the law of excluded middle. Thus, undei* the law of conHictives, if we know that a Ijody is si)her- ical, we know that it is not cubical; but if we sirjiply know that it is not spherical, we do not know that it is cubical, since it may be cylindrical or conical, or it may have any one of the multitude of possible forms. J^iit in the case of contradictories, the Y)ropositions are not only confiictive, so that the truth of either involves the falsity of the other, but they are universally inclusive, no other case being possible, so that the falsity of either involves the truth of the other. The intuition of the impossibility of an absolute com- mencement is, therefore, virtually, the intuition of the necessity of its contradictory — that every event must have a cause. We do not reach the judgment of cau- sality tlirough the imjmtency of the mind to conceive an absolute commencement, })ut thi'ough the pofenry of the intuitive faculty to ap])rehend that an absolute com- mencement is impossible. It is to be remarked that the inconcdvabUltij of an absolute commencement, as spoken of by Hamilton, is to ])e understood in the sense that we can not under- stand how it can be, and not in the sense that it can not be imagined; for the mind can, by Jin act of the imagination, form tlu^ ])icture of an object, springing, without cause, from non-entity into being. Though the picture of an absolute commencement can l)e formed, yet it is true, not ordy that the mind is unable to un- derstand how an absolute commencement can be, but tliat it has })ositive power to know tluit such commence- 70 PSYCHOLOGY. ment can not be at all, since it clearly apprehends that it is absolutely impossible for nonentity to spring into being. On the other hand, eternal existence is incon- ceivable in the sense that it can not be imagined, and not in the sense that it is known to be impossible. Thouo'h it were true that eternal existence is inconceiv- able by us in the sense that we can not understand how it can be, yet its necessity is apprehended by reason as the condition of the facts of the universe, otherwise non- entity must have sprung, without cause, into entity, Avhich is impossible. The above demonstration shows the falsity of the the- ory of Hume, that the relation of cause and effect is re- solvable into that of antecedent and consequent. It is true that we perceive succession, noi cause. But a mere antecedent of an event is simply that which accidentally goes before the event. Hence, the absence of a mere antecedent would not be followed by the disappearance of the event; for the antecedent, whose disappearance is followed by the disappearance of the event, is more than a mere antecedent — it is a condition. Hume held, it is true, that a cause is an immediate and invariable antecedent. Then it is more than a mere antecedent, since it is that without which the event would not take place; for, if the event could take. place without it, then it is not necessarily an invariable ante- cedent. But that without which the event could not take place is a condition of the event. The conditions of an event are, therefore, all those antecedents, whether d3mamical or non-dynamical, without which the event would not take place. A non-dynamical condition, though a necessary ante- cedent, is not efficient in bringing about the event, since then it is not non-djniamical. Thus, space is a non- dynamical condition of motion. The absence of support DYNAMICAL CONDiriONS. 71 is a non-dynamical condition of the fall of a body. In general, space, time, and the absence of preventing in- fluences are the non-dynamical conditions of the occur- rence of an}^ event. This is intuitively certain; for without space and time, there could be no event, or, if there be preventing influences, the event will, of course, be prevented, and consequently will not occur. A dynamical condition is that which is efficient in producing the event. Thus, force is a dynamical condi- tion of the change of the condition of a body with respect to rest or motion. The sum of the dynamical conditions of an event is the cause of the event. If Hume's theory be true, that a cause is nothing more than an immediate and invariable antecedent, then, though it is a condition, that without which the event would not occur, it is merely a non -dynamical condi- tion, totally devoid of efficiency. It has no influence in producing the event, for then it would not be non-dy- namical. Hence, the -event must bring itself into exist- ence ; that is, nonentity springs into entity, which is absurd. Hence, an event is impossible without dj^namical conditions as well as non-dynamical; but the sum of the dynamical conditions is the cause. Hence, every event must have a cause. The remaining laws may be more briefly treated. The second law is. The effect is alivays complex. Thus, a blow of the hammer drives the nail, agitates the air, produces sound, develops heat, etc. Sometimes the elements of a complex effect are si- multaneous, and sometimes successive. The third law is. The cause is always complex. This is true of the cause proper, or the sum of the dynamical conditions. For a stronger reason is it true of the sum of all the conditions, dynamical and non-dynamical. Thus, the path of a projectile is due to the intensity 72 PSYCHOLOGY, and direction of tlie projecting force, the action of gravity, and the resistance of the air. In addition to these dy- namical conditions, we have the non-dynamical condi- tions, space, time, and the absence from its path of solid obstacles, such as trees, buildings, etc. The fourth law * is. The complexity of the cause is pro- portionate to the coviplexity of the effect. Let us consider any effect and its cause, both of which we have found to be complex: IS^ow, any modification of the effect requires a modification of the cause, since the modification of the effect is an event which must have a cause. A new element in the effect, therefore, requires a new element in the cause. The fifth law is, Like causes and conditions are followed by like effects. For whatever exists in the causes and conditions to determine the effect in one case, exists to determine it in the other case, since, by hypothesis, the causes and conditions are essentially the same. It is, however, to be observed that two effects, alike in one aspect, may follow diverse causes. Thus two men may be killed, one by a pistol ball, the other by poison. As regards death, the effects are alike; but the immediate effects on the body are as diverse as the causes themselves. 3d. Z/aw of events. The law of an event is the mode of its occurrence. An event must occur in some manner, if it occur at all, and the manner of its occurrence is its law; hence, every event must have its law. That every event must have its law is affirmed, a priori^ by intuition; what that law is can be discovered only a posteriori^ by investigation. The nature of the cause and other conditions of an event determines the character of its law, and a knowl- - For the fourth law, the author is indebted to Prof. Tappan of Kenyon College. DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 73 edge of these may enable us to predict the character of the law; but the law should never be regarded as cer- tain till verified by experience. A knowledge of law enables us to predict wliat events will take place, or what phenomena will appear, as the effects of given causes under given conditions. Effects become, in turn, the conditions and causes of other effects. Thus, phe'- nomena, as appearances, affect the conscious subject, and are the conditions of other phenomena. A thought may awaken desire, and a desire may induce volition. The events of the material world are related according to law. Effects are known by experience, but a knowledge of conditions and laws often enable us to predict conse- quences. In this power of prevision lies one of the chief advantages of science. The absolute is that which is free from the relation of dependence- on any power without itself It is the un- conditioned It is not the unrelated — that which exists out of all relation; but it is the independent — that which is free from the one relation of dependence. Though, existing out of the relation of dependence upon any thing else, the absolute is not incapable of existing in other relations to other things. isTature appears as an indefinite chain, each link of which is both an effect and a cause, or, if not a cause, at least an instrument, both conditioned and a condition. Whence, then, is nature? Three sujopositions are possi- ble — the chain of causes and effects, as to the number of links, is infinite, or finite without an absolute head, or finite with an absolute head. If the chain is infinite, each link, as an effect, is con- ditioned, and affords no resting place for thought, nince the conditioned implies the condition. Tracing the series back from the conditioned to its condition, which is also conditioned, we find, under this supposition, nothing P y.-7. 74 PSYCHOLOGY. which is not conditioned, or no absohite condition. Though every thing seems to be accounted for, by re- ferring it to its condition, yet the condition of each conditioned link is itself conditioned, and notliing is ab- solutely accounted for, since every explanation requires further explanation as we go back along the series in- definitely. This series has no head, absolute or condi- tioned, since by supposition it is infinite. If the chain is finite without an absolute head, the first link, not being absolute, is dependent, or conditioned, and conditioned without a condition, which is imj)ossible. Since the first supposition is unsatisfactory and the second involves an impossibility, the rational mind will adopt the third, or only remaining supposition — that the chain is finite, as to the number of links, and has an absolute head. From the facts of the universe, it may be inferred that the Absolute is a Divine Personality, eternal and supernatural, endowed with intellect, sensibility, and will, involving in himself as Creator, liberty, spontaneity, and autonomy, and possessing power, wisdom, and goodness, in infinite perfection. Final cause, or purpose, follows, as a corollary, from the doctrine of the Absolute as the intelligent cause of the universe. CHAPTBK VI. INTUITIONS CONTINUED. The Ego is the subject of psychical phenomena — it is that which cogitates, and feels, and wills. Psychical phenomena are known by consciousness; but the conditional necessity of the ego is known by rational intuition. These phenomena imply a subject, and consciousness of them implies a conscious subject. The subject of the phenomena is identical with the sub- ject of the consciousness, since it is not possille for a subject to be conscious of the phenomena of any other subject than itself As events beginning in time, psychical phenomena must have causes. The cause of the phenomena may be the conscious subject, endowed with the faculties of intellect, sensibility, and will, or some external object acting upon the ego as susceptible of given affections, or the ego acting in conjunction with some external object. In the first case, the ego is chiefly active ; in the second, chiefly passive; in the third, both active and passive. A faculty of the ego — its power of acting in a given manner, or its susceptibility of being in a given state — is implied b}^ every act or state. Phenomena essentially alike are i*eferred to the same faculty, but phenomena essentially unlike, are referred to different faculties. Theories relating to the ego. — They are the follow- ing:: Hume's theory. ^' For my part, when I enter most in- timately into what I call myself, I always stumble on (75) 76 PSYCHOLOGY, some particular perception or other, — of heat or cold, liglit or shade, love oi- hatred, pain or pleasure. I never catch myself^ at any time, without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception." li psychical phenomenon^ which is more general, be sub- stituted for perception^ which is too narrow, the above statement would be, not only clear, but correct. Hume also says, ''If any one, upon serious and un- prejudiced reflection, thinks he has a different notion of himself, I must confess I can no longer reason with him." This is well enough so far as it implies that the im- mediate objects of consciousness are psychical phenom- ena, but not the soul itself; yet it is incorrect, if it im- plies that there is nothing but the phenomena. But Hume farther says, '' He may, perhaps, perceive something simple and continued, which he calls himself, though ] am certain that there is no such principle in me." Human Nature^ Part IV., 8ec. 2. Hume might have said, correctly enough, I am certain that I am not conscious of any such principle in me; but he was not warranted in saying, '' I am certain that there is no such principle in me." There might have been such a principle in him, though he was not con- scious of the fa::t; for the ego does not know itself by consciousness, but apprehends the conditional necessity of itself by rational intuition. Thus, if there is thought, there is something which thinks. What did Hume mean by ''I" and "me"? With all his positiveness, it is hardly to be supposed that Hume really identified himself, whom he calls "I," with what he calls '' perception." Does the perception stumble on the perception? The "I" which stumbles on the per- ception, is to be discriminated from the perception on which it stumbles. Without the " I " as the subject of perception, the perception itself would be impossible. THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 77 ReifTs tlieory. " I am conscious of perception, but not of the object I perceive; I am conscious of memory, but not of the object I remember Our sensations and thoughts do also suggest the notion of a mind and the belief of its existence, and of its relation to our thoughts." Inquiry^ Chapt. II., Sec. 7. This. is correct, as far as it goes, but the word "suggest" is hardly strong enough. Stewarfs theory. After considering matter, Stewart says, " The case is precisely similar with respect to mind. We are not immediately conscious of its existence; but we are conscious of sensation, thought, and volition — operations which imply the existence of something which feels, thinks, and wills." Steicarfs Philosophy, page 2. This is correct and well expressed. Hamilton's theory. " Our knowledge is either of matter or of mind. Now, what is matter? What do we know of matter? Matter, or body is to us the name, either of something known, or of something unknown. In so far as matter is a name for something known, it means that which appears to us under the forms of extension, solid- ity, divisibility, figure, motion, roughness, smoothness, color, heat, cold, etc. ; in short, it is a common name for a certain series, or aggregate, or complement, of appear- ances, or phenomena, manifest in co-existence. But as the phenomena appear onl}^ in conjunction, we are com- pelled, by the constitution of our nature, to think them conjoined in and b}^ something; and as they are phe- nomena, we can not think them the phenomena of nothing, but must regard them as the properties or qualities of something that is extended, solid, figured, etc. "Now, that which manifests its qualities — in other words, that in which the appearing causes inhere, that to which they belong, is called their subject, or substance j or substratum. To this subject of the phenomena of 78 PSYCHOLOGY, extension, solidity, etc., the term matter or material sub- stance is commonly given; and therefore, as contradis- tinguished from these qualities, it is the name of some- thing unknown and inconceivable. ''The same is true in regard to mind. In so far as mind is the common name for the states of knowing, willing, feeling, desiring, etc., of which I am conscious, it is only the name for a certain series of connected phenomena or qualities, and consequently expresses only what is known. But in so far as it denotes that subject or substratum in which the phenomena of knowing, willing, etc., inhere, — something behind or under these phenomena, — it expresses, what in itself, or in its abso- lute existence, is unknown. " Thus, mind and matter, as known or knowable, are only two different series of phenomena or qualities; mind and matter as unknown and unknowable, are the two substances in which these two different series of phenomena or qualities are supposed to inhere. The existence of an unknown substance is only an inference we are compelled to make, from the existence of known phenomena; and the distinction of two substances is only inferred from the seeming incompatibility of the two series of phenomena to cohere in one." Boiven's Hamil- ton^ page 89. This passage is worthy of study. If it contains error, it is in holding the substance of both matter and mind to be unknown and unknowable. It is true that we perceive the phenomena of matter and not its sub- stance ; and that we are conscious of the phenomena of mind, and not of its substance, or of the soul itself. But if we are compelled to infer the existence and the distinction of two substances, called matter and mind, as Hamilton declares, matter and mind are not altogether unknown and unknowable, unless, forsooth, we are com- THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 79 pelled by the constitution of our minds and b}^ the force of evidence to make illogical inferences. A thing is not to be declared unknown and unknow- able, because it is not known in a certain w^ay, as, for example, by perception or consciousness ; for inference and intuition are also modes of knowledge. By infer- ence we are not to understand a mere guess, but a log- ical deduction, such as a corollary in Geometry. It must, however, be admitted that the substance of neither matter nor mind is an object of intuition ; but the necessity of substance, w^hether matter or mind, is such an object. But if the necessity of mind, as the substance or substra- tum of psychical phenomena, is known, the actuality of mind, as a substance, is also known, as involved in its necessity; hence, the substance of mind is not absolutely unknown and unknowable. Hamilton further says, '^I, at present, avoid entering into the metaphysics of substance and phenomena. I shall oidy observe, in general, that philosophers have frequently fallen into one or the other of three different errors. Some have denied the reality of any unknown ground of the known phenomena, and have maintained that mind and matter have no substantial existence, but are merely the two complements of two series of asso- ciated qualities. This doctrine is, how^ever, altogether futile. It belies the veracity of our primary beliefs; it leaves unsatisfied the strongest necessities of our intel- lectual nature ; it admits, as a fact, that the phenomena arc connected, but allows no cause explanatory .of the fact of their connection. '• Others, again, have fallen into an opposite error. They have attempted to speculate concerning the nat- ure of the unknown grounds of the phenomena of mind and matter, apart from the phenomena, and have, ac- cordingly, transcended the legitimate sphere of philosophy. 80 PSYCHOLOGY. "A third party have taken some one or more of the phenomena themselves, as the basis or substratum of the others. Thus, Descartes, at least as understood and fol- lowed by Malebranche and others of his disciples, made thought or consciousness convertible with the substance of mind; and Bishops Brown and Law, with Dr. Watts, constituted solidity and extension the substance of bodj^. This theory is, however, liable to all the objections which may be alleged against the first ''Mind can be defined only a posteriori^ — that is, only from its manifestations What we mean by mind is simply that which perceives, feels, wills, desires, etc." Pages 100 and 101. This accords with the view of Aristotle, who defines the soul to be ''the principle by which we live, and move, and perceive, and understand." It also agrees with that of St. Augustine, who says, " Mens se cognoscit cognoscendp se vivere, se meminisse, se intelligere, se velle, cogitare, scire, judicare." John Stuart Mill's theory. "My mind is but a series of feelings, a thread of consciousness, with the back- ground of the possibilities of feelings." Exam, of Ham- ilton^ Chapter XII. Mill is too much inclined to identify the mind with its phenomena. Possibly he had a glimpse of the truth in what he called " the background of the possibilities of feelings." The "background" is the soul; the "feel- ings" and, as should be added, the cognitions and the volitions are its phenomena. Bain's theory. "The operations and appearances that constitute mind are indicated by such terms as feeling, thought, memory, reason, conscience, imagination, will, j)assions, afiections, taste. But the definition of mind asj^ires to comprehend, in few words, by some generali- zation, the whole kindred of mental facts, and to exclude every thing of a foreign character." Sen, and Int. Ch. II. THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 81 In speaking of " the operations and appearances that constitute mind/' Bain identifies mind with its phenom- ena. If ''the mind is the sum total of subject experi- ences," as Bain elsewhere declares, then we are conscious of mind, since w^e are conscious of these phenomena; but the recognition of a phenomenon on its recurrence, im- plies a spiritual subject enduring through the period from the occurrence of the phenomenon to its recurrence, and therefore distinct from the fleeting phenomena. The dis- crimination of one psychical phenomenon from another, can be explained only by referring them to a common subject, which, being affected differently by them, dis- criminates the one from the other. One phenomenon can not discriminate itself from another; for that would imply that an act or an appearance is an intelligent being, which is not the case. Dr. Porter's theory. "^^ Of the ego itself we are directly conscious." Porter's Elements, Part I., ChajD. I. This statement is not to be admitted on authority, and is not verified when consciousness itself is interrogated. Consciousness is immediate and, therefore, certain knowl- edge. If the ego is conscious of itself, any sound mind, to say nothing of such philosophers as Hume, Eeid, Stewart, and Hamilton, could be no more mistaken with regard to the fact, than it could be w^ith regard to the consciousness of cognitions, feelings, and volitions. There is a sense, however, in which we may admit the truth of Dr. Porter's statement. Taking conscious- ness in its literal sense, as knowing something along with knowing something else, we grant that the ego is conscious of itself; for it know^s itself along with know- ing any thing else — -it can not know any thing else without knowing itself; neither can it know itself with- out knowing something else. But how does the ego know itself? In knowing any thing else, it apprehends, 82 PSYCHOLOGY. by rational intuition, tlie conditional necessity, and hence the reality of itself as the subject of that knowledge. But to be conscious of any thing, in the ordinary ac- ceptation of the word conscious^ is immediately to expe- rience that thing. ISTo one holds that the mind in a quiescent state is an object of consciousness; for con- sciousness itself is inconsistent w^ith quiescence. Hence, the mind can not be conscious without some other object of consciousness than the mind itself, or the conscious- ness itself, or the mind as conscious; in other words, consciousness is impossible without some other object than the quiescent mind itself, or the consciousness itself, or the conscious mind itself But wdien the ego is con- scious of any act, it knows itself through the rational intuition of its conditional necessity, as the subject both of the act and of the consciousness of the act. How Dr. Porter was led to his view will, perhaps, be seen from the following quotation : " A psychical act or state is, as we have seen, in its nature complex, consist- ing of three elements in intimate relation to each other — the ego, the object, the acting or suffering of the passing moment. But the act or suffering is inconceiv- able, except as belonging to the ego and occasioned by the object. Of this double relation, consciousness must take notice. It must, therefore, also take notice of the terms or elements to vfhich it is related." The central thought here is, " The act or suffering is inconceivable, except as belonging to an ego and occa- sioned by an object." Dropping the last expression, ^'and occasioned by an object," as not now under con- sideration, we have left, "the act or suffering is incon- ceivable, except as belonging to an ego." But the in- conceivability of "the act or suffering, except as belong- ing to an ego," is not a consciousness of the ego, and does not establish Dr. Porter's doctrine that the ego is THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY. 83 conscious of itself. It simply shows that psychical phe- nomena are inexplicable without a subject. There is, however, more than an inconceivability of the act or suffering, except as belonging to an ego — there is a positive intuition of the necessity of the ego, on the condition that the act or suffering is experienced in consciousness, otherwise these phenomena, having no subject, would be the phenomena of nothing, w^hich is impossible. Consciousness, of course, takes notice of this intuition. Should it be said that if consciousness takes notice of the intuition of the relation of the act and suf- fering to the ego, as their subject, '* it must, therefore, also take notice of the terms or elements to which it is related," the answer is, not unless these terms are present phenomena, as consciousness of memory does not take notice of the past reality remembered, since we are not conscious of the past. But the intuition itself directly apprehends, not the ego, but the necessity of the ego. If, therefore, consciousness, in taking notice of this intuition, should take notice of the terms of this intuition, it would take notice of the necessity of the ego, and not of the ego itself. But the truth is, the ego is conscious, not even of the necessity of itself, but of the intuition of the necessity of itself, and in general, of psychical phenom- ena. By rational intuition, the ego apprehends that these j)henomena must have a subject, and identifies that sub- ject with itself, since it could not be conscious of the phenomena of any other subject. The question at issue is not whether the eo-o knows the fact of its own exist- ence, that is admitted, but how this knowledge is at- tained? Dr. Porter says, immediately by consciousness. We say by rational intuition — not the intuition of the ego itself, but of its necessity. Dr. Porter further says, " It is of the very nature and essence of a psychical state to be the act or experience 84 PSYCHOLOGY. of an individual ego. We are not first conscious of the state or operation^ and then forced to look around for a something to which it is to be referred, or to which it may belong." This is true, and accords with the fact that the conditional necessity of the ego is, at once, ap- prehended by rational intuition, and that to the ego, as subject, psychical phenomena are directly referred. We are conscious, not of phenomerui in the abstract, but of determinate phenomena, — not of phenomena without a subject, but of the phenomena of the ego, the same ego which is conscious of them, since it is impossible for an ego to be conscious of the phenomena of any other ego than itself. Again, Dr. Porter says, ^'A mental state which is not produced or felt by an individual self, is as inconceivable as a triangle without three angles, or a square without four sides." But that does not prove that the soul is conscious of itself, but that psychical phenomena are in- explicable without a subject; and not only inexplicable, but impossible without a subject; but this is knowing that the soul is, through the rational intuition of its necessity, and not by consciousness. Neither conceiva- bility nor inconceivability is a tcvst of truth. We may conceive, or picture by the imagination, an event without a cause; but intuition declares that an event without a cause is an impossibihty. Wo can not conceive, or pict- ure by the imagination, infinite space, yet intuition af- firms that infinite space is a reality. Dr. Porter says again, '■' This relation of the act to the self is not inferred, but is directly known. The fact cxf memory proves this beyond dispute. In every act of memory, we know or believe that the object now recalled was formerly before the mind; in other words, I, the person remembering, did ])reviously know or experience that which I recall. But how could this be possible if THE EOO AND PEnSONAL IDENTITY. 85 the first act or state was not known, when it occurred, to belong to the same ego w4iich now recalls it?" It was known to belong to the ego, that poijit is not the one in dispute; but how was it knowji to belong to the ego? The necessity of the ego, as the subject of the original phenomena, was known by intuition ; the neces- sity of the ego is, in like manner, knoAvn as the subject of the memory; but the subject of the memory must be the same as the subject of the phenomenon remembered, otherwise the memory itself would be impossible. The ego itself is not the object of consciousness, nor even of rational intuition ; but the conditional necessity of the ego is an object of direct intuition. Knowledge of the necessity of the ego involves a knowledge of its actuality, and of this knowledge there is consciousness; but consciousness of this knowledge should not be mis- taken, as it often is, for a consciousness of the ego; if the ego itself were, in its essence, an object of conscious- ness, then indeed might we solve the mysteries of the spirit.- The ego is not the object, but the subject of con- sciousness, and if the subject, then a reality. The ego is not known by consciousness as an act or state; for that would identify the ego with a phenomenon. Neither is the ego in a definite act or state known as the object of consciousness, but it is the act or state itself that is the object. This act or state is known by rational intuition to be impossible, unless it has the ego for its subject; but the intuition that an act or state, without the ego as its subject, is impossible, is the intuition of the necessity of the ego, on the condition that there is consciousness of the act or state. Whenever the ego, by consciousness, experiences a psychical phenomenon, it ap- prehends, by the act of rational intuition, the necessity of itself, as the condition or ground of the phenomenon. The subject and the object, though distinguishable, are 86 PSYCHOLOGY, not separable in cognition — one can not be known with- out the other; but the object is known empirically, while the subject is known rationally. Personal Identity is the continued essential sameness of the ego. Every sane person has an irresistible con- viction of his personal identity, as is clearly shown by the universal anticipation of the future consequences of past acts. The necessity of personal identity is known by rational intuition as the condition of the phenomena of memory; for, if personal identity be not a fact, memory would be impossible, since the person, not being the same, could not remember the past experience of another person as his own. As it is not strictly the ego itself, which is apprehended by rational intuition, but the conditional necessity of the ego, as the subject of psychical phenom- ena, so it is not strictly personal identity itself, which is apprehended by rational intuition, but the conditional necessity of personal identity, as the condition of the fact of memor}", since intuition at once knows that, un- less personal identity be a fact, memory itself would be impossible. Personal identity does not inhere in the cognitions, feelings, and volitions themselves, which are successive and continually changing, but in the ego which cogitates and feels and wills. The ego maintains its identity, wdiile its phenomena change continually. The fact of personal identity is absolutely incompatible with the doctrine of Mr. Bain and others, that ^'the ego is the sum-total of subject experiences;" for, in the ever shift- ing phenomena of which we are conscious, the universal belief of mankind in personal identity can find no possi- ble foundation. ]S[either does consciousness constitute personal identity, as Locke seems to teach. He says, "Since consciousness THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY. 87 alwa^^s accompanies thinking, and it is that which makes every one to be what he calls self^ and thereby distin- guishes himself from all other thinking beings, in this alone consists personal identity, i, 6., the sameness of a rational being; and as far as this consciousness can be extended backward to any 2)ast action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person; it is the same self now it was then ; and it is by the same self wnth this present one that now reflects on it, that that action was done." Essay, Book II.. Chapter XXYII., Section 9. Locke here confounds the evidence of ^^ersonal identit}^ with personal identity itself Consciousness reveals psy- chical phenomena, and this revelation .is the condition on which rational intuition apprehends the necessity of the ego; consciousness likewise reveals the memory of past phenomena, and this revelation is the condition on which rational intuition apprehends the sameness of the ego, that is, personal identity. Locke is incorrect in say- ing that "consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought," for consciousness is limited to present phenomena. We remember past phenomena, and are conscious of the memory, but not of the j)be- nomena. The mem or v, much less the consciousness, does not constitute personal identity, but is the evidence of that identity. Memory, though essential to my present knowledge of my past acts, though proving my connection with those acts, is not essential to that connection ; for I might have performed those acts, though I do not now re- member them. The identity, though essential to the memory, does not consist in the memory, since it may exist, and yet the memory be wanting. Evidence is es- sential to a knowledge of a fact, but not to the fact it- self, and should not be confounded with the fact. To illustrate the relation of memory to personal iden- 88 PSYCHOLOGY. tity, take a case similar to the one given by Dr. Reid. A boy wins a prize at school; in middle life, he is made a general and wins a battle; in later life, he is made president. The general, we may suppose, remembers winning the prize, and the president remembers winning the battle but not the prize. Since the general remem- bers winning the prize, he is identical with the boy; and since the president remembers winning the battle, he is identical with the general, and consequently is identical with the boy, since the general is identical with the boy; but if memory constitutes personal iden- tity, as Locke seems to teach, then the president is not identical with the boy, since he does not remember winning the prize. Hence, the president is both identi- cal and not identical with the boy, which is absurd. The identity of the president with the boy is of course consistent with such changes as physical growth and mental development. The identity of another person is, by that person, known by rational intuition, as my own identity is known by myself; but the identity of that person is believed by me, on evidence more or less conclusive; hence, this belief may vary in degree between the limits certainty and impossibility. The identity of things in general is known by re- semblance, but is consistent with great changes, as in the case of a tree, throughout growth and decay, where there is organic unity; or, as in case of a w^agon, which has been frequently repaired. CHAPTER YII. SENSATION. 1. Sensation defined and illustrated. — Sensation is the feeling which is occasioned by the excitement of some part of the organism. In general, sensation results from some external stimulus. Take an apple, for examj^le. Through the senses of smell, taste, touch, hearing, and sight, and the muscular power, we have, res]3ectively, the sensations of odor, flavor, roughness or smoothness, sound, color, and re- sistance. The sensations are not cognitions of the apj)le, but are contingent conditions of cognitions. Sensation is a phenomenon of the Sensibility, but from its intimate relation to the Intellect, as the condition of perception, it is necessary to treat it in this connection. Sensations are known by consciousness, are analyzed, compared, identified, discriminated, and classitied by reflection, and are referred, by rational intuition, to the ego as their subject, and to some object as their cause. 2. Conditions of sensation. — These are the sensorium, excitants, action of the excitants upon the sensorium, and the sensibility. 1st. The sensorium is the nervous system and the or- gans of the special senses. It is the first condition of sensation. (1) The nervous system is a mass of excitable substance consisting of a central mass called the brain, located in the head; the spinal cord, inclosed in the back-bone; the nerves, a system of ramifying filaments; and the Psy.-8. (39) 90 PSYCHOLOGY. ganglia, or exj)an8iori of the nerves into occasional knots, or subordinate nerve centers. The nervous sub- stance consists of white matter composed of fibers, and gray matter containing fibers and cells intermingled. The fibers are exceedingly minute, and constitute the media of connection and communication. The cells or corpuscles are rounded irregular little bodies, and serve as nerve centers, or junctions, where the fibers have their origin and termini, and multiply their connections. The nerves constitute the medium of communication be- tween the various parts of the organism and brain as principal center, or the ganglia as subordinate centers. One set of nerves, the afferent^ conduct impressions to the center, and another set, the efferent, convey stimuli from the center. (2) The organs of the special senses are the nostrils, the tongue and palate, the skin, the ears, and the eyes, which are, respectively, the organs of smell, taste, touch, hearing, and sight. The nervous system and the sense organs, taken col- lectively, constitute the sensorium, which is, as before stated, the first condition of sensation. 2d. An excitant is something which is capable of af- fecting the sensorium. It is the second condition of sensation. Thus, odorous objects excite the sense of smell; sapid objects, the sense of taste; tangible, the sense of touch; audible, the sense of hearing; and visi- ble, the sense of sight. Also, special agents, as heat, light, electricity, magnet- ism, etc., affect the nerves, and afford conditions of sen^ sation. The sensation corresponds to the nerve affected. Thus, the excitement of the optic nerve is followed by the sensation of light; an excitement of the auditory nerve, by the sensation of sound. A blow, or sudden shock, or injury, may, by exciting SENSATION. 91 the nerves of any special sense organ, be followed by the sensation usually experienced in that organ. Thus, a flash of light may accompany a severe blow. Sensations at certain localities may even be induced by a thought directed to those localities, especially if the thought is accompanied with emotion. In this case, the thought serves the purpose of an excitant, and thus a given nervous state is the resultant of an antecedent nervous state and a mental act combined. Sensations may also be due to the revivals of the re- sidual excitement of the sense organ. 3d. The action of an excitant upon the sensorium is the third condition of sensation. Thus, a luminous object reflecting light to the eye is the usual condition of vis- ion ; a material object in contact with the hand, or with some other portion of the body, is the condition of the sensation of touch ; and so on, for the other senses. 4th. The sensibility is the susceptibility of feeling. It is the fourth condition of sensation. The other condi- tions are chiefly physical; but this is psychical; and sensation is itself not a physiological, but a psychical phenomenon. The excitement of the nerves, though an antecedent condition of sensation, is not sensation itself. Sensation, then, is not the excitement of the sensorium, but the sympathy of the soul with this excitement. The fact that we feel, as consciousness attests, is proof of the fact that we have sensibility. 3. Sensations localized. — A sensation is localized in that part of the sensorium aflPected. That we have the power to localize sensations is an unquestioned fact, whether that power is original or is acquired by expe- rience. Thus, the toothache is located in the tooth af- fected, and not in the hand; an injury to the foot is not referred to the head ; taste is referred to the tongue and palate. But certain sensations are vaguely localized. 92 - PSYCHOLOGY, We know by intuition that the sensation is somewhere, and by experience that it is in the sensorium, though tlie exact place in the sensorium is not always definitel}^ determined. The sensorium, psychologically considered, is the locus of sensation. 4. Object of consciousness in sensation. — The object of which we are conscious in sensation is not the ex- citant ; it is not the sensorium itself as consisting of the nervous system and the sense organs; it is not the sen- sorium excited to some form of definite action ; it is not the excitement of the sensorium; but it is the sensation in the sensorium as the locus of sensation. Thus, when I grasp a ball in the hand, I am not conscious of the ball, nor of the hand, nor of the nerves of the hand, nor of the nerves excited, nor of the excitement of the nerves, but of the sensations of touch and resistance located in the hand. I am no more conscious that the sensation is to be referred to the nerves, than that it is to be referred to the muscles or veins. The soul is not conscious that the body has nerves; it ascertains this fact from anatomical investigation; and from physi- ological reseach, it discovers that the nerves are condi- tions of sensations, since, when destroyed or paralyzed in a particular part, sensation in that part ceases. But the excitement of the nerves is attended or followed by a sensation, which is the sympathy of the soul with the nervous excitement; and this sensation is the immediate object of which we are conscious. 5. Quality of sensations. — The quality of sensation involves existence and identity. The existence of a sensation is opposed to non-existence; it is reality as opposed to non-reality, or sensation as opposed to non- sensation. But the existence of a sensation does not imply that it must have a previously mentioned, speci- fied characteristic; for it may have some other charac- SENSATION, 93 teristic. If only the existence of a sensation be given, its character is left wholly indeterminate, and may be, so far as we know, of any kind whatever. The identity of a sensation is the fact that the sensation is itself, and nothing else; but the identity of a sensation involves peculiarity^ or the positive attributes characteristic of itself, and particularity^ or the negation of the positive characteristics of any other thing. 6. Quantity of sensations. — The quantity of sensation involves its degree of intensity, and its temporal and spatial relations. 1st. The degree of intensity may vary between the limits zero and a degree so great as to be insuj)portable, resulting in unconsciousness, as is illustrated by pain, and the sensations of light and heat. 2d. The temporal relations of a sensation involve the date, or time of its occurrence, and the duration, or time of its continuance. If sensation continues but for a mo- ment, duration vanishes into date. 3d. The spatial relations of a sensation involve its lo- cality in the sensorium, and, when more than a j^oint is affected, also its extent, and vaguely, perhaps, its fig- ure, or form, as may be illustrated in case of color and touch. If but a point is affected, extent and figure vanish into locality. 7. Analysis of sensations. — The analysis of a sensa- tion, is the resolution of the sensation into its elements. A simple sensation, comprising only one element as to peculiarity, is incapable of analysis; but a complex sensation, comprising more than one element, is capable of analysis. A complex sensation can sometimes be analyzed by attentive reflection. Sensations may appear simple to consciousness when in reality they are com- plex. These ma}^ frequently be analyzed by calling to our aid the methods of physical science, as in analyzing 94 PSYCHOLOGY, the HcnsatioiiH of color and Round. Reversing the pro- cesses of analysis, we may, by a synthetic process, re- combine the elements, so as to reproduce a sensation essentially like the oriii;inal sensation. 8. Relation, identification, and discrimination of sen- sations. — Sensations are similar or dissimilar in kind^ according as they are acquired through the same sense, or through different senses, and as such may be identi- £ed or discriminated. Sensations are similar or dissimilar in variety, accord- ing as they involve similar or dissimilar qualities, as to peculiarity, and as such may be identified or discrimin- ated. Sensations similar in kind may be similar or dissim- ilar in variety; but sensations dissimilar in kind are also dissimilar in variety. Sensations similar in kind and variety may agree or differ in degree of intensity, and may accordingly be identified or discriminated. Sensations similar in kind and variety, and agreeing in degree of intensity, may agree or differ in temporal relations, and may accordingly be identified or discrim- inated. Sensations similar in kind and variety, and agreeing in intensity and in temporal relations, may agree or differ in spatial relations, and may accordingly be iden- tified or discriminated. 9. Classification of sensations. — Sensations are classi- fied as to kind when referred to the senses or organs through which they are acquired. They may be subdi- vided, both as to quality and quantity. Sensations arc general or special. 1st. The general sensations comprise all those con- nected with the various portions of the organism, except the five senses. They are the following: SENSATION, 95 (1) The aensations connected with the muscular sys- tem compriwe all those arisini^ from any posture or movement of the })0(ly, involvin^^ the contraction or re- laxation of the muscles, as in standing, walking, lifting, pulling, pushing, striking, etc. (2) The sensations connected witli the nervous system comprise those arising from the state of the nervous system — its general condition, not from a special ex- citement. The nerves, are, however, concerned in all sensation. (3) The sensations connected with the nutritive and circulatory systems are such as result from hunger or thirst, or their opposites, and those resulting from an unhealthy state of tlie organs of digestion. (4) The sensations connected with the resjrlraiory system are such as the exhilaration resulting from copi- ous respiration in pure air, and the feeling of suffocation resulting from bad air or from a lack of air. (5) The sensations resulting from the general condition of the body are such as result from the vigor or elastic- ity of health, from the weakness of disease, from rest, from fatigue, from the degree of temperature, etc. 2d. The special sensations are those which are acquired through the special senses — smell, taste, touch, hearing, and sight. These senses are the principal means for acquiring a knowledge of external objects. (1) The sensations of smell are known by conscious- ness as located in the nostrils. They may be divided, as to quality, into agreeable and disagreeable, each of which may be subdivided, both with respect to qualit}^ and quantity, into an almost endless number of vari- eties. It is, y)erha|)s, true that no two I'oses, even from the same bush, have ])recisely the same odor, and that no two things smell exactly alike. Since it is impos- sible to apply names to all these varieties, so countless 96 PSYCHOLOGY. in numbers, it is customary to designate them, either by the effects which they cause in us, or by the objects from which they proceed. Thus, we speak of agreeable or offensive odors, of the odor of the rose, etc. (2) The sensations of taste are known by conscious- ness as located in the tongue, the palate, and a portion of the pharynx. These sensations, as those of smell, are divided with respect to quality into agreeable and disa- greeable, and each of these may be subdivided into numberless varieties. Perhaps no two dishes of food have precisely the same flavor. The wonderful discrim- inating power of taste is doubtless the reason why this sense, which ministers to a gross appetite, gives name to the power of appreciating the beautiful in Nature, Literature, and Art. As it is impossible to devise names lor all the varieties of flavor, they are designated, like those of odor, by their eff'ects or by their causes. (3) The sensations of touch may be experienced at every point on the surface of the body, but especially in the ends of the Angers, the lips, and the tip of the toniJ-ue. The nature of these sensations can be learned only from experience. The sense of touch is very im- portant. In fact, certain philosophers regard touch as the fundamental sense, and the other senses as its sj)ecial modifications. (4) The sensations of hearing are located in the ear. Sounds, when classified, both as to quality and quantity, exhibit a wonderful variety. They vary from low to high, through all the intermediate degrees, and, in like manner, from feeble to loud, from soft to harsh, from smooth to rough, from light to heavy, and from musical to discordant. ]^o two persons speak the same word exactly alike, even though speaking on the same key; for there will be a difference either in the qualities of their voices, or in their manner of speaking. SENSATION. 97 (5) The sensations of sight are acquired througli the eye, and are classified botli with respect to quality and quantity. Light varies from the faintest glimmer to the most dazzling brightness. The primary colors, by their possible degrees of intensity, and by their combi- nations with one another, afford shades of color wonder- ful in beauty, and countless in variety. Light is supposed to be due to the vibrations of a subtle medium called ether. According to Tyndall, " The color of light is determined solely by its wave- length. The ether-weaves gradually diminish in length from red to violet. The length of a wave of red light is about 3 9^0 of an inch ; that of the wave of violet light is about 57^00 of an inch. The waves which pro- duce the other colors of the spectrum lie between these extremes." The velocity of light is 192,000 miles per second, which, reduced to inches, and multiplied, respectively, by 39,000 and 57,500, will give 474,439,680,000,000, and 699,494,400,000,000, the number of vibrations, per sec- ond, respectively, of red and violet light. White light is produced by a combination of all the colors in due proportion. It may also be produced by certain combinations of two colors. Any two colors which, when mixed, will produce white, are called com- plementary. The different white lights thus produced cause sensations which are indistinguishable, though the lights themselves are physically distinguishable by their different reactions. Green is produced by combining blue and yellow; and violet, by the blending of red and blue. Psy.— 9. CHAPTER YIII. PERCEPTION. 1. Perception defined as an act and as a faculty. 1st. As an act^ perception is that process of the intel- lect by which it gains a knowledge of external objects. It is sometimes called sense-perception^ to distinguish it from other processes frequently called perception, as when one says, "My perception of this truth is clear.'' We shall, however, for the sake of brevity, employ the term perception in the technical sense of that of sense- perception. 2d. As a faculty^ perception is the power to perceive external objects by means of the senses. Thus, we say, " Man is endowed with the power of perception." 2. Conditions of perception. — The conditions of per- ception are an object to be perceived, a subject capable of perceiving, and such a relation of object and subject as to cause a sensation. 3. Elements of perception. — The elements involved in the act of percei)tion are the sensational, the intuitional, the inferential, and the ideational. 1st. The sensational element is the sensation accompa- nying an excitement of the nerves, caused by the ac- tion of an excitant upon the organism. This sensation is experienced in consciousness, and is analyzed, com- pared, identified or discriminated, and classified by re- flection. Abstraction and voluntary attention are involved in reflection as the first steps. Sensation, though in- volved in the complex process of perception, is rather (98) PERCEPTION,— GENERAL VIEW, 99 the antecedent or condition of perception than perception itself. As the beginning of perception it may be re- garded as an element of the process. In fact, sensation, original or revived, mingles more or less with the other elements of perception. 2d. The intuitional element is subjective or objective. The subjective intuitional element is the apprehension, by rational intuition, of the conditional necessity of the ego, with the faculties implied, as the subject of the per- ception. This element being always present does not attract especial attention. The objective intuitional ele- ment is the apprehension, by rational intuition, of the conditioned necessity of a cause of the sensation of which we are conscious. Intuition, though apprehending the conditional necessity of the cause of the sensation, does not apprehend the cause itself. 3d. The inferential eleynent is the judgment based on experience, or on investigation, or on information in any way acquired, by which we infer what the cause of the sensation is in reality. It is the conclusion which the intellect reaches concerning the object which causes the sensation. 4th. The ideational element is the construction by an act of the imagination, of the appearance of the object which causes the sensation. Thus, we look upon an object, and see it with our eyes open. We then close our eyes, and represent the same object. In the first case, we construct the appearance under the stimulus of sensation; but in the second case, we construct the ap- pearance, by the aid of the memory, in the absence of sensation. If we can picture the object in the absence of sensation, we certainly ought to be able to do it under the stimulus of sensation. The appearance is con- structed in much the same way in the two cases, though the object, w^hen presented to the sense, giving definite 100 PSYCHOLOGY, sensations, followed by definite inferences, compels defi- nite constructions. These constructions are more vivid and rich in elements than the appearances constructed in the absence of sensation. The construction of the pictures, by the imagination, in the absence of the sen- sation, is mainly an intellectual act. There may be re- sidual sensations, as when spots are seen after pressing the eye; or revived sensations, as the images which Newton could recall, by act of the will, after looking at the sun. But, more frequently, the image formed in the absence of the object or when the sense is closed, is purely the creation of the imagination, without sen- sation. This is clear in case an object is represented which has not been perceived or thought of for a long time. No residuum of the sensation can be supposed to remain, but the image formed by the imagination is clear and distinct. A percept is the knowledge of a quality of an object gained through a single sense, as the cause of a sensa- tion in that sense. A percept may be ideated^ that is, developed into an idea, which may be committed to the keeping of the memory, and recalled, as occasion may require. The combination of all the percepts relating to an ob- ject, gained through all the senses, is the appearance of the object, as acquired by the combined use of all the senses ; but the combination of our ideas of these various percepts is our idea of the object. The combination of all the qualities of an object which are known as the objects of all our percepts relating to that object, constitutes the object as known by the act of perception. The combination of all the qualities of an object which are known as the objects of all our percepts relating to the object, together with all other qualities and pow- PERCEPTION, — GENERAL VIEW. 101 ers in tliat objectj constitute that object as it is in it- self. The perceptions through the general sensations are more or less vague. It is only those through the spe- cial sensations that are clear and distinct, and these we shall now proceed to consider. 4. Order of treatment. — Any one of the three fbUow- ing orders might be adopted: We might begin with touch, then pass to the consideration of the other senses, regarding them as modifications of the general sense of touch ; or we might begin with sight, the highest sense, then descend through hearing, touch, and taste, to the sense of smell; or we might begin with smell, the low- est sense, then ascend, through the successive gradations, to sight, the highest and most perfect sense. We have adopted the latter order as being the most simple and satisfactory. CHAPTEE IX. PERCEPTION THROUGH SMELL AND TASTE. 1. Perception through smell involves sensation, intui- tion, inference, and ideation. 1st. Sensations of odor, as known by consciousness, are located in the nostrils. They are analyzed, compared, identified or discriminated, and classified by reflection. 2d. Rational intuition apprehends the conditional ne- cessity of the subject and also of the cause. (1) The sensation being given, intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of the ego with the faculties involved, as the subject of the sensation, and of the cor- responding perception. This element is unobtrusive, since the attention of the ego is directed, not to itself, as being present in every phenomenon, but to the sen- sation and its cause, especially to the sensation. (2) Intuition also apprehends the conditional necessity of the cause of the sensation, but not the cause itself It apprehends that the sensation must have a cause, but it does not apprehend what the cause is, nor decide whether it is within or without the organism. 3d. The inference is the judgment derived from expe- rience, investigation, or other sources, inferring the cause of the sensation. This cause is not in the ego; for the ego is passive in sensation, since sensations are experienced, not only without special volition, but in spite of volition. The cause is, therefore, objective to the ego, though it is not necessarily objective to the organism. From science we learn that the immediate cause of (102) PERCEPTION TITROUOH SMELL, 103 the sensation of odor is the excitement of the olfactory nerves located in the nose; that the cause of the excite- ment is some gaseous effluvium coming in contact with the organ of smell; and that this effluvium is exhaled from bodies, thence called odorous, since the sensation follows the presence of such bodies, and ceases on their removal. The variety in the sensation of odor, in different cases, is accounted for bv the difference in the remote cause, though the peculiar nature of the cause is wholly un- known. The reason why a certain effluvium should excite one sensation rather than another can only be conjectured. Having learned by experience the nature of the sen- sation excited by the exhalations of a given odorous body, then, whenever that sensation is experienced, w^e infer the presence of that body. There is a possibility of mistake in this inference, since different objects may excite sensations of odor scarcely distinguishable. Intu- ition in affirming that the sensation has a cause, does not err; but the judgment which affirms what the cause is in itself, may err. 4th. Ldeation pictures to the mind the remote cause of the sensation, after the judgment has inferred what that cause is. In constructing the appearance, the body from which the odor proceeds is usually represented as it appears through the other senses, especially through the sense of sight. 5th. The relative prominence of sensation, intuition, in- ference, and ideation, is a matter of interest. In smell, the sensation predominates, and mainly absorbs the at- tention. The intuition of the conditional necessity of the subject and object is unobtrusive, though perhaps less so in case of the object than of the subject. The inference relates to the object which causes the sen- 1 04 PSYCHOL OGY, sation, and. is more prominent than the intuition, but less prominent than the sensation. The idea of the im- mediate cause of the excitement of the organ is vague, since the nature of this cause is occult; but the idea of the remote cause from which the exhalation comes, is clear, derived as it is from sight. 6th. The utility of the sense of smell is threefold: (1) It affords pleasure through the sensations of agree- able odors, and thus adds to the enjoyment of life. (2) It guards us, through the sensations of disagreea- ble odors, against danger from deleterious exhalations or from unwholesome food. (3) It may sometimes be used as a chemical test in identifying a substance. 7th. The sense of smell is in close sympathy with the sense of taste, which is in immediate proximity. Savory odors excite the appetite, while offensive smells occasion disgust and disinclination for food. 2. Perception through taste involves sensation, intui- tion, inference, and ideation. 1st. Sensations of flavor^ as given by consciousness, are located in the tongue and palate, and a portion of the pharynx. They are analyzed, compared, identified or discriminated, and classified by reflection. 2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object as the cause of the sensation. 3d. The inference is the judgment inferring the cause of the sensation. This cause is not in the ego, which is passive in sensation, and is, therefore, objective to the ego, but not necessarily objective to the organism. By experience, we learn that the cause of the sensa- tion of taste is a sapid body brought in contact with the organs of taste, producing in these organs an ex- citement, which is the immediate cause of the sensation. PERCEPTION THROUGH TASTE, 105 From science, we learn the structure and functions of the organs of taste, and that a sapid body, to excite the sensation of taste, must be in a liquid state, or un- dergo, at least, a partial liquefaction. What the nature of the cause of the sensation of taste is, in itself, we know not, save that the cause must be adequate to the production of the sensation. There is, perhaps, chemical action between the sapid body and the organ of taste; but why one element should pro- duce one sensation, and another element another sensa- tion, we know not. What the object is, and that it produces the sensation, can be ascertained; but how it produces the sensation, or why that sensation rather than another, is a mystery. Having learned by experience with what bodies cer- tain sensations are connected, then whenever we identify a sensation which we have learned is caused by an ob- ject of a certain class, we infer the object which excites the sensation. There is a possibility of mistake in this inference, since different objects may excite sensations scarcely distinguishable; but the mistake, if it occur, is not in the intuition that there must be a cause, but in the judgment inferring what that cause is. 4th,- Ideation pictures, not the occult quality which is the real cause of the excitement of the nerves of taste, but the object of which this cause is a quality, as it has been found by experience to appear through the other senses, especially sight and touch, and thus completes the process of perception. 5th. As to the relative i^Tominence of these four elements, it is to be observed that sensation, as the chief object of attention, predominates, though not in so marked a de- gree as in smell. The ego with the faculties involved is implicitly assumed, but is not made the object of special attention. The intuition of the conditional necessity of 106 PSYCHOLOGY. the cause is more prominent. The inference is more conspicuous than the intuition, but less conspicuous than the sensation. The image formed by ideation is clear and distinct. 6th. The utility of the sense of taste is threefold : (1) It contributes to our enjoyment through the agree- able sensations which it affords. (2) It guards against danger through the disagreeable sensations, which deleterious articles of food excite. (3) It may be used as a chemical test in identifying a given substance. 7th. Taste is intimately associated with touch, as the organs of taste are also organs of touch. In general, we may say, taste gives the sensations of flavor, and touch the sensations of roughness or smoothness; yet in certain cases, these sensations approach and seem to blend. This fact suggests the inquiry whether taste is not a special modification of touch — that is, touch trans- formed and intensified, and located in proximity to the sense of smell with which it acts in sympathy. CHAPTEE X. PERCEPTION THROUGH TOUCH AND HEARING. 1. Perception through touch involves sensation, intui- tion, inference, and ideation. 1st. Sensations of touchy as given by consciousness, are located at the extremity of the nerves terminating in the skin, especially at the tips of the fingers, the lips, and the tongue. They are analyzed, compared, identi- fied or discriminated, and classified by reflection. 2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object as the cause of the sensation. 3d. The iyiference is the judgment inferring the cause of the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego. When the sensation of touch is experienced, we infer that this sensation is caused by some external body in contact with the organ of touch. As the pressure increases, the tactual sensation runs gradually into the muscular sen- sation, and the acute perception of touch proper is trans- ferred, by insensible degrees, into the perception of a resisting body, as the cause of the muscular sensation. From Anatomy and Physiology, we learn the structure and functions of the organs of touch in their relations to the muscular and nervous systems. Through the sense of touch, especially in its relation to the muscular sensation, we obtain unimpeachable ev- idence of the existence of objects external to ourselves — not external to our spirits only, but to our bodies. (107) 108 PSYCHOLOGY, We have already found that we are conscious of sen- sations localized more or less definitely in the sensoriiim, which is immediately known as the locus of sensation, but not as the nervous system and the sense organs, which constitute, as we learn from science, the material apparatus of sensation. The sensorium, as the locus of sensation, is immediately known to be extended, since the sensations, as localized, are known to be reciprocally external. Simultaneous sensations, not reciprocally ex- ternal, especially if the same in quality, would blend into one, and be indistinguishable. But the fact that such sensations are distinguishable, is proof that they are reciprocally external, and in fact, as such, they are discriminated. Space is at once apprehended by rational intuition as the necessary logical antecedent of the fact that similar simultaneous sensations are discriminated. If the tips of the fingers of one hand be moved along the other hand, a double sensation is at once excited — the sensation in the fingers touching, and the sensation in the hand touched. The sensations in the two hands are discriminated as situated in loci reciprocally exter- nal. As the fingers move along the hand, the motion is detected by the changing localities of the sensations in the hand touched. The loci of these sensations are noticed and constructed into unity, thus giving exten- sion. On pressing the fingers the sensation becomes muscular, a perception of resistance arises, and the hand touched is known, not only as extended, but as resist- ing. The belief in the correctness of this perception is strengthened and confirmed by grasping one hand with the other. The hand grasped is known to be extended by the loci of the sensations within itself and within the grasping hand; and it has the power of resistance, and is therefore a solid, as is known by its opposing the effort made to close the other hand. PERCEPTION THROUGH TOUCIT, 109 If now the hand of another person be substituted for the hand before grasped, the sensations in the grasping hand will be simihxr to those before experienced, and their loci will reveal extent, not only in the grasping hand, but in the hand grasped, and the resistance will reveal solidity. These perceptions will be confirmed by those of the other person. If another object be grasped by the hand, analogous sensations will be experienced in the grasping hand, followed, as before, by the perception of extension, form, and resistance. The hand applied to a great variety of objects will reveal, with respect to each, its size, form, and power of resistance, and will enable us to decide whether a given object is rough or smooth, hard or soft, solid or fluid, sharp or blunt, in motion or at rest. Having thus found that there are bodies external to our organism, then, when encountering a resistance to our locomotive energy, and not being conscious of caus- ing the resistance ourselves^ but being conscious of en- deavoring to overcome it, we judge that the power causing the resistance is e:j^ternal to ourselves, and by the application of the hand, learn other qualities of the resisting object. The sensations of jpain arising when the body is cut or pierced by sharp tools, or burned by a hot body, are not sensations of touch. Such sensations, by their greater intensity, obscure those of touch, and are fol- lowed by perceptions peculiar to themselves. 4th. Ideation pictures to the mind the nature of the surface, according to the sensation^ as rough or smooth, also the form of the body, and the appearance which it would present to the eye. 5th. As to the relative jprominence of the four elements connected with the sense of touch, it is to be observed that the sensation, the intuition, the inference, and the 110 PSYCHOLOGY, idea are, in average cases, in equilibrium. The tactual sensation is sensibly experienced; the intuition of the necessity of the subject and object is clear; the inference that the sensation is caused by an external object in contact with the organ is decided ; and the ideated pict- ure distinctly embodies the inferential judgment, and thus completes the process of perception. In passing from smell, through taste to touch, we find that, in average cases, the sensation diminishes, the in- tuition remains constant, the inference becomes more positive, and the idea more clear and distinct. 6th. The utility of the sense of touch will be manifest when we reflect that it reveals the external world more positively and certainly than any other sense. The causes of the sensations of smell and taste, though their necessity is apprehended by intuition, are in their nat- ure occult. The cause of the sensation of hearing can not, but by the aid of the other senses, especially of touch, be positively known to be external to the ear itself We may question whether the object supposed to be seen be not an illusion; but when we touch it, and handle it, and find it extended, figured, solid, and resist- ing, we no longer doubt its external reality. 7th. The relation of touch to the other senses is inter- esting. It is an opinion, ancient as the time of Democ- ritus, that all the other senses are only modifications of touch. This opinion, though rejected by Aristotle with the assertion that its impossibility is manifest, was re- vived by Telesius, an Italian philosopher of the sixteenth century, and has been adopted by many philosophers of modern times. All the senses involve touch, or contact of something external with the organs of sense; but smell and taste involve, perhaps, chemical action as well as mechanical contact. The sensations given by the vari- ous senses difi'er so widely, as is evident from a compar- PERCEPTION THROUGH HEARING. Ill ison of the sensations of odor, taste, touch, sound, and color, that there is good reason for the popular classifi- cation of the five special senses. 2. Perception through hearing, as through smell, taste, and touch, involves sensation, intuition, inference, and ideation. 1st. Sensations of sounds as given by consciousness, are located in the ear. They are analyzed, compared, iden- tified or discriminated, and classified by refiection. 2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object as the cause of the sensation. 3d. The inference is the judgment inferring the cause of the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego, but not necessarily objective to the organism. We learn from experiment that a vibrating body com- municates vibrations to the air, which are propagated to the ear, causing in this organ an excitement which is the immediate cause of the sensation of which we are conscious. From the sciences of Anatomy and Physiol- ogy, we learn the structure and functions of the organ of hearing. 4th. Ideation pictures the inference, and represents the cause as it would appear through other senses, especially sight, thus completing the act of perception. 5th. As to the relative prominence of the four elements involved in hearing, it is to be observed that the sensa- tion is noticeable, the intuition real, the inference prom- inent, and the ideation clear and distinct. Let us notice the working of these elements in the process of percep- tion through hearing. We are conscious of a sensation of sound, the attention is abstracted from other things, and directed to the sensation, which is analyzed and classified. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity 112 PSYCHOLOGY. of the subject with the faculties involved. This element is unobtrusive, since the ego is implied by every phe- nomenon, and does not, therefore, attract special atten- tion. Intuition also apprehends the conditional necessity of the cause, but not what the cause is. Science informs us that the immediate cause of the sensation is the ex- citement of the auditory nerves, caused by the vibrations of the air, which are, in turn, caused by the vibrations of the sonorous body. The inference is the judgment affirming the cause. The cause is objectified — that is, the sound is judged to be caused by the vibrating body, w^hich is more or less remote, the intermediate causes being but obscurely recognized. The cause is ideated, and we are said to perceive the object. The agitation of the nerves, and the immediate and remote causes of this agitation are the conditions of the sensation ; they are the antecedents of the complex process- of the per- ception, rather than elements of that process. 6th. It is not correct to say that we perceive an ob- ject through its representative idea, as if we began with the idea as a third thing intervening between the object and the mind; for the idea is the last step in the pro- cess of perception. It is the joint product of the action of the objective cause and of the percipient mind, and embodies our inference, or conclusion, concerning the cause of the sensation. 7th. The utility of the sense of hearing is evident. Sound not only reveals external objects, but, in certain cases, w^arns us of danger, and, as employed in language, is expressive of thought, feeling, or volition. To this sense we are largely indebted for the pleasures of social intercourse, and for the enjoyments derived from the arts of music and oratory. CHAPTER XL PERCEPTION THROUGH SIGHT. Perception through sight, as through the otlier senses, involves sensation, intuition, inference, and ideation. 1st. The sensations of color ^ light ^ and shade are located in*the eye. These sensations are given by conscious- ness, and are analyzed, compared, identified or discrim- inated, and classified b}^ reflection. 2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object as the cause of the sensation. 3d. The inference is the judgment as to the cause of the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego. By experience we learn that light is an essential con- dition of vision; and, guided by touch, we infer that a material object, more or less distant, from which light comes to the eye, is the remote cause of the sensation, and is the object of perception. From Optics, as a branch of Physics, we learn the nature and laws of light, and from Anatomy" and Phj^si- ology, the structure and function of the eye. Every point in the surface of an object sends out, in all directions, rays of light in straight lines diverging from that point From a single point in the visible surface of an object, the rays of a diverging pencil in the form of a cone whose vertex is at the point and whose base fills the pupil of the eye, enter the eye through the pupil, and are, by the lenses, brought to a Psy.-lO. ( 113^) 114 PSYCHOLOGY. focus at some point on the net-work of nerves, called the retina, which lines the dark choroid coat of the inner chamber of the eye. The focus of the rays of the converging pencil is the vertex of an interior cone of rays having a common base with the exterior cone. The accommodation of the eye so as to secure distinct vision, at different distances, needs attention. It is a condition of distinct vision that the rays diverging from a point, in a pencil, and entering the pupil of the eye be brought, by the lenses, accurately to a focus on the retina of the eye. Let us suppose a point at such a distance from the eye that the diverging rays from it, which enter the eye are brought exactly to a focus on the retina. Now, if the point be removed a little farther from the ej^e, the rays from this point, which enter the eye, would be less diverging, and it would seem that they would be brought to a focus before reaching the retina, and crossing at this focus, and diverging back of it, would be spread on the retina in a circle of diffusion having the central ray for its axis. If the point be moved nearer the eye than its first position, it would seem that the interior pencil would reach the retina before the rays are brought to a focus, giving, in this case, also a diffusion circle. A circle of diffusion would actually be formed whenever the point is at a greater or less dis- tance than a certain distance, about eighteen inches in normal cases, were it not for the power of accommoda- tion which the eye possesses. The accommodation is secured by a greater convexity of the anterior surface of the lens as the point is brought nearer the eye, or a less convexity, as the point is removed farther from the eye. This change in convexity is eff'ected by a contrac- tion of the ciliary muscle, when the point is brought nearer the eye, and by a relaxation of this muscle, when the point is removed to a greater distance. PER CEPTION THE O UOH SIGHT. 1 1 5 In directing attention from a distant to a near object, or the reverse, we are conscious of a feeling indicating a change going on in the eye — in the first case, of ac- tive accommodation; in the second, of relaxation. Both the fact and the necessity of accommodation can be shown by experiment. Fix two pins upright about 3 feet apart, and look at them with one eye nearly in range w4th the pins, and about 2 feet from the nearest pin. If attention be directed to either pin, the other will appear blurred. Either j)in can, at w^ill, be made to appear distinct, but not both at the same time. We have seen that from a single point in the visible surface of an object, rays of a diverging pencil enter the eye, and are brought to a focus on the retina. Rays of pencils from adjacent points in the surface of the object are brought to foci, on the retina, in adjacent points wdiich are symmetrically arranged with respect to the corresponding points in the object. In like man- ner, rays of pencils from all the visible j^oints of the object, are brought to their proper foci in corresponding points on the retina, thus forming on the retina an im- age w^hich is a miniature picture of the object. The cause of the sensation at each point of the image on the retina is, by an act of judgment, objectified and located in its proper position in the surface of the object. If the lenses of the eye bring the rays to foci before reach- ing the retina, or if they reach the retina before coming to a focus, circles of difiusion will be formed, which by overlapping one another and confusing the image, render the perception of the object indistinct. Near-sighted persons wear concave glasses to counter- act the excessive convexity of the lenses of their eyes. As persons grow old, they gradually lose the power of adjusting their eyes to near objects, especially when small, and are obliged to use convex glasses. 116 PSYCHOLOGY. 4th. Ideation combines and pictures in their true po- sitions the objectified causes of the sensations at all the points of the image on the retina, and thus constructs the objective appearance so as to embody the conclusions of the inferential judgment. The vivid pictures appear- ing in vision are our ideas of the objects which cause the sensations. These pictures embody our conclusions respecting the objects, and as objectified, coincide with the objects, though they are not the objects themselves, as will clearly appear, while we pursue our investiga- tions. 5th. As to the relative prominence of the four elements of vision, it is to be observed that the sensation is un- obtrusive, except in case of dazzling light, and brilliant or finely-blended colors; the intuition of the conditional necessity of the ego is implicitly assumed, while that of the cause is explicitly recognized; the inference is clear and definite; and the idea is distinct and vivid. In passing from smell, through taste, touch, and hear- ing to sight, in average cases, sensation decreases from its maximum in smell to its minimum in sight; intuition remains constant; inference and ideation increase from their minimum in smell to their maximum in siii^ht. In smell and taste, sensation is greater than intuition, intu- ition than inference, and inference than ideation ; in touch, sensation, intuition, inference, and ideation are in equilibrium; in hearing and sight, sensation is less than intuition, intuition than inference, and inference than ideation. 6th. The physiological conditions of sight are the eye, with its coats, the sclerotic, choroid, and retina, its cor- nea, iris, and crystalline lens, its pupil, chambers, and humors, also the optic nerve and higher centers. Seeing is not consummated in the eye. The optic nerve conveys the impressions made on the retina to a PER CEPTION Tim O UGH SIGHT, 117 cluster of four tubercules, or ganglia, called tlie tubercula quadrigemina,, where they are received and transmitted to higher centers. These tubercules, by reflex action, excite the iris, and thus automatically contract or ex- pand the pupil, so as to regulate the amount of light received by the retina. In like manner, by reflex action, the direction of the optic axes are automatically adjusted to an object near or remote. The tubercula quadrigemina, perhaps reinforced by the optic thalamic co-ordinate visual impressions with mus- cular sensations, and thus preside over those muscular efforts made in maintaining equilibrium or producing motion, in all cases in which sight is essential to perfect action. Let the experiment be made of balancing the body on one foot with the eyes first open then closed. The visual impressions made upon the retina, received and co-ordinated by the tubercula quadrigemina and optic thalami, are sent up to the angular gyms, a section of the parietal lobe, where they are photographed and still further elaborated, and forwarded to the frontal lobes of the brain, where the judgment as to the cause of the sensation is pronounced, the conclusion ideated, and the process of vision consummated. The following quotation from Dr. Clark's Visions, page 133, places the entire process of seeing, as viewed from a physiological stand-point, in a clear light: " When light waves from an uplifted dagger fall on the retina, the eye records the facts of color, size, posi- tion, motion, etc., and transmits an account of them to the tubercula quadrigemina. This center carefully ad- justs tlie mechanism of the eye, the iris, lenses, muscular apparatus and the like, to the demands of careful obser- vation, co-ordinates the general muscular system for any movement the emergency may require, and makes its visual report to the angular gyrus. The latter center 118 PSYCHOLOGY, receives the report, perceives all the details of the dagger, the hand grasping it, the face and action of the owner, whatever constitutes an exact picture of the scene, and transmits a corresponding pictorial re])ort to the frontal lobes. Upon receiving this report — this pictorial repre- sentation, — the lobes look at it, ascertain its significance, determine whether the uplifted dagger is raised for in- spection merely, or for a threatened or real plunge, or for other purposes, communicate with the instincts and emotions, and decide the will to act." 7th. The object 2)rimarily revealed in consciousness is not the remote object, or cause of the sensation, nor the waves of light reflected from the object to the eye, nor the image formed on the retina, nor the excitement of the nerves of the retina or of the optic nerve, or of the higher centers, but the sensation of color or of light and shade, obscurely located in the retina, though this sensation is unobtrusive, except in case of strong light or brilliant colors. The phenomena following sensation — the intui- tion, the inference, and the ideation, are also objects of consciousness. The object known by rational intuition is neither the sensation, nor the nature of the exciting cause, but the conditional necessity of the ego as the subject of the sen- sation, and the conditional necessity of the object as the cause of the sensation. The objects inferred by the judgment are the visible qualities in the external object which excite sensation. The idea is the picture, or appearance, embodying our conclusions respecting the object. This idea, though originally formed under the stimulus of sensation, can be retained and recalled in the absence of sensation, in which case it is less vivid but more indeterminate. 8th. To explain how we perceive the true 2)osition, magnitude, and form of objects, let it be observed that PERCEPTION TIIEOUOII SIOIIT. 119 the cause of a sensation at a point on the retina at the vertex of an interior pencil, is objectified, ideated, and located at the vertex of the corresponding exterior pen- cil, the point from which the rays came, and the only point from which they could come, having the direction with which they meet at the focus. The objective poiut is ideated, and thus seen in its true position. The perception of the point in its true place ma}-, in part, though this is not probable, be owing to a native insight, analogous to the instinct of a young chick which perceives a crumb in its true place, as is proved by the fact that it picks it up. In man, however, the power to perceive a point in its true place, is, no doubt, chiefly, if not entirely, acquired gradually by experience, guided, in some degree, by the sense of touch, which is tutor to the eye; for, if the point be within reach, its location can be verified by stretching out the hand and touching it, or if a little farther off, by going to it. The location of more distant objects can be only approximately deter- mined by sight; but no correct estimate of the distance of such remote objects as the stars can be made through vision. The determination of these distances requires the nicest measurements and accurate computation. The causes of the sensations at all the points of the image on the retina are objectified, ideated, and per- ceived to be located, respectively, at the corresponding points of the object, giving the assemblage of all the visible points in their true ^^ositions, and thus the object is seen in its proper place, form, and magnitude. The movement of a visible point in space is detected by the movement of the image of that point on the re- tina, though of this movement we seemed to be uncon- scious, since the attention is chiefly directed to the move- ment of the objective point. The perception of a varie- gated surface proves that the sensation at each point of 120 PSYCHOLOGY, the image is referred to its special cause in the object. The cause of the sensation at each point of the image being objectified, located, and pictured at the vertex of the corresponding exterior pencil, the point from which the rajs came, the assemblage of all these objective, pictured points gives a picture of the object, having not onl}^ color, but outline and form; but since the points of this picture coincide with the corresponding points in the surface of the object, it follows that the object itself has extent and form, and this is confirmed by the sense of touch. 9th. Why does the object appear at full size when the* image on the retina is a miniature picture? The axis, or central ray of the pencil, from the objective point through the center of the lens to the image of the point on the retina, is not refracted, and is, therefore, a straight line; that is, the axes of the two corresponding pencils, exterior and interior, form one straight line. The ex- terior pencil is longer than the interior, and hence the divergence of the exterior pencil, as the rays come from the point to the eye, is less than the convergence of the interior. Now take an object, as a cane, and hold it, in a vertical position, a few yards from the eye. The axes of the pencils of rays from the extreme points of the cane cross at the center of the crystalline lens; and since the exterior pencils are longer than the in- terior, the points at the extremities of the cane, which are seen in their true position, are farther apart than the images of these points on the retina; hence, the ob- ject appears at full size, while its image on the retina is only a miniature picture. Of this image we are un- conscious, since the sensation is unobtrusive, and the attention is directed to the objective appearance. 10th. Why is the image immrtedf and how is the ob- ject seen erect? Since the axes of the pencils of rays PER CEPTION Tim O UGH SIGHT. 121 from any two points cross each other at the center of the lens, and when prolonged in straight lines^ fbrni the axes of the corresponding interior pencils, the image of the highest point of the object will be lowest on the ret- ina, and the image of the low^est point of the object will be highest on the retina. The images of the intermediate points of the object are correspondingly^ arranged on the retina, the image of the higher of two points being lower on the retina; hence, the image is inverted. For like reasons, the sides of the image are reversed; hence the image is symmetrically arranged with respect to the object. How, then, is the object seen erect, and its sides in their true position? Since the cause of the sensation at the lowest point of the image is seen in its true posi- tion at the vertex of the corresponding exterior pencil, and hence at the highest point of the object, where it actually is, and since the cause of the sensation at the highest point of the image is seen where it is, at the lowest point of the object, the object is inverted with respect to the image, and since the image is inverted, the object appears erect. 11th. Binocular vision^ or double vision through the two eyes, demands attention. Why is it that we see an object single, when an image of it is formed in each eye? If we suppose two appearances for the same ob- ject, one for each eye, giving to thought two appear- ances, then, since each appearance is in coincidence with the object, the supposed two appearances, coinciding with the object, coincide Avith each other, and form but one appearance, as we find in reality; but this one ap- pearance is the combination of two appearances, as can be proved by their separation on pressing one eye. The two appearances blend, since for each point of the image on the retina of one eye, there is a corresponding Psy.— 11. 122 PSYCHOLOGY, point of the other image, similarly situated on the ret- ina of the other eye. The sensations at the two corres- ponding points are referred to the same objective cause in its true position, which is, therefore, seen as one point; and as the same is true for every otlier point in the visible surface of the object, it is evident that the object ought to appear single, as is really the case. To render this still clearer, let us consider the appear- ance, though not the object itself, as the spontaneous creation of the intellect, under the stimulus of the sen- sation, objectifying the cause of the sensation, assigning to it color, position, extent, and form, not as constitu- ting the object, nor as representing all its qualities, since it has other qualities as revealed by the other senses, but as representing the qualities known in vision. Now, the appearance in vision, considered as an external im- age, constructed by the imagination under the stimulus of sensation, as the product of the eifort of the intellect to assign the true cause to the sensation, is in coinci- dence with the object, as is verified by touch. That the appearance is an objective image, a construc- tion or creation of the mind, an idea embod^dng our inference as to the objective cause of the sensation, and not the object itself, is evident from the fact that if we push one eye, moving it gently, we shall see two images clearly separate, one at rest and the other in motion. If the objective appearance is the object, there arc two objects, one at rest and the other in motion; but there is only one object under consideration, and that one at rest; hence, the moving image is not the object. Neither is the image at rest the object; for pushing the other eye, this image moves as well as the other; but the ob- ject is at rest, relatively, at least, as can be ascertained from the testimony of a person touching it with his hand; hence, neither image is the object, nor in this I PER CEPTION TIIU O UGH SIGHT. 1 23 ca.se in coincidence with the object, since the images are moving while the object is at rest. The reason why the objective image does not coincide with the object, when the eye is pressed, is because the internal image is thus moved to another part of the ret- ina, where an image would be formed by an object in the position of the external image, if the eye were not pressed, and hence the objective image appears in that position. Moving the eye moves the image on the ret- ina the same as if the eye remained at rest, and the object moved as the objective image appears to move; hence, the appearance is constructed, when the eye is pressed, as if the object moved. If now the pressure be gradually removed from the two eyes, the two objective images will approach and finally coincide with each other and with the object, as can be verified by the hand. The object is not now seen double, though there is an image of it on the retina of each eye; for the objective image, the appearance, seen through one eye coincides with the object, and the appearance seen through the other eye coincides with the object; hence, these two appearances, or objective images, coinciding with the same object, coincide with each other, or appear as one objective image, though they maj^ be regarded as two coincident images. The creation of the image is, in popular language, called "seeing the object," and this language is best for common use. The spontaneous inference respecting the cause of the sensation, and the ideation of the inference, or the construction, by the imagination, under the stim- ulus of the sensation, of the appearance embodying the inference, is seeing the object. But the appearance seen, when the eyes are open, is no more the object than is the appearance imagined when the eyes are shut. The appearance seen when the eyes are open is held, by the 124 PSYCHOLOGY. sensation, to a correspondence with the reality, while the appearance imagined when the eyes are shut, can be changed at will. Seeing with the two eyes aids in the perception of reliefs by which a body appears to stand out from a plane, or to have a third dimension, that is, depth, or thickness, in addition to length and breadth. Thus, when a small object, as a marble, is held near the face, the part of the surface seen by either eye, is that hem- isphere whose pole is the nearest e!xtremity of the di- ameter which, when produced, would pass through the pupil of that eye ; hence, with the two eyes, more than half of the surface is seen. In seeing, as it were, par- tially around the object, on opposite sides, the object ap- pears raised, or stands out in space. A point is not seen in the same direction with the two eyes, though it is seen in the same position. Hold one finger near the face, and look at it towards a wall, first closing one eye, then opening that eye and closing the other. It will be found that the range of the finger on the wall has perceptibly changed. Open both eyes, and look at the wall in the direction of the finger. Two transparent images of the finger appear, through which the wall is seen beyond. In looking at the wall, the optic axes, or lines of vision, are adjusted for the distance of the wall, and not for the distance of the finger, which would require a greater convergence of the axes. Two objective images of the finger appear, since the internal images, with their sensations, have the same positions on the retinas of the two eyes, as they would have if caused by two objects, one for each eye, in the ranges of the re- spective objective images, and the mind constructs the images according to the usual interpretation of such sensa- tions. The images appear transparent, neither concealing the wall in the range with it and the eye with which it FEB CEPTION THE O UGH SIGHT. 125 is seen, since that portion of the wall is seen through the other eye. If one eye be closed, one image will vanish and the other will become opaque. If that eye be opened again, the image which vanished will reappear, and the other will again become transparent. The two images w^ill approach and finally coincide, as the attention is withdraw^n from the w^all and directed to the finger, and a spot on the wall in the direction of the finger w411 appear double. 12th. The material reality is the remote cause of the sensation. The appearance is the spontaneous creation of the mind, embodying its inference concerning the cause. This ideated inference, however, is not the cause itself The real objective, or remote cause is more than an image — it is a material reality. But how do w^e know that there is such a reality? The image which embodies our ideas of the cause of a visual sensation, combines the percepts of color, locality, extent, and form. This combination of percepts, as a mere creation of the mind, located in space, could not, in itself, afPect the sense of touch, nor offer any resistance to our muscular energy. It is absurd to supj)ose that the construction, by the imagination, projected into space, of the combi- nations of decisions that the cause of certain ocular sensations has a certain color, position, extent, and form, could also excite the sensation of odor, or flavor, or sound, or touch, or oppose our locomotive energy. These new sensations must have causes; and combining our conclusions as to their causes, with our visual image, we have a more perfect knowledge of the cause. The material object which has qualities capable of exciting ocular sensations has also qualities capable of exciting sensations through the other senses. The combination of qualities is the complex manifestation of the forces of a common substance. 126 PSYCHOLOGY, In perception, we infer what sort of an object that must be which gives us certain sensations, and the objective image, or ideated appearance, is the mental construction embodying our conclusion. This image cor- responds, more or less perfectly, with the object itself In a geometric sense, the correspondence between the image and its object may be perfect, as it is in normal vision. The objective image in its position, magnitude, and form, is the space conceived to be occupied by the material object, and unless the perception is abnormal, the image and the object are in coincidence. The image represents correctly the geometric properties of the ob- ject; but in other respects, we must take the words, corresponds and represents^ with some latitude. Thus, when we see a solid, we do not understand that the objective image is a solid, in the physical sense, but that the object is; that is, that it would offer a resistance if we pressed it with the hand. In seeing an apple, for instance, we perceive color, size, and form, and construct an image which coincides with the object. We experience a sensation of color, and infer in the apple a power to excite this sensation, and this power is localized, and has assigned to it extent and form; and if our perception be correct, the locality, size, and form of the image, coincide with the locality, size, and form of the apple. But the apple is more than the image constructed by the imagination, as colored, located, extended, and figured; for it can manifest itself through all the other senses; but it is more than the combination of the percepts acquired through all the senses. If the apple is simply a combination of all our percepts concerning it — merely a complement of images and notions, embodying our spontaneous inferences, then it has no existence independent of our perceptions, and would not exist if not perceived. Our notion of it is I 1 PERCEPTION THROUGH SIGHT, 127 undoubtedly a combination of percepts or of their rep- resentative ideas; but the apple itself is the combination of all the causes of the sensations which it occasions in us, together, perhaps, with other qualities altogether unknown. This combination of qualities and causes is not dependent on our perception for its existence, but our perception of it implies its existence. The apple does not exist because it is perceived, but it is perceived because it exists and is brought into relation to our powers of perception. It might even exist and not be perceived. ]^o doubt many apples exist that have never been perceived by any human being. The appearance may be regarded as the joint product of two factors — the underlying forces which are the causes of the sensations, and the mind which interprets the sensations by inferring and ideating their causes. If either factor of the product be removed, the product disappears. Take aw^ay the external forces, and the sen- sations v/ill cease, and the appearance will vanish ; change the forces, and the sensations will change and the ap- pearance will also change; remove the mind, and there will be neither sensation nor perception. The appear- ance is not independent of the mind; but the apple, as a substance involving a collection of forces, is independ- ent of the mind. Neither is the appearance independ- ent of the external forces — a mere creation of the mind ; for then there w^ould be no cause of agreement in the appearances as constructed by diiferent minds. But the appearances to two minds of the same object are essen- tially alike, which would not be the case if the appear- ances were exclusively subjective representations; hence the appearance, as a product, has an objective factor independent of the mind, and this factor is common to the appearances to the two minds, and is the cause of their agreement. 128 PSYCHOLOGY. That the objects whose qualities, as causes, excite sen- sations in ns, are independent of the mind, is also revealed by the fact that the mind can not create its sensations at will, since these sensations are forced upon the mind, which is passive in their reception. The laws governing the combination and succession of sensations are, therefore, the laws of a non-ego. Hence, there are causes independent of ourselves, which produce in us the sensations of which we are conscious. Strictl}^, sen- sations are the joint products of the external causes and the reactions of the internal sensibility. In perception, we pass judgment on the external causes, and construct our images so as to embody our notions of them as ex- ternal objects independent of ourselves, which they are in reality, unless our minds are false and deceive us in their spontaneous, unprejudiced decisions. At the sum- mit of thought, the conclusions of the Philosopher har- monize with the inspirations of the Poet. " Full many a gem of purest ray serene, The dark, unfathom'd caves of ocean bear; Full many a flower is born to blush unseen, And waste its sweetness on the desert air." 13th. The utility of sight is evident: it opens to us a world of marvelous beauty ; it is swift and delicate, and far-reaching, taking in, at a glance, a wide spread land- scape, locating its objects countless in number, marking the wonderful variety of forms, and the nicest shades of color; it reveals a multitude of worlds beyond our own, giving us the most sublime conceptions of the grandeur of Jehovah's empire. Indispensable is the information, infinite are the blessings, and exhaustless the pleasures which it confers. CHAPTEE XII. ACQUIRED PERCEPTION. 1. Original and acquired perception defined and il- lustrated. — An original perception is a perception, through a single sense, of the quality of an external object, which is the appropriate cause of a sensation in the organ of that sense. An acquired perception is the perception of the quality of an external object which would cause a sensation in the organ of one sense, through the original perception of a quality w^hich does cause a sensation in the organ of another sense, from the knowledge gained by experi- ence that these qualities are united in the same object. The perception of the color of an extended object, through the sensation which that object causes in the eye, is an original perception ; so also is the perception of a single quality of an external object, gained through a sensation in the organ of any other sense. The visual idea formed of the appearance of a person, from hearing his voice, is an example of an acquired perception. Thus, I hear a well-known voice in an ad- joining room, and say that my friend is in that room; and though I do not see him, yet I imagine how he would appear if seen. In this case, the image is not the person, who, by supposition, is not seen. This fact accords with the doctrine of the last chapter, that the appearance is an image constructed by the mind; for, if the image, in the absence of the corresponding sensation, that is, the sensation in the organ of the sense appro- (129) I 130 PSYCHOLOGY. priate to that image, can be constructed under the stimulus of another sensation, much more can it be con- structed under the stimulus of the 23roper sensation. The image constructed under the stimulus of a sensa- tion not corresponding to the image, is less distinct and more indeterminate than the image constructed under the stimulus of the appropriate sensation. Thus, on hearing the sound of the voice in the adjoining room, the image constructed may be consistent with the sap- position that the person is sitting or standing. Ho may be in either posture, or in some other; but on going into the room, the ocular sensations caused by the person, will, by their definiteness, determine in what posture the im- age constructed under the iiifluence of the sensation shall appear. If the person change his posture, the sen- sations will change, also the perception, thus revealing the fact that there is a reality present independent of our sensations; and this reality, by determining our sensations, determines our perceptions. Our perceptions, then, are not altogether voluntary, since, when the sen- sations are present, they are spontaneously determined by the mind informed by experience, and influenced by habit. There is a great variety of acquired perceptions. Thus, I hear musical sounds, and know that they come from a violin, a piano, or a guitar, as the case may be, and imagine how the instrument looks. We say a glowing coal of fire looks hot, imagining, by its appear- ance to the eye, how it would feel to the hand. In like manner, on seeing an apple, we imagine how it would feel, or taste, or smell. In original perception, the causes of the sensations are known through the sensations themselves; but in acquired perception, the cause of a sensation which would be experienced, if the object were brought into ACqUIBED FEECEPTION. 131 relation to a certain sense, is inferred, on occasion of an original perception of the cause of another sensation ac- tually experienced through another sense. Every act of acquired perception, therefore, involves a sensation, an original jDerception, an act of memory, and a represen- tation by the imagination. The act, so far as the rep- resentation is concerned, is regulated by the law of in- tegration^ hereafter explained, by which the mind re- peating any part of an entire process, tends to restore the whole. 2. Acquired perceptions through smell. — Through the sensation of smelly we not only perceive its cause, but represent, by the imagination, the object of which the cause of the sensation is a quality, as it would ap- pear to the sight, touch, or taste. In this process, the representation involves memory and is governed by the law of association, guided by the light of experience. Having learned by experience the peculiar odor ex- haled from a given object, then whenever we experience that odor, we not only infer its cause as an exhalation from the object, but we imagine the object as it would appear through the other senses. 3. Acquired parceptions through taste. — Through the sensation of taste, we not only perceive the quality which is its cause, but we imagine the object of which that quality is a property, as it would appear to the other senses. Thus, in tasting an article of food in the dark, we know, for example, that it is an apple of a certain variety, having a certain color and other properties not originally known by taste. 4. Acquired perceptions through touch. — The orig- inal perceptions through touch are accompanied by ac- quired perceptions representing the objects as they would appear to the other senses. 5. Acquired perceptions through hearing. — Through 132 PSYCHOLOGY. hearing, we have a variety of acquired perceptions. We hear a sound, and instantly know that it is, lor example, the sound of a bell, and can, perhaps, tell what belL We say that another sound comes from a drum, another from a coach. We strike a barrel, and know from the sound whether it is full or empty. We know from the tones of a person's voice whether he is pleased or angry, though we can not distinguish a word. We are peculiarly liable to mistake in judging of the cause of sound. The rumbling of a wagon over a bridge may be mistaken for thunder; the hum of a musquito, for the blast of a bugle; the rattling of a spoon in a tea- cup, for sleigh-bells; the beating of the heart, for a rap at the door. The noise made by a pet squirrel turning the cylinder of its cage, was actually mistaken for the noise made by burglars drilling into a safe, and the police were called out to capture the thieves. We judge the cause of any familiar noise, in the main correctly; but any unusual noise is apt to mislead us in our judgment concerning its cause; for we can learn this cause only by experience. 6. Acquired perceptions through sight. — Through sights we have acquired perceptions of objects, represent- ing them as they would appear through smell, taste, touch, and hearing. Thus, an orange at a short distance, as an object of visual sense, is simply a yellow circle; but by acquired perceptions it is represented as spher- ical, with a rough surface, as capable of exciting certain sensations of odor and taste, as naturally divisible into spherical ungula, and as probably having seeds. But the most important of the acquired perceptions through sight are those relating to the magnitude, dis- tance, and form of objects. 1st. The real magnitude of an object can be estimated from its distance and apparent magnitude. ACqUIEED PERCEPTION, 133 Let I denote a linear dimension of the real magnitude of an object; d the distance; v tlie visual angle subtended by Z, at the distance :ht into action. What occurs in a paroxysm, is often forgotten by the mind on recovering its natural state, and remembered in a subsequent paroxysm. Phantasms occurring in either waJicfulness or sleep, take the forms of clairvoyance and visions. PHANTASY. 239 Clairvoyance is the power of diHCOvering objects which are supposed not to be perceptible through the senses. Tliis state is analogous to liypnotism, or artificial som- nambulism, if indeed it is not identical with it. Tlie condition!^ of clairvoyance are: an excitable condi- tion of the nervous system; certain external influences acting upon the sensitive organism; a deficiency, for the time being, of will power; a predominence, at least tem- porary, of feeling over volition, and of rj^presentation over the other cognitive acts. As to form^ clairvoyance is involuntary^ when induced in the subject without his consent, though not necessa- rily against his will; or voluntary^ when the subject yields himself up, of his own accord, to external influ- ences or to the will of another. As to the phenomena., it is claimed that the clairvoy- ant can see, for example, the diseased parts in the in- terior of his own body, or objects through a bandage or a thick wall, or at a distance too remote for vision. After allowing for exaggeration, guess-work, deception, and the drawing of information from others by questions or cautious generalizations, these f)henomena may perhaps be explained, in part, at least, b}^ the condition of the subject, and his relation to physical influences or to other minds, if indeed there would be left any thing to be explained. The subject is in a highly sensitive condition, and his representative power is abnormally active. In case of internal disease in his own body, it is plain that the sensations would sutciifcst the nature of the disease which the activity of the representative power would vividly picture. It would be very natural, in such a case, to mistake representation for perception ; and this is prob- ably done when objects at a great distance are supposed to be seen, as cities on the otlier side of the globe. 240 I'S YCHQL OGY. The condition of the subject renders him peculiarly susceptible to magnetic or electrical influences. His mind is in intimate sympathy with other minds, and in some way, through mesmeric or higher spiritual influ- ence, seems to participate in their knowledge. The phenomena of clairvoyance and those of kindred nature have by some been attributed to the influence of disembodied spirits, as in modern spiritualism. A vision is the appearance of something, as if seen, when there is, through the eye, no corresponding per- ception of an objective reality. The conditions are a highly sensitive nervous system and an intense activity of the representative power. The forms are natural vision — that induced by natural agency, — and supernatural vision — that induced by su- pernatural agency. The truth of prophecy can not be decided a priori, but must be determined a posteriori^ by evidence, the same as that of historical questions. i DIVISION III. ELABORATION AND THE ELABORATIVE FACULTIES. CHAPTEE I. ELABOKATION. Elaboration is the process by which the intellect ar- ranges objects into classes, and forms and applies gener- alized concepts or notions of these classes. The processes of elaboration are classification, concep- tion, judgment, and reasoning. The prorZw<^^,s of elaboration are classes, concepts, judg- ments, and arguments. The conditions of elaboration are the acquisitions through consciousness, reflection, rational intuition, and percep- tion, the acts and products of representation, also the faculties implied in elaboration. The faculty of elaboration is variously denominated, thu^ The elaborative or discursive faculty^ since it is em- plo3^ed lU working up, into higher forms, the materials supplied by acquisition and reproduction; the logical Jucidty, since it is the faculty employed in logical pro- cesses; the comparative faculty^ since comparison enters, as an essential element, into all its processes ; the faculty of relations, since it deals with relations; the thought faculty^ since its acts are styled thought; the rationed facidty^ understanding^ or intelligence^ since it is the fac- ulty which characterizes man as rational, and thus dis- tinguishes him from inferior beings. Psy.-21. (241) 242 PSYCHOLOGY, Let us now give a brief recapitulation of the acts of cognition : Consciousness is the experience which the sonl has of its phenomena. It is essential to cognition; for without it, any supposed process would be to us as zero. Con- sciousness involves judgment. To be conscious of a phe- nomenon involves the judgment, usually informal and unexpressed, of the existence of that phenomenon as opposed to its non-existence. But consciousness is the experience of a determinate phenomenon; hence, the judgment involved in consciousuess is not that of bare existence, but of a determinate existence, involving the identity or peculiarity and particularity of the phenome- non, and thus implying an act of comparison. Uejiection is the turning back of our cognition to the consideration of psychical phenomena. The processes involved in reflection are abstraction, attention, analysis, synthesis, comparison, identification or discrimination, and classification. Though primarily applied to the phenomena of consciousness, these processes are also employed in the investigation of the properties and re- lations of material things. The classes formed by reflection consist of species, or collections of individuals having a common attribute, and of genera, or collections of species having more general attributes than the attributes severally characteristic of the species. A class, as a collection of individuals or of species, can be represented by the imagination, though inade- quately, since a greater or less number of individuals will, almost inevitably, fail to appear in the representa- tion of the class; but a concept, as a generalized product of the logical faculty, embracing only elements common to all the members, can not, as will be shown more fully hereafter, be imagined^ it can only be thought. GENERAL VIEW. 243 Rational intuition is the apprehension of the necessity of the conditions of phenomena. Tiius, a phenomenon experienced in consciousness is, by rational intuition, referred to the conscious subject or the ego^ which, as tlie subject of consciousness, is discriminated from the non-ego^ that is, from every thing else. By rational in- tuition, the intellect apprehends the necessity of space and time, as the universal conditions of phenomena; of fundamental truth, as the condition of valid thought; of substance, as the underlying power which manifests conjoined attributes; of cause, or that which is efficient in producing events; of laws, or the modes of the oc- currence of events; and of consequences, or the effects following. These intuitions play an important part in the processes of elaboration ; and in all of them compar- ison and judgment are involved. Perception is the ^^I'ocess by which we gain a knowl- edge of the properties of external objects. The elements involved in perception are the sensational, the intuitional, the inferential, and the ideational. Perception involves comparison and judgment, and deals with the concrete. Representation is the act by which the mind repro- duces its acquisitions. It takes the form of memory, imagination, or phantasy, according as it deals with past realities, with ideals, or with phantasms. Eepresentation involves comparison and judgment, and deals with the concrete. Elaboration generalizes its materials through the acts of comparison and judgment, and thus deals with the universal. By an examination of the above processes, we dis- cover that comparison is the typical act of thought, and that the typical product is the judgment. It is not to be supposed that any one of the above processes takes place by itself, that is, in complete iso- 244 PSYCHOLOGY. lation from the others. In fact, two or more of the processes occur simultaneously. We have used the word faculty to include both an active power and a passive susceptibility, of the mind; but some writers use the word faculty to denote a power of the mind, and the word capacity to denote a susceptibil- ity. Hamilton says : '^ We are surely entitled to say in general that the mind has the faculty of exerting such and such a class of energies, or has the capacity of being modified by such and such an order of affections. We here ex-cogitate no new, no occult, principle. We only generalize certain effects, and then infer that common effects must have a common cause; we only classify certain modes, and conclude that similar modes indicate the same capacity of being modified ^o accusation can, therefore, be more ungrounded than that which has been directed against philosophers, — that they have gen- erally harbored the opinion that faculties are, like organs in the body, distinct constituents of mind." Metaphysics, pages 269, 272. The faculties, then, are powers, active or passive, with which the soul is endowed. Even the passive faculties, the susceptibilities, or capacities, are powers in the sense that the accompanying phenomena are due to their re- sponse to stimuli, or to their reaction against impressions. CHAPTEE 11. CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION. Classification is the process of forming grou^DS of ob- jects having common qualities. In classification we may proceed by generalization — the arrangement of individuals into species, and of these species into genera; or by division — the resolution of genera into species, and of species into sub-species or individuals. Conception is that process of elaboration by which the intellect forms general notions of classes of objects havino; common attributes. The product of the act of conception is called a con- cept or notion. The term concept denotes the combina- tion of common attributes which is produced by the act of conception; but the term notion denotes the marks or signs, notce^ by which the individuals of a certain class may be known. Generalization embraces synthetic specification — the formation of species from individuals, and generification — the formation of genera from species. The importance of generalization is obvious; for the objects of the universe are countless in number, while the mind is finite in its powers of comprehension. Were it not for the fact of generalization, the finite powers of the mind would be overwhelmed by the infinity of the universe. But one aim of science is to reduce multiplic- ity to unity; and in the realization of this aim, science has been highly successful, and has thus enabled the (245) 246 PSYCHOLOGY. human mind to grapple with the innumerable facts of the universe. In generalization, we begin with an examination of individual things, whether psychical phenomena or ma- terial objects. By an examination of these things, we learn what we can of them through consciousness, re- flection, rational intuition, and perception. The qualities thus discovered and represented in memory, if the ob- jects be absent, can be predicated of these objects, thus forming individual judgments; as, this apple is red, etc. By comparison^ we find that many objects have simi- lar attributes, — so far similar, that they may be regarded as alike, and hence as common. The same objects that possess similar attributes, may also j)ossess dissimilar attributes. Abstracting our attention from the dissimilar attributes, and concentrating it upon the similar, we regard these objects as alike, since they possess similar attributes, and class them together. These common at- tributes are the marks or signs by which individual objects may be known as belonging to this class; and of any individual of this class, we may predicate any of the common attributes. Our ideas of the common attributes of a class, taken together as a combination, constitute our notion or concept of the class. Other classes, having other sets of attributes, may be formed in a similar manner, and thus the universe of objects may be formed into classes. Strictl}^ speaking, we abstract our thoughts from those attributes not common to the class, yet it is common to say that we abstract the common attributes, since we consider them apart from the other qualities possessed by a part only of the individuals of the class. The ideas of the common qualities thus said to be abstracted, are called abstracts^ because they are considered apart from the attributes not common to all the individuals of the CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION, 247 class. In like maimer, a single attribute of a single object, considered apart from the other attributes of that object, may be called an abstract. Thus, the form of a particular chair, considered apart from the other attri- butes of that chair, is an abstract. If we should form abstract ideas, were it possible, of all the objects of the universe, we should not only be overwhelmed by their infinitude, but we should have ideas of qualities apart from their objects, in which state they do not exist in nature; and, viewing these qualities thus separately, we should have no knowledge of their mutual relation. Hence, we see the necessity of com- parison, so that we may not only abstract but combine the common qualities, thus forming concepts or notions, by w^hich we recognize all the objects having the qual- ities involved in the concept as a plurality of individu- als embraced in the unity of a class. By generification^ we form genera from species. We do not rest at a first generalization by which we form species from individuals, and the concepts of these spe- cies; but comparing these concepts, disregarding their differences, we observe their common elements, which w^e abstract and combine into higher concepts of genera embracing the subordinate classes as species. By comparing the concepts of these genera, disregard- ing their difPerences, abstracting and combining their common attributes, which become fewer as we ascend, we obtain still higher concepts, embracing a greater number of subordinate classes and individuals. In like 4 manner, continuing the process, we arrive, at length, practically, at the summit of our ascent — the concept being^ the highest genus, embracing all reality, both dynamical and non-dynamical. By denomination J we assign names to the classes formed by generalization, and tlius these classes, together with 248 PSYCHOL OGY, the ideas, concepts, or notions of them become embodied in verbal signs. We have called being- the highest genus, and practi- cally it is so; but as all thinking is relative, and implies discrimination, it follows that every class or concept has its negative; hence, in speculation, there is no highest genus. Thus, being is discriminated from its negative, non-being, and both being and non-being may be re- garded as species of a higher genus, and so on. To these higher genera, no names have been assigned, as they are only objects of speculation. Though, absolutely, there is no highest genus, yet, practically, for all reality, being may be thus regarded; but, relatively to any science, there is some class or concept, lower than being, which may, for the special purpose of that science, be regarded as the summum genus. By division^ the reverse of generalization, we descend to the subordinate classes and individuals. If some of the objects of a class possess a quality not possessed by other objects of that class, this quality is a difference which divides the class into two species, — one character- ized by the presence of this difference, and the other by its absence, though perhaps possessing another differ- ence which also would have served as a mark of dis- crimination in dividing the class. Beginning, then, at heing^ we divide and subdivide by introducing at each division the differences w^hich* char- acterize the species and enable us to discriminate them from one another. We thus assign to each species a less extent^ that is, fewer classes and individuals than was assigned to the genus, but a greater content^ that is, more attributes. The process of divjsion may be continued till we reach the limit in the individuals. Thus, w^e may divide being into dynamic being and non-dynamic; dynamic, into matter and spirit; matter, CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION. 249 into organic being and inorganic; organic, into animal and vegetable ; animal, into vertebrates and invertebrates, and so on, till we reach dog, spaniel, and the individual Wag, Each logical division is bifurcate^ having two branches, that is, a dichotomy^ having two members. The lowest species^ practically, is that whose division will give individuals; yet, strictly, since we can continue the division so long as there is any diiference, however minute, it would be difficult to find a species which could not be subdivided into lower species. We reach the lowest species, then, when practically we do not care to discriminate more minutely, nor to carry our sub- divisions farther, though, strictly, the infima species has no existence except in speculation. For the purposes of Psychology, every class containing sub-classes is regarded as a genus of which the sub- classes are the species; hence, the same class may be both a genus and a species; it is a genus in regard to the classes contained under it, and it is a sj)ecies in reference to the class under which it is contained. But, for the purposes of Natural Science^ the degree of subor- dination in the series is designated by a name. Thus, X/innceus introduced five grades of subordination — class, order, genus, species, variety. With the progress of science, intermediate and additional grades have been introduced. The Botanical Congress held at Paris in August, 1867, recognized twenty-one grades — kingdom, division, subdivision, class, sub-class, cohort, sub-cohort, order, sub-order, tribe, sub-tribe, genus, sub-genus, sec- tion, sub-section, species, sub-species, variety, sub-variety, variation, sub-variation. Even this list is probably not complete. The important thing to be observed is the order of the subdivision; but the degree of importance assigned to any grade varies with the opinion of diflPer- ent minds. 250 PSYCHOLOGY. A definition is such a description of a thing as will distinguish it from all other things. A thing is defined by referring it to the class immediately containing it, and distinguishing it from other things of the class by means of its characteristics. Thus, a triangle is a poly- gon of three sides. A property^ of a class is an attribute which belongs to every object of the class, though it does not enter into the definition^ since it may belong also to other classes. Thus, it is a property of a rectangle that its angles are equal, but this is also true of any regular polygon. A generic property is one which is common to all the species of a genus. Thus, the sum of the three angles of every plane triangle is equal to two right angles. A specific property is a property which is common to all the individuals of a species. Thus, two angles are equal in every isosceles triangle. A peculiar property of a class is a property which is not found in any object of any other class. Thus, it is a peculiar property of the circle that, for a given peri- meter, it contains the maximum area. A constant property is a property which is always and every-where the same. Thus, inertia is a constant property of matter. A variable property is a property subject to change in degree. Thus, density, elasticity, etc., are variable properties of matter. • An accident is a quality which may or may not be- long to certain objects. Thus, the magnitude of a body is an accident. Denomination embraces nomenclature and terminology. Nomenclature is the collection of the names of the classes in a science. The number of natural groups is, however, so large that it is impracticable to devise or to remember names for all of them. Thus, the number CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION 251 of known species of plants is at least 60,000, to say nothing of the sub-species, varieties, and sub-varieties. Some artifice is, therefore, requisite to secure a practical nomenclature. In Eotany, the higher groups, down to genera, have distinct names; but the species take the name of the genus modified by that of some attribute, as geranium sanguineum. In Chemistry, we have an ex- ample of a nomenclature in which the prefixes and suffixes used in names are significant of the nature of the substance, as perchloric acid. Terminology is the collection of the names of the parts and properties of individual objects in the province of a science. Thus, included in the terminology of Botany, are the names calyx ^ corolla^ etc., expressive of parts of plants; also the names, pinnatifid, palmatifid, etc., ex- pressive of the shape of the leaf. CHAPTEE III. CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION. Classification is the formation of groups of objects having common qualities. It embraces both generaliza- tion and division. Generalization is the formation of classes from objects having common attributes. It embraces both synthetic specification and generification. Synthetic specification is the formation of species from resembling individuals. Let Aj JBj (7, be individual objects having the common attributes, a, 6, e, d, e, f, found by examination and com- parison, — A having the additional attributes, g, h, pe- culiar to itself; and B and C, respectively, the additional attributes, i, j, and J, k. Disregarding the attributes not common to A, B. (7, and abstracting and combining the common attributes giving them special prominence, we attribute to them a kind of separate existence, objectively fictitious, though subjectively real, and thus form the concept, which we shall call C\ of the class, which we shall call Jf, em- bracing the individuals, A, B, 0, having the common at- tributes, a, b, e, d, e, /. In the concept C\ no attribute can enter which is not common to all the objects of the class; hence, all the attributes peculiar to an individual, or common to any number of individuals, less than the whole number, must be excluded. The concept, in its pure form, can not be represented (2e52) ■ GENERAL DISCUSSTON, 253 by the imagination; yet it can be rej)resented, with in- dividual attributes, in a concrete form, by calling up one or more of the individuals, A.^ B^ C. But in calling up an individual, we introduce qualities peculiar to the individual, as well as the qualities common to all the individuals of the class, though we banish, as completely as possible, the qualities peculiar to the individual, and give to the common qualities special prominence. The image thus obtained is individual ; but It has a potential universality in the fact that we may vary it so as to represent any individual of the class, by droj)ping the j)eculiarities of one individual and incorporating those of another. But if we drop the peculiarities of one individual without incorporating those of another, the image itself would vanish. In attempting, for ex- ample, to represent, by the imagination, the concept of the class horse, we should call up the image of a horse of a particular color, form, size, etc., introducing not only the qualities common to all horses, but also those peculiar to some of the individuals of the class. We thus have an image of an individual, real or imaginary, but not the concept of the class. If we should drop all attributes not belonging to the concept, the image itself would vanish, since we could not construct the image, unless we assign to it some particular color, form, size, etc. Hence, a concept, in its pure generality, can not be reiiresented b}^ the imagination. On the other hand, if we should drop from the image all that is characteristic of the class horse, retaining, at the same time, the other elements, it would no longer be recoo-nized as the imas-e of a horse, but it would still have the elements common to animal, or, dropping these, the elements common to organic being, then the element common to being, dropping this, the image would vanish. Hence, every image must contain both particular and 254 PSYCHOLOGY, universal elements, and will vanish whenever either kind is dropped. The universal and the particular are, therefore, not two kinds of ideas, but the two elements of every idea. An idea that is exclusively general or exclusively particular can not be realized, but can only be approached by directing the attention especially to the one kind of elements or the other. " The common element that enters into every cognition is that of being; but with this, there is also always present, the subjective intuition of the conditional necessity of the ego, as the subject of the cognition. Though the general concept can not be represented, as a pure universal, by the imagination, yet it is possi- ble to represent the class as a collection of individuals. Thus, the class denoted by X is the collection of the individuals, A^ B^ (7, and as such, it is capable of repre- sentation. A class consisting of a vast multitude, as the class man, can not be represented in its totality, since great multitudes of individuals are unknown. Thus, many human beings have died, many are not yet born, yet such a number and variety can be represented, as will do fair justice to the entire class. We have formed the individuals A, 5, (7, having the common attributes, a, 6, c, d, e, /, into the class X, of which the concept C\ is the combination, abcdef of these common attributes. IN'ow, let Jj, Mj iV, be individuals having the common attributes, b, c, f] I, m, n, — L having the additional attri- butes, t, u, peculiar to itself; and M and iV, respectively, the additional attributes, v, w\ and iv, x. We thus form the concept (7", of the class which we shall call Y, con- taining the objects X, Jf, iV, having the common attri- butes, 6, c, /, ?, m, n. Generification is the formation of higher classes from species. These classes are called genera (sing, geyius). GENERAL DISCUSSION. 255 Taking the results obtained under synthetic specifica- tion, denoting the sum of the attributes by the proper letters, without the sign of addition, and writing the attributes of the individuals, and the concepts of the classes, as subscripts, we have A ahcdef gh BahcdefiJ )- ^= X abode f ■= C Cabcdefjk Lbcflmntu Mbcflmnviv V ^=^ Ybcflr)in=^ C" Nbcfl mnwx The expression, Ahcdef gh^ is read the individual A, whose attributes are a^h^ c^ d^e^f^g ; and Xabcdef = c' is read the class JT, whose concept, ah cd ef^ equals C\ l^ow, if we wish, by a higher generalization, to form a higher class containing the classes X and Y, we dis- regard the attributes a,d,e, peculiar to the concept, C", of the class Jl, also the attributes, I, m, n, peculiar to the concept, (7'', of the class Y, and, by abstracting and com- bining the attributes, 6, c,/, common to (7' and C'\ we ' form the concept, C^^\ of the genus which we shall call Z, embracing the classes, X and Y, as species. The process of generification is thus exhibited : JLabcdef=C'l ^x. ^ 1 bcjlmn=^ C" ) tn In like manner, having formed another genus con- taining attributes in common with Z^ we form a still higher genus, and so on. Division is the resolution of a class into sub-classes or individuals. Comparing the objects embraced in Z^ we find, not only that they possess the attributes, 6, c,/, in 256 PSYCHOLOGY, common, but that some of them possess the attributes, a, d^ e, not possessed by the remaining objects of the class, and that the remaining objects possess the attri- butes, I. m, n, not possessed by the first. We disregard the attributes, b, c, /, common to all the objects of the genus Zj and direct attention to the attributes, a, r/, e, and I, m, n, respectively common to the two parts of the genus ^. Either of the groups of attributes, a, d, e, and I, m, /I, is sufficient to divide the genus into two species, one containing the group of attributes under considera- tion, and the other not containing this group. We may, if we choose, take both groups into consideration in the division. We then divide the genus Z into the two species, designated, respectively, by ^ and Y, which, though containing the attributes, Z>, c, /, characteristic of the genus, and hence common to JT and Y, are charac- terized, respectively, by the attributes, a, d, e, and I, m, n. This division of the genus, Z^ into the two species, -Z and Y, is called analytic specification, to distinguish it from synthetic specification, in which a species is formed from similar individuals. In discriminating ^ and Y, as species of the genus Z, the attributes, a, d, e, and I, m, n, respectively character- istic of JT and Y, are made especially prominent, while the attributes, 6, c, /, characteristic of the genus Z, and hence common to JC and Y, are obscurely recognized. In generalization, similarities play the important part, but differences in division. Similarities are detected by identifivcation, and differences by discrimination. The discrimination of differences, unchecked by the identification of similarities, would individualize and iso- late every tiling, and render science impossible; but the identification of similarities leads to generalization, in- duction, and the comprehensive truths of science. The division of X gives the individuals. A, B, (7, each GENERAL DISCUSSION. 257 of which, though containing the attributes, a^ d, e, char- acteristic of JC, also the attributes, 6, lique; hence, triangles are divided into right tri- Q UA XTITY OF CONCEPTS. 277 angles and oblique triangles. This division gives a di- chotomy, of which the two parts are- contradictories, since they are niiittially repugnant, and together univer- sallv inchisive of all trianades. Btit shotild we divide triano'les into rio-ht triano'les, acute triano:ies. and obtuse triano'les, we should have a trichotomv. whose members are contraries, since thev are mtituallv reptici:nant. but no two of them universallv inclusive. The definition of a sj^ecies refers it to its genus, and characterizes it bv its content, and hence determines its extent and distingtiishes it from the other species of the genus. Analysis gives content: division, extent: and definition, both content and extent. The comprehension of a concept can not be repre- sented by the imagination, a2:)art from the extension, nor the extension apart from the comprehension : btit the class can be represented, as having both comji^rehen- sion and extension, as found in the realities of nattire. 3d. jRelation of t?ie comprehension and the extension of concepts. (l^ The comprehension of a concept varies inversely as its extension, that is. the o-reater the extent the less the content, aiul converselv: for the hio-her the o-entis. the greater the extension, and the less the comprehen- sion : and the lower the species, the less the extension and the greater the comprehension. Thtis. the compre- hension of the concept animal is less than that of the concept horse, since it contains those attributes only which are common to all the subordinate sjiecies. whereas the concept horse contains all the attribtites common to all these species, and to all the species of the gentis con- tainino- horse, toa'ether with what is characteristic of it- self Btit the extension of the concept animal is greater than that of the concept horse, since it contains the class 278 PSYCHOLOGY, horse, as a subdivision, together with a great variety of other subdivisions. (2) The simple concept being is a minimum as to com- prehension and a maximum as to extension. It is a minimum as to comprehension, since it contains in it no essential attribute which is not an attribute of every class, sub-class, and individual contained under it, and the only attribute thus common is existence. It is a maximum as to extension; for, since being is the high- est genus, it contains under it all other classes, sub- classes, and individuals. It is, therefore, extensive rather than comprehensive. (3) The class being is incapable of definition, the com- prehension of its concept is incapable of analysis, but the extension is capable of division. The class is inca- pable of definition, since it is not contained under a higher genus, neither has it a difi*erential attribute. The comprehension of its concept is incapable of analysis, since it contains but one element — existence. The ex- tension of its concept is capable of division, since by an analysis of the comprehension of the parts of the exten- sion, they are found to possess qualities peculiar to each; hence, the class being can be resolved into classes, sub- classes, and so on, down to individuals. (4) An individual concept is a maximum as to com- prehension and a minimum as to extension. It is a maximum as to comprehension, since it contains all the attributes common to all the individuals of its class, to- gether with what is peculiar to itself It is a minimum as to extension, since it contains no classes or individu- als under it. It is, therefore, comprehensive rather than extensive. (5) An individual is capable of definition, the compre- hension of its concept is capable of analysis, but the extension is incapable of division. An individual is ca- Q UANTITY OF CONCEPTS, 279 pable of definition, since it is contained under a class, and has peculiar qualities. The comprehension of its concej^t is capable of analysis, since it involves a plural- ity of attributes. The extension of its concept is inca- pable of division, since it contains neither classes nor individuals undei* it. (6) A concept neither simple nor individual is neither a maximum nor a minimum, either as to comprehension or to extension. Since it is neither the highest genus nor an individual, it is neither a maximum nor a mini- mum as to comprehension; for, the lower the species, the greater the comprehension, down to the individuals, and the higher the genus, the less the comprehension, up to the highest genus. For like reason, it is neither a maximum nor a minimum as to extension; for the higher the genus, the greater the extension, up to the highest genus, and the lower the species, the less the extension, down to the individuals. (7) A class, not the highest genus, is capable of defi- nition, the comprehension of its concept is capable of analysis, and the extension is capable of division. The class is capable of definition, since it is contained under a higher class, and has characteristic qualities. The comprehension of its concept is cajDable of analysis, since it involves a plurality of attributes, and the extension is capable of division, since the class contains other classes or individuals under it. It will be observed that a class may be defined unless it is the highest genus; that an individual may be de- fined; that a concept is identified by naming the class of which it is the concept; that the comprehension of a concept is analyzed but not divided ; that the extension of a concept is divided but not analyzed; that the com- prehension of the concept being, does not admit of anal- ysis, though its extension admits of division ; that the 280 PSYCHOLOGY, extension of the concept of an individual does not admit of division, though its comprehension admits of analysis; that the class beino- contains but one universal attribute — existence^ though all actual attributes are contained in its parts; and that being is divided by analyzing the contents of its parts. In rising, by generalization, from individuals to spe- cies, we abstract our thoughts from the peculiarities of the individuals, and overlook their idiosyncrasies. Thus, the concejDt of the species is less rich in attributes than the idea of the individual. In like manner, in rising from species to genera, and from these to still higher genera, the ascending hierarchy of concepts become more and more meager in content, till we reach that of being, which is characterized by no attribute but that of existence. Thus, the higher we rise, the greater the poverty of our concepts in content, till they terminate in the minimum of knowledge, if not in utter nescience. There are two remedies for this undesirable result: (1) The tendencies of abstraction and generalization are counteracted by those of division and discrimination. As we may rise higher and higher, and thus drop at- tributes continually, so we may descend deeper and deeper, and thus multiply attributes indefinitely. Though, as we ascend towards the summit, the general concepts of the higher classes necessarily contain fewer and fewer elements, yet the classes themselves contain, not as uni- versally diffused, but somewhere in their subdivisions, every actual attribute. As we rise, though we drop the elements not common from the contents of the general concept, 3^et we retain them as elements of parts of the extent. Thus being, though indeed containing but one universal attribute, that of existence, contains in its sub- divisions all attributes, and thus the division of being, not of the concept, but of the class, gives all reality. QUANTITY OF CONCEPTS. 281 (2) The intuition of reason declares the necessity of the conditions of whatever exists, thus giving to every thing its expUmation and law, and uniting all realities by their common dependence on the Absolute First Cause. 4th. Other forms of quantity. In addition to the two forms of quantity, the comprehension and extension of concepts, called the logical luJtoles, there are other wholes of which the following are specimens: (1) The dianoetic ivhole — the lohole of thought. Every thing has its negation, and the two comprise the uni- verse, — thus B and non-^. Then, we can say, A is B or non-^. (2) The mathematical whole — the whole of necessary form. Of this species, there are two varieties: The arithmetical ivhole, as a collection of objects, involving time in their reckoning. The geometric ichole, as a cubic foot of wood, a barrel of water. This is a mass whole, and space is involved. (3) The essential whole — the whole of being. Of this S23ecies there are two varieties : T/ie substantial whole — the substance with its attributes. The causal ichole — the cause and its effects. The substantial Avhole and the causal whole are the complementary parts of the essen- tial whole. (4) The corporate whole — the formal or aesthetic whole. This is the idea revealed in the matter by the form. (5) The accidental whole — the whole by accident. Of this species there are three varieties — Of degree^ as man- kind comprises the rich and the poor. Of position^ as the upper and the lower, the right and the left, etc. Of affinity^ as the family comprises the parent and the children. Psy.~24. CHAPTEE YTI. QUALITY OF CONCEPTS. The Quality of a concept has relation to the subject mind, and is chiefl}^ found in the pairs of opposites — clearness and obscurit}^, distinctness and indistinctness. 1st. Clearness and obscurity. A concept is clear when it is discriminated, as a whole, from other concepts. A concept is obscure^ when it is confounded with other concepts. Clearness is attained and obscurity avoided by definition of the class. The degree of clearness or obscurity of a concept is variable. Perfect clearness, obviating all confusion, is a possible, though a rare attainment. Total obscurity, ob- literating all distinction, would, when reached, cause the concept itself to vanish. The degree of obscurity, there- fore, varies between the limits, perfect clearness and total obscurity. A concept is characterized as clear or obscure, according to its prevailing quality. 2d. Distinctness and indistinctness. Distinctness and indistinctness have two varieties — comprehensive and extensive. A concept has comprehensive or extensive distinctness or indistinctness, according as the attributes involved in its content, or the subdivisions embraced by its extent, are discriminated or confounded. Compre- hensive distinctness is attained, and comprehensive in- distinctness is avoided, by analysis. Extensive distinct- ness is attained, and extensive indistinctness is avoided, by division. The degree of distinctness, in general, varies between ( 282 ) q UALITY OF CONCEPTS. 283 the limits perfect distinctness and com2:)lete indistinct- ness. A concept is characterized as distinct or indistinct, according to its prevailing quality. A concept may be clear, that is, be discriminated, as a whole, from other concepts, and yet be more or less indistinct. Thus, our concept of the genus animal may be clear, and still be far from having either comprehen- sive or extensive distinctness ; but a concept having both comprehensive and extensive distinctness, has also the quality of clearness. Distinctness is, therefore, a higher virtue than clearness, and its attainment is a higher achievement. 3d. Concepts admitting of distinctness. Since compre- hensive distinctness signifies a clear apprehension and discrimination of the attributes involved in the content • of a concept, and extensive distinctness, a clear apj)re- hension and discrimination of the classes and individu- als embraced in the extent, and bound together into unity by the nexus or content, it follows, (1) That the concept being — the highest genus, since it is a maximum as to extent, and a minimum as to content — is capable of extensive distinctness, but incaj)a- ble of comprehensive. (2) That an individual concept, being a maximum as to content, but a minimum as to extent, is capable of comprehensive distinctness, but inca])able of extensive. (3) That a concept neither the highest genus nor in- dividual, since it is not a minimum either as to content or extent, is capable both of comprehensive and exten- sive distinctness. 4th. Rules for distinctness. These are the following: (1) To secure comprehensive distiiictness, analyze the content of the concept, noting especially the positive, intrinsic, and essential elements, rather than the nega- tive, extrinsic, and accidental. 284 PSYCHOLOGY. (2) To secure extensive distinctness, divide the extent of the concejDt, according to the peculiar, positive char- acteristics of the parts. 5th. Sources of indistinctness. These are of two kinds: (1) The nature of the concept itself, which is multi- plicity, either as to content or extent, bound by a men- tal act, into unity. (2) The dependence of the concept on language, as the condition of its continuance. The name becomes a sym- bol for the concept, and frequently the mind is content to employ the word without taking the trouble to call up the concept. This may be well when we are able to call up, at pleasure, the meaning of the word, in a clear and distinct concept, thus relieving the mind of an unnecessary burden. But when the mind employs a word without the ability to call up the corresponding concept, indistinctness and confusion of thought are sure to follow. Use no word whose meaning; is not clear. 6th. Illustrations of clearness and obscurity^ distinctness and indistinctness. Hamilton says : '' The expressions, clearness and obscurity, distinctness and indistinctness, as applied to concepts, originally denoted certain modi- fications of vision; from vision, they were analogically extended to the other senses, to imagination, and finally to thought. It may, therefore, enable us the better to comprehend their secondary application to consider their primary. " To Leibnitz we owe the precise distinction of con- cepts into clear and distinct, and from him I borrow the following illustration: In darkness — the complete ob- scurity of night — we see nothing — there is no percep- tion, — no discrimination of objects. As the light dawns, the obscurity diminishes, the deep and uniform sensation of darkness is modified, — we are conscious of a change, — we see something, but are still unable to distinguish QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS. 285 its features, — we know not what it is. As the light in- creases, the outlines of wholes begin to appear, but still not with a distinctness sufficient to allow us to perceive them completely; but when this is rendered j)ossible by the rising intensity of the light, we are then said to see clearly. We then recognize mountains, plains, houses, trees, animals, etc. ; that is, we discriminate these objects as wholes, as unities, from one another. But their parts, — the manifold, of which these unities are the sum — their parts still lose themselves in one another; they are still but indistinctly visible. ^'At length, when daylight has fully sprung, we are enabled likewise to discriminate their parts; we now see distinctly what lies around us. But still we see as yet only the wholes which lie proximately around us, and of these only the parts which possess a certain size. The more distant wholes, and the smaller parts of the nearer wholes, are still seen by us only in their conjoint result, only as they concur in making up that whole which is for us a visible minimum. Thus it is, that in the distant forest, or on the distant hill, we perceive a green surface; but we see not the several leaves, which in the one, nor the several blades of grass, which in the other, each contributes its effect to produce that amount of impression which our consciousness requires. Thus it is, that all which we do perceive is made up of parts which we do not perceive, and consciousness is itself a complement of impressions which lie beyond its apprehension. '' Clearness and distinctness are thus only relative. For, between the extreme of obscurity and the extreme of distinctness, there is in vision an infinity of inter- mediate degrees. Now, the same thing occurs in thought. For we may either be conscious only of the concept in general, or we may also be conscious of its various con- 286 ' PSYCHOLOGY, stituent parts, or both the concept and its parts may be lost in themselves to consciousness, and only recognized to exist by effects which indirectly evidence their exist- ence." Logic ^ page 112. 7th. Other qualities of concepts. These are as follows: (1) Valid concepts are those which are known to cor- respond to their objects. Yalidity depends on evidence. (2) Invalid concepts are those which are not known to correspond to their objects. Invalidity implies want of evidence. (3) True concepts are those which correspond to their objects. True concepts may be valid or invalid accord- ing as there is a presence or absence of evidence. Valid concepts are always true, but true concepts are not al- ways valid. It is possible to assume the truth without evidence. A concept is true or false, since it is an im- plicit judgment, which is true or false. False concepts are those which do not correspond to their objects. False concej)ts are alwaj^s invalid, but invalid concepts are not always false. A concept, therefore, to be both true and valid must correspond to its object, and must be also known to correspond to its object. The correspondence must hold as far as the concept goes, though the concept may not do full justice to the object. (5) Congruent concepts are those in which all the ele- ments harmonize, that is, run together without conflict. (6) Incongruent concepts are those which embrace con- flictive elements — contrary or contradictory elements. Incongruity is a mark of invalidity, and indicates that some element has been assumed without warrant. Ya- lidity implies congruity ; but congruity does not imply validity, since there may be absence of evidence. (7) Complete concepts are those which involve all the common elements, and embrace all the divisions and sub- QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS, 287 divisions of the class down to the individuals. Com- pleteness is, in general, an ideal perfection. Yery few, if any, of our concepts are complete. (8) Incomplete concepts are those which embrace only a part of the elements or objects of the class. Incom- pleteness characterizes- most, if not all, of our concepts. Most objects have qualities which have escaped our ob- servation ; and most classes have individuals altogether unknown to us. Different persons may form different concepts of the same class, since one ]3erson may com- bine one set of attributes, and another person, another set. The same person may, at different times, form different concepts of the same class. The concept may change with advancing knowledge. 8th. Symbolic and intuitive knowledge. To illustrate this distinction, we quote from Leibnitz and from Taine. (1) Leibnitz says, as quoted by Hamilton: ''For the most part, however, especially in an analysis of an^^ length, we do not view, at once, the whole characters or attributes of the thing, but in place of these we employ signs, the explication of which into what they signify, we are wont, at the moment of actual thought, for the sake of brevity, to omit, knowing or believing that we have this explication always in our poAver. Thus, when I think of a regular chiliagon, I do not al- ways consider the various attributes of the sides, of their equality, and of the number, a thousand, but I use these words, whose meaning is obscurely and im- perfectly presented to the mind, in lieu of notions which I have of them, because I remember that I possess the signification of these words, though their application and explication, 1 do not, at present, deem necessary. This kind of thinking, I am used to call blind or symbolic. We employ it not only in algebra and arithmetic, but in fact universally. And certainly, when the notion is very com- 288 PSYCHOLOGY. plex, we can not think, at once, all the ingredient no- tions; but when this is possible — at least, inasmuch as it is possible — I call the cognition intuitive. " Of the primary elements of our notions, there is given no other knowledge than the intuitive; as of our composite notions, there is, for the most part, possible only a symbolic. From these considerations, it is evi- dent that of the things which we distinctly know, w^e are not conscious of the ideas, except so far as we em- ploy an intuitive cognition. Indeed, it happens that we often falsely believe that we have in our minds the ideas of things, erroneously supposing that certain terms which we employ had been applied and explicated ; and it is not true, at least it is ambiguously expressed, what some assert, — that we can not speak concerning any thing, understanding what we say, without having an idea of it actually present. For we frequently ap- ply any kind of meaning to the several words, or we merely recollect that we have formerly understood them; but because we are content with this blind thinking, and do not follow out the resolution of the notions, it happens that contradictions are allowed to lie hid, which perchance the composite notion involves." Logic, page 128. Symbolic and intuitive knowledge thus clearly differ. (2) Taine says : " My garden is surrounded b}^ a hedge, and my fruit is stolen ; I determine on enclosing it with a wall. I get wdiat workmen I can in the village — lour, for instance — and at the end of the day, I find they have built twelve meters of wall. This is not fast enough; I send to the next village for six other work- men, and ask myself how many meters a day will be added to the wall. To find out this, I no longer picture to myself workmen, with their blouses and trowels — the wall with its stones and mortar, — but replace my first workmen by the figure four, the first amount of work QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS, 289 by the figure twelve, the whole number of workmen by the figure ten, the amount of work they will do by the symbol x^ and write down the following proportion, 12 X 10 4.:l2::\{):x = =3 30. 4 ^'Henceforth, barring accident or drunkenness, if the new men work like the old, and all continue to work together, as the first four began, my ten men will build thirty meters a da^^. Operations of this kind occur daily, and all practical calculations are made in this way. ''For the real objects first imagined, figures are substi- tuted which replace them partially; they replace them in the only point of view in which we need consider them, that is, in point of number. This once effected, we forget the objects represented; they recede into the background; we only consider the figures; we assemble, compare, transpose, and manij^ulate them as more con- venient equivalents; and the figure we finally arrive at, indicates the object or group of objects at which we wish to arrive. "Substitution goes further than this, and figures sub- stituted for things have in turn letters substituted for them. After several similar calculations, I observe that, in all such cases, the proportion is written in the same way — that the first figure always represents the first workmen; the second figure, their work; the third, the whole number of workmen; the fourth, the unknown work; and I thus pass from arithmetic to algebra. Henceforth, I replace the first figure by A^ the second by B^ the third by (7, and write down as follows: ^X G A: B : : C :x = A •'I see tluit, in every such case, if I want to know Psy.~2.5. 290 PSYCHOLOGY. the amount of work which will be done by all the work- men^ it will be sufficient to multiply their number by that representing the work done by the first lot^ and then to divide the product by the number of workmen first employed. "Instead of this simj)le case, let us consider the labor of an analyist, who Writes equations by the hour. He lays aside the figures, but indirectly he is working on them, just as an arithmetician lays aside the facts, but works indirectly on the facts. Each of them arranges and combines symbols, and these symbols are substitutes. The fact is, they are not like proper names, substituted for the whole of the object they represent, but merely for a portion or an aspect of such object. The letter used in Algebra does not fully replace the arithmetical figure with its precise quantity, but only as regards its function and place in the equation it enters into. The arithmetical figure does not fully replace the thing it stands fi^r, with all its qualities and characters, but only as regards quantity and number. Each replaces a part only of the imagined object; that is to say, a fragment — an extract; the figure, a more complex extract; the letter, a less complex one; that is to say, an extract from the first extract. But the substitution, though partial, is none the less actual. Two complete and infinitely fertile sciences depend on it, and .derive their efficiency from it." Taine on Intelligence^ page 4.. ^ CHAPTEE VTII. RELATION OF CONCEPTS. The reciprocal relation of concepts may be considered with respect to their comprehension and to their exten- sion, thus giving two independent classifications. 1. As to comprehension, we may consider identity and diversity, congruity and incongruity, the intrinsic and the extrinsic, subordination and co-ordination. Ist. Identity and diversity. Two concepts, when com- pared, are found to comprise eitlier the same elements or different elements, giving rise to the distinctions of identical concepts and different concepts, or, in general, of identity and diversity. (1) Identity. Identical concepts are either absolutely identical or relatively identical. a. Absolute identity. No two concepts are absolutely identical; for, if so, they could not be distinguished as two, since they would have no difference by which they could be discriminated. This class of concepts, therefore, has not a real^ but only an ideal existence, and consti- tutes an imaginary member in the division of identical concepts. Even the concepts relating to the same class, formed by different minds, or by the same mind at dif- ferent times, which make the nearest approach to abso- lute identity, are distinguishable ; for, we can say, that the one w^as formed by this mind, and the other by that, or that one was formed by a mind at one time, and the other by the same mind at another time. These concepts, if otherwise identical, are numerically differ- ( 291 ) 292 PSYCHOLOGY. ent — one can be distinguished as the first, and the other as the second. The difference is not intrinsic, but ex- trinsic; not essential, but accidental. b. Relative identity. Concepts relatively identical are of two kinds — reciprocating, or convertible, and similar, or cognate. «. Concepts relatively identical are reciprocating^ or convertible^ when they relate to the same class, but des- ignate it, in the one case, by one set of attributes, and, in the other case, by another set. Thus, the concept of the class denominated equilateral triangles, designates the class by the equality of the sides, while the concept of the class denominated equiangular triangles, designates the class by the equality of the angles. But since, in the case of triangles, the equality of the sides involves the equality of the angles, and conversely, the class of triangles denominated equilateral is identical with the class denominated equiangular; hence, the concepts of this class corresponding to the expressions, equilateral triangles and equiangular triangles, though not abso- lutely identical, since in the one case, the equality of the sides is made prominent, and, in the other, the equal- ity of the angles, jai are relatively identical, or more specifically, reciprocating, or convertible, since one in- volves the other. ^. Concepts relatively identical are similar^ or cognate^ when they belong to the same family, and having the same origin are thus kindred. Certain languages are said to be cognate, and the same may be said of certain virtues or vices. (2) Diversity. Different concepts are either absolutely different or relatively different. a. Absolute difference. No two concepts are absolutely different; for, if not subordinate to an}^ lower genus, they are, at least, subordinate to being, the highest RELATION OF CONCEPTS. 293 genus, and hence agree in possessing existence^ the attri- bute of this genus, though they differ in other respects. Absolutely different concejits, therefore, constitute an ideal or imaginary member of the class different con- cepts, and merely give symmetry to the classification. h. Relative difference. Concepts relatively different are distinguished by the fact that they possess diverse at- tributes, though they have other attributes in common. The laws of resemblance and difference are as follows : (1) The law of homogeneity. However different two concepts, they m.ust, in some respect, at least in that of existence, be alike; for, every other concept is subordi- nate to that of being. Hence, things most dissimilar must, in one respect at least, be similar. (2) The laiv of heterogeneity. Every concept contains other concepts under it. In thought, therefore, the di- vision of concej^ts gives concepts, not individuals. Hence, things most similar, must, in certain respects, be dissim- ilar. Thus, take any two concepts with a small differ- ence. Now, this difference can be divided, thus giving new concepts distinguished by this partial difference, and so on, ad infinitum. But the infinite divisibility of concepts, like the infinite divisibility of space, time, or matter, exists only in speculations. To illustrate, let us classify angles, thus: Angles liight < Oblique V Acute Obtuse Here we pause, not because it is impossible to pursue 294 PSYCHOLOGY, the divisions further, but because it is not called for. But we can conceive these angles to be situated in a horizontal, a vertical, or an oblique plane, giving hori- zontal, vertical, or oblique angles. These angles may have any position in these planes, and the sides may take an infinite number of directions for each position of the vertex. The acute angle may vary through an infinite number of values, between the limits 0^ and 90^, and the obtuse angle may vary, in like manner, between the limits 90° and 180°. 2d. Congruity and incongruity. Again, as to compre- hension, two concepts are either congruent or conflictive. (1) Congruity. Two concepts are congruent, if they can be united in thought, so that one can be afiirmed of the other, or both can be afiirmed of the same object. Thus, triangles are polygons. A single concept is con- gruous if all its elements harmonize, as a square field. (2) Incongruity. Incongruous concepts are conflictive, since they involve inconsistent attributes. They are of two kinds — contraries and contradictories. a. Contrary concepts are mutually repugnant, though not universally inclusive of their genus. Thus, the con- cepts of the classes triangles and quadrilaterals are con- » trary, since they do not include all the divisions of the genus polygon. h. Contradictory concepts are mutually repugnant and universally inclusive of the genus of which they are species. Thus, right triangles and oblique triangles are contradictories within the sphere of the genus triangle. Any triangle is either right or oblique; if it is one, it is not the other; and if it is not one, it is the other. But within the sphere of another genus, as polygon, right triangles and oblique triangles are not contradictories. Hence, contradictories in a restricted sphere are not necessarily contradictories when the sphere is enlarged. RELATION OF CONCEPTS, 295 Thus, honest and dishonest are contradictories within the sphere of moral beings, but not within the sphere of beings. Thus, vertebrate and invertebrate are con- tradictories within the spliere of animals; organic and inorganic, within the sphere of beings; the ego and the non-ego, A and not-^1, being and non-being, are univer- sally contradictories, since their sphere is absolutely un- limited, the two members together comprehending every thing, existent and non-existent, A single concept is incongruous, when it involves con- flictive elements, as a round square. Identity is to be distinguished from congruity, and diversity from confliction. All identical concepts are congruent, but all congruent concepts are not identical. Thus, the concej)ts of the classes, equilateral triangles and equiangular triangles are relatively identical and congruent; learning and virtue are congruent, but not identical. All conflictive concepts are diverse, but all diverse concepts are not conflictive. Thus, virtue and vice, beauty and ugliness, are conflictive and diverse; but virtue and beauty are diverse but not conflictive. od. The intrinsic and extrinsic. As to comprehension, we may also regard concepts as intrinsic or extrinsic. - (1) Intrinsic concepts are those which involve the qualities necessary to the existence of the class — they contain essential elements. Thus, the concept of a tri- angle involving three sides and three angles, is intrinsic. (2) Extrinsic concepts are those which consist of ac- cidental qualities — those not essential to the existence of the class. Thus, the concept of a triangle involving the equality of its sides, is extrinsic. 4th. Subordination and, co-ordination. As to compre- hension, we may regard concepts in the relation of sub- ordination or co-ordination. (1) One concept is subordinate to another, as to com- 296 PSYCHOLOGY. prehension, when the first forms a part of the sum total of the elements which together constitute tlie compre- hension of the second. The concepts of sides, angles, and area of a triangle are involved in the concept of the class triangle. (2) Two or more concepts are co-ordinate^ as to com- prehension, when they are exclusive and both are im- mediately comprehended as elements of the same con- cept. . Thus, the concepts of the sides, angles, and area of a triangle, are co-ordinate with one another, though alike subordinate to the concept triangle. 2. As to extension, we may consider co-extension, subordination, exclusion, and intersection. 1st. Co-extension. One concept is co-extensive with an- other, when they relate to the same class, and thus have the same sphere. Thus, equilateral triangles and equi- angular triangles are co-extensive. In comprehension, these concepts are called reciprocating or convertible. Of the two elements, the equality of the sides, and the equality of the angles, that which is explicitly enounced in the one is implicitly involved in the other, and con- versely. The subject and j^redicate of a definition are co-extensive. Thus, in the definition, a triangle is a polygon of three side, the concepts, triangle, and a polygon of three sides, are co extensive. Co-extension may be symbolized by two equal co-incident circles, which appear as one, though indicated as two by two letters placed within, thus: 2d. Subordination. One concept is subordinate to another, when, as to extension, the former is contained under the latter, as an individual under a species, or a species under a genus. If one concept is subordinate to another, it is subordinate to any higher concept em- bracing the other. Thus, since horse is subordinate to RELATION OF CONCEPTS, 297 the genus equus, it is subordinate to quadruped, verte- brate, animal, organized being, being. Subordination may be symbolized by one circle within another, the inner circle de- noting the subordinate concept. Thus, A is subordinate to JB. 3d. Exclusion. One concept is excluded from another, when they have nothing in common as to extension. Thus, the concepts of the classes horse and dog, aiford an example of exclusion, as to extension, since they have neither species nor individuals in common. Exclusive concepts may be either co-ordinate or non- co-ordinate, — co-ordinate, when each is subordinate to the same concept, as acute angles and obtuse angles, which are immediately subordinate to oblique angles, — non-co-ordinate., when one, but not the other is immedi- ately subordinate to a third concept, as right angles and acute angles, right angles being immediately subor- dinate to angles, and acute angles to obliqe angles. Exclusive concepts are conflictive, as to comprehension, and are either contrary or contradictory, — contrary, when they are not universally inclusive of their genus, — contradictory, when they are universally inclusive of their genus. Thus right angles and acute angles are contraries, while right angles and oblique angles are contradictories. The exclusion of contraries may /^ X /^ ^ be symbolized by two exclusive cir- I A \ I B j cles. Thus, the circles A and B. V.__^ V__^ The exclusion of contradictories may be symbolized by one circle and the indefinite surrounding space in the plane of the circle y^ \ — the circle denoting one of the contradicto- (a ]B ries, and the indefinite space the other, as V__^ A and B in the annexed figure. 298 PSYCHOLOGY. 4th. Intersection. Two concepts intersect, when their extensions have a common part, and the extension of each a j)art not common with the other. Thus, the concepts men and liars intersect. For, some men are liars; some liars are men; some men are not liars; and some liars are not men. Intersection may be symbolized by two intersecting circles. The concepts sym- bolized by A and B^ intersect. This method of representing the rela- tion of the concepts of classes, as to extension, is due to Euler. The circles do not, of course, resemble the concepts, but the relation of the circles does correctly represent the relation of the extension of the concepts. CHAPTBE IX. JUDGMENT. 1. A judgment is the decision that a certain relation exists between two objects of thought. It has already been seen that every act of cognition involves a judgment. A concept itself is an implicit or undeveloped judgment. This is evident from an analy- sis of the act of conception, for, in conception certain attributes are regarded as belonging to all the objects of a class, thus involving the judgment that each object of the class has these attributes. The judgments involved in a concept are called pri- mary or psychological. They have individual objects for their subjects, and attributes or concepts for their predicates. Judgments in which concepts are predicated of concepts are called secondary or logical. 2. A proposition is the expression of a judgment. For the purposes of logic, a proposition is considered as con- sisting of three parts — a subject, always a substantive or a substitute for a substantive, that of which some- thing is affirmed or denied, a predicate, also a substan- tive or its substitute, that which is affirmed or denied of the subject, and the copula, is or is not, or in the plural, are or are not, which affirms or denies the predi- cate of the subject. Thus, horses are animals , lying is not a virtue. Such propositions as, trees grow; birds are beautiful, are put into the requisite form by saying, Trees are things which grow. Birds are beautiful animals. (299) 300 PSYCHOLOGY. A proposition does not necessarily imply the real ex- istence of the object denoted by the subject; for this object may be imaginary, as in the proposition, A cen- taur is half horse and half man. Whether the subject denotes a real or an imaginary object is to be deter- mined by considerations independent of the proposition. 3. The terms of a proposition, from termini^ limits or boundaries, are the subject and predicate, which limit or mark the extremes of a proposition. A term expresses an individual or a group of individuals, an attribute or a group of attributes. Ist. A singular term is expressive of an individual. Thus, Plato, George Washington, this boy, etc., are sin- gular terms. 2d. A common term is expressive of each individual of a class, as well as the class itself. Thus, man, horse, tree, etc., are common terms. 3d. A collective term is expressive of a group, but not of each individual of the group. Thus, the senate, the convention, the army, etc., are collective terms, since we can say this body of men is the senate, but not that Sherman is the senate, etc. 4th. An attributive term is an adjective or a partici]3le expressing an attribute or a group of attributes. Thus, white, human, etc. For logical purposes, a noun is un- derstood when an attributive is the predicate. Thus, Plato is human, is logically equivalent to, Plato is a human being. An attributive can not by itself be used as the subject, but only in connection with a noun, as this human being is Plato. 5th, An abstract term is a noun expressive of an at- tribute or a group of attributes considered apart from the object to which it belongs. Thus, humanity, virtue, form, color, etc. An abstract term may, b}^ itself, be either the subject or the predicate of a proposition. GENERAL VIEW. 301 4. The modality of a proposition is the view of it taken by the mind as influenced by the degree of evi- dence. It is expressed by an adverb in connection Avith the copula. Thus, This is certainly the boy who stole the fruit; this is probably the boy w^ho stole the fruit, etc. These propositions may be expressed in the usual logi- cal form, thus. That this is the boy who stole the fruit is a certainty, etc. 5. The classification of judgments may be with ref- erence to logical quantity, origin, validity, truth, or form. 1st. As to logical quantity^ judgments are comprehen- sive or extensive, according as the quantity of the predi- cate is comprehensive or extensive. (1) A comprehensive judgment is one in which the predicate is considered in reference to its content. Thus, these houses are white. (2) An extensive judgment is one in which the predi- cate is considered in reference to its extent. Thus, a horse is an animal. A comprehensive judgment may be turned into an extensive judgment. Thus, these houses are white, is equivalent to these houses are white objects. In a comprehensive judgment, the subject is the whole of comprehension of which the predicate is affirmed or denied to be a part. The copula is or is not, signifies comprehends or does not comprehend. In an extensive judgment, the predicate is the whole of extension of which the subject is affirmed or denied to be a part. The copula, is or is not, signifies is con- tained under or is not contained under. A definition is both an extensive and a comprehensive judgment; for the predicate as the genus of the subject is extensive, while the differential quality is comprehen- sive, and thus limits the extent of the subject to that part of the predicate characterized by this quality. 302 PSYCHOLOGY, 2d. As to origin^ judgments are primitive or derivative, according as they are original or derived. (1) A primitive judgment is assumptive or intuitive, according as the relation of the subject and predicate is an assumption or an intuition. Thus, Mars is inhabited, is a primitive judgment, since it is not derived from other judgments; and is assumptive, since it is not known to be true. Either of two equal quantities is a substitute for the other, is both a primitive and an intui- tive judgment. (2) A derivative judgment is demonstrative or proble- matical, according as it is capable or incapable of proof A judgment which is strictly demonstrative may be re- garded as problematical till it is proved true. 3d. As to validity^ judgments are valid or invalid. (1) A judgment is valid ^ when the concepts are valid, and the relation is intuitive or demonstrative. It is valid, if its truth is known. A valid judgment is true. (2) A judgment is invalid^ when the law of validity is not complied with. It is invalid, if its truth is not known. An invalid judgment is true or false. 4th. As to truths judgments are true or false. (1) A judgment is true^ when the relation expressed corresponds to the reality. A true judgment is valid or invalid according to evidence. (2) A judgment is false ^ when the relation exj)ressed does not correspond to the reality. A false judgment is invalid. Validity depends on evidence, and implies truth, but truth on correspondence, with or without evidence. 5th. As to form^ judgments are either categorical or conditional. (1) A categorical judgment is one. in which the rela- tion expressed is not qualified by a condition. Thus, horses are animals; some men are liars; >§ is P. GENERAL VIEW. 303 (2) A conditional judgment is one in which the rela- tion expressed is qualilied by a condition. There are three varieties of conditional judgments — hypothetical, disjunctive, and dilemmatic. a. A hypothetical judgment is a conditional judgment in which the qualifying condition is an hyj)othesis. Thus, if ^ is ^, is D. h. A disjunctive judgment is a conditional judgment in which the qualifying condition is an alternative. Thus, J. is £ or C, which is equivalent to, if A is not (7, A is -B, or if A is not B, A is C. c. A dilemmatic judgment is a conditional judgment in which there are two qualifying conditions — an hypoth- esis and an alternative. Thus, if J. is B, C is D or E. 6. The principles of expression are those warranting aflSrmation, negation, hypothecation, or disjunction. 1st. Affirmation is either immediate or mediate. (1) Immediate affirmation is warranted by knowledge gained by empirical intuition, as in consciousness, or by rational intuition, as the fundamental axioms of thought or the special axioms of the various sciences. (2) Mediate affirmation is warranted in several ways: a. By the law of contradictories. Thus, we can af- firm either of two contradictories, if we know the other is false. h. By valid inference from a single ^proposition. Thus, if I know that all S is P, I can affirm that some 8 is P, or that some P is S. c. By logical deduction from valid premises. Thus, if I know that all M is P, and that all >S' is M, I am warranted in affirming that all S is P. 2d. Negation is either immediate or mediate. (1) Immediate negation is warranted by the principle of identity — a thing is not any thing other than itself (2) Mediate negation is warranted in several ways: 304 PSYCHOLOGY, a. By the law of conflictives. Thus, knowing the truth of either of two conflictives, we are warranted in denying the other. h. By a valid inference from a single proposition. Thus, knowing that no S is P, we can afSrm that some S is not P, or that no P is aS'. c. By logical deduction from valid premises. Thus, knowing that no M is P, and that all S is M^ we are warranted in affirming that no S is P. 3d. Hypothecation is warranted, if the condition is a valid reason for the consequent, thus, if A has the fever, he is sick. 4th. Disjunction is warranted by two reasons: (1) When the parts of the predicate are contradicto- ries. Thus, a triangle is right or oblique. (2) When the parts of the predicate are all of the contraries. Thus, an angle is right, acute, or obtuse. 'M\ CHAPTER X. CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS. 1. Categorical judgments are classified as to quantity and as to quality. Ist. As to quantity^ categorical judgments are univer- sal or particular — universal^ when the predication, that iSj the affirmation or denial, is made of all the subject, as all S is P, no >S is P ; particular, when the predica- tion is made of only a part of the subject, as some S is P, some S is not P. 2d. As to quality, categorical judgments are affirmative or negative — affirmative, when the predicate is affirmed of the subject, as all S is P, some S is P; negative, when the predicate is denied of the subject, as no S is P, some S is not P. An individual proposition, as John is a man, is to be regarded as a universal. An indefinite proposition, one devoid of any mark of quantity, is to be interpreted, either as a universal or as a particular, according to the matter, but this inter- pretation is extra-logical, since logic deals with the form of thought and not with the matter. Thus, planets are subject to the law of gravitation, is interpreted as a uni- versal — all planets are subject to the law of gravitation. Metals are useful is inter j)reted as a particular — some metals are useful. Dividing w4th respect to quantity, and subdividing with respect to quality, denoting the universal affirma- tive by (A), the universal negative by (E), the particu- Psy.-26. ( 305 ) 306 PSYCHOLOGY, lar affirmative by (1). and the particular negative by (O), we have the following summary classification of categorical judgments: Universal Particular Affirmative (A) All 8 is P. Negative {E) ]N"o S is P. Affirnia'tive (/) Some S is P. Negative (0) Some S is not P. 2. The laws of trutli are the following: 1st. {A), All S is P, is true, if 8 is subordinate to P, or if 8 is co-extensive with P 2d. (^), No >S is P, is true, if 8 is excluded from P. 3d. (/), Some 8 is P, is true, if {A) is true, as above, also if 8 intersects P, or if P is sub- ordinate to 8. 4th. (O), Some /S is not P, is true, if (^) is true, as above, also if 8 in- tersects P, or if P is subordinate to 8. 3. The relation of the propositions, (J), (^), (/), (0), or as it is commonly called, their opposition^ is thus shown: CATEGOEICAL JUDGMENTS. 307 A Contraries E I 8ub-oontraries Q Ist. In relation to agreement or disagreement in quantity or quality. (1) (A) and {E) agree in quantity, both being univer- sal; they disagree in quality, (A) being affirmative, and {E) negative. (2) (/) and (0) agree in quantity, both being partic- ular; they disagree in quality, (/) being affirmive, and (0) negative. (3) (J.) and (Z) agree in quality, both being affirma- tive; they disagree in quantity, (A) being universal, and (7) particular. (4) {E) and (0) agree in quality, both being nega- tive; they disagree in quantity, (^) being universal, and (0) particular. (5) (A) and (0) disagree both in quantit}^ and in qual- ity, (A) being universal and affirmative, and (0) par- ticular and negative. (6) (jK) and (7) disagree both in quantity and in qual- ity, (7i^) being universal and negative, and (7) particular and affirmative. 2d. As to agreement or disagreement in truth or falsity. Let it be observed tliat there are five diiferent rela- tions possible between S and P, — S is subordinate to P, 308 PSYCHOLOGY. S is co-extensive with P, 8 is excluded from P, .8 inter- sects Pj and P is subordinate to ;S^. (1) (^) and (^E) are mutually repugnant, since neither relation, 8 is subordinate to P, or 8 is co-extensive with P, included in (^), is found in (P), nor is the relation, 8 is excluded from P, which is expressed by (P), found in (J.); hence, having no relation common, they can not both be true, and therefore the truth of either implies the falsity of the other. If it is true that all 8 is P, it is false that no 8 is P, and if it is true that no 8 is P, it is false that all 8 is P. (2) (J.) and (P) are not universally inclusive of all possible relations of 8 and P, since there are other re- lations, as 8 intersects P, P ij subordinate to 8, not found in either; hence, not including all possible rela- tions, they may both be false, and therefore the falsity of either does not imply the truth of the other. (3) Hence, (^) and (P) are called contraries, since they are mutually repugnant, but not universally in- clusive. Other relations are possible. (4) Since the relations in (4) are found in (7), the truth of (^) involves the truth of (7). For this reason, {A) and (7) are called subalterns, though, strictly, (7) is the subaltern of (A). (5) Since (7) contains relations not found in (A), as well as those in (J), the falsity of (A) does not imply the falsity of (7), nor does the truth of (7) imply the truth of (yl), but the falsity of (7) implies the falsity of (A), since the relations in (A) are in (7). (6) For like reasons, (0) is the subaltern of (P), the truth of (P) implies the truth of (0), the falsity of (P) does not imply the falsity of (0), nor does the truth of (0) imply the truth of (P), but the falsity of (0) im- plies the falsity of (P). (7) Since (7) and (O) contain the common relations, CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS. 309 S intersects P, and P is subordinate to S^ both may be true; hence, the truth of either does not imply the falsity of the other. (8) Since (/) and (0) are universally inclusive of all possible relations of S and P, both can not be false; hence, the falsity of either implies the truth of the other. (9) Since (/) contains relations not found in (0), and (0) a relation not found in (/), either may be true and the other false; hence, the truth of either does not im- ply the truth of the other. (10) (7) and (0) are subordinate to (^4.) and (^E^^ re- spectively, and hence are called sub-contriries. (11) (A) and (0) are mutually repugnant, since they contain no common relation ; hence, they can not both be true, and therefore the truth of either implies the falsity of the other; and since they are universally in- clusive of all possible relations of S and P, both can not be false, and therefore the falsity of either implies the truth of the other. Hence, (A) and (0) are called contradictories, since they are mutually repugnant and universally inclusive. (12) For like reasons, (^E) and (7) are contradicto- ries; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of the other, and the falsity of either, the truth of the other. 3d. These relations may likewise be thus expressed: (1) The truth of (A.) implies the truth of (7) and the falsity of (7^) and (O); but the falsity of (A) implies the truth of (0). (2) The truth of (E) implies the truth of (O) and the falsity of (A) and (7) ; but the falsity of (E) im- plies the truth of (7). (3) The truth of (7) implies the falsity of (E) ; but the falsity of (7) implies the truth of (E) and (0) and the falsity of (J). (4) The truth of (O) implies the falsity of (A); but 310 PSYCHOLOGY. the falsity of (0) implies the truth of {A) and (J) and the falsity of {E). Let the student answer the following questions: (1) What does the truth of (J.) imply? What the falsity of {A) imply? (2) What does the truth of (^) imply? What does the falsity of {E) imply? (3) What does the truth of (/) imply? What does the falsity of (/) imply? (4) What does the truth of (0) imply? What does the falsity of (0) imply? (5) What implies the truth of (A) ? the falsity of {A) ? (6) What implies the truth of {E)l the falsity of (^)? (7) What implies the truth of (/)? the falsity of (/)? (8) What implies the truth of (0)? the falsity of (0)? (9) Show in three ways that the falsity of (/) im- plies the truth of (0). (10) Show in three ways that the falsity of (0) im- plies the truth of (7). 4th. These relations may receive a more general ex- pression : (1) The truth of a universal implies the truth of its particular; but the falsity of a universal does hot imply the falsity of its particular. (2) The falsity of a particular implies the falsity of its universal; but the truth of a particular does not im- ply the truth of its universal. (3) The contraries can not both be true, but may both be false; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of the other; but the falsity of either does not imply the truth of the other. (4). The sub-contraries can not both be false, but may both be true ; hence, the falsity of either implies the truth of the other ; but the truth of either does not imply the falsity of the other. CA TEG ORICAL JUl) GMENTS. 31 1 (5) Two contradictories can not both be true nor both false; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of the other, and the falsity of either the truth of the other. In the above discussion, we have considered the form of the proposition but not the matter. 5th. The following statements, though extra-logical, may be found to be useful. (1) In necessary matter, the affirmatives, {A) and (J), are both true, and the negatives, {E) and (0), are both false. Thus, all triangles have three sides, and some triangles have three sides, are both true; but no triangles have three sides, and some triangles have not three sides are both false. (2) In contingent matter, the particulars, (/) and (0), are both true, and the universals, {A) and (J5/), both false. Thus, some triangles are right, and some triangles are not right, are both true; but all triangles are right, and no triangles are right, are both false. (3) In impossible matter, the negatives, {E) and (0), are both true, and the affirmatives, (^) and (7), both false. Thus, no triangles have four sides, and some tri- angles have not four sides, are both true; but all tri- angles have four sides, and some triangles have four sides, are both false. CHAPTEE XL CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS. 1. Distribution of terms. — 1st Definition and remarks. A term is distributed when it is applied to all the in- dividuals denoted by the name. Thus, in the expres- sions, all men^ no nien^ the term men is distributed. A term is undistributed when it is applied only to some of the individuals denoted by the name. Thus, men is undistributed in the expression some men. It would seem that distribution is applicable only to common terms; but as singular^ collective^ and abstract terms are, as \\q have seen, regarded as universal, they are regarded as distributed. When an attribute is used as a predicate, the noun un- derstood is to be supplied before the rule for distribu- tion is to be applied. Thus, the proposition, the bird is beautiful, is changed to, the bird is a beautiful animal. When an abstract term or an attributive Jms come to be regarded as a common noun, as virtue^ color ^ fig^^'^e, the good^ etc., its distribution or non-distribution is reg- ulated by the rules for common terms. 2d. Rules for the distribution and. non-distribution of the terms of a proposition. (1) The subject of every universal j)roposition is distrib- uted. Thus, the subject is distributed in the following propositions: Every man is liable to accident; All S is P; No selfish action is praiseworthy; No S is P; Any coward is contemptible. The distribution of the subject is shown by one of the words, every., all^ no, any. (312) CA TEG ORICAL JUD GMENTS. 313 (2) The subject of every particular projjosition is undis- tributed. Thus, the subject is undistributed in the fol- lowing propositions: Some men are liars; Some Sis F; Some men are not liars; Some S is not P. The non- distribution of the subject is indicated by the word some. It will b# observed that the distribution or non-distri- bution of the subject depends upon the quantity of the proposition — the subject is distributed in universals, and undistributed in particulars. (3) The predicate of every negative proposition is distrib- uted. Thus, the predicate is distributed in the following j)ropositions : ISTo horse is a ruminant; Some apples are not red; No S is P; Some S is not P; for every indi- vidual of the class ruminants is excluded from the class horse; every red object, from the class some apples; and every P, from S. (4) The predicate of an affirmative is undistributed^ unless the subject is co-extensive vjith the predicate^ or the p)redicate is subordinate to the subject. Thus, the predicate is un- distributed in the propositions, All horses are animals; Some Americans are poets; All S is P; Some S is P; for all animals are not horses; all poets are not Ameri- cans; nor is it certain that all P is S. It will be observed that the distribution or non-distri- bution of the 23redicate depends on the quality of the proposition — the predicate is distributed in negatives, and is, in general, undistributed in affirmatives. It may, indeed, be true, in fact, that the predicate of an affirmative is distributed, as in case of co-extension in (^) or (7), or when, in (Z), P is subordinate to S ; but this is extra-logical, since it is not indicated by the form^ with which alone logic has to deal. It is impor- tant, however, to note that co-extension is found in case of definitions, equations, identical propositions, and when S and P designate, by different properties, the same Psy.— 27. 314 PSYCHOLOGY, class. ThuSj A decagon is a polygon often sides; J ==: B ; A is A; All equilateral triangles are equiangular. P is subordinate to S in (7)^ when S is the genus of which P is a species, as some animals are horses. HencCj the rules for distribution may be thus stated: (1) All universals distribute their subject, • (2) All negatives distribute their predicate,- (3) No particular distributes its subject. (4) An affirmative does not, in general, distribute its predicate. 2. Conversion of propositions — definitions, rule, clas- sification. — The conversion of a proposition is the trans- position of its termSj or the interchange of the places of the subject and predicate. Thus, the conversion of the proposition, S is P, gives the proposition, P is S, The convert end, or exposita, is the original poposition to be converted. The converse is the proposition obtained by conversion. The general rule to be observed in conversion is the following: A term must not be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend. Conversion is divided into immediate and mediate^ and each of these into simple and by limitation, or per acci- dens, as it is also called. Conversion is immediate when the convertend is con- verted, without preliminary change of form; that is, the original proposition is itself converted. 1st. Immediate conversion is simple, when the converse has the same quantity and quality as the convertend, and is denoted by the same vowel. (1) (E) always admits of immediate simple conversion. {E) No 8 is P. .-. \e) ]Sro P is S. CATEGOBICAL JUDGMENTS, 315 P. (2) (7) always admits of immediate simple conversion. (J) Some S is ...(/) Some FiJ^'^^' ^^ ^^ ' '^'' ^ ' ^' 8. (3) (A) arim?:?^5 of immediate simple conversion in case S and P are co-extensive, as in definitions, etc., but not in general. (A) All S is P. .-, (A) All P is S. (4) (0) admits of immediate simple converse in case of exclusion or intersection, but not in general. (0) Some S is not P. .-, (0) Some P is not aS. It thus appears that (J5) and (J) universally admit of immediate simple conversion; and (A) and (0) in special cases — (J.) in case of co-extension, and (0) in case of exclusion or intersection. To convert (JL) by im- mediate simple conversion, in case 8 is subordinate to P, is to distribute P in the converse when it is not dis- tributed in the convertend, and thus to violate the gen- eral rule, that a term is not to be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend. In like manner, to convert (0) by immediate simple con- version, in case P is subordinate to 8, is to distribute 8 in the converse, when it is not distributed in the con- vertend, and thus to violate the rule. 2d. Immediate conversion is by limitation, when the 316 PSYCHOLOGY, quantity is reduced, the convertend being universal^ and the converse particular. (1) (A) always admits of immediate conversion by limi- tation. (A) All S is P. .-. (Z) Some P is S, (2) (i?) always admits of immediate conversion by limi- tation. {E) ISTo 8 is P. .*. (0) Some P is not >S. (7) and (0) having already reduced quantity^ can not be converted by limitation. Conversion is mediate when the convertend is con- verted through a preliminary change of form; that is, the original proposition itself is not converted, but is changed to another which is converted. Mediate con- version, when applied to (J.), or (JS^) is called conversion by contraposition, and when applied to (0), conversion by negation. 3d. Mediate conversion is simple when the converse has the same quantity and quality as the proposition into which the original is changed, and hence is denoted by the same vowel. (1) {A) can always be changed to {E) which may be converted simply. {A ) All S is P. =Ie) No S is non-P. .\ {E ) No non-P is S. (2) (J57), in case S and P are' contradictories, can be CA TEG OEICA L JUD G ME NTS. 317 changed into co-extensive (A) or (/) either of which may be converted simply. {E)m s i^ p= \ (^) ^^^ ^ ^^" ^^^-^- ^ (.(/) Some S is non-F. [ s .-. {A) All no/2-P is >?. (/) Some non-P is aS. (3) (/) does not admit of mediate simple conversion. (4) (0) can always be changed to (Z), which may be con- verted simply. (0) Some S is not P. = (/) Some S is non-P. .'. (7) Some non-P is S. Mediate conversion is by limitation^ when the quantity is reduced, the original proposition and the proposition into which the original is changed, being universal^ and the converse particular. (1) {A) cayi alicays be changed to (^), which may be con- verted by limitation. {A) All .9 is P. = (^) ISTo /S is non-P. .*. (0) Some non-P is not S. (2) {E) can always be changed into {A), which may be converted by limitation. (E) No S is P. = (A) All S is non-P. .-. (/) Some non-P is S. (3) (7) and (0), being particular, that is, already in re- duced quantity, can not be converted by limitation. CHAPTEE XII. CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS. Conditional Judgments are, as we have seen, of three kinds — hypothetical, disjunctive, and dilemmatic. 1. Hypothetical judgments may be divided into five groups, each containing four forms. Let the laws of truth of each be exhibited by Euler's notation of circles, thus: If A is B, A is C, True, if B is C. 1st. The subject of the condition is the subject of the con- sequent. (1) If A is B, A is a True, if B is C. (2) If Ais B, A is not C. True, if B is not C. (3) If A is not 5, A is C. True, if B and G are con- tradictories. (4) If A is not B, A is not C. True, if C is B. 2d. The subject of the condition is the predicate of the consequent. (1) If ^ is 5, is A, True, if C is B, and A is co- extensive with B. (2) If ^ is ^, is not A. True, if G is not B. (3) If A is not B, G is A. True, if G is not B, and A and B are contradictories. (4) If A is not J?, G is not ^. True, if G is ^. (318) CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS. 319 3d. The ^predicate of the condition is the subject of the consequent. (1) If ^ is B^ B m C. True, if A m (7, and is co-ex- tensive with B. (2) If A is Bj B is not C. True, if A is not C, and is co-extensive with B. (3) If A is not B, B is C. True, if A and C are con- tradictories. (4) If A is not B, B is not C. True, if C is A. 4th. The predicate of the condition is the predicate of the consequent. (1) If Ais B, C is B. True, if C h A. (2) If A h B, C is not B. True, if C is not A, and ^ is co-extensive with B. (3) If A is not B, C is B. True, if (7 is not A, and J. and B are contradictories. (4) If A is not ^, (7 is not B. True, if C is A. 5th. T/i6 subjects and predicates are different in the an- tecedent and. consequent. (1) If A is J5, C is D. True, if C is A and B is D. (2) If A IS B, C is not D. True, if C is J and B is not J). (3) If A is not J5, (7 is D. True, if A and 5 are con- tradictories, and either A or B is in _D, and C is not in the other. (4) If A is not B, C is not D. True, if C is either A or B, and D is the other. 2. Disjunctive judgments are those which present al- ternatives. These alternatives are either unexclusive or exclusive. 1st. Unexclusive alternatives are of two kinds: (1) When the alternatives are simply different words for the same thing. In this case, the judgment is dis- junctive only in expression. Thus, this electricity is vitreous, or positive. 320 PSYCHOLOGY, (2) When the alternatives are different but congruent tilings. Tims, this man is a knave or a fool; he may be both. Augustine was a saint or a philosopher; he was both. 2d. Exclusive alternatives have two forms, expressed, (1) In the copula. Thus, >S either is or is not P. This is equivalent to the proposition S is either P or non-P^ which, as pure contradictory opposition, is true by the law of contradictories. (2) In the terms, a. In the subject. Thus, either P or >SisP b. hi the predicate. S is either P or Q. If R and 8 or P and Q are contradictories, we have contradictory opposition, and the judgment is true by the law of contradictories. If P and S or P and Q are contraries, we have con- trary opposition, and hence can not affirm the judgment a priori^ but only a posteriori^ by showing that all other contrary judgments are false. Then, the same inferences follow as in contradictory opposition ; that is, one of the alternatives is true; if either is true, the other is false; if either is false, the other is true. Such a proposition as angles are right or oblique is divisive. It does not mean that all angles are right or all angles are oblique; but that angles are divided into right angles and oblique angles; that is, that some angles are right and some oblique, or that any angle is either right or oblique, which is disjunctive, not only in ex- pression, but in thought, and the alternatives are contra- dictories in the genus angles. Alternatives may be contradictories within a limited sphere, but only contraries if the sphere be extended. Thus, Vertebrates and invertebrates are contradictories in the sphere of animals; but only contraries in the sphere of organic beings. Any animal is either a vertebrate or CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS. 321 an invertebrate, but it will not do to say that every organic being, much less, that every thing, is either a vertebrate or an invertebrate animal. 3. The dilemmatic judgments are divided into two groups, each containing four forms. Let the law of truth be given for each and illustrated with circles, according to Euler's notation. 1st. When the condition is simple, (1) If A is B, S is either P or Q. (2) If A m B, S is neither P nor Q. (3) If A is not B, S is either P or Q. (4) If A is not B, S is neither P nor Q. 2d. When the condition is compound. (1) If either A m B or C is D, >S is either P or Q. (2) If either A i^ B or C is D, S is neither P nor Q. (3) If neither A is B nor C is D, S is either P or Q. (4) If neither A is B nor C is P, S is neither P nor Q. The disjunctive consequent is in contrary opposition; for if in contradictory opposition, then, in either group, the consequents of (1) and (3) would be true and the consequents of (2) and (4) would be false by the law of contradictories, and the reason in the conditional clause woald be redundant. Thus, it would be super- fluous to say, if A is B, S is either P or non-P, for J3 is either P or non-P, whether A is B or not. CHAPTEE XIII. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. Reasoning is the process by which the truth or falsity of a proposition is proved. An argument is the derivation of a judgment from another judgment or from other judgments. It infers, in the final proposition, what was virtually contained in the preceding. An immediate argument is an argument in which the relation of the terms of the derived proposition is inferred from another proposition, or from other propositions, with- out the intervention of a middle term. The varieties of immediate arguments are the follow- ing: 1st. Inferences from the relation of the four propositions^ {A), (E), (Z), (0). See Chapter X. (1) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of the proposition, (A), All S is P? from the falsity of (A)f (2) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of the proposition (^), :N'o ^ is Pf from the falsity of (E)? ^ (3) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of the proposition (J), Some S is Pf from the falsity of (I)f (4) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of the proposition (0), Some S is not P? from the falsity of(0).^ 2d. Inferences from the conversion of the propositions, (A), (E) (/), (0). See Chapter XI. (1) What inferences from conversion can be drawn (322) I MM EDI A TE ARG VMENTS, 323 from the proj)osition {A)^ in case of co-extension? in case of subordination? What from the 2)roposition, Pen- tagons are polygons of five sides? What from the prop- osition, Pentagons are polygons? (2) What inferences from conversion can be drawn from the proposition (^).^ What from the proposition, No knowledge is useless? (3) What inferences from conversion can be drawn from the proposition (/).^ What from the proposition, Some men are liars? (4) What inferences from conversion can be drawn from the proposition (0),^ What from the proj)osition, Some men are not liars? (5) State the contrary, the subaltern, and the contra- dictory of the proposition. All criminals deserve punish- ment. (6) Classify the proposition. All just acts are expedi- ent. What inferences can be drawn from it, by means of relation? What b}^ means of conversion? Classify and convert these inferences. (7) State and classify the propositions incompatible with the proposition. All liars are detestable. Convert each. 3d. Inferences from model restriction. The necessary, im- plies the actual; the actual, the probable; the probable, the possible. What inferences can be drawn from the proposition. Space is necessarily infinite? 4th. Inferences from composition. Thus, A is in C ; B is in C ; therefore, A and B are in C. ' 5th. Inferences from divisive judgments. Thus, S is P, Q, or R ; therefore, the P of S is neither the Q nor the P of S; the non-P of S is either the Q or the R of S; the neither P nor Q of aS is the R of S. Gth. Inferences by means of privatives. (1) All S is P; therefore, ISTo S is non-P, and all 324 PSYCHOLOGY, non-P iis non-S. Also, from the proposition. All non-S is no7i-Pj we infer, T^o non-S is P, and all P is /S. (2) Infer, by means of privatives, the conclusion from the proposition, JSTo /S is P; from, No non-8 is non-P. (3) What inference, by means of privatives, can be drawn from the proposition, Some >S is Pf From, Some non-S is non-Pf (4) What inference, by means of privatives, can be drawn from the proposition, Some S is not Pf From, Some non-S is not non-Pf 7th. Inferences by means of determinants. This class of inferences consists in joining the same modifier to both subject and j)redicate. Thus, An Indian is a fellow creat- ure; therefore, A happy Indian is a happy fellow creat- ure. Inferences of this kind are often fallacious. Thus, A president is a man ; therefore. An incompetent presi- dent is an incompetent man. A dwarf is a man ; there- fore, A big dwarf is a big man- The inference is valid in case of co-extension, or when the modifier does not afiect the characteristics of the subject. 8th. Inferences by means of complex conceptions. This class is clearly allied to the last. Thus, Metals are ele- ments; therefore, A mixture of metals is a mixture of elements. Inferences of this kind are often fallacious. Thus, Americans are human beings; therefore, A major- ity of Americans is a majority of human beings. CHAPTER XIV. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. A mediate argument is an argument in which the re- lation of the terms of the derived proposition is inferred from other propositions through the intervention of a middle term. The derived proposition is called the conclusion. The propositions from which the conclusion is inferred are called the premises. A syllogism is an argument in regular form. f All M is P. Thus, \ All S is M. .'. All S is P. A syllogism contains three terms : two extremes — -the major term and the minor term — and the middle term. The major term, P, is the predicate of the conclusion ; the minor term, S, is the subject of the conclusion ; and the middle term, M, is the medium of comparison. A syllogism contains three propositions: two premises — the major premise and the minor premise — and the conclusion. The major premise is the premise which expresses the relation of the middle term, M, to the major term, P. The minor premise is the premise which expresses the relation of the minor term, S, to the middle term, M. The conclusion is the proposition which expresses the (325) 326 PSYCHOLOGY. relation of the minor term to the major, as inferred from the premises. As an illustration of an argument, take the following : All responsible agents are free agents. Man is a responsible agent. .-. Man is a free a^ent. Man and a free agent, the subject and the predicate of the conclusion, are the extremes, — a free agent, the pred- icate, is the major term, and man, the subject, is the minor. The term, resj^onsible agents, with which the extremes are separately compared in the premises, is the middle term, and is in both premises, but not in the conclusion. All responsible agents are free agents, the premise which expresses the relation of the middle term to the major term, is the major premise Man is a resj^onsible agent, the premise which expres.Hes the relation of the minor term to the middle, is the minor jDremise. In extensive quantity^ the class res23onsible agents is subordinate to the class free agents; the class man is sub- ordinate to the class responsible agents; hence the class man is subordinate to the class free agents, according to the principle, a subordinate to a class is subordinate to any genus embracing that class, or, as it may be stated, a part of a part is a part of the whole. In comprehensive quantity^ the class responsible agents comprehends free agency as an element of resj)onsibility; the class man comprehends responsibility as one of its attributes; hence, the class man comprehends free agency as an attribute, on the principle that the whole compre- hends a part of a part. It is to be observed that the term ccreatest in exten- sion is least in comprehension; and that the term least in extension is greatest in comprehension. MEDIA TE AE G UMENTS. 327 The names, major and minor terms, are significant only in extensive quantity; but even in this quantity, the major term, as a matter of fact, as we shall hereafter see, is frequently less in extension than the minor term. These names are, therefore, to be regarded as mere technical expressions, the major term denoting the 2:>red- icate of the conclusion, and the minor, the subject. The expressions, major and minor premises, are also to be regarded as technical expressions, the major 2:)rem- ise being the premise containing the major term, and the minor premise the premise containing the minor term. The order of the premises is not essential, though the major premise generally stands first. The conclusion may even stand before the premises. The function of an argument is to prove that a certain relation exists between two terms, when that relation is not self-evident. In mediate arguments, this is accomplished by select- ing, as the medium of comparison, a third term, called the middle term, with which the other terms are sepa- rately compared. The • relations of the extreme terms to the middle term prove the relation of the extremes to each other. The conclusion must not only be compatible with the premises, but must be necessitated by them, otherwise the argument is a fallacy. This is shown in the following argument and illustra- tions. The conclusion may be accidentally true, as shown in the first set of circles, but it is not necessi- tated by the premises, as shown by the second set. '^o M is P. No S is M, ..-. No S is P. 328 PSYCHOL OGY. The same relations may have different expressions: ]^o 3f is P. /^7C\ /^~^ ^o P is M. All >S is .¥. ( ® i ( -^ ) All S is i¥. .-.JSTo /? is P. V_^ V_y .-.ISro S is P. These arguments are identical in thought, as is seen by the circles, with an accidental difference of expression. Does the syllogism beg the question? It has been as- serted, by John Stuart Mill and others, that the syllo- gism involves the fallacy called petitio principii, the beg- ging of the question. This charge is made, not in the sense that in all valid syllogisms the premises virtually assert the conclusion, — for this they must do, otherwise the argument is a fallacy, — but, in the sense that the conclusion, so far from being deduced from the premises, must be known to be true before the major premise can be established; but as the conclusion is not known to be true, the very thing to be proved is begged in the major premise, thus: All men are mortal. Gabriel is a man. .-. Gabriel is mortal. Mill says : '' That we can not be assured of the mortal- ity of all men, unless we were previously certain of the mortality of every individual man; that if it be still doubtful whether Socrates, or any other individual you choose to name, be mortal or not, the same degree of uncertainty must hang over the assertion, All men are mortal." The warrant for the major premise, All men are mor- tal, is not found in the fact that Gabriel is mortal; for we may be totally ignorant even of the existence of Gabriel. Much less is the major premise a case of so- MEDIATE AEGmiENTS, 329 called perfect induction, established by an examination of every individual man, which is impossible in the nat- ure of the case; and, yet, after examining a multitude of cases, we are warranted in asserting that all men are mortal, as an induction of a very high degree of prob- ability. Neither is the warrant for the conclusion, Gabriel is moi'tal, found only in the inajor premise, All men are mortal; for Gabriel may be an angel. We must also know that Gabriel is a man. Then, without begging the question, the conclusion, Gabriel is mortal, follows logi- cally from the premises, but with no higher probability than the major 2:)remise. The syllogism is based on classification ; and classifica- tion, on the law of Eeasoii and Consequent. An examin- ation of a great number of individuals of the human race reveals sufficient reason for concluding that, in the present condition of man, mortality is the law, or gen- eral fact, of humanity. Again, suj)pose I find a plant of a class v^hich I have never before seen, and am desirous of knowing the char- acter of its fruit, if indeed it bear fruit, not at present having any. I examine the plant according to the meth- ods of botany, and find it to belong to a certain class. Heading a further description of the class, I find the character of the fruit which plants of this kind bear. I then reason thus: Plants of this class bear a certain kind of fruit. This plant belongs to this class. .-.This i^lant bears this kind of fruit. This process is legitimate, and the conclusion is an im- portant extension of my knowledge. But how do botanists know that plants of this kind bear such fruit? Surely not because they have seen Psy.— 28. 330 PSYCHOLOGY, this plant bear such fruit; but because they have seen a great many specimens of this kind of plants bear such fruit, and have found no exceptions; that is, they have found no plants of this kind bearing a different species of fruit. Again, suppose we wish to know how many diago- nals can be drawn in a chiliagon, a polygon of a thousand sides. It would not be practicable to draw all the diag- onals and then count them; for they are too numerous; but the proper thing to do is to find a general formula for the number of diagonals that can be drawn in a polygon of n sides. This formula is not found by in- duction, that is, by finding the number of diagonals that can be drawn in polygons of four, fiYe, six, etc., sides; bat by reasoning thus: Since the polygon has n sides, it has n vertices. Now, from any vertex, a diagonal can be drawn to any ver- tex except itself and the two adjacent vertices; hence, from each vertex, n-3 diagonals can be drawn, and therefore from the n vertices, n times n-3, or n (n-3) diagonals can be drawn ; but in this w^ay, each diagonal is counted twice; hence the number of diagonals is I n (n-3.) • This formula has been established without any refer- ence to the chiliagon. Now, we reason thus : The num- ber of diagonals that can be drawn in a polygon of n sides is Jn(n-3), whatever be the value of n; but, in a chiliagon, n := 1000; hence, the number of diagonals that can be drawn in a chiliagon is 500x997 = 498500. Where is there even a shadow of petitio principu here? Again, suppose I stand on the lake shore and see a vessel sink w4th all on board. Now, need I know that John Jones was drowned to know that all on board were drowned? I may not even know that John Jones was aboard. The next da}^, however, I learn from wit- MEDIA TE AEG UMENTS, 331 nesses who saw the vessel leave a neighboring port that John Jones was aboard. Then I reason thus: All on board a certain vessel at a certain time were drowned. John Jones was on board that vessel at that time. .-. John Jones was drowned. There is no begging of the question here, since I knew the truth of the major premise before knowing the truth of the conclusion. The minor premise is as essential to the truth of the conclusion as the major; but if the tw^o j^remises be admitted, the conclusion can not logically be denied. An enthymeme is an argument w^ith one proposition, either of the premises or the conclusion, suppressed, thus: All men are mortal. .*. You are mortal. You are a man. .-. You are mortal. All men are mortal. You are a man. Such reasonings are common. The last form is im- pressive, as it leaves the hearer to draw his own con- clusion. CHAPTER XV. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. Categorical syllogisms are those in which the propo- sitions — the two premises and the conclusion — are cate- gorical. They are simple or compound. 1. Simple categorical syllogisms are those which con- tain only three terms and three propositions. The three terms are the two extremes — the major term, or the predicate of the conclusion ; and the minor term, or the subject of the conclusion; and the middle term, or the medium of comparison. The three propositions are the two premises — the major premise, or the premise con- taining the major term and the middle term; and the minor premise containing the minor term and the mid- dle term; and the conclusion containing the major term and the minor term. Laws warranting the conclusions, (J.), {E^^ (7), (0). 1st. The universal affirmative conclusion (^) is warranted^ if all the middle term is contained in the major, and all the minor in the middle. This general principle holds whether the relations ex- pressed be those of subordination or co-extension, as thus shown: All M is P. All S is M. .-. All S is P. 2d. The universal negative conclusion (E) is ivarranted, (332) CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS. 333 if all of either extreme is contained in the middle and all of the other is excluded from the middle. This general principle holds whether the relation in the affirmative premise be one of subordination or co- extension, and whether the terms in the negative prem- ise are contraries or contradictoi^ies. Illustrate by circles. All P is M. No P is M. ISTo S is M. All S is M, .-.No S is P. .-.No S is P. 3d. The jyarticular affirmative conclusion (7) is warranted, if all the middle is contained in both extremes, or if all the middle is contained in either extreme, and a part of the mid- dle in the other. In both cases, the same thing — either all or the same part of the middle — is contained in both extremes ; hence, the extremes must, in part at least, coincide with each other, or a particular affirmative conclusion, at least, is warranted. These princij)les hold, whether the relations in the universal premises be those of subordination or co-exten- sion, or the relation in the particular premise be that of co-extension, or intersection, or subordination, which- ever term be subordinate to the other. Illustrate: All M is P All M is P. Some M is P. All M is S. Some M is S. All M is S. .'. Some S is P. .*. Some S is P. .-. Some S is P. If both premises be particular, that is, if some of the middle is contained in the major term, and some in the minor, it will not be known that it is the same some ; the same thing, then, will not be known to be in both extremes, and there will be no w^arrant for the conclu- sion. The argument will then be a fallacy, thus: 334 PSYCHOL OGY, So mo 21 is P. Some ilf is S. .'. Some S is P. If. however, a part of the middle is contained in one extreme, and more tlian the complementary part in the other, the same thing — a part of the middle — is con- tained in each extreme, and the argument is valid,, thus: Two thirds of M is P. More than one third of M is S. ' .'. Some S is P. If, at a certain election, a majority of the electors voted for A, and a majority voted for 5, then some who voted for A, voted for B. 4th'. The particular negative conclusion (0) is warranted if all the major term is excluded from the middle, and some of the minor is contained in the middle; or, if all the major is contained in the middle, and some of the minor is excluded from the middle; or, if all the middle is contained in the minor, and some of the middle is excluded from the major. These principles hold for all possible relations of the terms in the premises, and in each case some of the minor, at least, will be excluded from the major. Illus- trate : No P is M. All P is M. Some M is not P. Some S is M. Some S is not M. All M is S. .'. Some S IS not P. .-. Some S is not P. .'. Some S is not P. 2. A compound syllogism is a combination of simple syllogisms. There are several varieties. 1st. The compound syllogism, composed of a prosyllo- gism and an episyllogism — the conclusion of the prosyl- logism being one of the premises of the episyllogism, thus : CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISM. 335 r All B is A. Prosyllogism } All C \^ B. (..-.AH (7 is ^. -) All D is (7. > Episyllogism. .-. All D is A. ) 2d. An epichirema is a syllogism in which the reasons for the premises are stated in connection with them, thus: (1) All true patriots are friends to religion, because religion is the basis of national prosperity. Some great statesmen are not friends to religion, because their lives are not in accordance with its precej)ts. Therefore, some great statesmen are not true patriots. !A is B, for A h C and C is B. D is A, for D is LJ and E is A. ..D'mB. 3d. The sorites^ or chain syllogism, is a compound ar- gument which may be indefinitely extended. There are several varieties which may be illustrated by circles. (1) When the predicate of each premise is the subject of the next. r All A is B. ( All A \s B. All B is 0. ^^ ,. I All B is a '^^^^ 1 Ml n ' T^ Negative < at ^ • , j All (7 IS D. ^ j No (7 IS If. I -.All A is D. I -.No A is n. (2) When the subject of each premise is the predicate of the next. f All B is A. All C is B. No B is A. All C is ^. Atnrmative -< , ,, -r^ - ^ Negative^ . n t^ . /^ All D IS (7. ^ AH i) IS C. I .-.All D is A I .-.No i) is A 336 PSYCHOLOGY, (3) When the first and second varieties are combined. Negative < All A is B, All B is C, No G is D, All E is D. All F is JS'. All G^ is F. .-. No ^ is G. Negative < V All A is 5. All B is (; All (7 is D. No i; is D, All i^^ is ^. All G is i^. .*. No A is ff. The laws of the sorites are the following: (1) Only one premise can be particular — the first in the first variety, the last in the second j and the first or last in the third — and the subject of the particular prem- ise is the subject of the conclusion. (2) Only one premise can be negative — the last in the first variety, or the first in the second variety. (3) In the third variety, one premise must be negative — the last in the first series, or the first in the second series. The expansion of the sorites is thus effected, trate by circles. lllus- (1) ^ ' All A is B, All B is G ^ All C is B. .: All A is D. V All A is 5. All B is G. .-. All A is G. All G is D. All A is G. .-. All A is D. It will be observed that the minor premise stands first in the first simple syllogism, and the major in the second. This order might, in either or both cases, have been reversed; hence, the order of the premises is not essen- tial. CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS, 337 (2) Expand each of the examples above given to il- lustrate the varieties. (3) Expand the following concrete example: The mind is a thinking substance. A thinking substance is a spirit. A spirit has no composition of parts. That which has no composition of parts is indissoluble. That w^hich is indissoluble is immortal. Therefore, the mind is immortal. Psy.-^29. CHAPTEE XVI. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. Conditional Syllogisms are divided into three classes — Hypothetical, Disjunctive, and Dilemmatic. 1, The hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism having an hypothetical major premise and a categorical minor. Its form is, therefore, determined by the law of Reason and Consequent. The hypothetical syllogism is said to be constructive, or modus ponens, the mood which posits or affirms, when the minor premise affirms the condition, and the conclu- sion the consequent, — and destructive, or modus tollens, the mood which removes or denies, when the minor premise denies the consequent, and the conclusion the condition. . The rule to be observed is that the antecedent condi- tion is to be affirmed in the minor premise and the consequent in the conclusion, or the consequent is to be denied in the minor premise and the condition in the conclusion. The following are illustrations: r If ^ has the fever, he is sick. Constructive I But A has the fever. C Therefore, A is sick. !If A has the fever, he is sick. But A is not sick. Therefore, A has not the fever. If the rule be violated, by either denying the antece- (338) CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS, , 339 dent in the minor premise or affirming the consequent, nothing follows, thus: If A has the fever, he is sick. But A has not the fever. It does not follow that A is not sick; for he may have some other disease, and hence be sick. It would, how- ever, follow that A is not sick, if fever were co-extensive with sickness. If A has the fever, he is sick. But A is sick. It does not follow that A has the fever; for his sick- ness may be the result of some other disease. It would, however, follow that A has the fever, if fever were co- extensive with sickness. The analysis of the hypothetical syllogism, therefore, gives the following results: 1st. The major premise is an hypothetical proposition, enouncing the dependency between a conditioning ante- cedent and a conditioned consequent, but affirming noth- ing in regard to the actual existence of either. 2d. The minor premise is a categorical proposition, either affirming the conditioning antecedent or denying the conditioned consequent. 3d. The conclusion is a categorical proposition, affirm- ing the consequent, if the antecedent is affirmed in the minor premise, or denying the antecedent if the conse- quent is denied in the minor premise. 4th. There is no conclusion, when either the anteced- ent is denied in the minor premise, or the consequent is affirmed, unless the predicate of the antecedent is co- extensive with the predicate of the consequent. The reduction of hypothetical syllogisms to categorical 340 PSYCHOL OOY, is effected by substituting for the major premise the condition of its truth, as determined in Chapter XII. Thus, the condition of the truth of the proposition, If A is B^ A is (7, is the proposition, B is C. Hence the reduction : r If A is B, A is a Constructive I But A is B, (..-. A is G. r B is a = \ A i& B, .'. A is C. Illustrate the above by circles, also the following: Destructive r If A is B, A is C. } But A is not C. L .'. A is not B, B is a A is not G, .-. A is not B. Clf A is B, G is JD. Constructive -j But A is B, (-.•. (7 is D. A is jB. G is ^. .-. C is B. B is B. ^} G is B. .'. G is D. rlf^is^, (7isi). Destructive < But (7 is not D. L.-. J- is not J5. r = < B is D. G is not Z). .-. G is not jS. (7 is A. G is not J5. .-. Some A is not B. The last constructive syllogism may be thus reduced The case of A being B, is the case of G being D. The present case is the case of J^ being B. .*. The present case is the case of C being 7). CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS. 341 Construct hypothetical syllogisms having for major premises the hypothetical propositions of Chapter XII. Eeduce them to categorical by employing the conditions of their truth as premises. 2. The disjunctive syllogism is a syllogism having a disjunctive major premise, and a minor premise in which the number of alternatives is reduced. 1st When there are only two alternatives. In this case, the form is determined by the law of contradictories. There are two moods: — -the affirmative, or modus po- nendo tollens, the mood which by affirming denies, when the minor premise affirms one of the alternatives, and the conclusion denies the other, — and the negative, or modus tollendo ponens, the mood which, by denying, af- firms, when the minor premise denies one of the al- ternatives, and the conclusion affirms the other: The following is the modus ponendo tollens: A is either B or C. But A is B. .-. A is not C. '^ The modus ponendo tollens proceeds on the supposition that there is opposition, contradictory or contrary, be- tween the alternatives. If the opposition is contradictory, the major premise is known, a priori, to be valid; but if the opposition is contrary, the truth of the major prem- ise is determined a posteriori. In either case, if one al- ternative is affirmed, the other must be denied. If there is no opposition between the alternatives, the affirmation of one does not involve the denial of the other. Thus, if we say : "A good book is valued either for the usefulness of its contents or the excellence of its style," it does not follow that if valued for the useful- ness of its contents, it is not valued for the excellence 342 PSYCHOLOGY, of its style. These alternatives are not in opposition, and the book may be valued both for the usefulness of its contents and for the excellence of its style. The alternatives are always diverse, but may be either congruents or conflictives, which are the two species embraced by the genus diverse things. The following is the modus toUendo ponens: A is either B or (7, But A is not B, • r,A is a The book is valued either for the usefulness of its contents or the excellence of its style. But it is not valued for the usefulness of its contents; therefore, it is valued for the excellence of its style. This will be a true conclusion, if the major premise be true, whether there is opposition between the alternatives or not. The analysis of the disjunctive syllogism in the case considered, therefore, gives the following results: (1) The major premise is a disjunctive proposition ex- pressing two alternatives. (2) The minor premise is a categorical proposition af- firming or denying one alternative. (3) The conclusion is a categorical proposition deny- ing one alternative, if the minor premise affirms the other, and if the alternatives are conflictives, or affirm- ing one alternative, if the minor premise denies the other, whether the alternatives are congruents or conflictives. (4) If the alternatives are not conflictives, the modus ponendo tolleiis fails, but the modus tollendo ponens is still valid. 2d. When there are more than two alternatives. In this case the minor premise may be either categorical or disjunctive, thus: CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS. 343 r Affirmative ^ ( A is either J5, C\ D, or ^. ] But A is 5. L.-.A is neither C, J), nor U. iui is either B, C, D, or ^\ But J is either B or C. .-.A is neither D nor LJ. Negative -^ A is either B, C, D, or K But J. is neither B, C, nor -D. .-. A is ^. A is either B, C, D, or U. But J. is neither B nor (7. .-.J. is either D or ^. The laws aj^plying to more than three conflictive al- ternatives are the following: (1) Affirming a j^art of the disjunctives, determinately or indeterminately, in the minor premise, denies all the others in the conclusion if the alternatives are conflict- ives, but not if the alternatives are congruents. (2) Denying a part of the alternatives in the minor premise, affirms the rest, in conclusion, determinately or indeterminately, according as one or more remain, whether the alternatives are conflictives or congruents. If the minor premise neither affirms nor denies an al- ternative, but affirms something to be contained in the subject, the conclusion is disjunctive, thus: • B is either C or D. Ah B. .'.A is either C or D. This syllogism is, in thought, categorical. 3. The diiemmatic syllogism is a syllogism having an hypothetical major premise and a disjunctive minor. 344 PSYCHOLOGY, There are at least four forms, as follows: 1st. The simple constructive dilemma. The major prem- ise has different antecedents and the same consequent; the minor j)remise disjunctively affirms the antecedents; and the conclusion affirms the consequent, thus: If A is B. X is Y. cA\^B, it A IS a, Ji \^ l.~\ CA IS i/, ^ If (7 is i), Jr is y. [ But either] or (7 is D, [ .-. X is T. If E is F, X is Y. J (or ^ is i^. 3 If the minor premise had been, X is not F, the con- clusion would have been, A is not ^, G is not D, and E is not F, This is virtually a destructive hyj)othetical syllogism, but is not strictl^^ dilemmatic, since the minor premise is not a disjunctive proposition. 2d. The simple destructive dMemma. The major prem- ise has the same antecedent and different consequents; the minor premise disjunctively denies the consequents; and the conclusion denies the antecedent, thus: If A is -S, (7is Z). ^ r G is not D, ^ If A is B, E is F. V But either \ or ^ is not F^ V .\ A is not B, If^isi?, G^isJyJ (.orG^isnotll.J If the minor premise had been A is B^ the conclusion would have been, (7 is D^ E is i^, and G is H^ which is virtually a constructive hypothetical syllogism but not dilemmatic. 3d. The comj)lex constructive dilemma. The major prem- ise has different antecedents and different consequents; the minor premise disjunctively affirms the antecedents; and the conclusion disjunctively affirms the consequents, thus : If A is 5, G is H. \ If G is B,J is K. [But either If E is F. E \s M.) A is B, or G is D, or E is F, . Either G is //, J is K. or X is M. CONDITIONAL SYLL O GISMS. 345 4th. The complex destructive dilemma. The major prem- ise has different antecedents and different consequents; the minor premise disjunctively denies the consequents; and the conclusion disjunctively denies the antecedents, thus: If A is B, am H.\ rG is not H, If is D, J is X. y But either ^ or J" is not K, If E is F, L is M. ) ( or X is not M. .-.Either A is not J5, is not D, or E is not F. To which class does the following dilemma belong? If a science furnishes useful facts, it is worthy of cul- tivation ; if the study of it exercises the reasoning pow- ers, it is worthy of cultivation; but a science either fur- nishes useful facts, or its study exercises the reasoning powers; therefore, it is worthy of cultivation. 4. The reductio ad absurdum is an indirect argument which, by employing some form of the conditional syl- logism, proves a proposition to be true by showing that the supposition that it is false involves an absurdity. It is based on the harmony of truth. There are two cases of the reductio ad absurdum: 1st. When only two relations are possible — one ex- pressed by the given proposition, and the other by its contradictory. In this case, either the given proposition or its con- tradictory is true. The given proposition is proved true by assuming that it is false, or, which is virtually the same, that its contradictory is true. We then rea- son on this assumed proposition till we reach a conclu- sion conflicting with a known truth, and hence absurd. Therefore, the assumed proposition, which led to this absurdity, is false, and if false, its contradictory, or the given proposition, is true, and is hence demonstrated. 346 PSYCHOLOGY. Thus, of two unequal quantitieSj a and 6, we can prove that ay>h^ if we can show that the supposition, aKb, involves an absurdity. 2d. When more than two relations are possible — one expressed by the given proposition, and the others by its contraries. In this case, the given proposition, or some one of its contraries, is true. The given proposi- tion is proved true, by assuming that it is false, or, which is virtually the same, that some one of the contraries is true. We then show that each of these contraries is false, because involving an absurdity; but the falsity of all the contraries implies the truth of the given propo- sition, which is, therefore, demonstrated. Thus, we can prove that a = ^, if we can show that each of the sup- positions, a > 6 and a < ^, involves an absurdity. In dealing with the second case, care must be taken that all possible contraries are considered. If a possible contrary is omitted, the conclusion is vitiated. As an example of this method, prove that the side opposite the greater of two unequal angles of a triangle is greater than the side opposite the less, — having first proved that the angles opposite the equal sides of an isosceles tri- angle are equal, and that the ayigle opposite the greater of two unequal sides of a triangle is greater than the angle opposite the less. CHAPTEE XVII. DEDUCTIVE REASONING, A formal fallacy is a fallacy which, in its form, vio- lates some law of thought. It is also called a paralogism^ or a fallacy in dictione or in voce. 1. Classification and Illustrations. — There are several varieties. 1st. A paradox^ or violation of a fundamental law of thought. It is self-contradictory, and, when explicitly stated, is at once detected. Thus, A is non-A. A part is greater than the whole, etc. 2d. Fallacies in immediate inferences. The varieties are : (1) Fallacies in the relation of the propositions, (J.), (F), (J), (0). Thus, inferring from the falsity of either (J.) or (^),the truth of the other; from the truth of either (7) or (0), the falsity of the other; from the falsity of (J.), the falsity of (I) ; from the truth of (7), the truth of (A) ; from the falsity of (JS"), the falsity of (0); from the truth of (0), the truth of (^). (2) Fallacies in conversion. Thus, All S is P; .-.All P is S. All seeds come from plants; .*. All plants come from seeds. Some S is not P; Some P is not S. Some animals are not horses; .-.Some horses are not animals. (3) Fallacies in extending modal restriction. Thus, ;S' is possibly P; .-. S is probably P. S is probably P; .-. S is actually P. aS^ is actually P; .-. S is necessarily P. (4) Fallacies from composition. Thus, A and B are C ; .'.A is C. In numbers, this fallacy is apparent, as 3 and 2 are 5; .-. 3 is 5. ( 347 ) 348 PSYCHOL OGY. (5) Fallacies from determinants. Thii8j a pony is a horse; .-.A big pony is a big horse. 3d. Fallacies in mediate inferences. There are several varieties : (1) Undistributed middle. This fallacy consists in com- paring each of the extremes with a part of the middlCy and, as it is not certain that it is the same part, the extremes are not known to be compared with the same thing, and hence there is no warrant for inferring their relations to each other. It will suffice, however, if the middle term be distributed in one of the premises. Let it be remembered that a term is distributed, if it is either the subject of a universal proposition or the predicate of a negative; and that a term is to bo re- garded as undistributed, if it is either the subject of a particular proposition or the predicate of an affirmative. In a valid argument, the conclusion is not only com- patible with the premises, but is necessitated by them, otherwise the argument is a fallacy. Take an argument with an undistributed middle: All P is Jf. All S is M. .'. All S is P. The middle term is undistributed, since in each term it is the predicate of an affirmative. The conclusion does not necessarily follow from the premises, as seen from the first diagram; but it may be accidentally true, as seen from the second, yet the argument is no less a fallacy, since the conclusion is not necessitated. If the relation in the major premise is known to be that of co-extension, in which case the conclusion is true, the argument can be relieved from the appearance FORMAL FALLACIES. 349 of fallacy by converting the major premise, as is ad- missible in case of co-extension, thus: All M is P. All S is M, .'. All S is P. What is the fallacy in the following argument? Every country under a tyranny is distressed. This country is distressed. .-. This country is under a tyranny. (2) Illicit process. This fallacy consists in distributing either the major or minor term in the conclusion, when it is not distributed in its premise. Take the following argument : All M \^ P P is distributed in the conclusion, since No S is M. it is the predicate of a negative, but is .-. No S is P. undistributed in the major premise, since it is the predicate of an affirmative; hence, we have an illicit process of the major term. Show the fallacy by circles. Take also the following: All M \^ P. S is distributed in the conclusion, since All M is S. it is the subject of a universal, but it is .*. All S is P. undistributed in the minor premise, since it is the predicate of an affirmative; hence, we have an illicit process of the minor term. Show the fallacy by circles. (3) Farticular premises. This name aids in detecting certain fallacies, since we know at once that there is a fallacy, when each of the premises begins with the word some; but this case is not another class of fallacies, since, it involves either the undistributed middle, or an illicit 350 PSYCHOLOGY, process. Show this in the following, and illustrate by circles: Some P is M, Some M is P. Some /S is ilf. • Some 8 is not M. .'. Some S is P. .*. Some S is not P. (3) A universal conclusion and one particular premise. This involves either an undistributed middle or an illicit process. Show this in the following, and illustrate by circles: Some M is P. All M is P. All S is M. Some S is not M. .', All S is P. .-. Some aS is not P. Some Jf is not P. Some ilf is not P. All If is 8. . All >S is M. .-.No >S is P. .-.ISro aS is P. (5) Negative premises. In this case, no conclusion is warranted; for the denial of certain relations between the middle term and the extremes, warrants neither the affirmation nor denial of any relation between the ex- tremes. Thus, show the fallacy of the following b}^ cir- cles: No P is M. Some M is not P. No 8 is M. No 8 is M. .'. No 8 is P. .*. Some 8 is not P. (6) ^n affirmative conclusion and one negative premise. The affirmative premise expresses the agreement, in whole or in part, of one of the extremes with the mid- dle; and the negative premise, the disagreement of the other extreme with the middle; hence, if any relation of the extremes follows, it is that of disagreement, or the FORMAL FALLACIES, 351 conclusion is negative. Show the fallacy of the follow- ing by circles: No M is P. No M is P. All 8 is M, . Some >9 is M. .-. All >S is P. .-. Some 8 is P. (7) A negative conclusion from affirmative premises. Both extremes agree in whole or in part with the middle, and hence if any relation is warranted, the extremes must agree with each other, or the conclusion is affirm- ative. Show the fallacy of the following by circles : All ilf" is P. All M is P. All 8 is M. Some 8 is M. .-.No 8 is P. .-. Some 8 is not P. (8) Fallacies in hypothetical syllogisms. This fallacy arises either when we deny the condition in the minor premise, and the consequent in the conclusion, or when we affirm the consequent in the minor premise, and the condition in the conclusion. The following is an example of the first kind: If this man has stolen, he is immoral. But he has not stolen. .-. He is not immoral. The following is an example of the second kind: If this man has stolen, he is immoral. But he is immoral. .-. He has stolen. (9) Fallacies in disjunctive syllogisms. This fallacy arises when, in case there is no conflict between the al- 352 PSYCHOLOGY, ternatives, we affirm one in the minor premise and deny the other in the conclusion. The following example will illustrate : This science i& valued either for knowledge or for discipline. It is valued for knowledge. .*. It is not valued for discipline. It may be valued for both knowledge and discipline. (10) Fallacies in dilemmatic syllogisms. These are analogous to those in the hypothetical syllogism, and consist in denying the condition, and hence the conse- quent, or in affirming the consequent, and hence the condition. (11) Fallacy of four terms. The use of four terms in a syllogism involves a fallacy nicknamed the logical quadruped. In this case, there are either two middle terms, and the extremes are separately compared with diiferent things, thus affording no warrant for inferring their relations to each other, or thei:e is a term in the conclusion not found in either premise, in which case one extreme is not compared with the middle, and hence its relation to the other extreme can not be inferred. The fallacy in this form is too glaring to deceive; hence, it generally assumes the form called the fallacy of equivocation — the same word being used with two distinct meanings. There are apparently but three terms, though in reality four. Any one of the three terms, the major, the minor, or the middle, is liable to be equivocal, but it is more fre- quently the middle term which is thus used in a double sense. In this case, the fallacy is called the fallacy of the amMguous middle. The following are illustrations: Light is contrary to darkness. FORMAL FALLACIES. 353 Feathers are light. .-. Feathers are contrary to darkness. All criminal actions ought to be punished by law. Prosecutions for theft are criminal actions. .-. Prosecutions for theft ought to be punished by law. (12) Fallacy of amphibology. This fallacy consists in the use of an ambiguous grammatical construction. Thus, the conclusion depending on the interpretation of the proposition, '^ The duke yet lives that Henr^^ shall depose," would be doubtful, since, from the con- struction, it is uncertain whether Henry is to depose the duke, or the duke, Henry. (13) The fallacy of composition. This fallacy occurs when the middle term is used distributively in the major premise and collectively in the minor, as in the following example: Three and four are two numbers. Seven is three and four. .-. Seven is two numbers. (14) The fallacy of division. This fallacy occurs when the middle term is used collectively in the major prem- ise and distributively in the minor, as the following: Seven is one number. Three and four are seven. .-. Three and four are one number. (15) The fallacy of accent or emphasis. This fallacy consists in misplacing the accent or emphasis. In the proposition, "The study of Logic is not supposed to communicate a knowledge of many useful facts," place the emphasis first on supposed^ then on 7nany, then on useful^ and state the sense expressed in each case. Psy.— 30. 354 PSYCHOL OGY, (16) The fallacy of figure of speech. Thus, the follow- ing will illustrate: A hero is a lion. A lion is a quadruped. .-.A hero is a quadruped. Designing persons are untrustworthy. Every body forms designs. .-. Ever}^ body is untrustworthy. 2. Bules guarding against fallacy. — These are. 1st. Every syllogism must have three, and only three, terms — the major term, the minor term, and the middle term, and these terms must not be ambiguous. 2d. Ever}^ syllogism must have three, and only three, propositions — the major premise, the minor premise, and the conclusion, and these propositions must not be ambiguous. 3d. The middle term must be - distributed at least in one of the premises. 4th. A term must not be distributed in the conclusion, unless it is distributed in one of the premises. 5th. If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion is affirmative. 6th. If one premise is affirmative and the other neg- ative the conclusion is negative. 7th. If both premises are negative there is no con- clusion. 8th. If the conclusion is universal, both premises are universal. 9th. If one premise is universal and the other partic- ular, the conclusion is particular. 10th. If both premises are particular, there is no con- clusion. 3. General laws of the syllogism. — These laws, on the FORMAL FALLACIES, 355 supposition that no formal fallacy is involved, are the following : 1st. The truth of the premises involves the truth of the conclusion ; for the premises necessitate the conclu- sion. 2d. The falsity of the conclusion involves the falsity of one of the premises; for if the premises were true, the conclusion would be true. 3d. The falsity of a premise does not necessitate the falsity of the conclusion. 4th. The truth of the conclusion does not involve the truth of the premises. The third and fourth laws are thus illustrated: Every month has thirty days April is a month. .-. April has thirty days. 4. Miscellaneous examples of fallacies. — Character- ize the following fallacies, stating the irregular examples in due form : 1. All good fathers provide food and clothing for their children. Mr. B provides food and clothing for his children. Therefore, Mr. ^ is a good father. 2. All moral beings are accountable. IN^o brute is a moral being. Therefore, no brute is accountable. 3. No Pagan is a Christian. Every villager is a Pa- gan. Therefore, no villager is a Christian. 4. Nothing is better than wisdom. Dry bread is better than nothing. Therefore, dry bread is better than wis- dom. 5. His imbecility of character might have been in- ferred from his proneness to favoritism; for all weak princes have this failing. 6. The express trains do not stop at this station. The 356 PSYCHOLOGY. train that has just passed did not stop at this station. Therefore, the train that just passed is an express train. 7. A successful author must be very industrious or very talented. Gibbon was a successful author and was very industrious. Therefore, Gibbon was not very talented. 8. Who is most hungry eats most. Who eats least is most hungry. Therefore, who eats least eats most. 9. The end of a thing is its perfection. Death is the end of life. Therefore, death is the perfection of life. 10. He who believes himself to be always in the right in his opinions lays claim to infallibility. You always believe yourself to be right in your opinion. Therefore, you lay claim to infallibility. 11. Improbable events happen every day. But what happens every daj^ is probable. Therefore, improbable events are probable. 12. The ancient Greeks produced the greatest master- ]3ieces of eloquence and philosophy. The Lacedemonians were ancient Greeks. Therefore, the Lacedemonians produced the greatest masterpieces of eloquence and philosophy. CHAPTEE XVIII. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. A material fallacy is a fallacy in the matter of thought. It is said to be a fallacy in re, and is, there- fore, extra dictionem, and, in fact, extra logical, unless it is also faulty in form. Material fallacies can be detected only hj those ac- quainted with the subject-matter, or with the special science under consideration. Thus, to settle matters of fact pertaining to plants, we appeal to botany; facts pertaining to the stars, fall within the province of as- tronomy, and so on. Though material fallacies can not be detected purely by the methods of logic, yet it is important to point them out and classify them, thus rendering the mind alert, and diminishing the liabilities of falling into error. We shall consider eight varieties of material fallacies: 1. Assumptions. — An assumption is that which is taken to be true without evidence. It may be true or false; but, resting on no basis of evidence, it is, in either case, invalid, not because known to be false, bat because not known to be true. To assume an assumption false on account of its lack of evidence, is a procedure as in- valid as to assume it true. There are several varieties of assumptions : 1st. The want of attention results in non-observation or mal-ohservation. Failing to notice many things, we are likely to assume their non-existence. Other things, not wholly overlooked, are, from inattention, misapprehended, ( 357 ) 358 PSYCHOLOGY. and assuming them to be what they are not, we are in- volved in confusion. 2d. Prejudice is a fruitful source of assumptions. JSTor is it easy to divest ourselves of its influence, though we are loath to admit that we are, in any degree, subject to its control. Prejudice which leads to assumptions vitia- ting our judgments and involving us in error, may arise from too high an opinion of ourselves, or from too low an opinion of others; from ruling desires; from national, party, church, or society relations; from preconceived opinions, association, ignorance, or defective education. A generous disposition, a love of truth, due caution, and patient investigation, are guards against the assumptions arising from prejudice. 3d. Superstition has, especially in the past, been fruitful in assumptions; consider the mythologies, oracles, omens, witchcrafis, apparitions, ghosts, fairies, signs, and charms. Nor has superstition yet lost its influence, as is indi- cated by such current sayings as these: ''If it rain the first Sunday of the month, it will rain every Sunday." ^' If you first see the new moon over your right shoulder, you will have good luck for that month." '' If you have floating tea-leaves in your cup, you will have visitors." 4th. Hasty generalization leads to assumptions and in- volves us in error. We thus assume that what is true of ourselves is true of others; that what is true of a few individuals of a class is true of the class; that edu- cation is not desirable, because a few have risen to emi- nence without it; that fortune favors fools, because a man confessedly below par has accidentally become rich. 5th. A ivaiit of thorough investigation may lead to the assunifjtion that a given appearance corresponds to the reality; that a temporary order of sequence is a law; that an accidental antecedent is a cause, or that an ac- cidental consequent is an eflect. MATEEIAL FALLACIES. 359 2. The fallacy of accident. — This fallacy consists in extending a rule to a case to which it is rendered in- applicable by some specific or accidental circumstance. There are three varieties. 1st. Arguing from the general to the special. Thus, every man has the right to inculcate his own opinions. A magistrate is a man. Therefore, a magistrate is justi- fied in employing his official powers in forwarding his political or sectarian views. A magistrate has the same general rights as other men, and he may properly em- ploy his powers as a man, but not as a magistrate, in propagating his opinions. 2d. In arguing from the special to the general. Thus, thieves are dishonest ; but thieves are men ; therefore all men are dishonest. 3d. In arguing from one special case to another. Thus, certain beggars do not deserve assistance; therefore, other beggars do not deserve assistance. 3. Irrelevant conclusion. — This fallacy, technically called ignoratio elenchij consists in arguing to the wrong point, or proving one thing when another should be proved. This fallacy is the great resource of those who have a weak case, or the wrong side of the question. A certain English statesman, instead of j)roving the ex- pediency of taxing the colonies, which was the real ques- tion to be considered, undertook to prove the right. A form of this fallacy, called argumentum ad hominem, consists in arguing the case, not on its merits, but in relation to the opinion or character of your opponent, as when it is attempted to refute an opjDonent by prov- ing that his present position is inconsistent with his previously expressed views or with his character. Another form of this fallacv, called araumentiim ad populum^ consists in appealing to the prejudice or pas- sions of the people. It is the weapon of demagogues. 360 PSYCHOLOGY. There is still another form of this fallacy called ar- gumentiim ad verecundiam. It is an apj)eal to reverence for resj)ected authority or venerable institutions. Closely connected with the irrelevant conclusion, which logically follows from the premises, though it is not the conclusion in question, is an unwarranted conclusion from premises which warrant another conclusion. Thus, it is often inferred that the conclusion is false because the premises are false or the reasoning is illogical. The true inference is, that the conclusion is not proved; but it may be trae, notwithstanding the premises are false. An able debater once said, "I have undertaken to prove the conclusion false, by showing the premises on which it is based to be unsound." 4. The begging of the question, petitio principii, called also a circle in reasoning, circulus in probando^ consists in taking for one of the premises something which de- pends on the conclusion, and then having deduced the conclusion, employ it in proving the premise. Thus, it is reasoning in a circle, to assume that a party is right, and hence conclude that you ought to support it, and then attempt to justify the assumption that the party is right because you ought to support it. The fallacy of reasoning in a circle may be unjustly charged. Thus, if your opponent sees that your propo- sition will lead to your conclusion, he may attempt to evade the force of your argument, by charging you with begging the question, and then escape in the cloud of dust which he raises. 5. The fallacy of the consequent. — This is the name of an argument so loose that no one can discover its cogency. It has no cogency. It is usually character- ized by the expression, non sequiter, that is to say, it does not follow. 6. The fallacy of false cause, or non causa pro causa. MA TERIAL FALL A CLES. 361 This fallacy consists in calling one thing the cause of another, because it is an antecedent, or one thing the effect of another, because it is a consequent. The fallacy of mistaking a consequent for an effect is described by the phrase, post hoc^ ercjo propter hoc, 7. The fallacy of many questions. — This fallacy con- sists in combining two or three questions in one, so that whether answered in the affirmative or negative, the answer can be turned to your disadvantage. Thus, if the question, "Have you left off beating your mother?" is answered in the affirmative, then the retort is that you formerly beat her; if in the negative, that you still beat her. 8. The fallacy of objections. — This fallacy consists in inferring a conclusion to be false, because objections can be raised against it. Very few things could be regarded proved, if only those are proved against which no pos- sible objection can be raised. It is, perhaps, true that objections can be raised against any thing whatever. But this does not prove that nothing is true; for objections can be raised against either of two contradictor}^ propo- sitions, one of which must be true. If, however, a proposition conflicts with a known truth, it can not be true, and we have a warrant for its rejection. Miscellaneous examples of fallacies. — Detect the fal- lacy in each of the following examples : 1. If Christianity were from God, it would be univer- sal. It is not universal. Therefore, it is not from God. 2. You are not what I am. I am a man. Therefore, you are not a man. 3. He who calls 3^ou a man, speaks the truth. He who calls you a knave, calls 3^ou a man. Therefore, he who calls you a knave, speaks the truth. 4. You do not know what I am going to ask you about. I am going to ask you about the nature of Psy.— 31. 362 PSYCHOLOGY, yourself. Therefore, yoii do not know about the nature of yourself 5, The following sophism^ called the Achilles^ was pro- posed by Zeno^ the Eleatic, and is very celebrated: If Achilles runs ten times as fast as a tortoise one mile ahead, he will never overtake it; for when Achilles has run this mile, the tortoise has run -^^ of a mile farther; when Achilles has run this y^^, the tortoise has advanced TOT ^^ ^ mile still farther, and so on, ad infinitum. 6, According to Zeno, a finite body is impossible. For if there be such a body, and if it be divided into any number of parts, the sum of the parts ought to be equal to the body. Let the number of parts be infinite. Then these parts either have magnitude, or they have no magnitude; if the parts have magnitude, their sum has infinite magnitude, since there is an infinite number of parts; if the parts have no magnitude, their sum will have no magnitude, since the sum of any number of zeros is zero. In neither case is the sum equal to the body, as it ought to be, since the sum of all the parts is equal to the whole. Hence, the supposition that there is a finite body, which led to this absurdity, is false. 7. The Diodorus Cronus^ so called from its inventor, at- tempts to prove the impossibility of motion, thus: If motion is possible, a body moves either in the place where it is, or in the place where it is not. But it can not move in the place where it is, since it fills that place, leaving no room. It can not move in the place where it is not, for it is not there. Hence, it can not move at all, or motion is impossible. 8. The Litigiosus^ or Beciprociis, is the notorious di- lemma concerning a matter of business between Protag- oras, the prince of Sophists, and Euathlus, his student in the law. Euathlus had contracted to pay his tuition fee when he gained his first case. But not being in a \ m MATERIAL FALLACIES. 363 hurry to commence the practice of law, Protagoras sued him for his fee, and thus addressed him in court: ^' Learn, most foolish of young men, that whatever be the decision of the judges, pay me my demand you must. For, if the judgment be against you, I shall ob- tain the fee b}^ decree of the court; but if the judgment be in your favor, I shall obtain my fee by the terms of our contract, since you will then have gained your first case." To this Euathlus replied, ^' Learn, most sapient of masters, from your own argument, that, whatever may be the decision of the court, absolved I must be from the payment of the fee. For, if the decision be in my favor, I shall pay nothing according to the decree of the court; but if the decision be against me, I pay nothing by virtue of the contract, since I shall not have gained my first case." 9. The mentiens, or sophism of the liar, was invented by Eubulides, and runs thus: ''If you say that you lie, and tell the truth, then you do lie ; but if you tell a lie, then you speak the truth. Hence, if you tell the truth you lie, and if you lie, you speak the truth." 10. If an event is to be, it w^ill be, and effort is use- less. If it is not to be, it will not be, and effort is use- less. But it is evident that the event either is to be, or is not to be. Therefore, effort is useless. 11. According to Empedocles, the subject which knows and the object which is known must be of like nature ; but the mind knows matter. Therefore, the mind and matter must be of like nature. Hence, the mind is re- solvable into matter, or matter into mind. 12. According to M. Comte, the events of the world are not controlled by supernatural will; for if so, they would be both variable and beyond human control; but they are not variable, since they are the objects of hu- 364 PSYCHOLOGY. man prevision in astronomy; neither are thej^ beyond human control, since they are subject to human modi- fication, as in physics. 13. Whatever I know, must be as I know, otherwise I could not know. I know that you are here. Tliere- fbre, you must be here, and hence are not a free agent. 14. Wiiatever God foreknows must be as He foreknows, otherwise he could not foreknow. God foreknows the actions of men. Therefore, these actions must be as God foreknows. Hence, these actions are necessitated, and men are not free agents. 15. If God is both able and willing to prevent sin, it would not occur; but sin does occur. Therefore, God is able to prevent it, but not willing; or willing, but not able ; or neither willing nor able. If He is able, but not willing, He is not holy; if He is willing, but not able, He is not omnipotent; if He is neither willing nor able. He is neither holy nor omnipotent; but any of these consequences is subversive of the idea of God; hence, there is no God. It may be remarked that fallacy, in general, may be summarily divided into fallacy of apprehension, fallacy of reasoning, and fallacy of assumption. Fallacy of apprehension consists in misapprehension in regard either to the proposition itself or to its grounds. Its essence is confusion. Fallacy of reasoning consists in illogical inference, and is either formal or material. Fallacy of assumption consists in taking the premises for granted without evidence. Probable premises, how- ever, ma}" be employed, if the conclusion also be re- garded as only probable. CHAPTEK XIX. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. 1. A knowledge of the doctrine of Mood and Figure^ as developed in this and the following chapter, though not essential in testing a sound argument or in detect- ing a fallacy, as the preceding discussions prove, is nevertheless interesting in itself and in its historical as- sociations. 2. The mood of syllogism is the designation of the quantity and quality of its propositions, taken in the order of major premise, minor premise, and conclusion, each by one of the symbols, ^, ^, /, 0. Thus, the mood of the following syllogism i^ E A E. No ikf is P. All S is M. ,-. No S is P. 3. The number of possible moods is thus determined: Any one of the four propositions, J., E^ /, O, may be the major premise, each having either A^ E, 7, 0, for the minor premise, making sixteen combinations of premises, each combination having either A, E, I, 0, for the con- clusion, making sixty-four possible moods. These sixty- four moods are therefore divided into four groups having A^ E, 7, O, respectively, for the major j)remise;- each group is divided into four sub-groups, having A, E, 7, O, respectively, for the minor premise ; and each sub-group is divided into four moods, having A, E, 7, 0, respectively, for the conclusion, as thus exhibited: ( 365 ) 366 PSYCHOLOGY, Group A. Group E. Group I. Group O. ' A A A E A A I A A A A Sub-group A < A A A E A I E A E E A I I I A E A I A E OAT u A E A I A A ' A E A E E A I E A E A Sub-group E < A A E I E E E E E I I I E E E I E E E I u E E E I E E •* ' A I A E I A I I A I A - cy 7 T A I E E I E I I E I E tSub-group I < A I I E I I I I I Oil 1 A I E I I I 10 1 (A A E A I A A I Sub-group < A A E I E E EOT I I E I E 1 , A E I 4. Valid moods are those in which valid arguments can be constructed. Invalid moods are those in which valid arguments can not be constructed. Most of the above moods are invalid, since they vio- late one or more of the following rules : (1) If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion is affirmative. (2) If one premise is affirmative and the other nega- tive, the conclusion is negative. (3) If both premises are negative, there is no conclu- sion. (4) If the conclusion is universal, both premises must be universal. (5) If one premise is universal and the other partic- ular, the conclusion is particular. MOOD OF SYLLOGISMS. 367 (6) If both premises are particular, there is no con- chision. (7) The middle term must be distributed in, at least, one of the premises. (8) ]^o term must be distributed in the conclusion which is not distributed in one of the premises. 5. The negative method o^ finding the valid moods is as follows: Point out the invalid moods, and tell which of the above rules are violated. The moods not violating any of the above rules are valid. Tell which moods are valid« Eemember that a mood is valid, if a valid argu- ment can be constructed in it, though other arguments in the same mood be invalid. The above method of determining the valid moods may be characterized as the negative method^ since the valid moods are not positively determined, but are those left, after striking out the moods that are invalid. The following moods are valid : A A A^ A A I^ A E E^ A E 0, A I T, A O 0, E A E, E A 0. E I 0, I A I, GAG. The mood LEG involves an illicit process of the major term. Prove this. 6. The positive method of determining the valid moods is as follows: 1st. If the conclusion is A, both premises must be A. For since the conclusion is universal, both premises must be universal, and hence both A, or both E^ or one A and the other E. Both premises can not be E, for then, by rule (3), there would be no conclusion. One premise can not be A and the other E, for then, by rule (2), the conclusion would be negative. Hence, if the conclu- sion is warranted at all, both premises must be A^ which is the only remaining case. That A A A is Si valid mood, is verified by the follow- ing valid syllogism : 368 PSYCHOLOGY, All M is R All 8 i^M, .'. All S is P. 2d. 7/" the conclusion is E^ one premise must he A, and the other E, Prove this and construct valid syllogisms having the moods, A E E^ E A E, respectively, 3d. If the conclusion is 7, both premises are affirmative, and one. at least, universal. Prove this and construct valid syllogisms having the moods, A A I, A I I, I A I, respectively. 4th. If the conclusion is 0, one premise must be affirma- tive, the other negative, and one, at least, universal. Prove this, and construct valid syllogisms whose moods are, A E 0, E A 0, A 0, A 0, E I 0, respectively. CHAPTBE XX. DEDUCTIVE REASONING. The figure of a syllogism is the position of its middle term with respect to the extremes in the premises. Let M denote the middle term, P the major, and S the minor, and let the order of the letters denote the order of the terms. Then we have the following figures: 1st. Fig. -2d. Fig. 3d. Fig. 4th. Fig. Major premise, MP P M MP P M Minor premise, S M S M M S MS Conclusion, S P S P S P S P In the first figure, the middle term is the subject of the major premise and the predicate of the minor. In the second figure, the middle term is the predicate of both premises. In the third figure, the middle term is the subject of both premises. In the fourth figure, the middle term is the predicate of the major premise and the subject of the minor. Eemember that a universal proposition, A or E^ dis- tributes its subject; that a negative, E or 0, distributes its predicate ; that a particular, / or 0, does not distrib- ute its subject; that an afiirmative, A or 7, does not, in general, distribute its predicate; also, that the middle term must be distributed, at least, in one of the premises; and that a term must not be distributed in the conclu- sion, if it is not distributed in one of the premises, since that would be an illicit process. (369) 370 PSYCHOLOGY, Figure T. cM P. 1st. Order of terms. The order of the terms, is ^ >S Jf. Is P. 2d. Definition. Figure first is that figure in which the middle term is the subject of the major premise and the predicate of the minor. 3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. I. are thus determined : (1) To have an affirmative conclusion, both premises must be afiirmative. The major premise must be uni- versal, otherwise the middle term would not be distrib- uted, since it is not distributed as the predicate of the afiirmative minor premise. If the minor premise is uni- versal, the conclusion may be universal or particular; but if the minor premise is particular, the conclusion is particular. Hence, A A A^ A A I^ A 1 1^ are valid af- firmative moods in Fig. I. The mood A A I i^ usually discarded, since the premises warrant the conclusion A, which implies I. (2) To have a negative conclusion, the major premise must be negative, in order to distribute the predicate which is distributed in the conclusion. The minor premise must be afiirmative, otherwise both premises would be negative, and there would be no conclusion. The major premise must be universal, in order to dis- tribute the middle term, which is not distributed as the predicate of the affirmative minor premise. If the minor premise is universal, the conclusion may be universal or particular; but if the minor premise is particular, the conclusion must be particular. Hence, E A E^ E A 0, E I Oj are valid negative moods in Fig. I. The mood E A is usually discarded, since the premises warrant the conclusion E, which implies 0. FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM, 371 4th. Doctrine, The doctrine of Fig. I. is the following: (1) The middle term is the subject of the major prem- ise, and the predicate of the minor. (2) The major premise is universal, and the minor af- firmative. (3) The conclusion agrees in quality with the major premise, and in quantity with the minor. (4) All forms of conclusion, J., E^ /, 0, are admissible in Fig. I. 5th, Aristotle's dictum. Whatever is predicated, affirm- atively or negatively, of any term distributed, may be predicated, in like manner, of whatever is contained under that term. This dictum is sometimes separated into two dicta: — the dictum de omni, Whatever is af- firmed of any term distributed, may be affirmed of any thing contained under that term ; and the dictum de nidlo, Whatever is denied of any term distributed, may be de- nied of any thing contained under that term. 6th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. I. are b Arb A r A^ c E I Ar En t, d Ar II, and f ErI 0. The vowels denote the propositions. Construct these ar- guments, using the letters, Jf, P, /S, and test their valid- ity by circles, also by Aristotle's dictum. Illustrate by concrete arguments. See Schuyler's Logic, pp. 65, 78. Figure II. rP M. 1st. Order of terms. The order of terms is I S M. Ls P. 2d. Definition. Figure second is that figure in which the middle term is the predicate of both premises. 3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. 11. are thus determined : In order to distribute the middle term, since it is the predicate of both premises, one of the premises must be 372 PSYCHOLOGY, negative; hence the other premise must be affirmative, otherwise there would be two negative premises, and therefore no conclusion. Since one premise is affirmative and the other negative, the conclusion is negative, aad therefore its predicate is distributed; hence, the major premise must be universal in order to distribute its subject, which is distributed as the predicate of the con- clusion. If the minor premise is universal, the conclu- sion may be universal or particular; but, if the minor premise is particular, the conclusion is particular. Hence, E AE, A E E, E A 0, AEG, E I 0; AGO, are valid moods in Fig. II. The moods, E A G, AEG, are usually discarded, since the premises warrant the conclusion Ej which implies 0. The striking fact in this figure is that the conclusion is always negative. 4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. I. is the follow- ing : (1) The middle term is the predicate of both prem- ises. (2) One premise is affirmative and the other is neg- ative. (3) The major premise is universal. (4) The conclusion is negative, and agrees in quantity with the minor premise. 5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. II. are cEsArE, cAmEstrEs, fEstInG, f A k G r G. Construct the arguments and test them by circles, and illustrate by concrete examples. Aristotle's dictum does not directly apply to any of the four figures except the first. Syllogisms in Figures II., III., or lY. can always be reduced to those in Fig. I., and then tested by the dictum, and thus it is shown that all categorical syllo- gisms conform to one principle, a fact of great scientific interest. The consonants in the names of the syllogisms furnish the key to the reduction, as shown hereafter. FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 373 Figure III. cM P. Ist. Order of terms. The order of the terms \h} M S. Is P. 2d. Definition. Figure third is that figure in which the middle term is the subject of both premises. 3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. III. are thus determined: In order to distribute the middle term, one of the premises must be universal. This is also true of any syllogism, in any figure. The conclusion can not be universal, either affirmative or negative. For: (1) The conclusion can not be a universal affirmative; for then both premises must be universal affirmative, and there would be an illicit process of the minor term, since it would be distributed in the conclusion, as sub- ject of a universal, but undistributed in the minor premise, as the predicate of an affirmative. (2) The conclusion can not be a universal negative; for then both premises must be universal, one affirma- tive, and the other negative; if the major premise is affirmative, there would be an illicit process of the major term, since it would be distributed in the conclusion as predicate of a negative, but not distributed in the major premise as predicate of an affirmative; if the minor prem- ise is affirmative, there would be an illicit process of the minor term, since it would be distributed in the conclu- sion, as the subject of a universal, but not in the minor premise, as predicate of an affirmative. Since the conclusion can be neither a universal affirm- ative nor a universal negative, it is particular, which is the striking fact in this figure. If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must be 374 PSYCHOLOGY, * affirmative. If the conclusion is negative, the major premise must be negative, in order to distribute its predicate, the major term, which is distributed as the predicate of the negative conclusion; and, therefore, the minor premise must be affirmative. Hence, A A I^ I A I, All, E AG, OAO, EI 0, are valid moods in Pig. III. 4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. III. is the follow- ing : (1) The middle term is the subject of both premises. (2) One premise is universal, and the miinor is affirm- ative. (3) The conclusion is particular and agrees in quality with the major premise. 5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Pig. III. are, dArApt I, dis A m Is, dAtlsI, f El AptOn, d Ok Am 0, fErlsO. Construct the arguments and test them by circles ; also illustrate by concrete examples. PiGURE IV. rPM. 1st. Order of terms. The order of terms is^ M S. (s P, 2d. Definition. Pigure fourth is that figure in which the middle term is the predicate of the major premise and the subject of the minor. 3d. Valid moods. The valid moods in Pig. TV. are thus determined: (1) If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must be affirmative, the minor premise universal, in order to distribute the middle term which is not distributed as the predicate of the affirmative major premise, the major premise may be universal or particular, and the conclu- sion must be particular, otherwise there would be an illicit process of the minor term, which is not distrib- uted as the predicate of the affirmative minor premise. FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 375 Hence, the valid affirmative moods in Fig. lY. are A A I, lAL (2) If the conclusion is negative^ one premise must be affirmative and tlie other negative, and the major prem- ise must be universal in order to distribute its subject, which is distributed as the predicate of the negative conclusion; and if the major premise is affirmative, the minor must be negative, since the conclusion is negative, and universal, in order to distribute the middle term, which is not distributed as the predicate of the affirm- ative minor premise, and the conclusion may be univer- sal or particular; but if the major premise is negative, the minor must be affirmative, either universal or par- ticular, and the conclusion must be particular, otherwise there would be an illicit process of the minor term. Hence, AEE, AEG, EA 0, EIOj are valid negative moods in Fig. TV. The mood AE is usually discarded, since the premises warrant E, which implies 0. 4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. TV. is the following: (1) The middle term is the predicate of the major premise and the subject of the minor. (2) Either the major premise must be negative or the minor universal. (3) If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must be affirmative, the minor universal, the major universal or particular, and the conclusion particular. (4) If the conclusion is negative, the major premise must be universal, and if affirmative, the minor premise must be a universal negative, and the conclusion uni- versal; but if the major premise is negative, the minor must be affirmative, either universal or particular, and the, conclusion must be particular. (5) All forms of conclusion, except A, are admissible in Figure TV. 5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. TV. 376 PSYCHOLOGY. are, hrAmAnt Ip^ c A mEnEs^ d Im A r Is, fEsAp 0, frEsIs On. Construct these arguments^ test them by circles, and ilhistrate by concrete examples. The fourth figure was not recognized by Aristotle, but is supposed to have been introduced by Galen. It is an awkward figure, and the propriety of giving it a place among the figures is questioned by many logicians. See Mahan, pp. 121-4; Hamilton, pp., 285, 302, 626; Coppee, p. 117; Tappan, p. 347; Thompson, pp. 201-6; Wilson, p. 110; Whateley, p. 96; Davis, 156-8. 5. Comparative view of the four figures. 1st. In the first figure, the middle term is the subject of the major j)remise and predicate of the minor; the major premise is universal, and the minor affirmative; the conclusion agrees in quality with the major premise, and in quantity with the minor; every conclusion. A, E, /, 0, is admissible in this figure, and A in no other; the dictum is directly applicable only to this figure, which, from this fact, as well as from its clearness, has been regarded by Aristotle and by other logicians, as the most perfect of all the figures. 2d. In the second figure, the middle term is the predi- cate of both premises; one premise is affirmative, and the other is negative; the major premise is universal; the conclusion is negative and agrees in quantity with the minor premise; this figure is naturally used in dis- proving a statement. 3d. In the third figure, the middle term is the subject of both premises; one premise is universal, and the minor is affirmative; the conclusion is particular, and agrees in quality with the major premise; this figure is naturally used when the middle term is singular, and in establishing objections, by proving exceptions to gen- eral statements. 4th. In the fourth figure, the middle term is the predi- FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 377 cate of the major premise and subject of the minor; either the major premise must be negative or the minor universal; if the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must be affirmative, the minor universal the major uni- versal or particular, and the conclusion particular; if the conclusion is negative, the major premise must be universal, and if affirmative, the minor premise must be a universal negative, and the conclusion universal; but if the major premise is negative, the minor must be affirmative, either universal or jDarticular, and the con- clusion must be particular; all the conclusions except A are proved in this figure. According to Lambert, "The first figure is suited to the discovery or proof of the properties of a thing; the second, to the discovery or proof of the distinctions between things; the third, to the discovery or proof of instances and exceptions; the fourth, to the discovery or exclusion of the different species of a genus." 6. The unfigured syllogism. — This demands notice. 1st. Definition, The unfigured syllogism is an argument in which the terms of the propositions do not sustain to each other the relation of subject and predicate. 2d. Examples^ A and B always co-exist. (V) Positive \ ^ ^^^ ^ always co-exist. .-. A and (7 always co-exist. A and B alw^ays co-exist. (2) Negative ] ^ ^i^^ ^ never co- exist. .'.A and C never co-exist. 3d. Laws. The laws of the unfigured syllogism are the following: (1) As far as two terms agree with a third term, so far they agree with each other. Psy.— 32. 378 PSYCHOLOGY. (2) As far as one term agrees and another disagrees with a third, so far they disagree with each other. 4th. Remark. Some logicians have questioned the ex- istence of the unfigured syllogism, claiming that such syllogisms can always be reduced to those in one or the other of the figures. But the question is not, Can the unfigured syllogism be made to assume a figure ? but, Does it, as it stands, have a figure? The following exercises will be useful: 1st. Eeduce the foregoing examples of the unfigured syllogism to syllogisms in the first figure. 2d. Deduce the conclusion from the following premises, and state the figure, mood, and name of the argument: (1) (2) (3) (4) I All mammalia are vertebrates. 1 Some amphibious animals are mammalia. 1 1^0 planets are self-luminous. 1 All planets are heavenly bodies. I ISTo fish suckles its young. (The whale suckles its young. f Ruminants are not predacious. I The lion is predacious. 3d. Construct an argument having false premises and a true conclusion. 4th. Supply premises which prove the following con- clusions, and state the figure, mood, and name of the syllogism : (1) ]^o vicious conduct is heroic. (2) ISTo wicked man is happy. (3) Some worthy of admiration are not philosophers. (4) Some who are admired are dreaded. CHAPTEE XXL DEDUCTIVE REASONING. Reduction is the transformation of an argument in the second, third, or fourth figures into one of the first. There are two kinds of reduction — the direct and the indirect. 1. Direct reduction. — The direct reduction of the so called imperfect figures to the perfect, that is, the second, third, and fourth to the first, is readily accom- plished by the subjoined method, than which, as Ham- ilton has remarked, " There are few human inventions ^hich display a higher ingenuity." First, thoroughly learn the following lines, which may be scanned as Latin Hexameters: B ArbAr A, cElArEnt^ dArll, fEr I Oque prions; CEsArE, cA7nEstrEs. /Est InO^ fAKOr 0, secundce; Tertia, dArApt I, d Is Am Is, dAtlsI, f El Apt On, DOkAmO, fEr I s On, habet ; quartet insuper addit BrAmAyit Ip, c Am EnEs, d ImAr Is, f E s A p 0, frEs Is On. The initial consonants denote reduction to syllogisms in the first figure, beginning with the same letters. Thus, initial b denotes reduction to b Arb Ar A; c, to cElArEnt; d, to dAr II ; f, to f Er 1 0. These conso- nants do not aid in making the reductions, but are a check on the result. The other consonants, so far as expressive, have the following significations; m denotes that the premises are (S79) 380 PSYCHOLOGY. to be transposed; s that the proposition represented by the preceding vowel is to be converted simply; j9, that the proposition represented by the preceding vowel is to be converted by limitation, that is, its quantity is changed from universal to particular, except in hrAra- Antlp, in which the quantity is changed from particu- lar to universal; ^, that the preceding A is to be changed to j5J, or to J, and the result converted simply. The following are given as specimen reductions : r IS^o P is Jf. ^ r 'No Mis P. cEsArE ) All >S is J£ V^cElArEnUAWSisM. l.-.l^o >S is Pj * (.-.IN'o >Sis P. r All P is M. \ r'Eo non-Mis F. fAkOrOj Some S is not M. I =fErIO ] Some>S^is non-M. (,.'.Some>SisnotP 3 C.'.SomeASisnotP The A of the major premise. All P is M, is changed to E^ No P is non-M^ as denoted by k^ which converted simply, gives No non-M is P. If the minor premise remain negative, no conclusion could be drawn, since we should have two negative premises ; moreover, the middle term would not be the same in form in the two prem- ises, giving the ambiguous middle; but if we change (9, Some S is not M, to /, Some S is non-M^ these difficul- ties will both be obviated, as seen above. Reduce all the syllogisms of the second, third, and fourth figures to those in the first. 2. Indirect reduction. — This is accomplished, not by the use of the consonants, but by the following nde : Substitute the contradictory of the conclusion for the major premise^ except in the second figure and in cAmEnEs of the fourth, in which substitute for the minor. One example will serve to illustrate the method : BED UCTION TO THE FIRST FIG UEE, 381 r No P is ilf. ^ r No P is ilf. \ cEsAvE} All S is M. [gives-] Some 8 is P VfErlO (.-.NoASisP ; (..-.Some /Sis not ilf J But Some S is not ilif is the contradictory of All S is M^ which is true by hypothesis; therefore, Some 8 is not M is false ; hence, either No P is M or Some 8 is P is false; but No P is ilf is true by hypothesis; there- fore, Some aS is P is false ; but Some /S is P is the con- tradictory of No 8 is P, which is, therefore, true. Ob- serve that, in the new syllogism, P is the middle term. The truth of the original conclusion is thus estab- lished by reasoning in connection with a new argument in the first figure. In some cases, the new conclusion is the contrary instead of the contradictory of the rejected premise; but it is false in either case. The falsity of the new conclusion involves the falsity of one of the prem- ises ; but one of these premises is a premise in the orig- inal syllogism, and is, therefore, true by hypothesis; hence, the other premise, which is always the contra- dictory of the original conclusion, is false, and since false, its contradictor}^, or the original conclusion, is true. By indirect reduction^ reduce all the syllogisms of the second, third, and fourth figures to those of the first, and vindicate the original conclusions. Construct concrete arguments, as the following, in the second, third, or fourth figures, and reduce them by both methods. No science is capable of perfection. All science is worthy of cultivation. .-. Something worthy of cultivation is not caj)able of perfection. CHAPTEE XXII. INDUCTIVE REASONING. Induction is the process of inferring general proposi- tions from particular instances. It includes, therefore, both the discovery of the particular instances, and the inference of the general proposition. Induction may be classified as follows : , {Mathematical — demon strative. r Perfect — demonstrative. Logical I Imperfect —probable. Mathematical induction is the process of proving a general proposition by means of an empirical fact to- gether with a conditional principle. The empirical fact is that the proposition holds true for several of the first of the consecutive cases; and the conditional principle is that if the proposition holds for any case, it holds for the next. The nature of mathematical induction will be made clear by the following illustrations: 1. In the series of odd numbers, 1, 3, 5, 7, . . ., find any term^ and the sum of the terms. To find any term, observe that, for the first term, 1=1X2 — 1; for the second term, 3=::=2X2 — ^^1; for the third term, 5 = 3 X 2 — 1 ; for the fourth term, 7 ^= 4 X2 — 1; that is, so far as examined, any term is twice the number of the term, minus 1, which is the empir- ical fact required. To prove by mathematical induction that the law is (382) MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. 383 general, it is necessary to prove the conditional princi- ple that if the law hold true for any number of terms, it holds for the next term. Assuming the law true for n terms, we have 1, 3, 5, 7, ... 2 n — 1. Since two added to any odd number gives the next greater odd number, we have, by adding 2, the next term, n—lJ^2==2n-^l=2 (n-f 1) — 1 . But 2(n + l) — 1 i^ twice the number of the term, minus 1; hence, if the law hold for any number of terms, it holds for the next term ; but the law does hold, as shown above, up to the 4th term; hence, by the above principle, it holds for the 5th term; and since for the 5th, then for the 6th, and so on up to the nth, that is, for any number of terms. To find the suvi of the tervis, observe that for one term, 1=12; for two terms, 1 -]- 3 ^^ 4: :===: 2^ ] for three terms, 1 -\- 3 -\- b = 9 =i^^ ] for four terms, 1 + 3 -f- 5 -|- 7 = 16=42; and so on, that is, so far as examined, the sum of the terms is equal to the square of the number of the terms, which is the empirical fact required. To prove the law general, it is necessary to prove the conditional princif)le, that if it hold for any number of terms, it holds for one term more. Assuming it true for n terms, we have 1 _f 3 + 5 + 7 -f , . . + 2 /I — 1 = 7^2. Adding the next term to both members, we have 1 + 3 + 5+7 + -. ..+2 n — l-f2n4-l = n2-f 2/1+1 ==(n + l)2. Hence, if the law hold for n terms, it holds for n -j-1 terms; that is, since n may be any number, if it hold 384 PSYCHOLOGY. for any number of terms, it holds for one term more, which is the conditional principle required; but the law holds, as shown above, up to the 4th term; hence, by the above principle, it holds for five terms; and since for five, then for six, and so on for any number of terms. Hence, the law is general. 2. The difference of the same powers of two quanti- ties is divisible by the difference of the quantities. By actual division, we shall find that (a — fc) --- (« — &):=: 1; (a2 — 62-)_^ ^a-~h)z=:a -^b; This gives the required empirical fact. If we should go on, in this way, to the 100th power, and find no exceptions, it would not prove the law gen- eral, though it would render it highly probable. This is the method of probable induction; and giving only probable conclusions, it is tolerated only when no better methods are attainable. To prove the law general, it is necessary to prove that if it hold for any power, it holds for the next higher power. GBo show this, let us divide a^' + i — 6" + ^ by a — b. (2^ + ^ — a'^b a a *' = quotient Eemainder :=a''b — 6^ + i=6(a^ — 6**). Now, it is evident that if a'' — b'\ which is a factor of the remainder, is divisible by a — 6, the whole re- mainder, and consequently the dividend, a^' + i — 6'' + ^, is divisible by a — b ; that is, if the difference of any pow- ers, of the same degree, of two quantities is divisible by the difference of the quantities, then the difference of MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. 385 the powers one degree greater is divisible by the differ- ence of the quantities, which is the conditional principle. But it has already been found, by trial, that the. dif- ference of the powers of the same degree, up to the 3d power, is divisible by the difference of the quantities; hence, by the above principle, the difference of the 4th powers is divisible by the difference of the quantities; and since the difference of the 4th powers, then the difference of the 5th powers, and so on to any de- gree. Hence, the law is general. 3. To find the law of bodies falling in a vacuum, on the supposition that gravity near the earth is a con- stant force. Let g be the velocity generated by gravity in one sec- ond. Since the body, by its inertia, retains all the velocity it has acquired, and gravity is a constant force, it receives each second an increment g of velocity; hence, the velocity generated varies with the time, and at the expiration of the successive seconds, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, . . ., is g, 2^, 3^, ^g, 5^, ... The body starts from, rest, and is uniformly accelera- ted, since gravity is constant; hence, the velocity at the expiration of the first second, which is g^ is twice the average velocity for the second; therefore, the space described the first second is ^g. The space described in any second is equal to the space which it w^ould have described without gravity, which is equal to the velocity at the expiration of the preceding second, plus \g^ the space due to gravity for one second. Hence, the spaces described in the successive seconds are, 29^ 2"^' 29i 2"^? "2^? • ' • The whole space described in any number of seconds Psy.— 33. 386 PSYCHOLOGY. is evidently obtained by taking the sum of the corre- sponding number of terms of the last series, and hence is By examining these series, we observe that the veloc- ity at the expiration of any second is equal to g multi- plied by the number of the second; that the space de- scribed in each of the successive seconds is equal to \g multiplied by one less than twice the number of the second; that the whole space is equal to the space de- scribed in the first second multiplied by the square of the number of seconds. These are the empirical facts. To generalize the laws, it will be necessary to show that if they hold for t seconds, they hold for t-\-l sec- onds. Assuming them true for t seconds, we have, (1) g, 2^, 3^, 4.g, ... tg, 2t—l (2) hg, ig, ig, ig, ••. — tt^ g- 11 \P) '^g-) 2"?? 2"9'j ~2~?7 • • • ~^^* The velocity for the (t-\-V)^^ second is evidently (t-\-V)g; the space described in the (t^l)'^ second is 2f + l 2(^H-1) — 1 ^g + ^g^ which IS equal to —^ g = g; the whole space, which is found as before, is f^ 2t + l __ t'^+2t+ l _ (?^ + 1) 2 ^ ~2^ 2^" 2 ^~~ 2^' Hence, if the laws hold for t seconds, they hold for ^ + 1 seconds; that is, since t may be any number of MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, 387 seconds, if they hold for any number of seconds, they hold for one second more, which is the conditional prin- ciple; but the laws hold, as shown above, up to five seconds; and since for tive, then for six, and so on, for any number of seconds up to t. Hence, the laws are general. Denoting the velocity by v, the space described in the V^ second by s\ and the Avhole space by 5, we have v=gxt; s' = lgxi2t — l)] s = lgXt''. From the foregoing illustrations of Mathematical in- duction, it is evident that the empirical fact that the law holds for several of the first consecutive cases, which is found by trial, gives, by itself, only a probable con- clusion, as in probable induction; that the conditional principle, gives, by itself, only the conclusion that if the law hold for any case, it holds for the next case; and that the empirical fact and the conditional principle, taken together, give an induction of the utmost gener- ality, whose truth is demonstrably certain. CHAPTEE XXIII. INDUCTIVE REASONING. The subsidiaries of induction are experience, observa- tion, experiment, hypothesis, analogy, classification, and denomination. 1. Experience is the accumulated knowledge of the past, and is either personal, that is, our own experience; or foreign, that is, the experience of others, obtained from testimony. 2. Observation is the direction of the attention to the facts of matter or mind. It takes the form of percep- tion, when the facts are external, or physical, and the form of consciousness, when the facts are internal, or psychical. 3. Experiment is the act of placing the facts in cir- cumstances favorable for observation, by means of instru- ments or apparatus by which we vary the conditions of the phenomena. In pure observation, we find our instances; but in experiment, we make them. By experiment we vary the circumstances or degree of the phenomenon under consideration, or isolate it, or combine it with other phenomena, and thus greatly extend our field of obser- vation. Trial is a simple experiment. It may be made with little apparatus, or with none at all. In some cases, experiment is impracticable, as in as- tronomy, where the facts are acquired by observation, though the observation may be aided by such instru- ments as the telescope. In other cases, experiment is ( 388 ) LOGICAL INDUCTION —SUBSIDIARIES. 389 indispensable, as in chemistry, Avliere experiment is the chief resource. In most sciences, both observation and experiment are requisite. To make an observation or to perform an experiment properly, the mind should be in a vigorous condition, and free from prepossession, partiality, or prejudice; and the attention should be withdrawn from all irrele- vant objects, and concentrated upon the object to be ex- amined, which should be divided, if necessary, till the perceptions become clear and distinct. 4. An hypothesis is a supposition made to account for the co-existence or succession of phenomena. The tendency of the human mind to frame hypotheses is very strong. The explanation of this tendency is found in the intuition of causality — that every event must have a cause. It should be remembered, however, that this intuition does not inform us what the cause is, but only that there must be a cause. Room is thus left for hypothesis; and since the hypothesis may be true or false, it should, therefore, be regarded as merely provis- ional, till verified or refuted by further investigation. The utility of hypotheses is evident from the follow- ing considerations: 1st. An hypothesis, though un verifiable, may be use- ful in affording a probable explanation of phenomena otherwise inexplicable. The hypothesis of an attenuated medium called ether pervading space, accounting for the transmission of light from the stars, is an example of an hypothesis of this kind. 2d. An hypothesis may be useful in affording an ex- planation, which, though conjectural, may afterwards be verified. Kepler discovered the laws of planetary revo- lution by making various hyj)otheses, some of which he afterwards verified. 3d. An hypothesis, though it prove false, may be use- 390 PSYCHOLOGY, ful in leading to another which may be verified. Kep- ler made no less than nineteen different hypotheses of planetary motion before he discovered the truth. 4th. An hypothesis may be useful in colligating and distinguishing the phenomena to be explained, thus di- recting the course of investigation, and preventing a waste of time and labor. The formation of hypotheses is due largely to the im- agination ; but as the inventions of this fertile faculty are not all worthy of the highest confidence, it is im- portant to guard against a hasty acceptance of a plaus- ible h3q3othesis. The characteristics of hypotheses worthy of considera- tion are the following: 1st. An hypothesis should be probably or at least possibly true. 2d. An hypothesis should, if possible, be of such a nature as to admit of verification or refutation, or at least of being rendered, by subsequent investigation, more or less probable. 3d. An hyjDOthesis should be capable of accounting for all the phenomena, without exception. The hypothesis which possesses these characteristics may be accepted, provisionally, as true, subject, of course, to subsequent verification or refutation. The hypothesis which affords, at the same time, an explanation of differ- ent classes of facts, has a very high probability of truth. The only possible hypothesis which can account for the phenomena must be accepted as the true explana- tion. Such an hypothesis has the force of an intuition. The following example will serve as an illustration of an hypothesis considered verified : To account for the deflection of the path of a planet from a straight line, Newton assumed a force directed towards the center of the sun. He then showed that the action of such a force LOGICAL INDUCTION—SUBSIDIARIES, 391 oa a planet, in connection with its projectile force, is the only force which could cause the radius vector of the planet to describe equal areas in equal times — a fact already known as one of Kepler's laws; hence, the hy- pothesis of a force directed towards the sun is regarded as established. It does not follow^, however, that the sun exerts this force, that is, attracts or draws the planet towards himself The force may possibly be due to currents of ether running in towards the sun. Newton also assumed that the deflecting force varies inversely as the square of its distance from the sun, and proved that this is the only supposition wdiich would account for Kepler's second and third laws— facts al- ready known; hence this hypothesis is also to be re- garded as verified. It is remarkable that this would be the law, if the deflecting force is due to currents of ether setting in towards the sun, 5. Analogy is the likeness of relations, or the resem- blance of two things, from which we infer that an addi- tional fact known of one is probably true of the other. The conditions to be complied w^ith in reasoning from analogy are the following: Ist. The objects compared must agree in certain re- spects. 2d. The attributes observed should be positive and essential, and not negative and accidental. The conclusion is only probable; but this probability is increased in proportion to the number of congruent attributes; to the importance of the congruent attributes; to the number and accuracy of the observations. The following is an example of analogical reasoning: A has the attributes p, ^, r, and s. L has the attributes p^ q, r, .'. L probably has the attribute s. 392 PSYCHOLOGY. This argument can be refuted, if it can be shown : Ist. That s is the effect of some cause found in A but not in L. 2d. That there are present with ^ and absent from X, certain circumstances which are indispensable to s. 3d. That L has attributes incompatible with s. 4th. That the circumstances attending L prevent the existence of s. As a concrete illustration of an argument from anal- ogy, and a counter argument, take the following: The earth is an opaque solid, nearly spherical^ derives its light and heat from the sun, and is inhabited. The moon is an opaque solid, nearly spherical, derives its light and heat from the sun. Therefore, the moon is probably inhabited. If the points of agreement are equally likely to be the conditions of life, the probability that the moon is inhabited would vary directly as the number of such points of agreement. The points of difference, that the moon is only a sec- ondary, that it is smaller and more rugged, that it re- volves on its axis but once in twenty-eight daj^s, that it has no atmosphere and no water, present a counter probability that it is not inhabited; and this counter probability is strengthened, when we reflect that some of the circumstances wanting on the moon, such as air and water, are indispensable conditions of life on the earth; we must, therefore, conclude either that the moon is not inhabited at all or that the conditions on which life depends on the moon are totally different from the conditions on which life depends on the earth. The conditions of life on the moon being, therefore, different from those on the earth, if they exist at all, the more points of resemblance established between the moon and the earth, the indispensable conditions of life which exist LOGICAL INDUCTION—SUBSIDIARIES. 393 on the earth being wanting in the moonj the less the probability of the supposed different conditions, and con- sequently, the less the probability that the moon is in- habited. Analogical arguments, if not refuted, may be usefully employed in showing the reasonableness of the conclusion ; in removing prejudice; in silencing objections; in pre- paring the mind for direct argument. 6. Classification and denomination are also subsidiary to induction; but these have been sufficiently treated in chapters II-Y. of this division. The distinction between knowledge and belief may be profitably considered in this connection. Knowledge implies that a truth be correctly expressed by a proposition; that this proposition be clearly ap- prehended; that the truth of the proposition, if primitive, be known by intuition, either empirical or rational; that the truth of the proposition, if derivative, be based on grounds whose truth is known by intuition or is logically derived from other grounds ultimately known by intui- tion. Belief implies a proposition based on probability ; and this probability may vary between the limits, known actuality and known impossibility, without ever reaching either limit; for if it reach either limit, the belief is transformed into knowledge, either of the truth or of the falsity of the proposition. CHAPTEE XXIV. INDUCTIVE REASONING. Logical induction is the process of discovering that a certain thing is true of parts of a class, and thence inferring that the same thing is true of the whole class. Mathematical induction generalizes its common fact, or proves it to be a law by showing that if it hold for any instance, it holds for the next; but logical induction passes from the parts to the w^hole, without the inter vention of a conditional principle. Logical induction is divided into two varieties — per- fect, or demonstrative, when all the instances are ex- amined; and imperfect, or probable, when only a part of the instances are examined. 1. Perfect induction is the process of establishing a general proposition by an examination of all the par- ticular instances. By discovering that a certain thing is true of all the parts, we prove that the same thing is true of the whole. The following are examples: By examination, we find that A has the property P, that B lias P, that C has P, and that D has P; but A, B^ C, and D constitute the class E ; therefore, all of the class BJ have the property P. In geometry, sc proposition involving several cases is proved to be true for each case, and hence to be uni- versally true. The reasoning in each case may be de- ductive ; but the method of establishing the general prop- osition by establishing its truth in each case, is essen- tially inductive. (394) LOGICAL INDUCTION. 395 Some logicians assert that what is called perfect in- duction is not induction at all, since, after finding that a certain thing is true of every case, nothing remains but to sum up and state, in one general proposition, what is already known. But the process in question conforms to the definition of induction, since, from the discovery of what is true of the parts, it establishes w4mt is true of the whole. Whether we examine all the in- stances or only a part of them, is not essential to in- duction itself, though it affords the discriminating char- acteristic by which we divide induction into perfect and imperfect. Perfect induction is the limiting case of im- perfect induction. The same general formula which expresses the degree of probability of the conclusion in imperiect induction, expresses, as will be shown here- after, the certainty of the conclusion in perfect induc- tion, thus showing, beyond question, that the two are sj^ecies of the same genus In perfect induction, the finding that a certain fact is true in the particular instances, does not warrant the certainty of the general conclusion, that it is true in all the instances, unless it is also known that the in- stances in which the fact is found true are all the in- stances. The minor premise does not assert that the fact is true of all the instances; for then it w^ould be identical with the conclusion; but that the instances examined are all the instances. The argument is not stated thus: A has the property P, so has B, and (7, and D. All of the individuals of the class E have P. .-. All of the individuals of the class E have P. This would be trifling; but the statement is thus 396 PSYCHOLOGY, A lias the property P, so has B and C and D. But Aj B^ Cj D are the whole of the class E. .'. All of the class JS have P. Perfect induction is applicable to those cases in which the instances are few in number and accessible. 2. Imperfect induction is the process of inferring tlie probability of a general proposition from an examina- tion of some of the particular instances. The following is an example: By examination^ we find that A has the property P, so has By and (7^ and D. . . . . But A, B, C, D, are some individuals of the class P; therefore, all of the class JE probably have the property P. This conclusion is logical so long as it is stated to be only probable; but it would be illogical if it were stated as certain. The following examples will serve to illustrate the difference between perfect and imperfect induction , the first being perfect, the second imperfect: Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., all move round the sun from west to east; but Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., are all the known planets; therefore, all the known planets move round the sun from west to east. Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., all move round the sun from west to east; but Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., are all the known planets; therefore, all the planets probably move round the sun from west to east. Whether the induction be perfect or imperfect, there must be no exceptions in the cases examined. No doubt that in perfect induction, before all the cases are examined, the mind jumps to the conclusion, or infers the general proposition by an imperfect induction, LOGICAL INDUCTION, 397 and then by a perfect induction verifies its conclusion. In an imperfect induction, the conclusion remains un- verified. A comparison of Probable induction and Analogy leads to the following results: Ist. By probable induction we infer that if many ob- jects of a class have a common quality, all the objects of that class probably have that quality; that is, an at- tribute known to be present in a part of the extent of a class is inferred as probably present in the whole ex- tent of that class. 2d. By analogy we infer that two objects agreeing in certain respects, probably agree in other respects; that is, an attribute known to be a part of the content of one of two objects whose contents agree in many com- mon qualities, is inferred as probably a part of the con- tent of the other object. 3d. Probable induction and analogy agree in the fact that they give only probable conclusions, and that the degree of the probability may vary between the limits, impossibility and certainty, without ever reaching either limit. 4th. There is, however, a most intimate relation be- tween induction and analogy, which we now proceed to point out. Eeasoning by induction is essentially the same as reasoning from analogy, but with this modifica- tion — that in simple analogy, we reason from one of the objects of a class to another object of that class, whereas in induction, we reason from several objects of a class to the remaining objects of the class, thus in- creasing the probability of the inference, by increasing the extent of the evidence, and diminishing the proba- bility of the inference, by increasing the extent of the conclusion. Let A and L be two objects of a class, each known 398 PSYCHOLOGY, to have the qualities, p^ q; r, and let A also be known to have the quality 5, then we infer that L probably has the quality s. This is reasoning from analogy. The argument is not, that because we have found s combined with p, q^ r, in many objects of the class, we shall, there- fore, find s combined with p, q, r, in L; but that because we have found that A and L agree in possessing so many qualities, ^, q^ r, in common, we may likewise find any quality, s, which is in A^ also in L. The ar- gument is based on the number of qualities common to the two objects, A and i, and not on the number of objects having the common qualities. ISTow, if another object 5, of the same class, has the same qualities, p^ q^ r, how would the probability that L has s be affected, if it is also found that B has sf The probability of the inference that L has s would evidently be strengthened by finding that B has s. Here we be- gin to pass from analogy to induction, not on the side of the conclusion, but on that of the evidence, by in- creasing its extent. The probability that L has s is likewise strengthened every time we find in the class an object, (7, D, j^, . . . having not only the qualities, p, q^ r, but also s. So far we have strengthened analogy, increasing the probability of the inference by increasing the extent of the evidence, and the process becomes inductive with respect to the evidence, but not with respect to the con- clusion. Let there be, in the same class, another object i¥, having the qualities, p, q^ r, and differing from L in no essential circumstance. The probability that M has s is evidently equal to the probability that L has s; hence, we can infer with the same probability that any other object, iV, Oj P, . . . not differing essentially from i, and having the qualities, p, g, r, and belonging to that class, LOGICAL INDUCTION. 399 has the quality 5. We still have, so long as we restrict the conclusion to one of the objects, Jv, Jf, O, P, . . . only a strengthened analogy, inductive as to the evidence, but not with respect to the conclusion. Now, if we infer that all the remaining objects, X, Jf, Nj 0, P, . . . known to have p, q, r, and belonging to that class, have the quality s, we reason by induction, both with respect to the evidence and the conclusion. But is the ^probability of the inference the same as before, or is it strengthened or weakened? In other w^ords, how does the probability that all the remaining objects, L, M, N, . , , of the class have the quality s, compare wdth the probability that any one of them, as X, has this quality? The probability that all have s is evi- dently less than that any one of them has s; for, since there is a chance of failure in each instance, there is greater probability that there will be failure when all the instances are considered than when only one is con- sidered. To estimate this probability, it is necessary to discuss briefly the doctrine of chances, including simple and com- pound probability. Thus, if there be a vase, containing m white "and n black balls, what will be the probability of drawing a white ball? There are m -f ^ chances of which m are favorable ; . m hence, the probabilitv of drawing; a white ball is ^ -^ . m + n Hence the measure of a simple probability is equal to the number of favorable chances divided by the whole m number of chances. Since m<^ ni -[- n.— << 1 ; hence, m -|- ^^ a simple probability is less than 1. If in another vase, there are t red and u blue balls. 400 PSYCHOLOGY. . t the probability of drawing a red ball is . If 2^ = 0, Jj — — u the probabilitj^ of drawing a red ball becomes — =^1, the symbol of certainty Now, if a ball be drawn from each vase, what is the probability that we shall have a white and a red ball? Combining the balls in the two vases, in sets of two, any one of the m -\- n balls can be combined with any one of t -\-u balls, giving (jn -\- n) (t ^ u) ^^mt -\~ m u -^ nt-\-nu possible chances, of which mt are favorable; hence, by the law of simple probability, the probability of mt drawing a white and a red ball is = mt-\-mu-\-nt-\-nu m t X = the product of the simple probabilities. m -f 71 t^u Hence, the compound probability of the joint occurrence of two chances is the product of their simple probabili- ties. In like manner, it can be shown that the proba- bility of the joint occurrence of any number of chances is the product of their simple probabilities. To return from this digression, let the probability that X X L has s be denoted by — ) then — will also express the probability, that any one of the objects, M.^ JV, 0, , . . has s. Let n denote the number of the objects, L^M^N^... Then since the compound probability that all of these objects, Jj, M, N, . . . have s is the product of the simple proba- bilities that they severally have s, we have for the com- pound probability that all have s, rp rp >y^ I /)•» I'H nr* rv* \Aj %A~f tX' * tA/ y cA-/ xAj — X — X ~~ • • • =1 — I 5 which is less than ^, since — < 1. y y y \ y J y y Since A^ B^ C, D . . . up to X are known to have s, the LOGICAL INDUCTION, 401 probability that all the objects of the class have s is (X y — I • This probability increases as the number of y I objects of the class known to have 5, increases, that is, as 71 diminishes; it becomes certainty when n=:0; but then the induction becomes perfect, since the objects known to have s are all the objects of the class. The increase of probability as n diminishes, is due to two causes — the extent of evidence is increased, and (X Y — I y I exhibits the law, since as more and more of the objects X of the class are found to have s, — increases and ap- y proaches 1, and n diminishes and approaches 0, and both these changes conspire to increase I — j . When all the X objects are found to have 5,-=^ = !, the symbol of cer- tainty, and ?z = 0, and we shall have 1^=^1, or the in- duction is perfect. / X Y Since the expression, I ~~ I , which denotes the proba- bility of the conclusion in imperfect induction, gives the certainty of the conclusion in perfect induction, the two cases are connected by the same law ; hence, perfect in- duction, so far from not being induction at all, as some logicians assert, is the limiting case of imperfect induc- tion; in other words, perfect induction and imperfect induction are the two species of the genus logical in- duction. Pry.— 34. CHAPTEE XXY. INDUCTIVE REASONING. From the fundamental agreement of induction and analogy, it follows that the ground of induction will be found, if we find the ground of analogy. According to the law of association, p^ q^ r, in L would suggest 5, since s is found in connection with p^ q^ r, in A; but this is merely the occasion of the suggestion, and not the ground of the inference. The ground of the induction is not found by throw- ing the induction into a syllogism, as Whately does, as thus exhibited : Whatever belongs to the individuals examined belongs to the whole class under which they come. s belongs to the individuals examined. .-. s belongs to the whole class. Observe that in the major premise the predication is made of every quality found in the individuals exam- ined, and not simply of the one quality 5. The major premise having, therefore, a wider subject than the con- clusion, a subject including that of the conclusion, is less probable, since it is more probable that any one quality .s found in connection with jp, ^, r, in A^ will also be found in connection with ^, ^, r, in i, than that every quality found in connection with p, ^, r, in A will also be found in connection with j9, q. r, in L. The wider induction of the major premise being less probable than the narrower induction of the conclusion, is more diffi- ( 402 ) [ THE GBOUND OF INDUCTION. 403 cult to establish, and can not, therefore, be taken for the proof of the conclusion, which is more evident than the major premise itself. If, however, the major prem- ise can be rendered probable in an}^ degree hj evidence, independent of the conclusion, it will follow that the conclusion will be probable in a still higher degree. But how is this major premise obtained, resolvable as it seems to be into the uniformity of the laws of nature? Whately replies, "Whether the belief in the constancy of Nature's laws, — a belief of which no one can divest himself — be intuitive, and a part of the constitution of the human mind, as some eminent metaphysicians hold, or acquired, and in what way acquired, is a question foreign to our purpose.' It is evident that Whately throws no light on the ground of induction. Mill says, "'Whatever be the most proper mode of ex- pressing it, the proposition, that the course of nature is uniform, is the fundamental principle or general axiom of induction. It would yet be a great error to offer this large generalization as any explanation of the inductive process. On the contrary, I hold it to be itself an in- stance of induction, and induction by no means of the most obvious kind. Far from being the first induction we make, it is one of the last, or at all events, one of those which are latest in attaining philosophical accuracy. .... Yet this principle, though so far from being our earliest induction, must be considered as our warrant for all the others in this sense, that unless it were true all other inductions would be fallaciou-s." If the induction, that the course of nature is uniform, is the latest induction, and is the warrant of all the others, then these others are made without warrant, and this so-called fundamental induction is itself without war- rant. We have here the fallacv of the vicious circle. Through the first inductions, made without warrant, we 404 PSYCHOLOGY, work up to the final induction, that the course of nature is uniform, and then take this generalization from un- warranted inductions, as the warrant of those unwar- ranted inductions of which it is the generalization. Experience, including observation and experiment, in furnishing the facts of analogy, has much to do with in- duction. We have thus often found that, in couples of objects having common qualities, an additional quality found in one, is afterwards found in the other. An ex- pectancy is thus awal^ened in other cases. The finding of the objects A and i, having the common qualities, j9, q^ r, is due to experience ; also the knowledge of the fact that A has s; then by analogy we infer that L probably has s. The strengthened analogy arising from finding in the class containing A and i, other objects B, C, Dj ... each having, not only p, q^ r, but also 5, is likewise due to experience. Other reasons than experience, however, seem to en- ter into the ground of the induction, since, for the same extent of experience, the induction is much more highly probable in some cases than in others. In certain cases, a single instance warrants an induction, with so high a degree of probability as to approach certaintj^ ; while in other cases, many instances are scarcely sufficient to warrant any induction at all, even of a low degree of probability. If s is an accident in A^ produced by circumstances not attending Jj, and not by causes inherent in A, or if the causes which produce s are inherent in A, but not in iy, or if L has some attribute inconsistent with s^ or if the circumstances attending L tend to prevent s, the probability that Ij has s is greatly diminished^ if not reduced to zero. The common ground of analogy and induction is found in the two following principles: THE GR O UND OF IND UCTION. 405 (1) Every constant coincidence of phenomena has its cause and its conditions. (2) Like conditions and causes are followed by like consequences. The reason of the coincidence of the first principle is that one phenomenon is the cause of the other, or that they have a common cause or some causal relation. The reason of the second principle is found in the fact that the two cases are essentially alike, and whatever determines the effect in the one case, is present to de- termine it in the other. These two principles, which are rational intuitions, fur- nish the warrant for the induction that nature is uni- form in her operations, the essential antecedents being, by supposition, the same in the cases compared. From the above principles, it follows that in the case considered, the probability that L has s varies with the probability that the conditions and causes connected with L are essentially the same as those connected with A. If this can be known with certainty, the conclusion that L has s will also be certain; and if it is also cer- tain that the same essential conditions and causes hold for each of the remaining instances, M^ iV, ... of the class, it will be equally certain that any one of these instances, M^ N^ ... has s; that is, the expression for the strength of the conclusion for each instance, which is X denoted by — becomes 1, the symbol for certainty; y hence, it is certain that all of the instances, L^M^N^ ... have 5, since the probability in this case is 1 X 1 X 1 X 1 , . . = 1** = 1 = certainty. To illustrate the above, take the case of the mathe- matician who in proving the proposition, The square of the hypotenuse of a right triangle is equivalent to the sum of the squares of the other sides, draws a particular right 406 PSYCHOLOGY. triangle and constructs a square on each of the three sides; and assuming the constructions perfect, proves by deductive reasoning that the square of the hypotenuse is equivalent to the sum of the squares of the other sides. He then concludes that the same is true for every right triangle of which there is an infinite number, varying in the relative proportion of their sides, and also in their magnitude, from those too small to be seen with the naked eye, to those whose sides are millions of miles in extent. Here we seem to infer the widest possible in- duction from a single instance; but the reason which determines the consequent is the same in everj^ instance. The proof does not turn on the relative length of the sides, nor on their magnitude, but solely on the fact that the triangle is right angled, and hence holds true for any triangle which conforms to this hypothesis, and, therefore, for all such triangles. Hence, the strength of the general conclusion is 1"° = 1 = certainty. The truth of the proposition, for the figure drawn, is not deter- mined experimentally, as that would be impossible ex- actl}^ to do; but it is determined deductively; and since like reasons hold for every like case, the proposition is true for every particular case, and hence for all cases, and is, therefore, universally true. We are now able to see how mathematical reasoning is characterized by demonstrative certainty — its facts are definite, and its processes strictly logical; it keeps the essential facts clearly in view, and disregards those that are not essential. Since the essential antecedent condi- tions are the same in each of the infinity of possible instances, and the conclusion is demonstrated for one, it is certain for any other, and hence is true for all. • Pascal has remarked, that '' Geometry is almost the only subject as to which we find truths wherein all men agree; and one cause of this is, that geometers alone THE GROUND OF INDUCTION. 407 regard the true laws of demonstration." These are the following : " 1st. To define nothing which can not be expressed in clearer terms than those in which it is already ex- pressed. "2d. To leave no obscure or equivocal terms undefined. "3d. To employ in the definition, no terms not already known. "4th. To omit nothing in the principles from which we argue, unless we are sure it is granted. "5th. To lay down no axiom which is not perfectly self-evident. "6th. To demonstrate nothing which is already as clear as it can be made. "7th. To prove every thing in the least doubtful by means of self-evident axioms, or of propositions already demonstrated. "8th. To substitute mentally the definition instead of the thing defined." These principles are of especial application in deduc- tion; but they have their bearing upon induction, since deduction is often employed in establishing the particu- lar instances which are used in inferring the general proposition of induction. In cases not mathematical, the probability of the gen- eral proposition approaches certainty in proportion as the antecedents in the cases compared approach essential identity. This exj)lains why, in certain cases, as in chemistry, a very few experiments warrant an induction of very high probability, if not certainty, whereas, in other cases, as in natural history, many observations give to the induction but a moderate degree of proba- bility. Thus, it was thought to be a well established induction, that all swans are white; but black swans were afterwards found in Australia. 408 PSYCHOLOGY. Since, in the inductions of nature, we can never be absolutely certain from observation that the conditions and causes are essential!}' alike, the induction can never be absolutely certain, but at best can possess only a high degree of probability. The methods of conducting experimental inquiry have been elaborately discussed hj Mr. Mill under the desig- nation of the Method of Agreement, the Method of Dif- ference, the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference, the Method of Residues, and the Method of Concomitant Variations. The reader is referred to MilVs Logic ^ Chapter VIII., and to Fowler's Inductive Logic, Chapter III. See also Jevon's LogiCj Lessons XXVII. to XXXI. CHAPTEE XXVI. MODERN LOGIC. 1. Hamilton, by the quantification of the predicate, made eight propositions, four of which are ambiguous: ( U) All S is all P. © {A) All S is some P. ( r) Some S is all P. (7) Some S is some P. © V 8{ P (IE) Any /? is not any P. [ .s ] ( T \ Psy.-35 (409) 410 PSYCHOLOGY. (7j) Any S is not some P. (0) Some S is not any P. > ( a>) Some >S is not some P. In Hamilton's scheme, botli (A) and (Y) express the relation of subordination. In {A)^ the subordinate con- cept is the subject, but in (F), the subordinate concept is the predicate; but since we can, if we choose, always take the subordinate concept for the subject, we shall, in the following scheme, treat (A) and (Y) as one. 2. Definite deduetion.— In definite deduction the prop- ositions are all definite, each expressing but one relation between the subject and the predicate. There are only four possible relations between two terms in extensive quantity- — co-extension, exclusion, subordination, and intersection. Definite propositions are obtained by expressing these relations. Let the initial letters, ((7), (-E^), (aS), (/), respectively, MODERN LOGIC, 411 express the relations of co-extension, exclusion, subordi- nation, and intersection. Then we have the following definite propositions: ((7) aS is co-extensive with P. (E) S is excluded from P. S (/S) /S is subordinate to P. (/) S intersects P. The laws warranting the conclusions, ((7), (i^), (aS), (/), may be stated and exemplified thus: 1st. The relation of co-extension is warranted in the con- clusion^ if each extreme is co-extensive with the middle term. !P is co-extensive with M. S is co-extensive with M. .\ S is co-extensive with P. Let the argument be stated in the other figures. 2d. The relation of exclusion is icarranted in the conclu- sion^ if either extreme is either subordinate to, or co-extensive with, the middle, and the other extreme is excluded from the middle. P is subordinate to Jf. (1) -l S is excluded from M. S is excluded from P. \: 412 PSYCHOLOGY. P is excluded from M. (2) -] aS is subordinate to M. ..'. S is excluded from P. P is co-extensive with M. (3) ^ /§ is excluded from M, ,-. S is excluded from P. P is excluded from M. (4) } S is co-extensive with M, .'. S is excluded from P. 3d. T/ie relation of subordination is warranted in the conclusion^ if the middle term is subordinate to the major, and the minor to the middle; or if the middle is co-exten- sive with the major, and the minor is subordinate to the middle; or if the middle is subordinate to the major, and the minor is co-extensive with the middle. M is subordinate to P. (1) ■< aS is subordinate to M. .'. S is subordinate to P. M is co-extensive with P. (2) ^ >S is subordinate to M. .-. S is subordinate to P. M is subordinate to P. (3) -< aS is co-extensive with M. .'. S is subordinate to P. 4th. The relation of intersection is warranted in the con- clusion, if the middle term is co-extensive with one extreme and intersects the other. I <*.i 1' MODERN LOGIC. 413 M is co-extensivo with P. (1) \ S intersects M. .-. S intersects P. M intersects P. (2) ^ /S is co-extensive with M. ■. 8 intersects P. Let us now restate the above syllogisms in the brief- est possible manner, by using (C) for is co-extensive with, (_JE) for is excluded from, (S) for is subordinate to, and (7) for intersects. Then we have P (C) M. 8 (C) M. .: 8 (C) P. P (8) M. 8 {E) M. .: 8 (E) P. M (8) P. 8 (8) M. .: 8 (8) P. M (C) P. 8 (I) M. .: 8 (I) P. Illustrate this and the following by circles. P (E) M. 8 {8) M. 8 (E) P. M (C) P. 8 (8) M. 8 (8) P. M (7) P. 8 (C) M. 8 (7) P. P (C) M. 8 (E) M. 8 (E) P. M (8) P. 8 (C) M. 8 (8) P. P (E)'M. 8 (C) M. .: 8 (E) P. This method is remarkable for clearness, precision, and simplicity. The propositions are perfectly definite, each denoting but one relation. {A), (7), (0) in Aristotle's sj^stem, and (7), (jj), (0), (e Morgan, Boole, and Jevons are worthy of attention. For a knowledge of these systems, we refer to the works of these authors. i PART II. FEELING AND THE SENSIBILITY, (415) CHAPTER I. PHYSICAL FEELINGS. Feelings are agitations of the soul. They embrace all those phenomena of the soul not included in cogni- tions and volitions. In feeling, the soul is chiefly j^as- sive in the reception of an incitement, but is involunta- rily active in its response. The feelings may be roughly classified as physical, vital, and psychical. The physical feelings are those especially related to the organism, as sensations, instincts, and appetites. The vital feelings are those which are especially re- lated to the vitality or health of the organism, as a sense of rest or fatigue, of vigor or languor, and of health or sickness. The psychical feelings are those especially related to the soul, as emotions, affections, and desires. The word feeling^ as a generic term, includes all these phenomena, and is, therefore, the term needed; whereas, the word emotion^ used by Dr. McCosh, is too specific, since it includes only a part. The feelings imply the sensibility or susceptibility of feeling. Without the sensibility, as a faculty or suscep- tibility, feeling, as a phenomenon, would be impossible. The susceptibility of experiencing any specific feeling is called an appetence. The feelings also imply causes^ external or internal, physical or psychical, real or ideal, which excite them and call them forth as phenomena of consciousness. (417) 418 PSYCHOLOGY, Cognitions tend to excite feeling, and the wider the sweep of the cognitions, the wider the range of the ob- jects concerning which feeling may arise; but there is no necessary ratio between the strength of the intellect and the intensity of feeling. The feelings are also more or less intimately related to certain organic affections, either as causes or as effects. We then have feelings as phenomena of consciousness, the appetencies implied by these feelings, the exciting causes, and the organic affections. The physical feelings have been defined as those es- pecially related to the organism, and classified as sensa- tions, instincts, and appetites. 1. Sensations are those feelings which are occasioned by the excitement of some portion of the organism, caused, in normal cases, by the action of a stimulus. Since sensation has already been discussed as the con- dition of perception^ it will suffice, in this connection, to give a brief summary^ and assign it to its place among the feelings. The conditions of sensation are the sensorium consist- ing of the nervous system and sense organs, excitants or objects capable of exciting the sensorium, the action of excitants on the sensorium, and the sensibility or general susceptibility of feeling. Sensations are, in general, localized, definitely or vaguely, that is, are referred to the part of the sensorium affected. In certain instances, the location of the sensation is quite definite, but in other instances it is only vaguely apprehended. The object of consciousness in sensation is neither the sensorium excited, nor the external excitant, but the sensation itself as a state of the sensibility. The quality of sensation involves existence as opposed to non-existence, and identity, or the fact that the sen- PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 419 sation is itself and nothing else, involving peculiarity, or the positive characteristics of the sensation, and par- ticularity, or the negation of the positive characteristics of any other thing. The quantity of a sensation involves its degree of in- tensity ^ varying between the limits zero and a degree so great as to be insupportable, its temporal relations of date and duration, and its spatial relations of locality, and, in some instances at least, but more vaguely, of extent and form. Complex sensations only are capable of analysis, which may be effected, in some cases, by reflection alone, but in other cases, only by the aid of experiment. Sensations are identified or discriminated as similar or dissimilar in kind, according as they are acquired through the same sense or through different senses. Sensations are identified or discriminated as similar or dissimilar in variety, according as they involve similar or dissimilar qualities. Sensations similar in kind may be similar or dissimi- lar in variety, but sensations dissimilar in kind are also dissimilar in variety. Sensations similar in kind and variety may agree or differ in degree of intensity or in temporal or s^Datial relations, and, as such, may accordingly be" identified or discriminated. Sensations are classified as to kind, w^hen referred to the organs or senses through w^hich they are acquired. They are subdivided both as to quality and quantity. Agreeable or pleasurable sensations are those w^hich arise from normal excitement of the sensorium ; and dis- agreeable or painful sensations are those which arise from abnormal exciteme»nt of the sensorium. The general sensations comprise all those connected with the various portions of the organism, except the 420 PSYCHOLOGY. five senses. They raay be divided into the muscular, the nervous, the nutritive, the circulatory, and the re- spiratory. The special sensations are those connected with the organs of the five senses, — smell, taste, touch, hearing, and sight. 2. Instincts are blind tendencies to actions, having for their ends the physical well-being of the individual or of the species. The actions prompted by instinct are automatic in their impulses, though, in form, apparently intelligent and voluntary. They occupy the border territory be- tween the purely automatic movements below, as the beating of the heart, and the rational activities above, as in reasoning. The instincts have their basis and spring in the spon- taneous movements of the living organism. By the ev- olutionist, they are regarded as habits — not as acquired habits, induced by the actions of the individual, but as hereditary habits, organized and embodied in the phys- ical constitution, and manifested as reflex actions of a more or less complicated character. The truth probably is that they have their origin in the constitution of the species as formed by the Creator, modified by inherited habits formed through successive generations and organ- ized in the physical constitution. Though instincts are directed towards ends, there is no reason for supposing that these ends are clearly con- ceived or deliberately aimed at by the individual. The brute is, no doubt, blind to the end, though his actions are directed towards the end with as much precision as if it were clearly apprehended and deliberately pur- sued. The end of instinctive actions is the j^hysical well- being of the individual or of the race, designed and se- PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 421 cured by the Author of Nature, through the automatic action of the organism. The instincts may be classed as follows : 1st. Those relating to subsistence, as in procuring, storing, and eating food. 2d. Those relating to the propagation of the species, as pairing, building nests, and the care of the young. 3d. Those of a more general nature, as hybernation and migration, excited by causes internal and external. Instincts have the following characteristics: 1st. Through organic states, they blindly prompt to actions w^hose end is the physical well-being of the in- dividual or of the species. That the actions prompted by instinct are blindly directed and not the result of reflective intelligence is illustrated by the fact that a hen will sit as readily on stones as on eggs; that she shows the same solicitude for the ducklings which she has hatched as for the chickens from her own eggs; and that when her ducklings take to the water, she manifests great alarm, yet her eyes are not opened to the fact that she is rearing the children of strangers. That in- stinctive actions are prompted by organic conditions is illustrated by the fact that a hen determined to sit may be cured of this propensity by dipping her breast sev- eral times in cold water. 2d. The instinctive actions are always performed by individuals of the same species in essentially the same way without the guide of experience or education. Thus, young mammalia are impelled to suck their mother's breasts; the young chick to pick up a grain of wheat at first sight; the young robin to open its mouth to receive the food which its mother brings. 3d. The instincts, in certain cases, at least, act j)eri- odically, corresponding to the wants of the individuals or their offspring. Thus, the old birds care for their 422 PSYCHOLOGY. young till they ure fully fledged, and then leave them to care for themselves. 4th. The instincts are not rigidly fixed but are, within certain limits, plastic, varying with the physical struct- ure of the individuals, and accommodating themselves, to a certain extent, to the modifications of external cir- cumstances, thus enabling the individual to adapt itself to its environment. Thus, a hen will sit more than three weeks to hatch the eggs of turkeys or geese, or less than three weeks to hatch those of quails. Under domestication, instincts are modified — in some cases in- tensified, in other cases weakened, so that it might ap- pear that certain instincts are acquired, and others lost. Thus, animals can be taught many things they do not know by nature, and which they will continue to do as if from instinct. The conditions for the manifestation of instinct are stimuli, external or internal, which incite the impulsive action of the organism. Thus, a young dog of sufficient age will bark at a stranger, though he has never barked before or heard any other dog bark. Birds of passage, incited by the increasing cold of autumn, take flight for warmer climes. Examples of instinctive actions may be found in the construction of the spider's web, birds nests, and honey comb, and in hibernation and migration. As we rise in the scale of being, instinct diminishes and intelligence increases till we reach man, who, though exhibiting traces of instinct, is especially characterized, not by instinct, but by reason. The difierence between man and the lower animals is strikingly apparent: Ist. Animals, in caring for their oflfepring, are con- cerned alone with their physical wants, and with these, only till they are able to care for themselves; whereas. PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 423 the solicitude of human parents for their children ex- tends also to their intellectual, social, moral, and spirit- ual welfare, and continues unabated till the end of life. 2d. The thinking of animals, if thinking it may be called, is from particulars to particulars; whereas, man generalizes his ideas into concepts, and proves general propositions. 3d. Animals have no language but the instinctive one prompted by nature; while man has developed an arti- ficial language, both spoken and written, admirably adap- ted to meet his present requirements, and to provide for unlimited advancement. 4th. As to knowledge, animals are stationary, except within narrow limits in the training they receive in domestication, while man is progressive without appar- ent limit. 5th. Animals are destitute of moral and religious faculties, which are the crow^ning glory cf man. 6th. The training of animals has been accomplished by man, but this training is only within a very narrow range; and w^hen withdrawn, the animal relapses into its original condition. This renders the view that man is the development of an order of animals, very im- probable. There was no higher race to train him. He is indeed a high order of animal — a rational animal, a moral animal, a noble animal, but he was created so, as we must conclude, if we regard the facts of the case, to say nothing of the teachings of revelation. 3. Appetites are the cravings prompted by the recur- ring wants of organic life. Appetites are distinguished from sensations by their periodicity and by the fact that they are cravings di- rected to the end of satisfying wants, natural or artifi- cial, while sensations may occur at any time and are not characterized as craving's. 424 PSYCHOLOGY. Appetites are distinguished from instincts by the fact that they are feelings consciously impelling to their gratification as an immediate end, though undoubtedly they have an ulterior end in the good of the individual or of the species, while instincts unconsciously prompt to actions which secure results that are only means to ul- terior ends. Thus, the spider is incited by instinct to weave his web, but by appetite to eat his prey. The appetites are illustrated by the following crav- ings — for sleep, for exercise, for rest, for food or drink. The periodicity of the appetite for sleep is notorious. After a certain period of wakefulness, there is a craving for sleep, which becomes more resistless the longer it is frustrated, unless determined effort or a new excite- ment causes a reaction, which may, for a time, dispel drowsiness. The craving for the alternations of exercise and rest have the character of appetite, though in a less marked degree. After toil, physical or mental, there is a craving for rest ; and, after sufficient rest, there is a prompting to activity. It should, however, be kept in mind that the function of rest is to recruit exhausted energy, and to prepare it for further action. Though there is satisfac- tion in rest, when it is needed, yet the pleasure it affords is by no means so exhilarating as that which springs from the normal activity of vigorous powers. Hunger and thirst afford the best examples of appe- tites. These are familiar on account of their frequent occurrence and decided character. Mr. Bain well says, " In the case of hunger, there is a double spur to the taking of food; first, the stimulus of uneasiness, and next, the impulse arising out of the pleasure of eating. It is well understood that these two things are quite different, and on their difference hangs the whole art of refined cookery. Yery plain food would satisfy the PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 425 craving for nutrition, but there is a superadded pleas- ure that we have to cater for." Senses and Intellect, page 243. The appetites have the following characteristics: 1st. They are physical as to their origin, conditions, and immediate ends. 2d. They are not continuous but periodical in their manifestations. 3d. As craving, or sense of want, they involve uneas- iness or discomfort, and their gratification is attended with satisfaction or pleasure. 4th. The end of appetite is both immediate satisfac- tion and ulterior good, either to the individual or to the species. Appetites may also be considered as natural or ac- quired. The natural appetites are the gifts of God, and may be innocently gratified, in due moderation, if in their gratification no moral law is violated. The excessive gratification of appetite leads to slug- gishness, gluttony, debauchery, and degradation. Acquired appetites are modifications of natural ap- petites, directed towards specific objects. In certain cases, they are harmless, as when the appetite is culti- vated for a certain kind of food, as tomatoes, not at first relished. More frequently the acquired appetites are harmful, as those disgusting and degrading appetites for tobacco, opium, and intoxicating drinks. These ap- petites become morbid and well nigh uncontrollable. Even the natural appetites for food and drink may be indulged to excess, leading to gluttony, a vice more re- spectable than drunkenness, more common, and hence, perhaps, more generally disastrous. Acquired appetite may be transmitted, and thus be- come hereditary — a fact which, in the case of vicious appetites, ought to lead to reflection and reformation. Psy.— 36. 426 PSYCHOL OGY, Simple habits are powerful in their influence; but how much more irresistible do they become when urged on by the cravings of an insatiable appetite! The cravings of appetite are guides to proper action only in case the appetite is natural or unperverted. Diseased or perverted appetites should never be gratified, or rather they never should be acquired; but whether acquired by the individual, or inherited from his pro- genitors, they should be corrected as soon as possible; for the end thereof is death. It is discreditable to hu- manity that perverted appetites are common among men, but are rare, if not entirely unknown, among brutes. As appetite may intensify and strengthen habit, so may habit, acquired by forethought and persistent effort, restrain, modify, or even overcome perverted appetite, inherited or acquired. This fact affords a ground of hope to those who are enslaved by degrading appetite. It is possible to be free. CHAPTBE 11. VITAL FEELINGS. The vital feelings are those feelings which are espe- cially related to the vigor of the organism. They are the feelings induced by the states of rest or fatigue, vigor or languor, health or sickness, and by those more permanent states called temperaments. 1. Rest and fatigue. — The feeling of rest comes as a consequence of ceasing, for a time, from labor, and in- dulging in repose. It is both agreeable and stimulating. After due rest, there is felt an incentive to renewed activity. This activity, if not excessive, is itself a source of enjoyment, till the vitality accumulated in rest is so far exhausted that demands are made on the reserve forces of the system. Activity prolonged beyond this point brings on a feeling of fatigue, which may be pro- tracted till exhausted nature refuses longer to work, when rest again becomes imperative. In practice, labor is seldom carried to the point of exhaustion, but it is frequently carried beyond the point where rest would be beneficial. 2. Vigor and languor. — These states are analogous to the preceding, but are, in general, of longer duration. A man's general condition, for a protracted period, may justly be described as vigorous; and yet, in this period, he may experience many alternations of rest and fatigue. Vigor is that general condition in which vitality pre- dominates over decay. The feeling of vigor is exhilara- ting, and impels to activity and achievement. Languor (427) . 428 PSYCHOL OGY. » is a consequence of low vitality. The tone of the sys- tem is relaxed, and there is a tendency to decay. The feeling of languor is depressing, causing an aversion to activity, and a desire for repose. It is the consequence of more general conditions than those of a feeling of fatigue, which may be induced by a few hours of labor, and dispelled by a few hours of rest. It can be over- come only by restoring tone to the system. 3. Health and sickness. — These are opposites. Health is the state characterized by the felicitous performance of the vital functions. It is the normal condition of a human being. Sickness may be regarded as an ab- normal condition of the living organism attending dis- ease or injury. The feelings attending health are agree- able and exhilarating, and, when invigorated by rest, prompt to active exertion. The feelings attending sick- ness are depressing, disagreeable, and often painful, even to the limit of endurance. They are more marked than those of health, since it is a law of human nature, that the unusual and the abnormal are more noticeable than the usual and the normal. The feelings of sickness have also a far greater vari- ety than those of health. Each of the innumerable mul- titude of diseases has its special sj^mptoms, and is attended by its peculiar feelings, which, to be realized, must be experienced. For a classification of diseases, and a description of their symptoms and accompanying feelings, the reader is referred to works on pathology. 4. Temperaments. — Temperament denotes an original quality of the constitution supposed to be due to the predominance of one or more of the vital systems — the respiratory, the circulatory, the nutritive, the nervous, and the muscular, modified also by the conditions and relative proportion of the solids and fluids of the system. VITAL FEELINGS,' 429 It is more fundamental and permanent in its influ- ence than the preceding conditions, and its effects are more difficult to trace. 1st. There are four simple temperaments — the sanguine, the bilious, the lymphatic, and the nervous. Of these, two have been regarded as primary, — the sanguine and the bilious; and two as secondary, — the lymphatic and the nervous, called also the encephalic. Even the bili- ous has been by some regarded as a modification of the sanguine, produced by external influences. (1) The sanguine temperament is characterized by the predominance of the respiratory and the circulatory systems, whose centers are the lungs and heart. It is indicated by a strong and rapid pulse, plump figure, fair skin, light eyes, soft and light hair, approaching red, a cheerful disposition, and a love for pleasure. This is the prevailing temperament of the English peo- ple. Combined with a well-developed muscular system, it constitutes, in the absence of mental culture, the ath- lete, a well developed animal with little mind. (2) The bilious temperament, due to the predominance of the nutritive system, is characterized by strong pulse ; skin, hair, and eyes dark; flesh muscular rather than fat, strong passions, inflexible wdll, and boldness of character. This is the temperament of those born to command. (3) The lymphatic temperament results from the great relative proportion of the fluids to the solids, in conse- quence of the activity of the secreting system and the inactivity of the absorbents. It is characterized by well- rounded figure, shapeless person, adij)ose tissue, full cheeks, flabby muscles, and soft skin. It is aggravated by wealth, and begets a desire for an easy life, but is not incompatible with many good qualities. It is the temperament of a mandarin. 430 -PSYCHOLOGY, (4) The nervous temperament is characterized by a prominence of the nervous system. It is indicated by a slender person, narrow chest, light hair, and mental vigor. This is the usual temperament of the artist and the scholar. 2d. The compound temperaments result from a union of the simple temperaments, giving rise to binary, ter- tiary, and quaternary combinations. They exhibit the characteristics of their components mutually modified. Of the compound temperaments, it will suffice to no- tice the following: (1) In the sanguine bilious temperament, the hair, the eyes, and the complexion are light or dark, according to the preponderance of one or the other of the compo- nents. The head is compact, and the muscles are firm. It is a good combination, and is found in many great men, giviag them a natural superiority. (2) In the sanguine lymphatic temperament, the per- son is plump, the head round, the chest full, and the complexion fair. Though it is frequently attended with beauty of person, it is an unfavorable combination, tend- ing rather to criminal pleasure than to noble achieve- ment. It is favorably modified by an earnest life. (3) In the sanguine nervous temperament, the person is slight, head narrow, forehead high, the skin light, the muscles feeble, the disposition amiable, and the charac- ter too gentle for successful contests with the stern re- alities of life. Persons of this temperament are better fitted for the counting room than for the open field. ' (4) In the bilious lymphatic temperament, the person is full, head rounded, hair and eyes dark, and the mus- cles, though well developed^ rounded over with adipose matter. Persons of this temperament are usually sound in judgment, conservative in opinion, and prudent in conduct. VITAL FEELINGS. 431 (5) In the bilious nervous temperament, the person is slender, the head high, the hair and eyes dark, and the muscles firm though slender. Persons of this tempera- ment are inclined to moral enterprises and to achieve- ments which tend to advance the welfare of mankind. (6) In the sanguine bilious lymphatic temperament, the forehead is low and retreating, the lips thick, and the form and disposition that of the prize-fighter. (7) In the sanguine bilious nervous temperament, the person is well formed, the head large, the forehead high and expanded, indicating great physical and mental power and fertility in resources. (8) In the sanguine nervous lymphatic temperament, the head is large, forehead high and broad, indicating great capacity for literary pursuits, but less adaptation to the external contests of life. Marriage alliances contracted between persons of simi- lar temperaments are supposed to be unfavorable to the well-being of the offspring. The disposition of a person is largely determined by health and temperament. It may be cheerful or morose, generous or miserly, sedate or volatile, good-natured or quarrelsome, pleasant or peevish, etc. It may, however, be modified or controlled by the will, or even perma- nently changed by persevering effort which has become habitual. CHAPTER TIL PSYCHICAL FEELINGS. An emotion is the agitation of the sensibility, purely psychical, seeking neither, as in desire, to bring some- thing to the subject, nor, as in affection, to go out to an object. Though a purely psychical feeling, it is pre- ceded by physical conditions, and accompanied or fol- lowed by physical effects, as the blu^h accompanying shame, or the blanched cheek attending fear. Pleasure and pain. — In addition to the peculiar char- acteristics of the several emotions, they are, for the most part, attended with pleasure or pain, which are contra- ries, not contradictories, since certain emotions, so far as pleasure or pain is concerned, may, perhaps, correctly be regarded as indifferent. Let us, in a brief digression, consider the theory of pleasure and pain. Pleasure is the reflex feeling which accompanies nor- mal activity or passivity. It results whenever an object induces, in due degree and duration, the energy of one or more of the active powers, or the excitement of one or more of the passive susceptibilities. The pleasure is the most complex and agreeable when the object is of such a character that it involves the greatest number of powers or susceptibilities, and induces such energy or excitement as is neither excessive nor defective, either in degree or duration. By excess, we are to understand a greater degree of intensity or a longer period of dura- tion than the constitution of the power or susceptibil- ity can endure without injury. By defect, we are to (432) EMOTIONS. 433 understand a less degree of intensity, or a shorter 2)eriod of duration, than the full gratification of the power or susceptibility requires. It is to be remarked that, in general, the degree of intensity varies inversely as the duration of the energy or excitement, and the number of powers or suscepti- bilities involved. The most intense pleasures are short lived. They can not be long endured. The soul returns with satisfaction to the less intense, but more prolonged, enjoyments. Pain is the reflex feeling w^hich accompanies abnormal activity or passivity. It results whenever an object in- duces, in undue degree or duration, the energy of one or more of the active powers, or the excitemeiit of one or more of the passive susceptibilities. Not only does excess or defect, in either the degree or duration of the activity or -passivity, diminish or frustrate the pleasure attending normal activity, but it induces irregular or abnormal action, thus causing pain. Injury or lesion of any portion of the physical system is also a cause of pain, often intense and prolonged. The soul sympathizes and suffers with the body. Pleasure and pain are both positive elements in feel- ing, and each appears augmented when in antithesis with the other. As our -views enlarge and embrace the future, our conceptions of pleasure and pain naturally lead to those of haj^piness and misery, which are not mere momentary pleasures or pains, but are more abiding satisfactions or discomforts. There is a tendency to exercise our strongest faculties, since these afford us our highest pleasure, and to leave dormant those which most need cultivation, since their exercise is attended with difficult}^ labor, or even pain. The emotions may be divided into several classes: Psy.— 37. 434 PSYCHOLOGY. 1. Emotions arising from general conditions. 1st. Cheerfulness is a state characterized by joj^ous emotions of moderate intensity and indefinite duratioxi. It may arise from good health, sanguine temperament^, amiable disposition/ good fortune; satisfactory social re- lationSj or good prospects for the future. Dejection is the opposite of cheerfulness^ and is caxised by contrary conditions. Content or discontent, gladness or depression, joy or sorrow, raj^ture or melancholy, may be regarded as hav- ing the same general characteristics as cheerfulness and dejection, each, in general, more intense than the pre- ceding, though usually less prolonged. In youth, these states are transient and are affected by slight causes, though, at this period, cheerfulness and joy prevail. In mature years, these states are usually more permanent, and less easily affected, but not infre- quently sadness and melancholy prevail. 2d. Self-satisfaction is the emotion which a person feels in view of his excellences, real or imaginary. It may arise in consideration of physical perfection — strength, agility, or beauty, — or from intellectual en- dowments or attainments — -genius, talent, knowledge, skill, or accomplishments. Self- dissatisfaction is the emotion which a person feels in view of his defects. It is the opposite of self-satis- faction, and arises from contrary causes. Self -complacency arises when, on the whole, we are satisfied with our past life; and self-displacency when we are dissatisfied.' Self-congratulation or self-reproach arises in view of a deed nobly or ignobly done. Exultation or chagrin arises in view of success or failure, irrespective of moral quality. Self-sufficiency or self- depreciation arises from a confi- dence or distrust in our abilities. EMOTIONS. 435 2. -31sthetical emotions. — These have reference to the sentiment of taste, and to the different forms of the beautifuL 1st. Novelty awakens and gratifies curiosity. A novel object is sure to attract attention and to excite wonder; but if it has no other merit, its notoriety and the curi- osity which it excites will be short-lived. It is, how- ever, preferable to dull monotony, which results in weariness and emiui; but even ennui is useful as a stim- ulus to action. The effect of novelty is due to previous ignorance, and is dispelled by knowledge. Familiarity soon de- prives novelty of its charms. This is seen in the fickle- ness of fashion. JSTovelt}^ affords little pleas are to the philosophic mind, since such a mind seeks rather for agreement, general principles, universal law, than for disagreements and novelties. The curiosity excited by novelty is frequently a vul- gar desire for gossip, characteristic of a mind weary of dull monotony, and ignorant of the rich sources of truth and beauty found in nature, science, literature, and art. ]^ovelty often marks the decay of art. The lack of originality and beauty is supplied by the new and the startling, which, for the lack of merit, soon lose their hold on the attention, and are dis^Dlaced by something- still more fantastic. Association has much to do with the pleasure of taste. It throws around certain objects the dignity of rank, wealth, genius, or worth, and around others the deg- radation of poverty, ignorance, or vice. Fashion is governed chiefly by novelty and associa- tion. The leaders seek in novelty that which will distin- guish them from the vulgar; but the common herd fol- lows, through the influence of association, till general 436 PSYCHOLOGY. coiiformity forces the leaders to seek distinction in other novelties, perhaps less beautiful, or still more devoid of good taste. Habit and custom have a powerful influence on the pleasures of taste. Habit is tendencj^ acquired by repe- tition, and is applicable to the individual. Custom is the habit of society. Fashion and custom are antagonistic. Fashion seeks the new. Custom clings to the old. The one has greater influence in youth ; the other in mature years. Fashion has the greater influence in dress; custom, in architect- ure, in manners, and in etiquette. 2d. Wit^ humor^ ridicule^ the comic^ the ridiculous^ are sources of the pleasures of taste, though not of a high order. They elicit attention, provoke laughter, and, as aflbrding pleasure, have their place, so long as they do not degenerate, as they are liable to do, into the trifling, the low, the malicious, or the immoral. 3d. Variety in unity is a source of aesthetic pleasure. By unity we are to understand, not the absolute sim- plicity of the object, but the union of the parts in the whole — many members in one body, E plurihus unum. Yariety in unity is always pleasing in the scoj^e which it gives to the intellect in tracing relations and adap- tations. The unity in variety may be seen, with in- creasing admiration, as the scale is enlarged from the individual to the family and dwelling, the citizens and the state, the human race and the world, rational beings and the universe. Harmony is the concord of diversity, and may relate to tone, color, form, character, or relation. Multiplicity w^ithout relation and adjustment of individuals, as a dis- ordered mass, is unattractive and displeasing. Grace, the harmony of attitude or movement, both soothes and delicchts the emotions. It is seen in the free EMOTIONS. 437 movements of nature — the winding rivulet, the swaying branches, the curling smoke, the fleecy cloudy tiie gam- bols of the lamb, the circling flight of the bird, or in the plays of children. It is seen as art in the attitudes and gestures of the orator. Contrast^ in things beautiful, is a source of pleasure by giving play to thought, and by heightening the effect of the contrasted objects. 4th. Begularity^ proportion^ or symmetry has each its peculiar effect. Eegularity affords pleasure in revealing law", and order, and utility. Proportion, the harmony of the Avhole and parts, and symmetry, the harmony of part with corresponding part, attract and j^lease, while deformity repels and offends. 5th. Beauty is that form of expression of idea, thought, or design, which affords a universal, disinterested, and necessary feeling of satisfaction. It is a general quality, including all the sources of aesthetic pleasure. Beauty is found in various forms, and in countless varieties of objects from the crystal to the human face divine. Thus, we have the beauty of color, light, and shade, addressed to the eye; the rythm of poetry, and the harmony of music, addressed to the ear; the smooth, velvet surface, addressed to the touch; the agreeable flavor or odor, addressed to taste or smell. Indeed, the word cjesthetics — the name of the science of the beautiful — indicates that the senses are the avenues through which beauty approaches the mind. The agreeable assthetic feeling has its origin in the alternate excitation and rest of the nerves of the several senses. The repose after stimulation restores the susceptibility and reactive power of the nerves, and prepares them for fresh excitement. The mind, in sympathy w^ith the sensorium, anticipates the renewal of the stimulation, enjoys the sensation con- sequent upon the excitement, and is disaj)pointed at its 438 PSYCHOLOGY. non-recurrence. Hence arises the pleasure from the rythmof poetry, of music, and of the dance, and the displeasure from discord. The beautiful is not realized by itself. It is always some object which has an end or purpose, which exhib- its an idea or thought, design or skill, that awakens in the beholder the emotions of beauty. Beauty is subject to limitation or restraint. Infinite profusion would overwhelm the finite faculties of man. Both nature and art observe the law of economy — nat- ure, in seeming accommodation to human limitations; art, from necessity. . Beauty seeks the alliance of that which has intrinsic dignity — natural, intellectual, or moral worth; and on such objects, both nature and art display their power. It shuns the ignoble and the degraded. 6th. The grand and the sublime exalt the thoughts and ennoble the emotions. Objects of surpassing greatness are sublime — the plunging cataract, the lofty mountain chain, the broad expanse of ocean, the movement of armies and shock of battle, the flash of lightning, the roar of thunder, the concussion of the earthquake, in- finite space, endless duration, and omnipotent power. Beauty charms and soothes; sublimity elevates and awes. The one is gentle and abiding; the other, powerful and short-lived. Unpleasant sesthetical emotions are excited by monot- ony, by deformity, b}^ ugliness, by discord, by degrada- tion, and by decay. The elements of poetic imagery are originally derived through sense perception. Note the contrast of the poetic and unpoetic words — pink, scarlet, crimson, pur- ple, violet, blue, green, azure, orange, or golden, — dun, brown, drab, bay, or black; lustrous, luminous, spark- ling, twinkling, pearlj^, or silvery, — dull, dingy, or tur- EMOTIONS. 439 bid; curving, winding, curling, flowing, — straight, stiff, or angular; clear, soft, musical, mellow, melodious, — shrill, harsh, hoarse, grating; smooth, soft, velvety, — rough, harsh, coarse; luscious, sweet, delicious, — sour, bitter, acrid; fragrant, perfumed, sweet-scented — pun- gent, stifling, suffocating. The conditions for the gratification of the pleasures of taste are found both in nature and in art; — in nat- ure, through countless diversities of landscape, adorned with hill and dale, and winding stream, and silvery lake, and distant mountain range, with azure sky and floating clouds, with trees and bowers, with fields of grass and waving grain; with living forms, and hum of bees,, and song of birds, and merry sports of childhood; in art, in grounds and dwelling, park and palace, in matchless form of sculptured marble, in speaking canvass, in the melody of the human voice or harmony of or- chestral band, in persuasive words of eloquence, or in the divine creations of poetic power. Novelty excites surprise and gratifies curiosity ; beauty and sublimity awaken admiration. 3. Ethical emotions.- — The intellect discovers the fact that man is under law, divine and human; that the di- vine law, whether revealed in nature, in the constitu- tion of man, or in the written word, has for its end the welfare of the human race; that human law, though more or less imperfect, has the same end, and in the main is conducive to human happiness; that it is, there- fore, right to obey just law, and wrong to disobe^^, and that we should endeavor to promote the general good. Ethical acts are accompanied by three distinct classes of ethical emotions, or phenomena of conscience. 1st. Preceding the act, there is a sense of obligation to do the right and to avoid the wrong. 2d. Preceding, accomjDanying, or following the act, 440 PSYCHOLOGY. there is a sense of responsibility, either to divine or human authority, for moral actions, whether right or wrong. 3d. Following the act, there is a sense of recompense — for a right act, the approval of conscience, of our fel- low-men, and of God, — for a wrong act, the disapproval of conscience, in a sense of guilt, of shame, of regret, or of remorse, also the disapprobation of our fellow-men, and of God. I CHAPTEE lY. PSYCHICAL FEELINGS. Affection is, in general, either love or hatred of an object. Emotion is, as we have seen, an agitation of the sensibility. It may be comjDared to ripples upon the surface of water. An affection is an emotion with a current directed outward, and terminating on an external object. A desire is an emotion with a current directed inward and terminating on self. Passion is violent and controlling aifection or desire. Inclination is the tendency of the aifections or de- sires to affect others or to gratify ourselves. Disposition is the prevailing spirit or character. Propensity is the constitutional bent or proneness which gives direction to the inclinations. The aifections are divided into two general classes — the benevolent affections, characterized by love, and the malevolent, characterized by hate. 1st. The benevolent affections. A benevolent affection is an interest in an object, an inclination towards it, an attachment to it, with a disposition to care for it, or do it good. The inclination, attachment, and benevolent intention, naturally, though not necessarily, follow from the inter- est which the object excites. Though the benevolent affections may, in general, be characterized as love, yet they are more definitely designated by specific names: (1) Sympathy is feeling with others as they feel. It (441) 442 PSYCHOLOGY. originates in the social nature of man, and is fostered by the satisfaction which arises when our feelings har- monize with the agreeable feelings of others. It is not, however, limited to feelings of pleasure, but is extended to those of distress. Through sympathy, we not only rejoice with those who rejoice, but weep with those who weep. Personal experience, or at least some knowledge or conception of a feeling, is a condition of sympathy in respect to that feeling. We sympathize more readily with others in those feelings which have deeply affected ourselves or those with whom we are acquainted. Certain signs are associated with certain feelings, and are their indications. Perceiving these signs, we infer the feelings, and enter into sympathy with them. A knowledge of these signs is essential to sympathy. Persons susceptible to external influences, especially if they are also characterized by a refined sensibility, are usually more sympathetic than others, though their sympathy may be superficial and evanescent, like the sympathy felt for strangers; but the sj^mpathy between friends of kindred spirit is deeper and more abiding. Community of interests, of circumstances or opinions, of hopes or fears, tends to augment sympathy. The tendency to sympathy is checked by press of business, a selfish disj)Osition, irascible temper, avarice, ambition, or disparity in age, education, temperament, or social position. Not only does inordinate self-regard diminish sympa- thy, but also self-abnegation. The hermit or anchorite is not in sympathy with mankind. (2) Fity is the sympathy with others excited by their sufferings. It regards its object, not only as suffering, but as weak or helpless, and hence as inferior, at least, in regard to that which awakens pity. Though a be- AFFECTIONS. 443 nevolent sentiment, it is, in regarding its object as in- ferior, allied to contempt. The condescension implied in pity is humiliating to a high-minded sufferer. He does not like to be pitied, though he may desire to be relieved. The sense of humiliation in being pitied is usually obviated, to some extent at least, either by the intensity of the suffering, or by habitual admission of inferiority on the part of the object of pity. (3) Compassion is sympathy excited by misfortune, and extends to persons in all conditions — inferiors, equals, or superiors. It is a feeling akin to pity: but pity may be a mere sentiment, a sym]3athetic emotion, resulting in no effort for relief; but compassion prompts to an effort to relieve the distress. The priest and the Levite, no doiibt, felt pity for the man who fell among thieves, yet they passed by on the other side; but the good Samaritan had compassion on him, and went to him, and dressed his wounds, and poured in oil and wine, and put him on his own beast, and took him to an inn, and paid for his care. A benevolent heart, in performing acts of compassion, will guard against wounding, by a display of condescen- sion, the self-respect of those whom he relieves. If, how- ever, pride in the sufferer is overborne by his sufferings, and anxiety for relief, the display of condescension may be disregarded or overcome by a sense of relief and gratitude to the benefactor. (4) Mercy is compassion extended to fallen enemies or to those exposed to suffering for demerit, by one who has the means of vengeance or the power to remit or mitigate the penalty. Pity may be bestowed when jus- tice forbids mercy ; it is felt, even for one w^ho suffers for crime, though it is augmented by extenuating cir- cumstances; but mercy seeks for those extenuating cir- cumstances as a justification for mitigating the penalty. 444 PSYCHOL OGY. Though justice forbid mercy, compassion offers consola- tion and softens the rigors of the penalty. Pity, compassion, and mercy, though differing in their manifestations or in their objects, have the common ele- ment of sympathy with others in their distress. Pity may be felt for men or even brutes, though affording no relief. Compassion for any object in distress, seeks to relieve the distress. Mercy is extended to those in our power, whether enemies or criminals, in forgiveness of injury, or in remitting or mitigating the penalty of violated law. God pities the miseries of mankind, shows his com- passion by relieving our distress and by his bountiful provision for our wants, and exhibits his mercy in the forgiveness of sins. (5) Gratitude is the feeling experienced towards a benefactor for benefits conferred. It involves satisfac- tion in the benefit received, admiration for the generous deed, esteem for the benefactor, and a desire to make suitable returns. (6) Thankfulness is a sense of kindness received, and a readiness to acknowledge it in words or other appro- priate signs. Genuine thankfuhiess may be regarded in its mani- festations as the expression of gratitude; but the form of thankfulness may be employed, when gratitude is not felt. A profusion of thanks may be offered by one whose conduct proves him to be ungrateful. Regarding mere thankfulness as an imperfect return for benefits received, gratitude seeks to make more ade- quate returns in appropriate deeds. The common sentiment of mankind approves of thank- fulness, but demands gratitude. Unthankfulness is re- garded as a breach of etiquette; ingratitude is branded as a moral baseness. AFFECTIONS. 445 (7) Esteem is the regard which we feel for others in consideration of their excellences of character. Though entering as an element in gratitude and friendship, it is not identical with either, since it may be felt in the absence of benefits received or of personal attachments. It can be called out only by good qualities, real or sup- posed, in the object of esteem. (8) Friendship is the mutual attachment of two per- sons who have esteem, regard, or predilections for each other, exclusive of natural relationship or the tender passion of love. It presupposes an intimate acquaint- ance, and finds expression in the reciprocation of kind offices. It implies community of feeling, congruity of character, and mutual sympathy; though, in many re- spects, true friends may be diverse, or even the com- plements of one another, each supplying the deficiencies of the other, and admiring in the other what is lacking in himself. True friendship is the mark of a generous and noble character, and can be felt by no other. A person des- titute of true friends is certainly wanting in generous qualities, and is an object of pity. Appreciation of high and noble qualities in another, though an essential condition of friendship, is not iden- tical with it, since it may exist when friendship is want- ing. True friends will stand by one another in ad- versity, that test which distinguishes false friends from true. Nothing but an unexpected discovery of unworthi- ness in the character of one of the parties, showing that the other was mistaken in him, or that he is not what he once was, will sever the tie of friendship, and even then he will always be regarded w^ith a melancholy in- terest which would manifest itself in deeds of kindness. The friend of former years can never be regarded as an alien or a stranger. 446 PSYCHOLOGY. Friendship seeks the good of the object of its regard, and is disinterested and self-sacrificing. It is not blind to faults, but sees them and endeavors to correct them, and thus to render the object of regard more worthy. Friendship is progressive. Time strengthens and con- firms it, and renders it proof against the rude blasts of adversity. It sympathizes both in joy and in sorrow, rejoicing in the one, affording consolation in the other. The question has been raised whether friendshij^ can be cherished between more than two persons. The num- ber of i^ersons towards whom a warm friendship can be cherished is not indeed very great; but there is no rea- son why the number should be limited to a single in- dividual. The acquisition of a new friend does not im- ply the loss of an old one, neither is it a just cause of jealousy. In this respect, friendshij) differs greatly from love between persons of opposite sexes, which, in the very nature of the case, is exclusive. (9) Self-love is that form of love in which the subject and the object are identical. It is the regard of the in- dividual for himself, and leads him to guard against danger and to seek to promote his own happiness. Self-love is said to be the first law of nature. It is either due or undue. Due self-love, or self-respect, which guards our own welfare and restrains us from whatever is debasing, is proper and commendable. The injunction, Love thy neighbor as th^'self, implies that, within reasonable lim- its, it is right to love ourselves. We are at liberty to promote our own interests, when, in doing so, we do not disregard the interests of others. True greatness is modest, generous, and self-sacrificing. Undue self-love is selfishness. It seeks our own grati- fication, regardless of the rights of others. It is egotism when it seeks to make one's self conspic- AFFECTIONS, 447 nous, and obtrudes the great I whenever it finds an opportunity. It is haughtiness^ when it looks down with contempt upon others regarded as inferior. It is j^riV/e when it exalts self, and glories in its own importance or achievements, exclaiming, ''Is not this great Babylon that I have built for the house of the kingdom, by the might of my power, and for the honor of my majestj'?" It is selfish cwibition, wdien, for self-glory, it seeks for ecclesiastical, political, or military power, regardless of the misery which it causes. (10) Conjugal love is the reciprocal attachment of two persons of opposite sexes, who are united by the mar- riage engagement or tie. It is, perhaps, the strongest affection of the human heart. There is a natural affinity or attachment between the sexes; and if a marriageable man and woman of suita- ble ages and social position, entertain mutual friendship, no other attachment intervening, that friendship is almost certain to develop into love. This affection, awakened by mutual attraction, and in- tensified by restriction to a single object, becomes, by action and reaction, an all-controlling passion. The lovers are blind to each other's faults, and each sees in the other the perfection of every excellence. Conjugal love ought to be enduring as life, and will be thus enduring if the parties are well mated, con- siderate, forbearing, and true. But how often is the ardent love before marriage transformed into indiffer- ence or hate ! Its very ardor and intensity is unfavor- able to its constancy. More selfish than friendship, love is exclusive, easily excited to jealousy, and brooks no rival. Friendship demands genuine virtues, and is confirmed and tested by time; but love, capricious and inconsider- 448 PSYCHOLOGY, ate, blind to faults, deaf to advice, too often sows to the wind and reaps the whirlwind. (11) Parental and filial love is that love which exists between parents and children — parental, the love of parents for their children ; and filial, the love of children for their parents. It is an instinctive feeling, exhibited by the lower an- imals as well as by man; but in the lower animals, it ceases when the young are able to care for themselves, while, in man, it is not only an instinctive feeling, but a rational sentiment, as enduring as life itself. This affection seems to have been implanted by the Creator for the wise purpose of caring for the young and preserving the species. Parental love is stronger than filial, and maternal than paternal. With what unceasing care the mother watches over her children through the years of helpless infancy and dependent childhood! The feeling of parental and filial love is strengthened by the relation of the parties as protector and protected, by association and habit, by worth in the parents and dutiful conduct in the children; but that these circum- stances do not constitute the affection, or wholly explain it, is evident from the difierence between the feeling towards one's own child or parent and that with which a step-child or a step-parent is regarded. (12) Fraternal love is the love existing between broth- ers and sisters. Though less intense than conjugal, pa- rental, or filial love, it is a beautiful sentiment, and is abiding as life. The family affections — conjugal, parental and filial, and fraternal love, constitute a group by themselves. They exhibit divine w^isdom in their origin; and, surviv- ing the loss of Eden, continue to work for the good of the race. AFFECTIONS, 449 The affections, the source of the dearest joys of life, are also the occasions of the sharpest pangs. Sorrow for the loss of friends refuses to be comforted, save in the hope of a reunion in a future life. The fact that love out- lives the natural life of the person loved, is in harmony with the doctrine of immortality, but is out of harmony with the gloomy view that death is an eternal sleep. (13) Philanthropy is the love of mankind. It is a broad and generous sentiment, neither bounded by state lines, nor restricted by language or race. It is the power Avhich moves a Howard or a Wilberforce to deeds of love, and gives him a place in the hearts of mankind. Our j)bilanthropic impulses are often overborne by nar- rower or more selfish feelings. (14) Patriotism^ or love of country, is a noble senti- ment. Though inferior to philanthropy in breadth, it is superior to it in depth. It has for its object the good of country, and is gratified with national prosperit}^, and stirred to self-sacrificing activity in times of national peril. In times of peace, men are engaged with their own pursuits, and the sentiment of patriotism slumbers; but if the country be threatened with invasion, or if its life be imperiled by rebellion, the slumbering fires of patri- otism will burst forth into flame, and, through sympa- thy, patriotism becomes contagious. (15) The love of home is kindred with that of patri- otism, but warmer, and, in ordinary cases, more intense. Nostalgia^ or home sickness, indicates the strength of the affection for home. It more severely affects the un- cultivated than it does the cultivated — those who through knowledge and discipline have resources of hapj)iness within themselves. (16) Piety is love for God. It is a complex affection involving reverence^ or profound respect, for the divine character; adoration^ or worship of Him as Supreme; Psy.— 38. 450 PSYCHOL OGY, gratitude for mercies and blessings received; and trust in God, or confidence of safety and welfare under his pro- tection and providence. True love to God prompts to obedience to the divine laws, and stimulates every noble sentiment. 2d. The malevolent affections. A malevolent affection is a feeling of resentment awakened by an object which disagreeably affects us. The most favorable view that can be taken of them is that they serve the purpose of inciting to prompt ac- tion in case of sudden personal danger, and that they lead to the detection and punishment of crime, and thus to the protection of society. In this light they may be regarded as a natural response to a sense of injury. More frequently, however, they are suffered to control action, when they should themselves be restrained, or directed by reason. Though originally constituted by the Creator for wise purposes, they have been perverted by sin, and have become the occasions of evil. (1) Dislike is the repugnance felt towards an object which displeases. It is more than the negative indiffer- ence with which those objects are regarded wd:iich neither awaken desire nor call forth the benevolent or malev- olent affections. Something in an object awakens unpleasant feelings which find expression in some token of disfavor. The feeling is not positive hatred, but there is aversion or a disposition to repel the object. (2) Antipathy is a strong dislike, indicating not only a want of sympathy, but positive disagreement or dis- cord. In certain cases it may be regarded as constitu- tional, since no other reason can be assigned for it. Certain persons feel antipathy to others at first-sight, so do certain animals. (3) Contempt is the feeling of dislike and disapproba- AFFECTIONS, 451 tion manifested towards those who are considered base. These are regarded as justly deserving to be branded for their meanness. It is not external circumstances, such as poverty or mental inferiority, that render a person an object of contempt, but baseness of character, or in- tentional meanness of conduct. Contempt is not incompatible with the hope that the obloquy cast upon the person may cause a reaction of his moral nature leading to reformation. When a person is despised as beneath contempt, he is regarded as hope- lessly lost to all that is good. (4) Scorn is the feeling w^hich leads to the rejection of something proffered as unworthy of our acceptance. Contempt implies that something is not good in itself; scorn, that it is not good enough for us. Scorn is alto- gether a perversion when the wicked scorn the right- eous or that which is good. (5) Disdain is the feeling entertained by a haughty person towards others whom he despises as unworthy of his consideration. Haughtiness is the effect of pride, and leads to the feeling of disdain for those regarded as inferior, and to an indifference alike to their j)raise or censure. Arrogance is a compound of pride and vanity, and manifests itself in pretensions to superiority and in demands for deference. A haughty man treats with disdain those whom he regards as destitute of marks of distinction. An arro- gant man makes lofty pretensions, and claims superior- ity for himself, and exacts deference from those whom he regards as his inferiors. The pride of an arrogant man would lead to disdain, if his vanity did not covet praise. His vanity modifies his pride and excludes dis- dain ; his pride makes his vanity arrogant. (6) Envy is the resentment felt at the success or su- j)eriority of others. The envious person, seeing in the 452 PSYCHOLOGY. success of another his own failure, or in the superiority of another his own inferiority, resents it by attempting to lower him by depreciation, insinuation, or slander. Envy is always base and degrading. It is without justification or palliation. The true remedy for envy is to bring ourself up, and not to bring a superior down. If any one would de- velop, to their full extent, all the possibilities of good in himself, he would find little occasion for envy. (7) Jealousy is a burning desire to possess or to keep something regarded as valuable, coupled with a fear that another will appropriate it to himself Envy regards, with an evil eye, the possessions, the success, the reputation, or the superiority of others. Jealousy fears that another may deprive us of what we desire or possess. We may be envious at the success or the superiority of others, when it simply reveals, but does not cause our own failures or inferiority; but we are jealous of the success or the superiority of others when it is believed to sustain to our failures or inferiority the relation of cause to effect. We are envious of superiors in position, influence, or fortune. We are jealous of equals who supplant us or gain at our expense. Thus, one child is jealous if another is praised in his presence, imagining that the other withdraws praise from himself Those of the same profession, whose success depends, to a great extent, upon their popularity, are most liable to be jealous of one another, as musicians, actors, physi- cians, or preachers. The typical case of jealousy is that exhibited by a lover who believes that he is supplanted by a rival in the affections of the one he loves. In this case, the more ardent the love, the more violent the jealousy. Eeginning with suspicion, which implies doubt, jealousy becomes furious when evidence dispels doubt, and turns AFFECTIONS, 453 uncertainty into dreaded certainty, and ardent love into murderous hate. "Thy numbers, Jealousy, to naught were fixed, Sad proof of thy distressful state ! Of differing themes the veering song was mixed ; And now it courted love, now raving called on hate." (8) Malice is ill-will cherished towards others, termin- ating in evil intent or premeditated injury. Though it may be called out by prejudice, or dislike, or injury, •real or imaginary, it springs from a bad disposition, or a wicked heart, and is without justification or excuse. It is exactly the opposite of benevolence, which is the cardinal virtue. (9) Resentment is the reaction of feeling in response to a sense of personal affront or injury. It seeks ex- pression in some form of retaliation. Arising from a sense of wrong received, it tends to continue till the wrong is redressed. Wrongs to our friends are resented, since they are regarded, as in a certain sense, personal. We consider them as wrongs to ourselves. Resentment implying malice is to be distinguished from indignation^ or the feeling awakened by the unjust or atrocious conduct of others. Indignation springs from a high sense of honor, and, being exempt from selfish personality, is devoid of malice, and not irreconcilable with a benevolent disposition. , (10) Hatred is cherished resentment. It broods over wrong, takes time for consideration, and deliberately plans retaliation. Less violent than anger, it is more lasting. Hatred between individuals leads to feuds be- tween families, and clans, or tribes. (11) Anger is sudden and strong resentment. It often produces intense excitement, and manifests itself in deeds of violence. Anger is usually of short duratiou ; its 454 PSYCHOLOGY. very intensity forbids its continuance; lience, it has been defined as a short-lived madness. Anger may, by sudden provocation, be aroused in hearts devoid of mal- ice, but it is unsafe to be subject to its control, since it may lead to deeds which may be the lasting regret of our lives, and which no repentance can remedy. (12) Wrath is heightened anger felt by a superior to- wards an inferior. It may be displeasure or righteous indignation, devoid of malice, felt towards the guilty, as the wrath of God; but, when provoked by personal in- juries, if involving malice, it becomes haughty vindic- tiveness, dangerous or destructive to its object. (13) Rage is a violent ebullition of anger^ breaking out into extravagant expressions and vehement demon- strations of resentment. (14) Fury is excessive rage, lashing the soul to such a pitch of excitement, that it is no longer under the control of reason. (15) Revenge is deep-seated hatred, manifesting itself in retalliation for injuries received. It is a destructive passion, seeking satisfaction in returning injury for in- jury, and usually with interest compounded. Not satisfied with the retribution which civil or Divine jus- tice will visit upon the offender, it takes upon itself the work of retribution, forgetting that God has said, "Avenge not j^ourselves, but rather give place unto wrath; for vengeance is mine, I will repay, saith the Lord." CHAPTEE V. PSYCHICAL FEELINGS. Desire is a cleaving for a supposed good not in pos- session. The object of desire must either be known or believed to be a good, that is, something whose pos- session would afford satisfaction, or gratify the feelings. Desire may be regarded as an emotion with a current directed towards self Aversion is the opposite of desire. It may be re- garded as negative desire — a desire to be rid of a suj)- posed evil. The object of aversion must be either known or believed to be an evil, that is, somethiog which would disagreeably affect the sensibility. In desire, the order is, a supposed good not in pos- session, an interest in that good or an affection for it, a desire or craving to possess it. In aversion, the order is, a supposed evil, a dislike excited against that evil, and an aversion to it. Desire attracts; aversion repels. The object of desire pleases; the object of aversion dipleases. 1st. General desires and aversions. There are three general classes of legitimate desires and aversions — de- sire for happiness, for perfection, for usefulness; and aversion to misery, to imperfection, and to uselessness. (1) A desire for happiness^ or an aversion to misery, is universal. Man desires not only pleasure, the gratifi- cation of a passing hour, but happiness, rational enjoy- ment; and desires it to be abiding, eternal, which in- volves a desire for continued existence. (455 ) 456 PSYCHOLOGY. Happiness is attainable only by a compliance with its conditions; but a knowledge of these conditions is in- dispensable to compliance. What, then, is happiness, and what are the conditions of its attainment? Happi- ness is the agreeable emotions which spring from the enjoyment of good. It is not quiescence — it does not consist in rest. It springs both from the exertion of our active powers, and from the excitement of our passive susceptibilities. But neither is every action nor every excitement a source of happiness. Certain actions or certain excitements re- sult in positive misery. Happiness springs only from proper actions or from proper excitements, that is, from such exertion of the active powers or excitement of the 2)assive susceptibilities as are in accordance with the laws of our being. Obedience to law is a condition of happiness, and a knowledge of law is a condition of obedience, and therefore a condition of happiness. A desire for happiness naturally leads to the desire for those things which confer happiness. An aversion to misery leads to an aversion to whatever is a cause of misery. (2) A desire for perfection and an aversion to imper- fection, is natural to man, and is, therefore, legitimate, when not selfishly pursued at the expense of others. Perfection is either physical, intellectual, or moral, each contributing to the others, all being essential to the perfection of man. Physical perfection^ embracing health, strength, agility, and beauty, is rather an ideal towards which some prog- ress can be made, than an end which can be definitely attained. A desire for physical perfection tends to guard life and to preserve health and beauty. It prompts to the observance of the physical laws in exercise and rest, in DESIRE AND A VERSION, 457 food and drink, in pure ,air and proper clothing, and in cleanliness of person. Physical well-being is favorable to intellectual and moral perfection, and contributes to human happiness. Intellectual perfection^ consisting in the symmetrical development and complete control of our mental powers, is a loft}^ ideal which can be approximated, though never reached. The desire for the attainment of this ideal is an incentive for assiduous culture. A knowledge of the conditions and laws of happiness is the indispensable condition of obedience to these con- ditions and laws, and obedience results in happiness. By knowledge, man avoids many evils, otherwise inev- itable, enlarges his dominion over the forces of nature, and thus multiplies the sources of enjoyment. Moral perfection^ or virtue — integrity of purpose, pu- rity of heart, love to God and to man, uprightness of life, is not only a noble and inspiring ideal, but is, by the help of God, an attainable end. Moral perfection is a never-failing fountain of pure and unalloyed happiness, and will ensure peace of mind and rest of soul, in spite of poverty, persecution, sick- ness, loss of friends, or even death itself (3) A desire for usefulness grows out of man's social relations, and is legitimate and praiseworthy. It nat- urally leads to thoughtful plans and noble deeds. It stimulates the benevolent affections, which seek the good of others. Its language is, May others be blest, and may I bestow the blessing. 2d. Special desires and aversions. The special desires and aversions can be reduced to three classes — desire for knowledge, for wealth, and for power, and aversion to ignorance, to poverty, and to inferiority and obscurity. (1) The desire for knowledge is more than a vulgar curiosity, a desire for novelty. It embraces the wide Psy.— 39. 458 PSYCHOLOGY. field of science, literatnre, and art^ also the professional, commercial, mechanical, and agricultural purBuits, The desire for knowledge is closely related to the do- sire for intellectual perfection. It arises from the utility of knowledge, from the constitution of the intellectual powers, from the scope for activity which the pursuit of knowledge affords, and from the pleasure which tlie acquisition confers. Knowledge is a power and a great utility — a means of distinction and influence. The activity of the intellect is itself a means of happiness. The field of knowledge, vast and greatly diversified, is a never-failing source of pure enjoyment. The desire for knowdedge arises, there- fore, naturally from the constitution of man in relation to the world in which he lives. It usually assumes specific forms — a desire for a knowledge of a certain science, art, language, or profession. In early life, the desire for knowledge partakes more of the character of curiosity; but in mature years, it seeks rather for the practical, and, in some cases, for the speculative and the universal. Aversion to ignorance is the necessarj^ counterpart of the desire for knowledge. It is also augmented by a consideration of the disabilities attending ignorance. (2) The desire for wealth is natural, and within cer- tain limitations, useful and commendable. It checks vice, promotes industry, and fosters the useful arts. The pursuit of wealth affords pleasure in the activity which it calls forth. The possession gratifies the desire for its acquisition, affords the means for the gratification of other desires, confers the dignity of independence and social distinction, and supplies the means for promoting the welfare of others. Avarice^ or the undue desire for wealth, induces anx- 0U8 care and slavish toil, begets covetousness, or desire DESIRE AND A VERSION. 459 for the property of others, and culminates in a mammon- worship or miserly wretchedness. Aversion to poverty^ the necessary consequence of the desire for wealth, is strengthened by a knowledge of the evils of j^overty. (3) Ambition^ the desire for j^ower or farae^ is a native and powerful impulse to action. The ambition to be useful is a laudable virtue; but selfish ambition is a vul- gar vice, detestable in itself, and dangerous to society. The selfish possessor of power is a tyrant, and the am- bitious conqueror has been the scourge of mankind. The desire for the approval of the wise and the good, coupled with an effort to merit that approval, leads to worthy achievement; but vanity^ the undue desire for the approbation of others, is a weak and silly vice, usu- ally exhibited by those destitute of merit. Coupled with untruthfulness, it leads to deceit or hypocrisy. Pride desires power; vanity fame. Pride elevates us in our own estimation; vanity seeks elevation in the estimation of others. Mortification is wounded vanity. Aversion to inferiority or obscurity is the counterpart of ambition, or desire for power or fame. 3d. Compound desires. These are hope and fear. (1) Hope is the desire and expectation of good. It points to the future. We do not hope for that which we now possess, nor for that which we either do not desire, or do not expect. Desire and expectation, the two elements of hope, are not always in equilibrium. Expectation is an intellect- ual element, and varies with the degree of probability. When the probability is small, the exjDcctation is weak, and we are said to hope against hope, that is, against expectation ; but when the probability is great, the ex- pectation is strong, giving the assurance of hope. If the desire is weak, and the expectation also, but little in- 460 PSYCHOLOGY. terest is taken ; if the desire is weak, and the expecta- tion strong, hope approaches pure expectation; if both desire and expectation be strong, the hope becomes a joyful anticipation. Faith is confidence in a person or thing from which we hope to realize some object of desire. The object of hope is a good; but the object of faith is a person or thing regarded as the source of good. Trust implies the committal of an interest to the keeping of an object of faith . Hope is a powerful spring to action. The loss of hope usually paralyzes effort; but, when coupled with resentment, it may lead to the rashness of despair. (2) Fear is the aversion felt towards expected evil. Expectation is common to hope and fear, but the objects of expectation, in the two cases, are opposites. In hope, the object of expectation is some form of good ; in fear, the object is some form of evil. The desire of hope, and the aversion of fear are also opposites. Anxiety is a form of fear in which the evil is rather possible and uncertain, than probable and expected. It is usually more continued than fear. Apprehension indicates a stronger probability than anxiety. It anticipates danger. Alarm is the fear excited by the presence of sudden danger. Dread is the fear of some impending calamity. Terror is paralyzing fear. Horror is the sympathetic terror induced by the sud- den calamity of others. Despair is the absence of all hope of deliverance from present evil. It may result in complete inactivity or it may, as sometimes in war, exhibit prodigious effort known as the courage of despair. PART III, VOLITION AND THE WILL. (461) CHAPTER I. GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION. 1. Phenomena and faculties of the soul. — We have already found that the phenomena of the soul are reduci- ble to three classes, — cognitions, feelings, and volitions. These phenomena imply three classes of faculties, — the Intellect, the Sensibility, and the Will. Since the soul has cognitions, that is, since it knows, it has the power to know, or the faculty of knowing, and this faculty is called the intellect. Since the soul feels, it has the susceptibility of feeling, and this sus- ceptibility is called the sensibility. Since the soul puts forth volitions, that is, since it wills, or chooses between alternatives, it has the power of decision or of choice, and this power is called the will. The faculties of the soul are not divisions of the soul; they are capabilities, or susceptibilities, or powers of the soul. W^hen it is said that the soul has intellect, sensibility, and will, the meaning is, the soul can think, and feel, and choose; but these processes go on together, though one may be more prominent than the others. In cognition, the soul thinks. The intellect, or faculty of cognition, is the faculty, which the soul sj^ecially ex- erts; but the other faculties, the sensibility and the will, are relatively, not absolutely, quiescent. In feeling, the susceptibilities are agitated, and though thought and vo- lition may be present, the phenomena of the sensibility are especially prominent. In volition, the soul exerts its powers of choosing between alternatives, but the in- (463) 464 PSYCHOL OGY. tellect and the sensibility are not only not absent, but not even quiescent. The cognitions make known the properties of things, and thus awaken our appetites, or induce affections and desires or aversions, which become springs to action. In saying that the will decides which alternative it will choose, the meaning is, the soul exerts its power of choice, called the will, and decides which alternative it will elect. 2. Definition of terms. — In order to avoid ambiguity, it is necessary to define the principal terms employed. Decision sometimes signifies an intellectual act, as when a judge decides a question of law, or, in general, when the intellect decides whether a given proposition is true or false; but when used in connection with the will, de- cision means that we have made up our minds to act or not to act in a given manner; and growing out of this, is a secondary meaning of firmness or adherence to the alternative chosen. A decision to act is always an act of the will; and, conversely, an act of the will always involves decision. A purpose is a predetermination to enter upon a given course of action. Intention is the deliberate purpose to accomplish a certain result. • Yolition is the intentional decision to act in a given manner. It is the typical act ^ of the will. Choice is the election of one of two or more alterna- tives in view of motives rationally apprehended. The relation of choice to volition is that of a species to its genus. Choice is rational volition, electing its alternative in view of reasons. It implies preference. Alternatives are necessary to choice; that is, where there is no alternative, there can be no choice. Ea- tional motive is also a condition of choice. The term GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION. 465 rational motive is here generalized, and signiiies motive in view of reasons good or bad. Volitions may be put forth in view of motives rationally apprehended, or from impulses of the sensibility without reflection, or without motive or impulse. In the first case, the volition is elective; in the second, impulsive; in the third, arbitrary. All volition is conative ; choice is not only conative, but elective. Refusal is the expressed decision not to accept a given proffer, or not to comply with a given request. But to refuse to accept a proffer, is to choose its alternative, not to accept; and to refuse to comply with a request is to choose its alternative, not to comply. Eefusing is negative choosing, or choosing the negative. Thus, an apple is offered me, I may either choose or refuse to accept it; that is, I may choose to accept it, or I may choose not to accept it. I may be requested to lend $100, 1 may either choose or refuse to comply with the request; that is, I may choose to comply with the request, or choose not to comply. To decline to accept an invitation is a polite refusal to accept, expressing the choice not to accept. More than two alternatives may be presented. Thus, I may choose to take one of two or more apples, or I may choose to take more than one, or I may choose iio4^ to take any. The alternatives here considered are not congruents, but conflictives, and are either contradictories or contra- ries — contradictories, if but two in number; contraries, if more than two. Volition is not to be confounded with the external executive act. Thus, the decision to take an apple pre- cedes the act of putting forth the hand and taking it, and is, therefore, distinguishable from the act. Volition is to be distinguished from desire; for desire 466 PSYCHOL OG Y. is a craving for an object in view of appropriating it to the use of self; but the decision to act in reference to it is a volition. The object of desire is something con- sidered as a good. The object of volition is the execu- tive act consequent upon the volition. Desires are pas- sively determined by something foreign to self, consid- ered as a good. Volitions are intentionally determined . by the will itself, usually in view of motives. Desires are phenomena of the sensibility, and do not necessarily eventuate in action. Volitions are sovereign acts of the will, determining executive actions. In like manner, volition is to be distinguished from aversion. A purpose is, as we have seen, a general choice or predetermination to enter upon a given course of action. It may be regarded as a general volition, determining many subsequent volitions. Thus, the purpose to lead a virtuous life, that is, the general choice of virtue, de- termines many subordinate choices or volitions. The will is the faculty of volition. A motive is an inducement soliciting the will to choose between alternatives, or to decide to act in a given manner. The expression to act is to be understood in a general sense, and may signify not only to act, but to refrain from acting in a given manner. To will is to decide or to exert the power of volition. To will and to choose are nearly synonymous, differing slightly in their applications. It is correct to say, I choose virtue, not I will virtue, though it is right to say, I will to be virtuous; and this is the meaning of the expression, I choose virtue. A preference is the favor accorded to one alternative in deeming it rather to be chosen than another. It naturally precedes choice. Indifference is the absence of preference. It signifies GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION. 467 that one alternative is neither more nor less to be chosen than another. The opposing motives are equal, whatever be their influence. In this case, as there is really no preference, the alternative may be left to be determined by another jDcrson. or by chance, or in gen- eral by circumstances foreign to choice, or the person may decide for himself; if so, he decides without pref- erence. It is then virtually volition without motive. Inclination^ propensity^ and disposition have already been defined; but it is imj)ortant to remember that in- clination is the reaching forth of the affections or desires for an object; that a propensity is a constitutional ten- dency to a given course of action ; and that disposition is the general attitude of the soul with regard to other things, out of which arises the favor or disfavor with which a given thing is regarded. 3. Order of the phenoraena.— 1st. Pre-volitional. The intellect discovers the properties of many objects which affect the sensibility as agreeable or disagreeable, thus exciting the appetites, and inducing affections and de- sires or aversions. The appetites crave gratification. The affections and the desires seek those objects which are agreeable to the sensibility. The aversions repel those which are disagreeable. The appetites, the affections, the desires, and the aver- sions furnish motives or springs of action which solicit the will to act in choosing between alternatives. 2d. Volitional. The soul, as rational, reflects upon these alternatives, and by the power of the will decides which alternative it will choose. The motives do not all solicit the will to choose the same alternative. The will is frequently, perhaps commonly, solicited b}^ conflicting motives. In view of all the motives, the soul prefers one alternative, and exerts its power of Avill in choosing that alternative, and rejects the other alternatives. 468 PSYCHOLOGY, 3d. Post -volitional. The decision of the will being made in the choice of the alternative, there remains the post- volitional act by which the volition is executed. Thus, having decided to consult a certain book lying at hand, I put forth my hand and take the book, and open it, and read a certain passage. The threefold phenomenon can be thus simply illus- trated. An apple is offered me. My appetite is excited, and a desire for the apple induced, which acts as a mo- tive soliciting the will to decide to accept the offer, '^o counter motives appearing, or none of sufficient weight, the will decides to accept the apple. It now" remains to put forth the hand and take it. This is the external execution of the volition, and is a voluntary action. CHAPTEE II. FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 1. Nature and limitations of freedom. — Freedom is exemption both from restraint and from constraint, that is, from prevention and from compulsion, whether in- ternal or external. Liberty is external freedom to act as we choose, that is, to execute our volitions. It is freedom from external restraint or prevention, and from external constraint or compulsion. It is not necessarily freedom from all re- straint, or from all constraint; for freedom from restraint in doing any particular thing is liberty to do that thing, and freedom from constraint to do any thing is liberty not to do that thing. A man is not free to appropriate the property of his neighbor without his consent, or to injure his reputa- tion or his person. From such actions he is restrained by civil law. This restraint is not, however, absolute, since he may violate the law; but for this violation, he is subject to penalty. He is not free from contributing his just proportion in bearing public burdens, in defray- ing the expenses of government. He is compelled to pay his taxes. Man is not free from obligation to obey the laws of God, but he is free from compulsion. If he violate these laws, as he has power to do, he is not free from the consequences of the violation. Though a man may pos- sibly escape the penalty of violated human law, he can not escape the just judgments of God. (469) 470 PSYCHOLOGY, Within certain limits, however, man is free to act as he pleases; that is, he has liberty, so long as he violates no law, to execute his volitions. He can choose his place of residence, and engage, without hinderance, in any business or profession. He can act with the party he prefers, unite with the church of his choice, or refuse to co-operate with any party or church. In such cases man is free, that is, he has liberty of action. Liberty, or external freedom, applies, therefore, not to all external actions, but to those which violate no law. In regard to these, man has liberty to execute his voli- tions. Hence, in respect to external action in general, man has but a partial, or limited freedom; but this is not the freedom of the will, but freedom to execute those volitions of the will which violate no law, either human or divine. Liberty of action in the cases in which it is found, is not only freedom from external restraint, as a stone thrown into the air is free to fall, but it is also free^ dom from external constraint. A man is not free in doing what he is compelled to do. Freedom includes exemption from external compulsion. It is, therefore, freedom from co-action^ that is, both from external re- straint and from external constraint. Though liberty of action implies freedom from both external restraint and constraint, yet such action is not free from the control of the man himself. The person, by the power of his will, puts forth the volition, and the volition, in the absence of external hinderance, neces- sitates the action. By liberty of action, we are, there- fore, to understand the liberty of the person to act. The action, as such, abstractly considered, is not free from constraint, for it is caused by the volition; but it is free from restraint. It has the same kind of freedom that a stone has when thrown into the air. The stone FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 471 is free to fall, that is, it is not hindered from falling; but it is not free from falling; for it is constrained to fall by the force of gravity. In like manner, though an action may be free from restraint, it is not free from in- ternal constraint, since it is determined by the volition; yet free action, so far as man is concerned, is freedom both from external restraint and from external constraint. 2. Volitions are free from restraint, but not from constraint. — To suppose them not free from restraint is to suppose that volitions actually^ put forth have been prevented from being put forth, which is absurd, since whatever is, has not been prevented from being. But volitions are not free from constraint. As events, they come under the law of causality, which may be stated. All events have causes. That volitions have causes, that is, that they are caused or necessitated, can be jDroved sj^llogistically, thus: • All events have causes. Human volitions are events. .-. Human volitions have causes. Every volition is, therefore, caused or necessitated; but, as we shall presently see, the volition is caused, not by the motive, but by the will itself. When it is said that volition is not free from con- straint, it is not to be understood that the volition pre- viously existed, and that it is forced, in opposition to its resistance, to be what it otherwise would not be, for the volition has no previous existence to be acted upon ; but it is to be understood, in saying that the will constrains the volition, that the will brings the volition into being, that is, causes it to be, and to be as it is. In like manner, when it is claimed, though incor- 472 PSYCHOLOGY, rectly, that motives constrain or compel volition ^ it is not to be understood that the motives constrain or com- pel a volition already existing to change, or to be what it otherwise would not be, but that motives, acting upon the will, not as a volition, but as a faculty, compel it to assume a certain state, condition, or attitude, called volition, thus bringing the volition into being, and causing it to be what it is. If this be so, the will is not an active power, but a passive susceptibility, and choice is a j)assive determination of the will, and not its free action. 3. Is the will free? — The will is the cause of volitions; but, because volitions are caused, it does not follow that the will, which is the cause of volitions, is caused to cause them. The question is not. Are volitions free? but. Is the will free? In what sense is the will not frcQ? In what sense is the will free? The will is not free in the sense that it is, in general, exempt from the influence of motives. But what is the nature of this influence? Are motives causes compelling the will to choose as it does, or are they reasons for the choice? The question is not, Is the will free from the solicitation of motives, but, Is it free from compulsion and from prevention? But prevention from a certain decision is compulsion not to make the decision, that is, compulsion to the contradictory decision or to some contrary decision. Motives are indeed causes; but causes of w^hat? What are their eflects? They are causes in the sense that they awaken thought, afl'ect the sensibility, and influence the will. But what is the nature of this influence? Do motives compel, or do they solicit the will? Do the motives cause the volitions, or does the will cause the volitions in view of motives? If the motives cause the volitions, then the will is passive in volition, and the FBEEDOM OF THE WILL, 473 volitions are phenomena caused in a passive susce2:)tibil- ity, called the will, by the action of forces called motives, thus bringing the phenomena of the will within the province of Mechanics. Eat is the will a j)assive sus- ceptibility, and not an active power? Can the phenom- ena of volition be brought within the province of Me- chanics? That the phenomena of volition are not included within the province of Mechanics is demonstrably certain ; for, if so, the volition would, in a given case, be the result- ant of the action, at the time, of all the forces called motives. Thus, a person standing at one corner of a square, and solicited by two friends, one at each of the adjacent corners, the motives for going to the two being equal, would go in the diagonal of the square, passing the other diagonal by his momentum, till drawn back by the motives, and after a few vibrations, Avould finally come to a stand at the middle point of that diagonal. But this would not be the case. If it be said that the motives are never equal, the reply is, that so long as either is not zero, the volition, if caused by the motives, woctid be the resultant of the action of the motives. But the fact is, that in choosing one alternative, the motive soliciting the choice of the other, though not without influence in inducing deliberation, is without volitional effect. Hence, motives are not causes of which volitions are effects. The will, therefore, though not in general, free from the solicitation of motives, is free from necessitated determination by motives. The will is not passive in volition; for, if so, it would not itself make the decision, but being quiescent, save as it is passively affected, the volitions would be the necessitated movements of the will, analogous to those of a foot-ball as it is kicked about by contending parties. The same results would follow, so long as the Psy.-40. 474 PSYCHOLOGY, will is regarded as passive, whether the motives are impulses, attractive forces, allurements, or enticements, acting through the appetites, affections, desires, or aver- sions. The motives would be causes determining the volitions as effects. This would make a volition the re- sultant of motives, which as we have shown above, is not the case. The will is free to suspend choice, that there miay be opportunity for further reflection. The will is active in volition ; it makes the decision. We are conscious of the exertion of the power of the will in making the choice. The motive does not choose; but the will chooses. The will is not a passive instru- ment swayed by motives, as the weights sway the bal- ance; but it is the power which a reasonable soul has to decide in view of motives as reasons. The will as free may refrain from putting forth volitions which it has full power to put forth; hence, the absence of a vo- lition does not imply the absence of the power to bring it into being. As motives do not constrain or necessitate the decis- ion of the will, so neither do they restrain or prevent the decision; for then they would necessitate the con- tradictory or some contrary decision. The will is equally free from constraint and from restraint. The freedom from restraint is freedom to choose a given alternative. The freedom from constraint is freedom to choose any other possible alternative. But why does the will choose one alternative rather than another? The choice of any alternative is accounted for by the fact that the will has alternative power. An effect is explained by a cause capable of producing it. In the order of time, the choice follows the consider- ation of the motives, and the execution follows the choice. FBEEDOM OF THE WILL, 475 4. Does the will ever act without motive P — In case of contradictory alternatives, the decision must, in some way, be made in favor of one or the other, since, in this case but two alternatives are possible. Let the motives to choose these alternatives be equal, and let the will itself make the decision. Then the will decides, virtually, in the absence of motives; for, since, by hypothesis, the al- ternatives are contradictories, to choose either is not to choose the other, and the motive to choose either is an equal motive not to choose the other, and since the pos- itive motives for choosing the alternatives are equal, and these are equal motives for not choosing the other, the motives for choosing either reduce to zero, or there is no choice; but, since a decision is made, it is made virtually without motives. To make this still clearer, let the contradictory al- ternatives, the fact of deciding in favor of one or the other, and the equal motives remain, and let the motives diminish equally till each becomes zero, then there is decision absolutely without motive, proving that, in this case, the will is free. Let the motives still diminish equally. They will become negative, but will continue equal. Each motive becomes a motive for choosing the other alternative, -and cancels the motive for not choosing that alternative, and again, we would have decision virtually without motive. In these cases, there is volition, if not choice, without motive. 5. Condensed statement of phenomena. — The com- plex phenomena connected vfith the will are, therefore, the following: Alternatives, any one of which is a pos- sible object of^ choice or volition ; in general, motives soliciting the will to choose one or more of the alterna- tives; deliberation or consideration of the motives in favor of the different alternatives; freedom of the will 476 PSYCHOL OOY. from compulsion and from prevention ; the decision, that is, the volition or choice of one alternative; the execu- tion of the volition, that is, the external action which secures or accomplishes the alternative chosen. 6. The decisions of the will not necessarily unrea- sonable. — Though the will is free, the soul is rational; hence, the decisions of the will are not necessarily arbi- trary or irrational. These decisions ought to be, and may be, in the highest degree, both intellectually reasona- ble and morally right. When truth and right are in- volved, the will is under moral obligation to decide in accordance with the light of reason and of conscience. Though the decisions of the will are not necessarily ir- rational, yet they may be so, and often are so, as a matter of fact. The will has the fearful power to decide to act contrary to the dictates of truth and righteous- ness, and this power it often exerts; but, for the exer- tion of this power, it is responsible. 7. Meaning of the words obligation and responsibil- ity. — The words, obligation and responsibility or responsi- ble^ are of frequent occurrence in discussions pertaining to the moral aspects of the will, and hence their mean- ing should be clearly understood and discriminated. When it is said a person is under obligation to do or not to do a certain thing, the meaning is, he ought or ought not to do that thing. When it is said a person is responsible for his actions, the meaning is, that he is justly accountable, or deserves reward or punishment, according as the actions are good or bad, and that he must meet the consequences. CHAPTEE III. MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. 1. Freedom is an essential condition of responsibil- ity. — If the will is necessitated by motives to choose a given alternative, that is, if the choice is unavoida- ble, the person choosing is not morally responsible. He neither merits praise for a right choice, nor deserves blame for a wrong choice. Indeed, the choice can, on this supposition, be properly called right or wrongs only by a comj)arison of the choice with an external stand- ard, and not in the sense that the man is commendable or censurable for his choice, since he chooses as he does, because he can not do otherwise. How could it be mor- ally wrong for an individual to choose what he can not help choosing? How could he be guilty for such a choice? Since the choice determines the action, how could he be responsible for the action? If a man suf- fers his will to be enslaved by passion, he is responsi- ble for this enslavement and its consequences; but this enslavement is, in general, not absolute. If the will is not free, it would always be unjust to the individual to punish him for crime. It could be justified only on the ground that such punishment is a motive deterring others from similar crimes. But even this motive does not always deter from crime. Notwith- standing the punishment, crime is still committed. The offender, must, therefore, be impelled by a stronger mo- tive, and can not avoid the crime; hence, to him, pun- ishment would be an act of injustice. (477) 478 PSYCHOLOGY. 2. There is no exception to the principle that freedom is an essential condition of responsibility. — If a debtor should willfully squander his resources^ and thus deprive himself of the power to discharge his obligations, he is not, therefore, released from moral responsibility. He had the power to meet his obligations, and for the proper use of this power he is responsible. In will- fully squandering his resources, he has incurred guilt; and for this guilt, he may justly be branded as dishon- est by honorable men. If it be asked, Is he now under obligation to pay his debts, and can he justly be branded for not doing it? the answer is: Though the legal obligation is still in force, unless he has availed himself of the provisions of a bankrupt law, he is not under moral obligation to do what he can not do, and he (^ught not to be held re- sponsible for not doing an impossibility; but. when he had power to pay his debts, he was under moral obli- gation to pay them. He is now held responsible for failing to do what he had the power to do, and what he was under obligation to do. If the ability to pay the debt should return, the moral obligation to pay it would revive. Present obligation implies present power. A man may indeed now be guilty for a past crime which he can not now avoid, since it is done and can not be recalled, though he may repent of it; but the guilt was incurred when the crime was commited, when he had power to avoid it. He is not now guilty for not undoing what he can not now undo; but he is guilty for having done what, at the time, he had power to avoid. 3. Freedom of the will is freedom to choose any- one of the possible alternatives. — The question is some- times asked, Can the will choose differently from what it does choose? It is possible to become mystified by MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. 479 such a question. It is, of course, im^^ossible for the will to choose a given alternative, and, at the same time, not to choose it, but to choose a different alternative. The true question is, Can the will choose a different alterna- tive from any designated one of the possible alternatives? The answer is. It can. Let A name any one of sev- eral possible alternatives, then B can always choose another. It is sometimes said that we are conscious of the power to choose differently from the choice actually made, but this is not correct, since we are not conscious of powers, but of phenomena. We know powers by the rational intuition of their conditional necessity as the log- ical antecedents, or necessary conditions, of phenomena; but in case of the power of contrary choice there is no phenomenon implying such a 2)C)wer, since there is no choice contrary to actual choice. If there is in the human mind a consciousness of the power to choose contrary to the actual choice, this fact of consciousness would settle the question, and controversy would be at an end. The fact that the existence of such power of choice is called in question by a large class of thinkers, is proof that there is no consciousness of such a power, for a datum of consciousness always compels recognition. There is, however, in every unsoj)histicated mind a belief or conviction that there is power of contrary choice, and of this belief or conviction such a mind is conscious. Before choice, there is a conviction that there is power to choose any one of the possible alterna- tives; and, after choice, that any other one of the possi- ble alternatives might have been chosen instead of the one actually chosen; but a conviction that there is a certain power is not a consciousness of that power. That the will can choose any one of the possible al- 480 PSYCHOLOGY. ternatives, follows from the fact that the volition is not a resultant of motives, but is an act of the will. Since the volition is an act of the will and not a re- sultant, it is free both from the constraint and the re- straint of motives. Freedom from constraint is freedom from the necessity of choosing any given alternative; and freedom from restraint is freedom to choose any possible alternative. Freedom, both from constraint and from restraint, that is, the freedom of the will both from compulsion and from prevention, is the indispen- sable condition of responsibility. 4. The voice of conscience is decisive as evidence in favor of liberty.^ — But what does the conscience of the criminal say? It declares him guilty and deserving of punishment. The criminal arraigned before the bar of his own conscience, confesses his crime, admits his guilt, and acknowledges the justness of his punishment. If he believed that his choice was necessitated, his conscience would acquit him of guilt, not that he did not do the deed, or that he did not will to do it. but that he could not help doing it, since he could not help willing to do it. But his conscience does not acquit him of blame. In his inmost soul, he believes that he is guilty. He could not be guilty, iii the sense of being to blame, unless his will was free in the act of volition. He could not believe himself to be guilty, unless he be- lieved himself to be free; but he does believe himself to be guilty; therefore he believes himself to be free. The voice of conscience is not the voice of a sophist, but it is the voice of nature, yea, the voice of God declaring in tones not to be misunderstood, that the transgressor is not passive, but active in his crimes. Conscience, in approving the right and condemning the wrong, postulates the freedom of the will. If, there- fore, the will is not W^a^ the action of conscience, tht) MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, 481 noblest of our moral powers, is based on a false postu- late, and the very constitution of our nature is self- contradictory. It would, of course, be reasoning in a circle, to assume responsibility, and deduce freedom from this assumption, and then from freedom deduce responsibility, or the re- verse. The fact is, either responsibility or freedom can be established on evidence independent of the other; and, when established, the other may be inferred as a logi- cal antecedent or a logical consequent. The phenomenon of conscience is a proof of responsi- bility; but responsibility implies freedom as its neces- sary condition, or logical antecedent. The fact that a volition is not a resultant of motives is a proof of the freedom of the will ; but this freedom involves responsibility as its logical consequent. 6. Ground of responsibility. — The ground of respon- sibility is moral obligation to do right and to avoid wrong. Freedom of the will is the condition of moral obligation, and hence of responsibility. Man is respon- sible for the use he makes of his freedom of will and liberty of action. Though the freedom of the will is the condition of obligation, it is evidently not the ground. The fact that a man is free to do a certain thing, is no reason why he should do it. Not only is there liberty to perform one action and to avoid another, but there is reason why the one should be performed and the other avoided. But why should a person do one thing and avoid another? What is the ground of obligation? Every man knows that happiness is an object of de- sire, and that misery is an object of aversion; that in all lawful ways, he has the right to seek to gain the one and to avoid the other; and that, so long as he does not forfeit his liberty by crime, or encroach on Psy.-41. 482 PSYCHOL O G Y, the rights of others, he has the right to enjoy, with- out hinderance, the fruit of his labor. The rights which one claims for himself, he is under obligation to concede to others, since they have the same right to claim for themselves what he demands for himself JS^ot transient pleasure, frivolous or unsatisfying, but happiness, substantial and abiding, is the birthright of man, and this he may enjoy by obedience to the laws of his being, which are the laws of God, unless, like Esau, he sells his birthright for a mess of pottage. To attain to happiness, man must have the opportu- nities of education in the development of his powers, physical, intellectual, and moral. He must have the right of pro^Derty, or the enjoyment of the fruit of his own labor. He must be protected in person and prop- erty. To secure these blessings, they must be mutual and universal, limited only by the requirements pertain- ing to the general good. Since others have no right to encroach upon our rights, we have no right to encroach upon theirs. Since our happiness is promoted, not only by our own efforts, but by the good- will, and, in certain cases, by the aid of others, and since this good-will and aid we gladly accept, they, in like manner, are entitled to our good- will and aid, so far as that aid can be reasonably af- forded. Mutual benevolence is, therefore, the fundamen- tal moral obligation between man and man, and is of universal application. Therefore, ^^All things whatsoever ye icould that men should do to you, do ye even so to them.'' This is the law of righteousness. Man has no right to squander the powers which God has given him, but he is under obligation to develop these, in order to promote his own happiness and that of others. To promote his own happiness, it is neces- sary that he guard his life, liberty, and reputation, pre- MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, 483 serve his health, protect his property, and promote his physical, intellectual, and moral perfection. The prepa- ration which enables him to advance his own interests, best qualifies him to promote the welfare of others. The family relations of husband and wife, parents and children, brothers and sisters, involve peculiar and sacred obligations. Special duties are implied in the relations of teacher and pupil, pastor and people, employer and employee. Man is also under certain obligations to society, to his government, and to the world at large. Our obligations to God are based upon the relations which we sustain to Him as our Creator and Benefac- tor. In this case, the inequality of the parties modifies the statement of the law of benevolence. It would not do to say. Whatsoever we would that God should do for us, we should do for him; for we desire His help and protection, and many other favors which we are una- ble to render Him. But certain things are due to God from man. We should show repentance towards God for past sins by confessing and forsaking them. We should have faith in His mercy and constant goodness. We should exhibit reverence for God in view of His power, wisdom, and holiness. Above all, we should ren- der obedience to His righteous laws. The science of Ethics may, however, be well under- stood by those who refuse to reduce its principles to prac- tice. Virtue is not identical with knowledge, as Socrates taught, since man does not always do what seems to him to be morally right. The will does not always choose the greatest apparent good. A man may know that virtue is the highest good, and that it will bring the greatest reward; and yet, with this knowledge before his mind, and w4th his eyes open to the consequences of evil, he may follow the lead of his appetites and passions, 484 PSYCHOLOGY. and pursue the path of sin and death. Justly may lie apply to himself the language of the poet, *^ Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor." His will, in yielding to the solicitations of appetite and desire, refuses to obey the voice of reason and con- science. His moral nature is disordered, and he is brought into captivity to the law of sin and death ; yet he is free to seek what he so much needs — the regener- ating energy of the Spirit of the living God. 4^^'7 ^3 Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process. Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide Treatment Date: Oct. 2004 PreservationTechnologies A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111