t^f^mmyz-'^^^'^m^
Pass 'B F 1 3 '
Book__
GoipghtN?.
coEHUGHr DEjraste
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2011 with funding from
The Library of Congress
http://www.archive.org/details/empiricalrationaOOschu
EMPIKICai^ AiNiJ KATIONAL
PSYCHOLOGY n^.
'^030
J^
Embracing Cognitions, Feelings, and Volitions
BY
A. SCHUYLER, LL. D.
President of Baldwin University. Author of Principles
of Logic, and a Series of Mathematical Works
"How charming is divine Philosophy/
Not harsh and crabbed, as dull fools suppose,
But musical as is Apollo's lute,
And a perpetual Feast of nectared sweets,
Where no crude surfeit reigns.'"
VA]^ ANTWEEP, BEAGG & CO.
Cincinnati Kew York
/ft....
i\r
Eclectic Educational Series.
Dr. Schuyler's Works. .
Schuyler'' s Principles of Logic \0 n ^n^
Schuyler^ s Psychology. ^ '^
Schuyler^ s Complete Algebra.
Schuyler^ s Elements of Geometry.
Schuyler'' s Trigonometry and Mensuration (Pay^s Series).
Schuyler^ s Surveying and Navigation [Pay^s Series).
Descriptive List and Prices on Application.
Copyright
1882.. : .
Van Antwerp, Bragg & Co.
(ii)
PEEFAOE.
Psychology treats directly of Cognition, Feeling, and
Volition, and indirectly of Intellect, Sensibility, and Will.
Greater prominence is thus given to the phenomena of
the soul, with their conditions and laws, than to the
faculties implied by these phenomena.
Though much light has, no doubt, been thrown upon
Psychology by the investigations of Physiologists, — light
which the Psychologist should heartily welcome,— yet to
know any phenomenon, as it is in itself, we must study
it as revealed in consciousness. This is especially true
of the higher processes of thought. Thus, to understand
the nature of the reasoning process, it will not suffice to
examine the structure and functions of the nerves, the
ganglia, the brain, and the organs of sense, but we must
analyze the reasoning process itself as a known fact of
conscious experience.
The discussion of the Intuitions is introduced at an
early stage, since they afford the fundamental principles
for subsequent investigations. To defer the consideration
of fundamental principles to the last pages, as is com-
monly done, would embarass all preceding discussions.
AVhat would be thought of a writer on Geometry, who
should put his axioms on the last page of his book?
The difficulty of discussing fundamental princij^les is no
justification for such an arrangement, since any mind
mature enough to undertake the study of Psychology, is
certainly prepared to understand a clear presentation of
its first piinciples.
(ill)
iv PREFACE.
The elements involved in the act of Perception have
been discriminated with much care, and an attempt has
been made to exhibit clearly and correctly the nature of
this act. That a correct explanation of perception has
been given, will, it is believed, be admitted by those who
will carefully study this process in itself,- as revealed by
their own consciousness, and as developed in the chap-
ters pertaining to this subject.
The interesting phenomena of Eepresentation, embra-
cing Memory, Imagination, and Phantasy have been con-
cisely and clearly exhibited. Light has been thrown on
the Law of Association, especially in regard to the transi-
tion from one series of representations to another.
The processes of Elaboration have been fully and care-
fully treated. These phenomena can be understood only
by actually exhibiting them, and developing their laws.
No vague discourse about the logical processes will suffice
to make known their principles and laws, or to unfold
their philosophy.
The Aristotelian Logic will, perhaps, never be super-
seded; but, as is needful, it will be supplemented by
Modern Logic, which supplies the defects of the ancient,
while the ancient affords the necessary basis for the
modern. Each may, therefore, be regarded as the com-
plement or indispensable counterpart of the other.
The brief space of a few pages only has been given to
the subjects of Mood, Figure, and Eeduction. These sub-
jects, though not essential to Logic itself, are interesting
in themselves, and in their historical associations.
There is a growing demand, by progresssive teachers,
to have Logic presented in connection with Psychology.
To meet this demand, the third division of Part I. is
made a course of Logic. It is even more and better
than this, since it presents, not only the logical pro-
cesses themselves, but their philosophy, and the relation
PREFACE. V
of elaborated thought to the elementary phenomena of
the mind.
To those students who have not studied Logic, this
division will prove an ample course; and to those who
have, it will be a thorough review, giving broader views
of thought, and deeper insight into the abstruse pro-
cesses of the intellectual powers.
The phenomena of Feeling and Yolition, with their
corresponding faculties of Sensibility and Will, have, in
the second and third parts, been as fully discussed as
the limits of the book w^otild permit. It is believed that
these parts, though necessarily concise, will be not only
interesting, but clear and thorough.
The value of philosophic studies can scarcely be over-
estimated, and it has been maintained by philosophers of
opposing schools. John Stuart Mill, in his Examination
of Hamilton's Philosophy, Vol. I, page 10, says, ^'That
a true Psychology is the indispensable scientific basis of
morals, of politics, of the science and art of education;
that the difficulties of Metaphysics lie at the root of all
science; that these difficulties can only be quieted by be-
ing resolved ; and that until they are resolved, positively
if possible, but at any rate negatively, we are never as-
sured that any human knowledge, even physical, stands
on solid foundations."
Sir Wm. Hamilton, Metaphysics^ Lecture 11.^ says: ''In
the compass of our experience, we distinguish two series
of facts, — the facts of the external or material world,
and the facts of the internal world, or world of intelli-
gence. . . . The phenomena of the material world are
subjected to immutable laws, and are produced and re-
produced in the same invariable succession, and manifest
only the blind force of a mechanical necessity.
'' The phenomena of man are, in part, subjected to the
laws of the external universe. As dependent upon a
vi PREFACE.
bodily organization, as actuated by sensual propensities
and animal wants, he belongs to matter; and in this re-
spect, he is the slave of necessity. Eut what man holds
of matter does not make up his personality. They are his,
not he; man is not an organism, — he is an intelligence
served by organs. For, in man, there are tendencies, —
there is a law, — which continually urge him to prove
that he is more powerful than the nature by which he
is surrounded and jDcnetrated. He is conscious to him-
self of faculties not comprised in the chain of physical
necessity; his intelligence reveals prescriptive principles
of action, absolute and universal, in the law of duty,
and a liberty capable of carrying that law into effect, in
opposition to the solicitations, the impulses of his mate-
rial nature
^'Now, the study of Philosophy operates in three ways
to establish that assurance of human liberty which is
necessary for a rational belief in our moral nature in a
moral world, and in a moral Euler of that world.
"In the first place, an attentive consideration of the
phenomena of mind is requisite in order to a luminous
and distinct apprehension of liberty as a fact or datum
of the intelligence. For though, without philosophy, a
natural conviction of free agency lives and works in the
recesses of every human mind, it requires a process of
philosophical thought to bring this conviction to clear
consciousness and scientific certainty
'' In the second place, a profound philosophy is neces-
sary to obviate the difilculties which meet us whenever
we attempt to explain the possibility of this fact, and to
prove that the datum of liberty is not a mere illu-
sion
" In the third place, the study of mind is necessary to
counterbalance and correct the influence of the study of
matter; and this utility of Metaj)hysics rises in propor-
FREFA CE. vii
tion to the progress of the natural sciences, and to the
greater attention which they engross."
Psychology, including Logic, constitutes the essential
basis of a philosophic course. However valuable a work
on Metaphysics, as that of Ferrier's or Bowne's may be,
it requires, as the indispensable condition of its profita-
ble perusal, a preliminary knowl^edge of the phenomena
and laws of mind.
A few words in reference to the time and method of
study may not be amiss. In case the school year is
divided into three terms, as is now usually the case,
Psychology ought to be studied by the senior class of
the Public Schools, or by the junior or senior class of
the Colleges, the first and second terms, and the History
of Philosophy the third term; but if the teacher prefers.
Psychology can be taken the first term by itself, and, in
connection with the History of Philosophy, the second
and third terms.
For valuable critical suggestions, thanks are due to
B. A. Hinsdale^ late President of Hiram College, now
Superintendent of Public Instruction, Cleveland, Ohio,
who kindly consented to read the manuscript.
This work is presented to the public with the hope
that it will be profitable, not only to the student, but
to the general reader who may desire to understand the
facts and laws of mind; that it will prove especially in-
teresting to those who may wish to revive their knowl-
edge of Philosophy; and that thus the time and labor
and thought bestowed in its preparation may not be
wanting in good results.
CO^'TENTS.
PAGE
Introduction 11
PAKT I,— COGNITION AND THE INTELLECT.
DIVISION I.— ACQUISITION.
CHAPTER
I. — Consciousness 19
-IL— Eeflection , '.29
III. — Rational Intuition — General View 39
IV. — Intuitions Continued — Non-Dynamical Conditions. . 46
V. — Intuitions Continued — Dynamical Conditions. ... 59
VI. — Intuitions Continued — The Ego and Personal Identity. 75
VII. -Sensation 89
VIII. — Perception — General View 98
IX — Perception through Smell and Taste 102
X. — Perception through Touch and Hearing . . . . . 107
XL — Perception through Sight 113
XII. — Acquired Perception 129
XIII. — Development and Product of Perception 139
XIV. — Errors in Perception ... 145
XV. — Passivity and Activity and Conditions 152
XVI. — Theories of Perception — Ancient, Medieval, Cartesian. 156
XVII. — Theories of Perception Continued — Locke, Berkeley,
Hume ... 165
XVIII. — Theories of Perception Continued — Kant, Reid, Ham-
ilton 174
XIX. — Theories of Perception Concluded — Mill and Porter . 184
(viii)
CONTENTS. ix
DIVISION II.- REPRESENTATION.
CHAPTER PAGE
I. — General View of Kepresentation 195
II. — Laws of Kepresentadon 202
III. — Peculiarities of Roif^esentation 210
IV.— Memory . . ./. 218
V. — Imagination m 228
VI.— Phantasy 232
DIVISION III.— ELABORATION.
I. — Elaboration — General View 241
II. — Classification and Conception — Preliminary Discus-
sion 245
III. — Classification and Conception — General Discussion . 252
IV. — Classification and Conception— Names, Classes, Concepts 261
V. — Classification and Conception — Order of Procedure in
Classification 268
VI. — Quantity of Concepts . 275
VII.— Quality of Concepts ....'. 282
VIII.— Relation of Concepts .291
IX. — Judgment — General View 299
X. — Categorical Judgments — Classification and Relation . 305
XL — Categorical Judgments — Distribution and Conversion 312
XII. — Conditional Judgments 318
XIII. — Deductive Reasoning — Immediate Arguments. . . . 322
XIV. — Deductive Reasoning — Mediate Arguments .... 325
XV. — Deductive Reasoning — Categorical Syllogisms . . . . 332
XVI. — Deductive Reasoning— Conditional Syllogisms . . . 338
XVII. — Deductive Reasoning — Formal Fallacies 347
XVIII. — Deductive Reasoning — Material Fallacies 357
XIX. — Deductive Reasoning — Mood of Syllogisms .... 365
XX. — Deductive Reasoning — Figure of the Syllogism. . . 369
XXL — Deductive Reasoning — Reduction to the First Figure . 379
XX 1 1. — Inductive Reasoning — Mathematical Induction. . . 382
XXIII. — Inductive Reasoning — Logical Induction — Subsidia-
ries 388
XXIV. — Inductive Reasoning — Logical Induction 394
XXV. — Inductive Reasoning — The Ground of Induction . . 402
XX VL— Modern Logic . 409
CONTENTS,
PAET II.— FEELING AND THE SENSIBILITY.
CHAPTER PAGE
I. — Physical Feelings 417
IL— Vital Feelings 427
HI. — Psychical Feelings — Emotions 432
IV. — Psychical Feelings — Affections 441
V. — Psychical Feelings — Desire and Aversion ..... 455
PAET III.— VOLITION AND THE WILL.
I. — General View of Volition 463
IL— Freedom of the Will 469
III. — Moral Eesponsibility ............ 477
PSYCHOLOGY.
INTRODUCTION.
Psychology is the science which treats of the phe-
nomena and the faculties of the human soul. It treats
directly of phenomena and indirectly of faculties, since
faculties are known only through phenomena.
The aim of psychology is to ascertain the phenomena
of the human soul, to analyze and classify these phe-
nomena, and to determine their conditions and laws.
The utility of psychology is evident from the fact that
it supplies the fundamental principles for all the sciences
pertaining to man as an intellectual, moral, social, and
religious being; that it cultivates the mind loj calling its
faculties into vigorous exercise, thus contributing to our
perfection and consequently to our happiness; and that
it checks the evils resulting from too exclusive pursuit
of physical science, by directing our attention to our
spiritual nature, moral dignity, and probable destiny.
The means for psychological study may be divided
into two classes — principal and collateral.
The principal means for psychological study are con-
sciousness, reflection, and rational intuition.
Consciousness is the immediate knowledge which the
soul has of its phenomena. It is the primary means of
(11)
12 PSYCHOLOGY.
collecting the facts pertaining to the operations of the
various faculties of the soul.
Reflection is the turning back of the thoughts to the
consideration of psychical phenomena. It is the means
by which the phenomena of the soul are analyzed, com-
pared, identified or discriminated, and classified. Thus,
by reflection, psychical phenomena are found to be redu-
cible to three classes — cognitions, or acts of knowledge;
feelings, or sensations, instincts, appe'tites, emotions, af-
fections, and desires; and volitions, or choices.
Rational intuition is the immediate apprehension of
necessary truth. It is the means by which the soul ap-
prehends the necessity of the conditions and laws of its
phenomena. Thus, by rational intuition, the phenomena
of the soul are referred to causes capable of producing
them; for, these phenomena, beginning in time, are not
eternal. They can not bring themselves into existence,
since they can not act before they exist.
A faculty of the soul is its capability of doing a cer-
tain act, or its susceptibility of being in a certain state.
Hence, the faculties of the soul, its powers and sus-
ceptibilities, are, as inferred from its phenomena, like-
wise reducible to three classes — the Intellect^ or faculty
of cognition; the Sensibility, or susceptibility of feeling;
and the Will, or power of volition.
It is, therefore, evident that the intimate relation of
the psychical phenomena, the cognitions, feelings, and
volitions, implies the intimate relation of the faculties,
the intellect, the sensibility, and the will, and the unity
of the soul, their common origin; that these phenomena,
though fleeting, imply, from their continued succession
and spiritual character, a permanent spiritual subject,
variously called the soul, spirit, mind, I, self, or ego, en-
dowed with the faculties of intellect, sensibility, and will.
The collateral means for psychological studj^ are the
INTR OD UCTION, 13
sciences of Biology, Anthropology, Sociology, Anatomy,
and Physiology.
Biology is the science of life. It treats of the phenom-
ena manifested by the living beings of the two organic
kingdoms, vegetable and animal. As a science, Biology
is fundamental and comprehensive. It throws great light
on all the other sciences pertaining to living beings.
Anthropology is the science which treats of man ac-
cording to the methods of Natural History. It consid-
ers him as a complex being, consisting of body, animal
life, and soul or spirit. It views man in a general way,
as to race, sex, age, heredity, and the reciprocal influ-
ence of body and soul. It studies him as affected by
climate, education, religion, government, employment,
and accidental circumstances, leaving the more profound
and scientific study of the physical and spiritual natures
of man to distinct and special sciences.
Sociology is the science of society. It treats of man
in social organizations — the family, society, the church,
or the state. Man's capabilities are known by his man-
ifestations .and achievements. In war, he has exhibited
ambition and patriotism, courage and cruelty, genius
and rapacity. In peace, he has cultivated science, liter-
ature, and art; he has engaged in agriculture, in the
mechanic arts, and in commerce; he has founded gov-
ernments, organized religions, and developed the learned
professions.
Anatomy and Physiology are related sciences which
treat of the structure and functions of man's physical
organism. A knowledge of these sciences is a valuable
preparation for the study of mind; since the body, es-
pecially the nervous system, sustains vital relations to
the phenomena of the soul. In the perception of exter-
nal objects, the mind uses the organs of the five senses.
In executing its volitions, it employs the body as its in-
14 PSYCHOLOGY.
strument; but in the higher operations of thought, it
seems to act independently of all material organs, exhib-
iting phenomena totally unlike the properties of matter.
In endeavoring to ascertain the relations existing be-
tween the body and soul, the approved methods of
science — observation, experiment, induction, and deduc-
tion — are to be employed; and though nothing is to be
assumed without evidence, yet it may be allowed, in the
course of an investigation, to form an hypothesis, with
the understanding that it is merely provisional, and that
it must stand or fall according as it is confirmed or re-
futed by subsequent investigations.
It is legitimate to endeavor to ascertain what physi-
cal conditions, if any, are the invariable antecedents or
consequents, as the case may be, of certain psychical
states; but it is not legitimate to assume, without proof,
except provisionally, that every psychical phenomenon
must have fixed physical antecedents or consequents.
Though our knowledge of the body has already en-
larged our knowledge of the conditions of the phenom-
ena of the soul, and may be expected to do so more
and more as our investigations are continued, yet it is
to be remembered that we can understand neither per-
ception, nor representation, nor elaboration, by examin-
ing the nerves with the Physiologist, nor by feeling the
head after the manner of the Phrenologist, but only by
studying these processes themselves, in the light of con-
sciousness, by the aid of reflection and rational intuition.
The Rules for Investigation are the following:
1. Employ the principal and collateral means of study.
2. Take, as fundamental facts, the psychical phenomena
given in consciousness, all the phenomena, and nothing
but the phenomena.
3. Carefully observe, analyze, compare, and classify
the phenomena.
INTR OD UCTION.
15
4. Determine the conditions and laws of the phenomena.
5. Eefer phenomena essentially alike to the same fac-
ulty, and those essentially unlike to different faculties.
6. Make an accurate register of the results.
In order to present a bird's-eye view of the subject,
we subjoin a summary classification of the phenomena
of the human soul, also a classification of the faculties
implied by these phenomena. These classifications give
an outline of the subject, and they will be useful for
reference, as we pursue our investigations.
It will be observed that certain phenomena and the
corresponding faculties have the same names, a defect
unavoidable on account of the imperfection of language.
The word JReason is used to denote the reasoning power.
It is sometimes used to denote the logical power in gen-
eral, also the power of rational intuition.
Cognition
CLASSIFICATION OF PSYCHICAL PHENOMENA.
c^ 1-. ^- I Consciousness.
Subjective { ^^^^^^^^^^^_
Rational — Intuition.
Obj ective— Perception.
Memory.
Feeling
Volition.
Acquisition
Representation
Elaboration
Physical feeling
- Vital feeling
Psychical feeling
Imagination.
Phantasy.
Conceiving.
Judging.
Reasoning.
Sensation.
Instinct.
Appetite.
Of rest or fatigue.
Of vigor or languor.
Of health or sickness.
Emotions.
AffectionSo
Desires.
Solicitation— the antecedent of volition.
Volition — the choice or decision.
Execution — the consequent of volition.
16
PSYCHOLOGY,
CLASSIFICATION OF THE PSYCHICAL FACULTIES.
Subjective
( Consciousness.
Intellect
Acquisitive faculties
Representative faculties
Sensibility
^ Logical faculties
Physical sensibility
Vital sensibility
Psychical sensibility
\ Reflection.
Rational— Intuition.
Objective— Perception.
Memory.
Imagination.
Phantasy.
Conception.
Judgment.
Reason.
Sensation.
Instinct.
Appetite.
Of rest or fatigue.
Of vigor or languor.
Of health or sickness.
Susceptibility of emotion.
Susceptibility of affection.
Susceptibility of desire.
Will
Passive susceptibility— as solicited by motive.
Elective power— ability to choose or decide.
Executive energy — as exerted in execution.
Eeview. — Eeproduceon blackboard, expand 6 and 7, and elucidate.
1. Definition.
2. Aim
Introduction
3. Utility
4. Means of study
1st. Principal
2d. Collateral
1st.
2d.
5. Rules for investigation -i. ^^^
5th.
6th.
6. Classification of psychical phenomena.
7. Classification of psychical faculties.
PART I.
COaNITION AND THE INTELLECT.
Psy.-2. (17)
DIVISION I.
ACQUISITION AND THE ACQUISITIVE FACULTIES.
CHAPTEE I.
CONSCIOUSNESS.
1. Consciousness as an act defined and character-
ized.— Consciousness is tlie immediate knowledge which
the soul has of its phenomena. It is empirical^ since it
apprehends its object as contingent, and not as nec-
essary. It is intuitive^ since it reaches its object di-
rectly, and not through any medium, as the senses, the
memory, or the reasoning processes. It is, therefore,
empirical intuition.
2. Consciousness implied by all psychical phenom-
ena. — Cognition implies consciousness ; for if I know, I
know that I know, since if I do not know that I know,
I do not know\ In like manner, it can be proved that
feeling implies consciousness, and that volition implies
consciousness. Hence the absurdity of the opinion that
consciousness is impossible, as held by M. Comte, who
says in reference to the consciousness of intellectual ac-
tivity, ^'In order to observe, your intellect must pause
from its activity; yet it is this very activity you want
to observe. If you can not effect the pause, you can
not observe ; if you do effect it, there is nothing to ob-
serve." Comte's Positive Philosophy, by H. Martineau, page
33. But instead of its being impossible to be conscious
of knowing, it is impossible to know without being con-
(19)
20 PSYCHOLOGY,
scions of knowing. Consciousness is involved in know-
ing, as an essential element.
3. Consciousness an intellectual act. — Though con-
sciousness is implied by all psychical phenomena, whether
cognitions, feelings, or volitions, yet it is itself an act
of the intellect. The etymology of the Avord conscious-
ness^ from con and sciOj indicates its meaning — that
along with knowing an object, I know also the know-
ing. In case the object of consciousness is a phenome-
non of the sensibility, the consciousness of the feeling is
scarcely distinguishable from the feeling. Thus, if to be
conscious of pain is not identical w^ith the feeling of pain,
it is to be aware of the feeling. The faculties of the soul
are so intimately related, that they do not act independ-
ently of one another. Knowledge affords the condition
of desire and affection; and both knowledge and feeling
precede and accompany volition.
4. Consciousness as a faculty defined and considered.
— Consciousness is the capability of knowing our psychical
acts or states. If the soul is conscious of its cognitions,
feelings, and volitions, it has the faculty of being con-
scious of these phenomena, and this faculty is called
consciousness. The term consciousness., then, is used to
denote both an act and the faculty to which the act is
referred. As an act, it is the immediate cognizance
which the soul takes of its phenomena, and is implied,
as a necessary condition, by the phenomena of cognition-,
feeling, or volition. As a faculty, it is the capability of
immediately knowing psychical phenomena, and is im-
plied by the act of consciousness, as a necessary condition.
5. Objects of consciousness psychical phenomena.—
The objects of consciousness are psychical phenomena,
actual and present. The soul is conscious of all its phe-
nomena — all appearances; for, if there is an appearance,
tliat appearance is known or realized, otherwise it is not
CONSCIOUSNESS. 21
an appearance; but a realization of the appearance is
consciousness.
The object of consciousness is nothing else than a psy-
chical phenomenon. In the first place, we are not con-
scious of an external object, as a house. If we perceive
a house, we are conscious of the perception, but not of
the house. Consciousness is immediate knowledge; but
the knowledge of an external object is mediate, since it
is derived from the sensation w^iich the object causes.
In the second place, we are not conscious of the soul,
nor of the soul as knowing, feeling, or willing, but of
the knowing, feeling, and willing, as phenomena. The
necessity of the soul, as the subject of these phenomena,
is apprehended by rational intuition, as will be more
fully shown hereafter.
6. Processes which are not objects of consciousness. —
In saying that the soul is conscious of all its phenomena,
we do not affirm that it is conscious of all its processes.
Phenomena are processes that appear. The soul is con-
scious of these processes, otherwise they could not be
phenomena, that is, could not appear.
There are, however, other processes that are not phe-
nomena; and since these do not appear, their existence
is not an object of consciousness, but a matter of infer-
ence. This is ultimately true of consciousness itself,
which, though an act, is not a distinct phenomenon, but
an element of a phenomenon. For, if the act of conscious-
ness is a distinct phenomenon, it appears, and is, there-
fore, an object of consciousness. That is, in being con-
scious of a phenomenon, we should, on this supposition,
be conscious of the consciousness, and in like manner,
we should be conscious of this second consciousness, and
so on, which involves an infinite series of acts of con-
sciousness, an impossibility in finite time. Granting that,
by special efi'ort, an indefinite number of acts of con-
22 PSYCHOLOGY,
sciousness might thus take place, yet, in general, the
phenomenon is the object of attention, but not the con-
sciousness of it, much less the consciousness of the con-
sciousness of it, and so on.
There are other psychical processes, inferred from their
effects, which are unknown to consciousness. These pro-
cesses have, by certain philosophers, been inconsistently
called latent modifications of consciousness, and by others,
unconscious cerebrations. They are latent processes, whether
purely psychological, physiological, or mixed.
7. Idea and ideation. — The j)henomenon which is an
object of consciousness develops and crystallizes into an
idea of the phenomenon. The development of the idea
is called ideation. The idea may afterwards be recalled
in the memory, but not the original phenomenon. The
idea when recalled is an object of consciousness.
8. Consciousness simultaneous with its object. — In
the first place, the consciousness of a phenomenon can not
be antecedent to that phenomenon, since we should, in that
case, be conscious of that which has no existence, *which
is impossible. In the next place, the consciousness of a
phenomenon can not be subsequent to that phenomenon,
since, before the consciousness, the supposed j)lienomenon
could not appear, and hence would not be a phenome-
non ; that is, consciousness is essential to the phenome-
i^on, and is, therefore, not subsequent to it. The formula
of consciousness, I know that I know, does not imply
that I first know, then, after that, know that I know;
for, if I first know, without being conscious that I know,
then, at the first instant of knowing, before the con-
sciousness of the knowledge, I know, without knowing
that I know, which is absurd.
The view that the consciousness of a psychical phe-
nomenon is subsequent to that phenomenon, makes con-
sciousness depend on memory. But if we are not con-
CONSCIO USNESS. 23
scions of a phenomenon at the instant of its occurrence,
we should know nothing of it at that instant, and, there-
fore, have nothing to remember; hence, memory itself
would be impossible, and consciousness, thus depending
on memor}^, would also be impossible; but as both mem-
ory and consciousness are facts, the theory that con-
sciousness is subsequent to its object, which annihilates
both memory and consciousness, can not be true.
We have now found that consciousness of a phenom-
enon is neither antecedent to that phenomenon nor sub-
sequent to it; hence, the consciousness of a phenomenon
is simultaneous Avith that phenomenon.
9. Consciousness a logical consequent of its object. —
Though consciousness of a phenomenon is simultaneous
with the phenomenon, yet the phenomenon involves the
consciousness as its logical consequent, otherwise it could
not be a ^^li^nomenon, that is, could not appear; and
the consciousness implies the phenomenon as its logical
antecedent, otherwise there would be nothing of which
to be conscious.
That a logical consequent may be chronologically sim-
ultaneous with its logical antecedent, may be illustrated
by the equation.
y=f(x).
This equation is read, y is equal to a function of x^
and signifies that the value of y depends on that of x,
so that, if X changes, changing the value of /Or), y
changes, so as always to be equal to f{xy
Now, let X change, the change in x changing the value
of /(x). The change in f{x) is simultaneous with the
change in :r, otherwise f{x) has the same value while x
has different values, which is impossible.
As x changes, the change in x is followed by a change
in y ; but the word foUoiced is used in a logical^ not in
a chronological sense; for the change in y is simultaneous
24 PSYCHOLOGY,
with the change in x, since if y could remain, with-
out change, a moment after the change in x^ then, for
that moment, y would not be equal to /(x), which is
contrary to the sup230sition that y is always equal to
f(x). Hence, the change in y, though logically conse-
quent to the change in x, is chronologically simultane-
ous with that change.
This will serve to illustrate the possibility of the fact
that logically consciousness may be the consequent of a
phenomenon, while chronologically the phenomenon and
the consciousness of it may be simultaneous.
10. Kinds of consciousness — natural, ethical, and ab-
normal. — 1st. Natural consciousness is that ordinary form
of consciousness which is common to all healthy minds.
It is simply immediate knowledge of psychical phenom-
ena, whether cognitions, feelings, or volitions.
2d. Ethical consciousness is that form of conscious-
ness which is induced by those who practice self-inspec-
tion in view of ascertaining their moral condition. It
indicates the controlling influence of conscience, and a
sensitiveness with regard to right and wrong. The de-
velopment of this form of consciousness is mainly due
to the influence of moral and religious systems. Ethical
consciousness is, strictly speaking, reflection applied to
moral states.
3d. Abnormal consciousness is that form of consciousness
which is exhibited by bashful persons, who imagine that
others are noticing their awkwardness. They are said to
be self-conscious.
11. Varying intensity of consciousness. — Consciousness
may vary in intensity from obscurity and indistinctness,
through all the intermediate degrees, to clearness and dis-
tinctness. The degree of intensity de]3ends largely upon
the condition of the body, the character of the mind, age,
culture, and the concentration of attention.
CONSCIO USNESS, 25
12. General conditions of consciousness. — These are
a living subject, a faculty of consciousness, and psychical
phenomena.
1st. A living subject is a condition of consciousness; for
consciousness implies a being who is conscious.
2d. A faculty of consciousness is a condition of the act
of consciousness; for without the faculty, or capability
of being conscious, the act would be impossible.
3d. A psychical phenomenon is a condition of conscious-
ness; for psychical phenomena are the only objects of
consciousness ; hence, in the absence of these phenomena,
there can be no consciousness, since there would bo
nothing of which to be conscious.
13. Conditions of vivid consciousness.^ These are the
general conditions, above named, also varying psychical
phenomena, abstraction, attention, and cultivation.
1st. The general conditions of consciousness are condi-
tions of vivid consciousness; for whatever is essential to
consciousness itself, is essential to any degree of con-
sciousness, and hence, to vivid consciousness.
2d. Varying psychical pjhenomena are conditions of vivid
consciousness; for a continuance in a state the same in
kind throughout, would be attended by a decreasing de-
gree of intensity of consciousness, tending to total un-
consciousness. Thus, the miller is scarcely conscious of
hearing the noise of the mill, though if it made an un-
usual noise, he w^ould at once be clearly conscious of the
chan, are congruents. Both are true, if b is less than a;
both false, if b is equal to a; one true and the other
false, if 6 is greater than a.
Consec[uence. From mere congruence, the truth or
NON-DYNAMTCAL CONDITIONS. 53
falsity of either of two propositions can not be inferred
from either the truth or the falsity of the other.
(3) The law of conflictives. Two conflictive propositions
can not both he true. For, whether contraries or contra-
dictories, they are incompatible ; hence, if both were true,
the truth of each would involve the falsity of the other,
and both would be false ; then each is both true and false,
or a truth is. a falsity, which contradicts the negative
part of the law of indentity — that a thing is not any
thing else than itself. Thus, the propositions, this tree
is an oak, and the same tree is a walnut, are con-
flictives, and both can not be true.
Consequences. 1) If one of two conflictives is true,
the other is false. 2) Two true propositions can not be
conflictive. 3) All truths exist in harmony. 4) A prop-
osition is false, if it involves the conflictive of a truth.
The law of conflictives is commonly called the law of
contradiction. It follows as a corollary from the nega-
tive part of the law of identity. As a law of the genus
conflictives^ it is applicable to both species, contraries
and contradictories, w^hich also have special laws.
(4) The law of contraries. Two contrary propositions can
not both he true, hut may both he false. For since they are
conflictives, both can not be true; and since they are
contraries, they are not universally inclusive; hence,
other cases are possible, and both may be false. Thus,
the propositions, a is equal to h, and a is greater than
6, are contraries; both can not be true, but both may
be false, since a may be less than h.
Consequences. 1) The truth of either of two contra-
ries involves the falsity of the other. 2) The falsity of
either of two contraries does not involve the truth of the
other.
(5) The law of contradictories. Two contradictory prop-
ositions can not both be true, nor both false. For, since
54 PSYCHOLOGY,
they are conflictives, both can not be true; and since
they are contradictories, they are universally inclusive;
hence, no other cases are possible, and both can not be
false. Thus, the propositions, a and 6, are equal, and a
and h are unequal, are contradictories; both can not be
true, nor both false.
Consequences. 1) One of two contradictories is true
and the other false. 2) The truth of either of two
contradictories involves the falsity of the other. 3) The
falsity of either of two contradictories involves the truth
of the other.
The law of contradictories is commonly called the law
of excluded middle, since any middle supposition is ex-
cluded.
This law has a special application to the two proposi-
tions, one affirming that an object of a genus belongs to
one of the two contradictory species of a genus, and the
other affirming that it belongs to the other species.
Thus, let A be a genus divided into the two contradic-
tory species, B and (7, and let D be an object in A.
Then, the propositions, D is ^, and D is 6\ are contra-
dictories; hence, D is either B or C; if it is one, it is not
the other; and if it is not one, it is the other. Thus,
since the genus propositions may be divided into the
contradictory species, true propositions and false propo-
sitions, any proposition is either true or false; if it is
true, it is not false; and if it is false, it is not true.
What is involved in a true proposition is also true; but
what is involved in a false proposition may be either
trne or false.
The truth of the laws of harmony has been denied
by certain philosophers, notably by Heraclitus and Hegel.
Thus, Ferrier, in his History of Greek Philosophy, says,
in his article on Heraclitus: ''Opposite determinations
are not only compatible in the same object, but they are
J.
NON-DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 55
even necessary to the constitution of every object. . . .
How does a thing get out of one state into another?
Because, says Heraclitus, in being in the state in which
it is, it is already out of it. Being in it is being out of
it; and being out of it is being in another The two
moments, the moment of being in it, and the moment
of being out of it, are one, and constitute one indivisible
conception of becoming
" Suppose the changing states of an object to be rep-
resented by A^ B, (7, D, etc. The state A appears, and
in appearing disappears. A's disappearance is the ap-
pearance of Bj which, in like manner, disappears in the
very act of appearing; but B's disappearance is the ap-
pearance of (7, which no sooner appears than it vanishes
into D, and so on. Kow, here the moments of being
and not being are inseparable. A's being is A's not-
being; A's not-being is B's being; B's being is ^'s not-
being; B's not-being is C's being, and so on.
"Let us try the other alternative — A's being is not
A's not-being, because, on this supposition being and
not-being are held asunder as separate conceptions; and
neither is A's not-being, or disappearance, B's being, or
appearance. Our supposition is, that appearance, or be-
ing, and disappearance, or not-being, are separate con-
cepts, and, therefore, we must not suppose that the dis-
appearance of A is the appearance of B What,
then, happens ? This happens, that there is an interval
between the appearance or being of A and the appear-
ance or being of B, in which the thing is in no state at
all And this is the ridiculous and contradictor v
conclusion to which we are driven, if we suppose change
to take place by leaps, and that being and not-being, in-
stead of being mere elements of one indivisible concep-
tion, are themselves distinct and completed conceptions."
This view arises from a misconception of what the
56 PSYCHOLOGY,
laws of harmony require. Absolute being and absolute
not-being are certainly incompatible; so also are the
being of A^ and, at the same instant, the not-being of
A; but the not-being of A is not incompatible with the
being of B^ though not identical with it, since in place
of the being of B^ there might be the being of (7, or of
D, or of E^ etc.
There is truth in the view of Ileraclitus that things
do not remain for a definite time in a fixed state, and
then change by a sudden leap. The change is continu-
ous, though the rate of change may be variable. But
it is not true that a thing is in a state and not in that
state precisely at the same instant. The thing, however,
does not rest in that state, but passes through it.
It is easy to reduce the Heraclitean view to an ab-
surdity. Thus, to take a case chosen by Ferrier himself,
let the temperature of water, at the successive moments,
as it is raised from the freezing to the boiling point, be
denoted by A, B, 0, D Then, according to Ferrier,
"^1'5 being is A's not-being; A's not-being is B's being;
B's being is B's not-being; B's not-being is C's being,
and so on." Also, according to this view, the water in
the state A is already out of it. " The two moments, the
moment of being in it, and the moment of being out of
it, are one;" and since "being out of it is , being in an-
other," the water is in the states A and B at the same
moment. For like reasons, it is, at the very same mo-
ment, in the states B and C, and, at precisely the same
moment, in the states D, BJ, etc., to the boiling jDoint.
Hence, the water is freezing and boiling at the very
same moment, and at the same time has all intermediate
temperatures !
This consequence is fairly deduced from the premises;
whereas the absurdity, that a body is, for a time, in no
state at all, was deduced by Ferrier on the false assump-
NON-D YNA MFC A L CON I) I TIONS. 57
tion that the law of identity requires us to hold that not-
A is incompatible with B.
The laws relating- to the sequence of thouglit, called the
laws of Reason and Consequent^ are the following:
(1) No judgment is warranted icithont a sufficient reason.
We know by intuition that a reason is necessary to war-
rant a judgment, but not what the reason is, unless the
judgment is intuitive.
(2) To affirm the reason is to affirm the consequent. Thus,
to affirm that A has the fever is to affirm that he is sick.
(3) To deny the consequent is to deny the reason. Thus,
to deny that A is sick is to deny that he has the fever.
" (4) To'deny a particular reason is not to deny the conse-
quent^ but to deny every reason is to deny the consequent.
Thus, to deny that A has the fever is not to deny that
he is sick, since he may have some other disease; but to
deny every disease is to deny that he is sick.
(5) To affirm the consequent is not- to affirm a specified
reason, but it is to affirm some reason. Thus, to affirm that
A is sick is not to affirm that he has the fever, but it is
to affirm that he has some disease.
The reason may be simply the reason of knowing —
ratio cognoscendi, or it m^j also be the reason of being — •
7^atio essendi ; but the laws of sequence are concerned only
with the reason, as the reason of knowing, and not with
the reason, as the reason of being, or the cause, which is
a dynamical condition.
2d. The special axioms of the various sciences may be
illustrated by those of Geometry, the fundamental axiom
of which is the following :
Either of two magnitudes identical in any respect is, in
that respect, a substitute for the other.
By remembering that similar magnitudes are identical
in form, that equivalent magnitudes are identical in ex-
tent, and that equal magnitudes are identical in both
58 PSYCHOLOGY.
form and extent, this fundamental axiom can be expli-
cated into three special axioms.
(1) The axiom of similarity. Either of two similar magni-
tudes is, in respect to form, a substitute for the other.
(2) The axiom of equivalencij. Either of two equivalent
magnitudes is, in respect to extent, a substitute for the other.
(3) The axiom of equality. Either of tico equal magni-
tudes is, in respect to both form and extent, a substitute for
the other.
The ordinary so-called axioms of Geometry may be
deduced from the above as corollaries, [See Schuyler s
Geometry, Art. 23.]
The act of substituting one thing for another, renders
an advance in thought possible; and substitution, ac-
cording to the axiom, is always legitimate when the two
magnitudes are identical in respect to the attributes
under consideration.
The special axioms may also be illustrated by the
fundamental axiom of Ethics — Benevolence is the primal
duty. The necessity of benevolence as the condition of
the performance of duty is a rational intuition.
CHAPTER V.
INTUITIONS CONTINUED.
1. Substance. — Substance is the substratum or under-
lying power which manifests conjoined properties or
qualities.
Attributes are the conjoined properties or qualities
which are manifested by a substance.
Attributes are known by experience. Substance itself
does not appear — it is not a phenomenon; but on the
condition of the manifestation of its attributes, its ne-
cessity is a2:)prehended by rational intuition. Attributes
imply substance as their ground or source; and sub-
stance involves attributes as the modes of its existence.
Attributes are not the manifestations of nothing, but of
underlying power capable of manifesting them. The
fact that attributes are conjoined in groups is explained
by their dependence on a common substance, but is
otherwise inexplicable. A substance must have attri-
butes, though not necessarily a specified attribute; for,
if it exist at all, it must exist in some way, and the modes
of its existence are its attributes. A substance, through
the action of other substances, may change its manifes-
tations ; but the substance of the material universe can
not be augmented or diminished, except, ab extra, by
supernatural agency, and the manifestation of attributes,
without substance, is impossible.
A tJwig is a substance with its conjoined attributes.
It is contained in space, and has date and duration in
(59)
60 PSYCHOLOOY,
time. The general attributes of things are quantity,
quality, relation, and modality.
A thing has quantity involving unitijj when regarded
as one whole; plurality ^ when regarded as a substance
with a multiplicity of attributes; totality ^ when regarded
as the sum of the substance and conjoined attributes.
A thing has quality involving existence and identity.
Existence as opposed to non-existence involves reality as
opposed to non-reality^ something as opposed to nothimj^
or entity the negation of non-entity. It is not possible
for a thing to be and, at the same time, not to be.
Identity, or the fact that a thing is itself and nothing
else, involves peculiarity, or the positive attributes char-
acteristic of the thing, and particularity, or the negative
of the positive characteristics peculiar to other things,
though it may have other attributes in common with
those things.
A thing has relation, involving the inherence of its
attributes in the substance in j^erjoetual time; causality,
when it is the cause of an effect, or the effect of a cause
in successive time; reciprocity, when acting or reacting
in simultaneous time.
Modality is the view of a thing tiUven by the mind as
influenced by the evidence relating to its reality. It
embraces the following couples: Necessity, when the
thing must be, or contingency, when the thing is actual
or possible, but not necessary; probability, when the ev-
idence of its reality overbalances the evidence of its
unreality, or inqjrob ability, when the evidence of its un-
reality overbalances the evidence of its reality; possibility,
when the evidence does not absolutely exclude its real-
ity, or impossibility, when the evidence absolutely ex-
cludes its reality; certainty, wlien the evidence excludes
doubt, or uncertainty, when the evidence does not ex-
clude doubt.
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, 01
Substance is divided into matter and spirit. Mailer
is an extended substance. It occupies space, and is
contained in space, and continues in time. As occupy-
ing space, it has magnitude, and form, and ultimate in-
compressibility. As contained in space, it has location
and mobility. As continuing through a period of time,
it has date and duration. Sjnrit is that sul)stance which
is endowed with intellect, sensibility, or will. If a spirit
does not occupy space, it is nevertheless contained in
space, and has locality and mobility. As contained in
time, a spirit has date and duration.
It follows, from the fundamental laws of thought, that
two congruent attributes may both be present in the
same thing, or both absent, or either may be present
and the other absent, and that the presence or absence
of either does not involve either the presence or the
absence of the other; that two conflictive attributes can
not both be present in the same thing, and that if
either is present, the other is absent; that two contrary
attributes can not both be present, but may both be ab-
sent, that the presence of either involves the absence of
the other, but tliat the absence of either does not involve
the presence of the other; that two contradictory at-
tributes can not both be present in the same thing,
nor both absent, that the presence of either involves the
absence of the other, and that the absence of either in-
volves the presence of the other.
2. Cause. — A cause is that which produces an event.
An event is that which comes to pass or takes place.
It is a change either in the elements of a thing or in
its relations to other things. An effect is an event pro-
duced by a cause.
1st. Kinds of causes. Aristotle distinguishes four kinds
of causes — formal, material, etiicient, and final.
The formal cause of a thing is the essential character-
62 PSYCHOLOGY,
istic which distinguishes it from other things. Thus,
the plan of a house is its formal cause, since it distin-
guishes it from other objects.
The material cause is the matter out of whicih a thing
is made. Thus, iron is the material cause of a stove.
The efficient cause is the force, energy, or exertion of
power which produces a thing, or changes its place or
state. Thus, a blow from a bat is an efficient cause
which will change the direction of a moving ball.
The final cause is the end or purpose which the thing
la designed to subserve. Thus, vision is the final cause
of the eye.
A cause is said to be imminent when it exists and
operates within the thing itself It is identical with the
formal cause.
A cause is transcendent^ or transeunt^ when it goes
beyond that in which it inheres and acts upon other
things, ab extra. It is identical with the efficient cause.
The word cause is sometimes used to denote simply
an immediate and invariable antecedent, exclusive of the
idea of efficiency. This view improperly identifies cause
with a non-dynamical condition, and resolves the rela-
tion of cause and effect into that of antecedence and
consequence, that is, into a law of sequence. Thus, a
law of nature is a general fact embracing a multitude
of particular facts. A law when known enables us to
predict the particular fact. It is not a cause of the
facts, but a cause of our knowing them — not a ratio
essendi, but a ratio cognoscendi.
The word cause is also used improperly in the sense
of instrument, as when it is said, a pistol was the cause
of the man's death. The pistol was the instrument,
while the one who fired it was the cause.
The signification of the word cause is sometimes en-
larged so as to embrace, not only that which is efficient
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, 63
in producing the event, but also all antecedent condi-
tions, wliether dynamical or non-dynamical; in short,
whatever is necessary to the occurrence of the event.
Thus, Mill says: "The cause, philosophically speaking, is
the sum total of the conditions, positive and negative,
taken together; the whole of the contingencies of every
description, which, being realized, the consequent invari-
ably follows."
It is best, however, to restrict the application of the
word cause to those dynamical conditions which conspire
to produce an event, and to employ the word conditions
to signify all necessary antecedents, both negative and
positive, includiag the cause.
According to this view, a cause is a condition, that is,
it is indispensable to the event; but a condition is not
necessarily a cause. Thus space is a condition but not a
cause of motion. The relation of cause to condition is
that of species to its genus. Cause is that dynamical
condition which produces an event.
Of the various senses of the word cause, the efficient
cause is the one which corresponds to the popular notion,
and this is the sense in wdnch the word is here used. By
using the w^ord condition to denote any necessary ante-
cedent, positive or negative, dynamical or non -dynamical,
and the word cause to denote the sum total of the d}"-
namical conditions, the philosophical and popular signifi-
cations of these terms are brought into harmony, which
is a result greatly to be desired.
Causes are to be distinguished from reasons, which as
intellectual, moral, or spiritual influences, are either the
grounds of inference or the motives for volition.
As grounds of inference, reasons influence the judg-
ment, and, according to their strength, warrant the con-
clusion as probable or certain.
As motives of volition, reasons, though causes of
64 PSYCHOLOGY,
desires, are conditions but not causes of volition. They
solicit, but do not compel volition. The cause of volition
is the will itself When several forces, as causes of mo-
tion, act upon a body, the eifect is the resultant of the
combination of causes; but when different ]notives solicit
action in different directions, the will, in deciding to
act in accordance with the solicitations of one of these
motives, sets aside the others. Volition is, therefore, not
the resultant of motives, but is the act of the will in
view of motives.
Effects, as events, are known by experience. An event
being known by experience, the conditional necessity of
a cause as that which produced the event, is known by
rational intuition. That there is a cause is known by
intuition; what the cause is, is known by investigation.
An event being given, its cause is necessary; but the
supposed event not being a reality, either the cause or
some other antecedent is not only not necessary, but
not actual; for if all the antecedent conditions, including
the cause, were actual, the event would be necessitated.
The cause is, therefore, not absolutely, but conditionally
necessary — it is necessary on the condition that there
is an event.
An event, as known by experience, is regarded as
contingent; but the cause and all other antecedent con-
ditions being given, the event is necessary; that is, the
character of the cause and other conditions determines
the nature of the effect; but since the cause is not abso-
lutely necessary, the event is not absolutely necessary.
2d. Laws of causality. These are the following:
(1) Every event must have a cause.
(2) The eff'ect is always complex,
(3) The cause is always complex.
(4) The complexity of the cause is proportionate to
the complexity of the effect.
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS, C5
(5) Like causes and conditions are followed by like
effects.
The first of these laws is, Every event must have a eause;
that is, every event is an effect. This law is sometimes
stated. Every effect must have a cause; but this state-
ment is tautological; for, by definition, an effect is that
which is produced by a cause; hence, the statement.
Every effect has a cause, is equivalent to the statement,
Every thing which is produced by a cause is produced
by a cause. But an event is that which comes to pass
or takes place; and though it is true that every event
has a cause, yet this is not implied in the word itself.
The theories concerning the origin of the first law, re-
garded as a causal judgment, are the following:
1) This judgment has its origin in the perception of cause.
The first objection to this theory is that we have no
such perception. This is now generally admitted. AVe
perceive an event, but not the energy which produces
the event.
The second objection is that, if we had such a percep-
tion, it could not, as a matter of experience, relating
only to particular cases, account for the universality and
necessity found in the judgment of causality — that every
event must have a cause.
2) The casual judgment has its origin in a consciousness
of causal efficiency. It is true, for example, that we are
conscious of the volition to move the hand ; that we are
conscious of making an effort to move it; and that we
are conscious of perceiving the hand move ; but we are
not conscious of the mode in which the effort produces
the effect. AYe know not what intermediate ai^encies
there may be between the effort and the effect.
In the consciousness of effort, we find that there is
something more in cause than mere antecedence. Here,
perhaps, Ave have consciousness, not of cause or iiower
Psy.-(}.
eQ PSYCHOLOGY.
itself, but of the exertion of the power in a partieular
case, though not of the mode of its producing the effect.
But this does not account for the universality aud ne-
cessity found in the judgment of causality.
3) TTie judgment of causality is attained by induct io7i.
According to this theory we find that events have causes
in particular cases, and hence infer that they have
causes in all cases. But as we do not perceive causes
in particular cases, as we have before seen, but only
succession, we have no facts to warrant the induction,
unless we resolve the relation of cause and effect, as
Hume has done, into that of antecedent and consequent.
But should we do so, the fact would be, that, so far as
observed, every event has an antecedent, or every event
is a consequent; hence, by induction, it is inferred that
all events, observed or unobserved, have antecedents.
But such inductions give us probability only, not neces-
sity. Hence, the causal judgment is not derived from
induction, since this judgment affirms, as we shall see,
the necessity of an efficient cause, not the probability
of an antecedent.
4) The principle of causality is derived from association
or custom. If this theory be true, the conviction is a
growth, and should have degrees; but the conviction is
as strong when the law is first apprehended as ever
afterwards. Association, custom, or habit can not ac-
count for a necessary principle.
5) The principle of causality is the product of a special
faculty. There is no necessity of referring the causal
judgment to a special faculty whose only office is to
affirm this judgment ; for rational intuition, which affirms
the necessity of other a priori truths, is competent to
affirm this also.
6) The principle of causality is derived from the expec-
tation of the uniformity of nature. But this expectation
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 67
gives only the probable, not the necessary; and does
not, therefore, give us the causal judgment.
7) The principle of causality is derived from the law of
contradiction. This is impossible; for, though under this
law, more properly called the law of conflictives, we can
reason from affirmation to denial, yet we can not reason
from denial to affirmation.
8) The principle of causality is derived from the law of
the conditioned. This is the opinion of Hamilton, who
derives the principle of causality, not from a potency^
but from an impotency of mind. "It is the inability
we experience of annihilating, in thought, an existence
in time past, in other words, our utter impotence of
conceiving its absolute commencement, that constitutes
and explains the whole phenomenon of causality." Bow-
en's Hamilton's Metaphysics, page 554.
It will be observed that Hamilton rejects an absolute
commencement on account of its inconceivability; but if an
absolute commencement is rejected, a cause for every event
must be admitted ; hence, there never was a time when
there was absolutely nothing, since, on that supposition,
there must have been an absolute commencement. Eter-
nal existence is, therefore, a reality ; but eternal exist-
ence is inconceivable. The mind is impotent to conceive
the eternal. Now, if we derive a principle from this
impotence, according to Hamilton's method, and reject
the fact of eternal existence, because it is inconceivable,
we must admit its contradictory — that there must have
been an absolute commencement. If an absolute com-
mencement can be rejected on the ground of its incon-
ceivability, and its contradictory affirmed — that every
event must have a cause, and hence that there must
have been eternal existence, then, certainly, we are au-
thorized to reject eternal existence on the ground of its
inconceivability^ and to affirm its contradictory — an abso-
08 PSY(JirOL()(JV.
lute commoricemont; hut this «(3t8 aside the hiw of enn-
sulity, whieh is, therefore, hy Haniilton's owd method,
shown not to be rieeessary. This method must, therefore,
he eharaeterized as "impotent," since it fails to account
for the necessity of the law of causality, as we are at
liberty to choose hetween the two inconceivahle alter-
natives. The universal rejection hy mankind of one of
these inconceivahle alternatives, and the acceptance of the
other, |)rov(^s that the ground of the rejection is not its
inconceiva})ility.
l)j Tlic inipossihllity of an ahHolutc conimenceynent is
krurwn hij rational intuition^ and hence the necessity of its
contradict or ij — t/uit encrfj event must /taoe a, cause. It is
true that we can not conceive the eternal. The imag-
ination is not competent to deal with the infinite. In-
tuition ordy has this j)Ower. Though the imagination
can not grasp the eternal, it is yet ahle to see that there
is no past date, however I'cmote, ])efore which there
mir, fjrfore a thing is, it can not act, and can
not, therefore, bring itself into existence ; if it does act, it
already is, and hence does not bring itself into existence.
The propositions. There is an absolute commencement,
and Every event must have a cause, are virtually contradic-
tories, as has hefore heen shown ; but the falsity of either
of two contradictories, is logically identical with the
truth of the other; hence, the impossibility of an abso-
lute commc^ncement, that is, that an event can take place
without a cause, is the necessity that every event must
have a cause.
In estahlishing the law of causality, we do not employ
th(; law of conflictives, or, as it is commonly called, the
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 69
law of contradiction ; for, under this law, tlioiii^h wc can
pasH from tlic affii'rnation of cither of two confiictivcB to
the denial of the other, yet we can not pass from the
denial of either, to the affirmation of the other; but
this we can do under tiie law of contradictories, com-
monly called the law of excluded middle. Thus, undei*
the law of conHictives, if we know that a Ijody is si)her-
ical, we know that it is not cubical; but if we sirjiply
know that it is not spherical, we do not know that it
is cubical, since it may be cylindrical or conical, or it
may have any one of the multitude of possible forms. J^iit
in the case of contradictories, the Y)ropositions are not
only confiictive, so that the truth of either involves the
falsity of the other, but they are universally inclusive,
no other case being possible, so that the falsity of either
involves the truth of the other.
The intuition of the impossibility of an absolute com-
mencement is, therefore, virtually, the intuition of the
necessity of its contradictory — that every event must
have a cause. We do not reach the judgment of cau-
sality tlirough the imjmtency of the mind to conceive an
absolute commencement, })ut thi'ough the pofenry of the
intuitive faculty to ap])rehend that an absolute com-
mencement is impossible.
It is to be remarked that the inconcdvabUltij of an
absolute commencement, as spoken of by Hamilton, is
to ])e understood in the sense that we can not under-
stand how it can be, and not in the sense that it can
not be imagined; for the mind can, by Jin act of the
imagination, form tlu^ ])icture of an object, springing,
without cause, from non-entity into being. Though the
picture of an absolute commencement can l)e formed,
yet it is true, not ordy that the mind is unable to un-
derstand how an absolute commencement can be, but
tliat it has })ositive power to know tluit such commence-
70 PSYCHOLOGY.
ment can not be at all, since it clearly apprehends that
it is absolutely impossible for nonentity to spring into
being. On the other hand, eternal existence is incon-
ceivable in the sense that it can not be imagined, and
not in the sense that it is known to be impossible.
Thouo'h it were true that eternal existence is inconceiv-
able by us in the sense that we can not understand how
it can be, yet its necessity is apprehended by reason as
the condition of the facts of the universe, otherwise non-
entity must have sprung, without cause, into entity,
Avhich is impossible.
The above demonstration shows the falsity of the the-
ory of Hume, that the relation of cause and effect is re-
solvable into that of antecedent and consequent. It is
true that we perceive succession, noi cause. But a mere
antecedent of an event is simply that which accidentally
goes before the event. Hence, the absence of a mere
antecedent would not be followed by the disappearance
of the event; for the antecedent, whose disappearance is
followed by the disappearance of the event, is more than
a mere antecedent — it is a condition.
Hume held, it is true, that a cause is an immediate
and invariable antecedent. Then it is more than a mere
antecedent, since it is that without which the event
would not take place; for, if the event could take. place
without it, then it is not necessarily an invariable ante-
cedent. But that without which the event could not
take place is a condition of the event. The conditions
of an event are, therefore, all those antecedents, whether
d3mamical or non-dynamical, without which the event
would not take place.
A non-dynamical condition, though a necessary ante-
cedent, is not efficient in bringing about the event, since
then it is not non-djniamical. Thus, space is a non-
dynamical condition of motion. The absence of support
DYNAMICAL CONDiriONS. 71
is a non-dynamical condition of the fall of a body. In
general, space, time, and the absence of preventing in-
fluences are the non-dynamical conditions of the occur-
rence of an}^ event. This is intuitively certain; for
without space and time, there could be no event, or, if
there be preventing influences, the event will, of course,
be prevented, and consequently will not occur.
A dynamical condition is that which is efficient in
producing the event. Thus, force is a dynamical condi-
tion of the change of the condition of a body with
respect to rest or motion. The sum of the dynamical
conditions of an event is the cause of the event.
If Hume's theory be true, that a cause is nothing
more than an immediate and invariable antecedent, then,
though it is a condition, that without which the event
would not occur, it is merely a non -dynamical condi-
tion, totally devoid of efficiency. It has no influence in
producing the event, for then it would not be non-dy-
namical. Hence, the -event must bring itself into exist-
ence ; that is, nonentity springs into entity, which is
absurd. Hence, an event is impossible without dj^namical
conditions as well as non-dynamical; but the sum of the
dynamical conditions is the cause. Hence, every event
must have a cause.
The remaining laws may be more briefly treated.
The second law is. The effect is alivays complex. Thus,
a blow of the hammer drives the nail, agitates the air,
produces sound, develops heat, etc.
Sometimes the elements of a complex effect are si-
multaneous, and sometimes successive.
The third law is. The cause is always complex. This is
true of the cause proper, or the sum of the dynamical
conditions. For a stronger reason is it true of the sum
of all the conditions, dynamical and non-dynamical.
Thus, the path of a projectile is due to the intensity
72 PSYCHOLOGY,
and direction of tlie projecting force, the action of gravity,
and the resistance of the air. In addition to these dy-
namical conditions, we have the non-dynamical condi-
tions, space, time, and the absence from its path of solid
obstacles, such as trees, buildings, etc.
The fourth law * is. The complexity of the cause is pro-
portionate to the coviplexity of the effect. Let us consider
any effect and its cause, both of which we have found to
be complex: IS^ow, any modification of the effect requires
a modification of the cause, since the modification of the
effect is an event which must have a cause. A new
element in the effect, therefore, requires a new element
in the cause.
The fifth law is, Like causes and conditions are followed
by like effects. For whatever exists in the causes and
conditions to determine the effect in one case, exists to
determine it in the other case, since, by hypothesis, the
causes and conditions are essentially the same.
It is, however, to be observed that two effects, alike
in one aspect, may follow diverse causes. Thus two
men may be killed, one by a pistol ball, the other by
poison. As regards death, the effects are alike; but the
immediate effects on the body are as diverse as the
causes themselves.
3d. Z/aw of events. The law of an event is the mode
of its occurrence. An event must occur in some manner,
if it occur at all, and the manner of its occurrence is
its law; hence, every event must have its law. That
every event must have its law is affirmed, a priori^ by
intuition; what that law is can be discovered only a
posteriori^ by investigation.
The nature of the cause and other conditions of an
event determines the character of its law, and a knowl-
- For the fourth law, the author is indebted to Prof. Tappan of Kenyon
College.
DYNAMICAL CONDITIONS. 73
edge of these may enable us to predict the character of
the law; but the law should never be regarded as cer-
tain till verified by experience. A knowledge of law
enables us to predict wliat events will take place, or
what phenomena will appear, as the effects of given
causes under given conditions. Effects become, in turn,
the conditions and causes of other effects. Thus, phe'-
nomena, as appearances, affect the conscious subject, and
are the conditions of other phenomena. A thought may
awaken desire, and a desire may induce volition. The
events of the material world are related according to law.
Effects are known by experience, but a knowledge of
conditions and laws often enable us to predict conse-
quences. In this power of prevision lies one of the
chief advantages of science.
The absolute is that which is free from the relation of
dependence- on any power without itself It is the un-
conditioned It is not the unrelated — that which exists
out of all relation; but it is the independent — that which
is free from the one relation of dependence. Though,
existing out of the relation of dependence upon any
thing else, the absolute is not incapable of existing in
other relations to other things.
isTature appears as an indefinite chain, each link of
which is both an effect and a cause, or, if not a cause,
at least an instrument, both conditioned and a condition.
Whence, then, is nature? Three sujopositions are possi-
ble — the chain of causes and effects, as to the number
of links, is infinite, or finite without an absolute head,
or finite with an absolute head.
If the chain is infinite, each link, as an effect, is con-
ditioned, and affords no resting place for thought, nince
the conditioned implies the condition. Tracing the series
back from the conditioned to its condition, which is also
conditioned, we find, under this supposition, nothing
P y.-7.
74 PSYCHOLOGY.
which is not conditioned, or no absohite condition.
Though every thing seems to be accounted for, by re-
ferring it to its condition, yet the condition of each
conditioned link is itself conditioned, and notliing is ab-
solutely accounted for, since every explanation requires
further explanation as we go back along the series in-
definitely. This series has no head, absolute or condi-
tioned, since by supposition it is infinite.
If the chain is finite without an absolute head, the
first link, not being absolute, is dependent, or conditioned,
and conditioned without a condition, which is imj)ossible.
Since the first supposition is unsatisfactory and the
second involves an impossibility, the rational mind will
adopt the third, or only remaining supposition — that
the chain is finite, as to the number of links, and has
an absolute head.
From the facts of the universe, it may be inferred
that the Absolute is a Divine Personality, eternal and
supernatural, endowed with intellect, sensibility, and will,
involving in himself as Creator, liberty, spontaneity, and
autonomy, and possessing power, wisdom, and goodness,
in infinite perfection.
Final cause, or purpose, follows, as a corollary, from
the doctrine of the Absolute as the intelligent cause of
the universe.
CHAPTBK VI.
INTUITIONS CONTINUED.
The Ego is the subject of psychical phenomena — it
is that which cogitates, and feels, and wills.
Psychical phenomena are known by consciousness;
but the conditional necessity of the ego is known by
rational intuition. These phenomena imply a subject,
and consciousness of them implies a conscious subject.
The subject of the phenomena is identical with the sub-
ject of the consciousness, since it is not possille for a
subject to be conscious of the phenomena of any other
subject than itself
As events beginning in time, psychical phenomena
must have causes. The cause of the phenomena may
be the conscious subject, endowed with the faculties of
intellect, sensibility, and will, or some external object
acting upon the ego as susceptible of given affections, or
the ego acting in conjunction with some external object.
In the first case, the ego is chiefly active ; in the second,
chiefly passive; in the third, both active and passive.
A faculty of the ego — its power of acting in a given
manner, or its susceptibility of being in a given state —
is implied b}^ every act or state. Phenomena essentially
alike are i*eferred to the same faculty, but phenomena
essentially unlike, are referred to different faculties.
Theories relating to the ego. — They are the follow-
ing::
Hume's theory. ^' For my part, when I enter most in-
timately into what I call myself, I always stumble on
(75)
76 PSYCHOLOGY,
some particular perception or other, — of heat or cold,
liglit or shade, love oi- hatred, pain or pleasure. I never
catch myself^ at any time, without a perception, and
never can observe any thing but the perception."
li psychical phenomenon^ which is more general, be sub-
stituted for perception^ which is too narrow, the above
statement would be, not only clear, but correct.
Hume also says, ''If any one, upon serious and un-
prejudiced reflection, thinks he has a different notion of
himself, I must confess I can no longer reason with him."
This is well enough so far as it implies that the im-
mediate objects of consciousness are psychical phenom-
ena, but not the soul itself; yet it is incorrect, if it im-
plies that there is nothing but the phenomena.
But Hume farther says, '' He may, perhaps, perceive
something simple and continued, which he calls himself,
though ] am certain that there is no such principle in
me." Human Nature^ Part IV., 8ec. 2.
Hume might have said, correctly enough, I am certain
that I am not conscious of any such principle in me;
but he was not warranted in saying, '' I am certain that
there is no such principle in me." There might have
been such a principle in him, though he was not con-
scious of the fa::t; for the ego does not know itself by
consciousness, but apprehends the conditional necessity
of itself by rational intuition. Thus, if there is thought,
there is something which thinks.
What did Hume mean by ''I" and "me"? With all
his positiveness, it is hardly to be supposed that Hume
really identified himself, whom he calls "I," with what
he calls '' perception." Does the perception stumble on
the perception? The "I" which stumbles on the per-
ception, is to be discriminated from the perception on
which it stumbles. Without the " I " as the subject of
perception, the perception itself would be impossible.
THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 77
ReifTs tlieory. " I am conscious of perception, but not
of the object I perceive; I am conscious of memory, but
not of the object I remember Our sensations and
thoughts do also suggest the notion of a mind and the
belief of its existence, and of its relation to our
thoughts." Inquiry^ Chapt. II., Sec. 7. This. is correct,
as far as it goes, but the word "suggest" is hardly
strong enough.
Stewarfs theory. After considering matter, Stewart
says, " The case is precisely similar with respect to mind.
We are not immediately conscious of its existence; but
we are conscious of sensation, thought, and volition —
operations which imply the existence of something which
feels, thinks, and wills." Steicarfs Philosophy, page 2.
This is correct and well expressed.
Hamilton's theory. " Our knowledge is either of matter
or of mind. Now, what is matter? What do we know of
matter? Matter, or body is to us the name, either of
something known, or of something unknown. In so far
as matter is a name for something known, it means that
which appears to us under the forms of extension, solid-
ity, divisibility, figure, motion, roughness, smoothness,
color, heat, cold, etc. ; in short, it is a common name for
a certain series, or aggregate, or complement, of appear-
ances, or phenomena, manifest in co-existence. But as
the phenomena appear onl}^ in conjunction, we are com-
pelled, by the constitution of our nature, to think them
conjoined in and b}^ something; and as they are phe-
nomena, we can not think them the phenomena of
nothing, but must regard them as the properties or
qualities of something that is extended, solid, figured, etc.
"Now, that which manifests its qualities — in other
words, that in which the appearing causes inhere, that
to which they belong, is called their subject, or substance j
or substratum. To this subject of the phenomena of
78 PSYCHOLOGY,
extension, solidity, etc., the term matter or material sub-
stance is commonly given; and therefore, as contradis-
tinguished from these qualities, it is the name of some-
thing unknown and inconceivable.
''The same is true in regard to mind. In so far as
mind is the common name for the states of knowing,
willing, feeling, desiring, etc., of which I am conscious,
it is only the name for a certain series of connected
phenomena or qualities, and consequently expresses only
what is known. But in so far as it denotes that subject
or substratum in which the phenomena of knowing,
willing, etc., inhere, — something behind or under these
phenomena, — it expresses, what in itself, or in its abso-
lute existence, is unknown.
" Thus, mind and matter, as known or knowable, are
only two different series of phenomena or qualities;
mind and matter as unknown and unknowable, are the
two substances in which these two different series of
phenomena or qualities are supposed to inhere. The
existence of an unknown substance is only an inference
we are compelled to make, from the existence of known
phenomena; and the distinction of two substances is only
inferred from the seeming incompatibility of the two
series of phenomena to cohere in one." Boiven's Hamil-
ton^ page 89.
This passage is worthy of study. If it contains error,
it is in holding the substance of both matter and mind
to be unknown and unknowable. It is true that we
perceive the phenomena of matter and not its sub-
stance ; and that we are conscious of the phenomena of
mind, and not of its substance, or of the soul itself.
But if we are compelled to infer the existence and the
distinction of two substances, called matter and mind,
as Hamilton declares, matter and mind are not altogether
unknown and unknowable, unless, forsooth, we are com-
THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 79
pelled by the constitution of our minds and b}^ the force
of evidence to make illogical inferences.
A thing is not to be declared unknown and unknow-
able, because it is not known in a certain w^ay, as, for
example, by perception or consciousness ; for inference
and intuition are also modes of knowledge. By infer-
ence we are not to understand a mere guess, but a log-
ical deduction, such as a corollary in Geometry. It must,
however, be admitted that the substance of neither matter
nor mind is an object of intuition ; but the necessity of
substance, w^hether matter or mind, is such an object.
But if the necessity of mind, as the substance or substra-
tum of psychical phenomena, is known, the actuality of
mind, as a substance, is also known, as involved in its
necessity; hence, the substance of mind is not absolutely
unknown and unknowable.
Hamilton further says, '^I, at present, avoid entering
into the metaphysics of substance and phenomena. I
shall oidy observe, in general, that philosophers have
frequently fallen into one or the other of three different
errors. Some have denied the reality of any unknown
ground of the known phenomena, and have maintained
that mind and matter have no substantial existence, but
are merely the two complements of two series of asso-
ciated qualities. This doctrine is, how^ever, altogether
futile. It belies the veracity of our primary beliefs; it
leaves unsatisfied the strongest necessities of our intel-
lectual nature ; it admits, as a fact, that the phenomena
arc connected, but allows no cause explanatory .of the
fact of their connection.
'• Others, again, have fallen into an opposite error.
They have attempted to speculate concerning the nat-
ure of the unknown grounds of the phenomena of mind
and matter, apart from the phenomena, and have, ac-
cordingly, transcended the legitimate sphere of philosophy.
80 PSYCHOLOGY.
"A third party have taken some one or more of the
phenomena themselves, as the basis or substratum of the
others. Thus, Descartes, at least as understood and fol-
lowed by Malebranche and others of his disciples, made
thought or consciousness convertible with the substance
of mind; and Bishops Brown and Law, with Dr. Watts,
constituted solidity and extension the substance of bodj^.
This theory is, however, liable to all the objections which
may be alleged against the first
''Mind can be defined only a posteriori^ — that is, only
from its manifestations What we mean by mind
is simply that which perceives, feels, wills, desires, etc."
Pages 100 and 101. This accords with the view of
Aristotle, who defines the soul to be ''the principle by
which we live, and move, and perceive, and understand."
It also agrees with that of St. Augustine, who says,
" Mens se cognoscit cognoscendp se vivere, se meminisse,
se intelligere, se velle, cogitare, scire, judicare."
John Stuart Mill's theory. "My mind is but a series
of feelings, a thread of consciousness, with the back-
ground of the possibilities of feelings." Exam, of Ham-
ilton^ Chapter XII.
Mill is too much inclined to identify the mind with its
phenomena. Possibly he had a glimpse of the truth in
what he called " the background of the possibilities of
feelings." The "background" is the soul; the "feel-
ings" and, as should be added, the cognitions and the
volitions are its phenomena.
Bain's theory. "The operations and appearances that
constitute mind are indicated by such terms as feeling,
thought, memory, reason, conscience, imagination, will,
j)assions, afiections, taste. But the definition of mind
asj^ires to comprehend, in few words, by some generali-
zation, the whole kindred of mental facts, and to exclude
every thing of a foreign character." Sen, and Int. Ch. II.
THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY, 81
In speaking of " the operations and appearances that
constitute mind/' Bain identifies mind with its phenom-
ena. If ''the mind is the sum total of subject experi-
ences," as Bain elsewhere declares, then we are conscious
of mind, since w^e are conscious of these phenomena; but
the recognition of a phenomenon on its recurrence, im-
plies a spiritual subject enduring through the period from
the occurrence of the phenomenon to its recurrence, and
therefore distinct from the fleeting phenomena. The dis-
crimination of one psychical phenomenon from another,
can be explained only by referring them to a common
subject, which, being affected differently by them, dis-
criminates the one from the other. One phenomenon
can not discriminate itself from another; for that would
imply that an act or an appearance is an intelligent
being, which is not the case.
Dr. Porter's theory. "^^ Of the ego itself we are directly
conscious." Porter's Elements, Part I., ChajD. I.
This statement is not to be admitted on authority, and
is not verified when consciousness itself is interrogated.
Consciousness is immediate and, therefore, certain knowl-
edge. If the ego is conscious of itself, any sound mind,
to say nothing of such philosophers as Hume, Eeid,
Stewart, and Hamilton, could be no more mistaken with
regard to the fact, than it could be w^ith regard to the
consciousness of cognitions, feelings, and volitions.
There is a sense, however, in which we may admit
the truth of Dr. Porter's statement. Taking conscious-
ness in its literal sense, as knowing something along
with knowing something else, we grant that the ego is
conscious of itself; for it know^s itself along with know-
ing any thing else — -it can not know any thing else
without knowing itself; neither can it know itself with-
out knowing something else. But how does the ego
know itself? In knowing any thing else, it apprehends,
82 PSYCHOLOGY.
by rational intuition, tlie conditional necessity, and hence
the reality of itself as the subject of that knowledge.
But to be conscious of any thing, in the ordinary ac-
ceptation of the word conscious^ is immediately to expe-
rience that thing. ISTo one holds that the mind in a
quiescent state is an object of consciousness; for con-
sciousness itself is inconsistent w^ith quiescence. Hence,
the mind can not be conscious without some other object
of consciousness than the mind itself, or the conscious-
ness itself, or the mind as conscious; in other words,
consciousness is impossible without some other object
than the quiescent mind itself, or the consciousness itself,
or the conscious mind itself But wdien the ego is con-
scious of any act, it knows itself through the rational
intuition of its conditional necessity, as the subject both
of the act and of the consciousness of the act.
How Dr. Porter was led to his view will, perhaps, be
seen from the following quotation : " A psychical act or
state is, as we have seen, in its nature complex, consist-
ing of three elements in intimate relation to each other
— the ego, the object, the acting or suffering of the
passing moment. But the act or suffering is inconceiv-
able, except as belonging to the ego and occasioned by
the object. Of this double relation, consciousness must
take notice. It must, therefore, also take notice of the
terms or elements to vfhich it is related."
The central thought here is, " The act or suffering is
inconceivable, except as belonging to an ego and occa-
sioned by an object." Dropping the last expression,
^'and occasioned by an object," as not now under con-
sideration, we have left, "the act or suffering is incon-
ceivable, except as belonging to an ego." But the in-
conceivability of "the act or suffering, except as belong-
ing to an ego," is not a consciousness of the ego, and
does not establish Dr. Porter's doctrine that the ego is
THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY. 83
conscious of itself. It simply shows that psychical phe-
nomena are inexplicable without a subject.
There is, however, more than an inconceivability of the
act or suffering, except as belonging to an ego — there is
a positive intuition of the necessity of the ego, on the
condition that the act or suffering is experienced in
consciousness, otherwise these phenomena, having no
subject, would be the phenomena of nothing, w^hich is
impossible. Consciousness, of course, takes notice of this
intuition. Should it be said that if consciousness takes
notice of the intuition of the relation of the act and suf-
fering to the ego, as their subject, '* it must, therefore,
also take notice of the terms or elements to which it
is related," the answer is, not unless these terms are
present phenomena, as consciousness of memory does
not take notice of the past reality remembered, since we
are not conscious of the past. But the intuition itself
directly apprehends, not the ego, but the necessity of the
ego. If, therefore, consciousness, in taking notice of this
intuition, should take notice of the terms of this intuition,
it would take notice of the necessity of the ego, and not
of the ego itself. But the truth is, the ego is conscious,
not even of the necessity of itself, but of the intuition of
the necessity of itself, and in general, of psychical phenom-
ena. By rational intuition, the ego apprehends that these
j)henomena must have a subject, and identifies that sub-
ject with itself, since it could not be conscious of the
phenomena of any other subject. The question at issue
is not whether the eo-o knows the fact of its own exist-
ence, that is admitted, but how this knowledge is at-
tained? Dr. Porter says, immediately by consciousness.
We say by rational intuition — not the intuition of the
ego itself, but of its necessity.
Dr. Porter further says, " It is of the very nature and
essence of a psychical state to be the act or experience
84 PSYCHOLOGY.
of an individual ego. We are not first conscious of the
state or operation^ and then forced to look around for a
something to which it is to be referred, or to which it
may belong." This is true, and accords with the fact
that the conditional necessity of the ego is, at once, ap-
prehended by rational intuition, and that to the ego,
as subject, psychical phenomena are directly referred.
We are conscious, not of phenomerui in the abstract, but
of determinate phenomena, — not of phenomena without
a subject, but of the phenomena of the ego, the same
ego which is conscious of them, since it is impossible
for an ego to be conscious of the phenomena of any
other ego than itself.
Again, Dr. Porter says, ^'A mental state which is not
produced or felt by an individual self, is as inconceivable
as a triangle without three angles, or a square without
four sides." But that does not prove that the soul is
conscious of itself, but that psychical phenomena are in-
explicable without a subject; and not only inexplicable,
but impossible without a subject; but this is knowing
that the soul is, through the rational intuition of its
necessity, and not by consciousness. Neither conceiva-
bility nor inconceivability is a tcvst of truth. We may
conceive, or picture by the imagination, an event without
a cause; but intuition declares that an event without a
cause is an impossibihty. Wo can not conceive, or pict-
ure by the imagination, infinite space, yet intuition af-
firms that infinite space is a reality.
Dr. Porter says again, '■' This relation of the act to the
self is not inferred, but is directly known. The fact cxf
memory proves this beyond dispute. In every act of
memory, we know or believe that the object now recalled
was formerly before the mind; in other words, I, the
person remembering, did ])reviously know or experience
that which I recall. But how could this be possible if
THE EOO AND PEnSONAL IDENTITY. 85
the first act or state was not known, when it occurred,
to belong to the same ego w4iich now recalls it?" It
was known to belong to the ego, that poijit is not the
one in dispute; but how was it knowji to belong to the
ego? The necessity of the ego, as the subject of the
original phenomena, was known by intuition ; the neces-
sity of the ego is, in like manner, knoAvn as the subject
of the memory; but the subject of the memory must be
the same as the subject of the phenomenon remembered,
otherwise the memory itself would be impossible.
The ego itself is not the object of consciousness, nor
even of rational intuition ; but the conditional necessity
of the ego is an object of direct intuition. Knowledge
of the necessity of the ego involves a knowledge of its
actuality, and of this knowledge there is consciousness;
but consciousness of this knowledge should not be mis-
taken, as it often is, for a consciousness of the ego; if
the ego itself were, in its essence, an object of conscious-
ness, then indeed might we solve the mysteries of the
spirit.- The ego is not the object, but the subject of con-
sciousness, and if the subject, then a reality. The ego
is not known by consciousness as an act or state; for
that would identify the ego with a phenomenon. Neither
is the ego in a definite act or state known as the object
of consciousness, but it is the act or state itself that
is the object. This act or state is known by rational
intuition to be impossible, unless it has the ego for its
subject; but the intuition that an act or state, without
the ego as its subject, is impossible, is the intuition of
the necessity of the ego, on the condition that there is
consciousness of the act or state. Whenever the ego, by
consciousness, experiences a psychical phenomenon, it ap-
prehends, by the act of rational intuition, the necessity
of itself, as the condition or ground of the phenomenon.
The subject and the object, though distinguishable, are
86 PSYCHOLOGY,
not separable in cognition — one can not be known with-
out the other; but the object is known empirically, while
the subject is known rationally.
Personal Identity is the continued essential sameness
of the ego. Every sane person has an irresistible con-
viction of his personal identity, as is clearly shown by
the universal anticipation of the future consequences of
past acts.
The necessity of personal identity is known by rational
intuition as the condition of the phenomena of memory;
for, if personal identity be not a fact, memory would be
impossible, since the person, not being the same, could
not remember the past experience of another person as
his own. As it is not strictly the ego itself, which is
apprehended by rational intuition, but the conditional
necessity of the ego, as the subject of psychical phenom-
ena, so it is not strictly personal identity itself, which
is apprehended by rational intuition, but the conditional
necessity of personal identity, as the condition of the
fact of memor}", since intuition at once knows that, un-
less personal identity be a fact, memory itself would be
impossible.
Personal identity does not inhere in the cognitions,
feelings, and volitions themselves, which are successive
and continually changing, but in the ego which cogitates
and feels and wills. The ego maintains its identity,
wdiile its phenomena change continually. The fact of
personal identity is absolutely incompatible with the
doctrine of Mr. Bain and others, that ^'the ego is the
sum-total of subject experiences;" for, in the ever shift-
ing phenomena of which we are conscious, the universal
belief of mankind in personal identity can find no possi-
ble foundation.
]S[either does consciousness constitute personal identity,
as Locke seems to teach. He says, "Since consciousness
THE EGO AND PERSONAL IDENTITY. 87
alwa^^s accompanies thinking, and it is that which makes
every one to be what he calls self^ and thereby distin-
guishes himself from all other thinking beings, in this
alone consists personal identity, i, 6., the sameness of a
rational being; and as far as this consciousness can be
extended backward to any 2)ast action or thought, so far
reaches the identity of that person; it is the same self
now it was then ; and it is by the same self wnth this
present one that now reflects on it, that that action was
done." Essay, Book II.. Chapter XXYII., Section 9.
Locke here confounds the evidence of ^^ersonal identit}^
with personal identity itself Consciousness reveals psy-
chical phenomena, and this revelation .is the condition
on which rational intuition apprehends the necessity of
the ego; consciousness likewise reveals the memory of
past phenomena, and this revelation is the condition on
which rational intuition apprehends the sameness of the
ego, that is, personal identity. Locke is incorrect in say-
ing that "consciousness can be extended backwards to
any past action or thought," for consciousness is limited
to present phenomena. We remember past phenomena,
and are conscious of the memory, but not of the j)be-
nomena. The mem or v, much less the consciousness, does
not constitute personal identity, but is the evidence of
that identity.
Memory, though essential to my present knowledge of
my past acts, though proving my connection with those
acts, is not essential to that connection ; for I might
have performed those acts, though I do not now re-
member them. The identity, though essential to the
memory, does not consist in the memory, since it may
exist, and yet the memory be wanting. Evidence is es-
sential to a knowledge of a fact, but not to the fact it-
self, and should not be confounded with the fact.
To illustrate the relation of memory to personal iden-
88 PSYCHOLOGY.
tity, take a case similar to the one given by Dr. Reid.
A boy wins a prize at school; in middle life, he is made
a general and wins a battle; in later life, he is made
president. The general, we may suppose, remembers
winning the prize, and the president remembers winning
the battle but not the prize. Since the general remem-
bers winning the prize, he is identical with the boy;
and since the president remembers winning the battle,
he is identical with the general, and consequently is
identical with the boy, since the general is identical
with the boy; but if memory constitutes personal iden-
tity, as Locke seems to teach, then the president is not
identical with the boy, since he does not remember
winning the prize. Hence, the president is both identi-
cal and not identical with the boy, which is absurd.
The identity of the president with the boy is of course
consistent with such changes as physical growth and
mental development.
The identity of another person is, by that person,
known by rational intuition, as my own identity is
known by myself; but the identity of that person is
believed by me, on evidence more or less conclusive;
hence, this belief may vary in degree between the limits
certainty and impossibility.
The identity of things in general is known by re-
semblance, but is consistent with great changes, as in
the case of a tree, throughout growth and decay, where
there is organic unity; or, as in case of a w^agon, which
has been frequently repaired.
CHAPTER YII.
SENSATION.
1. Sensation defined and illustrated. — Sensation is the
feeling which is occasioned by the excitement of some
part of the organism. In general, sensation results from
some external stimulus.
Take an apple, for examj^le. Through the senses of
smell, taste, touch, hearing, and sight, and the muscular
power, we have, res]3ectively, the sensations of odor,
flavor, roughness or smoothness, sound, color, and re-
sistance. The sensations are not cognitions of the apj)le,
but are contingent conditions of cognitions.
Sensation is a phenomenon of the Sensibility, but from
its intimate relation to the Intellect, as the condition of
perception, it is necessary to treat it in this connection.
Sensations are known by consciousness, are analyzed,
compared, identified, discriminated, and classitied by
reflection, and are referred, by rational intuition, to the
ego as their subject, and to some object as their cause.
2. Conditions of sensation. — These are the sensorium,
excitants, action of the excitants upon the sensorium, and
the sensibility.
1st. The sensorium is the nervous system and the or-
gans of the special senses. It is the first condition of
sensation.
(1) The nervous system is a mass of excitable substance
consisting of a central mass called the brain, located in
the head; the spinal cord, inclosed in the back-bone;
the nerves, a system of ramifying filaments; and the
Psy.-8. (39)
90 PSYCHOLOGY.
ganglia, or exj)an8iori of the nerves into occasional
knots, or subordinate nerve centers. The nervous sub-
stance consists of white matter composed of fibers, and
gray matter containing fibers and cells intermingled.
The fibers are exceedingly minute, and constitute the
media of connection and communication. The cells or
corpuscles are rounded irregular little bodies, and serve
as nerve centers, or junctions, where the fibers have
their origin and termini, and multiply their connections.
The nerves constitute the medium of communication be-
tween the various parts of the organism and brain as
principal center, or the ganglia as subordinate centers.
One set of nerves, the afferent^ conduct impressions to
the center, and another set, the efferent, convey stimuli
from the center.
(2) The organs of the special senses are the nostrils,
the tongue and palate, the skin, the ears, and the eyes,
which are, respectively, the organs of smell, taste, touch,
hearing, and sight.
The nervous system and the sense organs, taken col-
lectively, constitute the sensorium, which is, as before
stated, the first condition of sensation.
2d. An excitant is something which is capable of af-
fecting the sensorium. It is the second condition of
sensation. Thus, odorous objects excite the sense of
smell; sapid objects, the sense of taste; tangible, the
sense of touch; audible, the sense of hearing; and visi-
ble, the sense of sight.
Also, special agents, as heat, light, electricity, magnet-
ism, etc., affect the nerves, and afford conditions of sen^
sation. The sensation corresponds to the nerve affected.
Thus, the excitement of the optic nerve is followed by
the sensation of light; an excitement of the auditory
nerve, by the sensation of sound.
A blow, or sudden shock, or injury, may, by exciting
SENSATION. 91
the nerves of any special sense organ, be followed by
the sensation usually experienced in that organ. Thus,
a flash of light may accompany a severe blow.
Sensations at certain localities may even be induced
by a thought directed to those localities, especially if
the thought is accompanied with emotion. In this case,
the thought serves the purpose of an excitant, and thus
a given nervous state is the resultant of an antecedent
nervous state and a mental act combined.
Sensations may also be due to the revivals of the re-
sidual excitement of the sense organ.
3d. The action of an excitant upon the sensorium is the
third condition of sensation. Thus, a luminous object
reflecting light to the eye is the usual condition of vis-
ion ; a material object in contact with the hand, or with
some other portion of the body, is the condition of the
sensation of touch ; and so on, for the other senses.
4th. The sensibility is the susceptibility of feeling. It
is the fourth condition of sensation. The other condi-
tions are chiefly physical; but this is psychical; and
sensation is itself not a physiological, but a psychical
phenomenon. The excitement of the nerves, though an
antecedent condition of sensation, is not sensation itself.
Sensation, then, is not the excitement of the sensorium,
but the sympathy of the soul with this excitement. The
fact that we feel, as consciousness attests, is proof of the
fact that we have sensibility.
3. Sensations localized. — A sensation is localized in
that part of the sensorium aflPected. That we have the
power to localize sensations is an unquestioned fact,
whether that power is original or is acquired by expe-
rience. Thus, the toothache is located in the tooth af-
fected, and not in the hand; an injury to the foot is
not referred to the head ; taste is referred to the tongue
and palate. But certain sensations are vaguely localized.
92 - PSYCHOLOGY,
We know by intuition that the sensation is somewhere,
and by experience that it is in the sensorium, though
tlie exact place in the sensorium is not always definitel}^
determined. The sensorium, psychologically considered,
is the locus of sensation.
4. Object of consciousness in sensation. — The object
of which we are conscious in sensation is not the ex-
citant ; it is not the sensorium itself as consisting of the
nervous system and the sense organs; it is not the sen-
sorium excited to some form of definite action ; it is not
the excitement of the sensorium; but it is the sensation
in the sensorium as the locus of sensation. Thus, when
I grasp a ball in the hand, I am not conscious of the
ball, nor of the hand, nor of the nerves of the hand,
nor of the nerves excited, nor of the excitement of the
nerves, but of the sensations of touch and resistance
located in the hand. I am no more conscious that the
sensation is to be referred to the nerves, than that it
is to be referred to the muscles or veins. The soul is
not conscious that the body has nerves; it ascertains
this fact from anatomical investigation; and from physi-
ological reseach, it discovers that the nerves are condi-
tions of sensations, since, when destroyed or paralyzed
in a particular part, sensation in that part ceases. But
the excitement of the nerves is attended or followed by
a sensation, which is the sympathy of the soul with the
nervous excitement; and this sensation is the immediate
object of which we are conscious.
5. Quality of sensations. — The quality of sensation
involves existence and identity. The existence of a
sensation is opposed to non-existence; it is reality as
opposed to non-reality, or sensation as opposed to non-
sensation. But the existence of a sensation does not
imply that it must have a previously mentioned, speci-
fied characteristic; for it may have some other charac-
SENSATION, 93
teristic. If only the existence of a sensation be given,
its character is left wholly indeterminate, and may be,
so far as we know, of any kind whatever. The identity
of a sensation is the fact that the sensation is itself, and
nothing else; but the identity of a sensation involves
peculiarity^ or the positive attributes characteristic of
itself, and particularity^ or the negation of the positive
characteristics of any other thing.
6. Quantity of sensations. — The quantity of sensation
involves its degree of intensity, and its temporal and
spatial relations.
1st. The degree of intensity may vary between the
limits zero and a degree so great as to be insuj)portable,
resulting in unconsciousness, as is illustrated by pain,
and the sensations of light and heat.
2d. The temporal relations of a sensation involve the
date, or time of its occurrence, and the duration, or time
of its continuance. If sensation continues but for a mo-
ment, duration vanishes into date.
3d. The spatial relations of a sensation involve its lo-
cality in the sensorium, and, when more than a j^oint
is affected, also its extent, and vaguely, perhaps, its fig-
ure, or form, as may be illustrated in case of color and
touch. If but a point is affected, extent and figure
vanish into locality.
7. Analysis of sensations. — The analysis of a sensa-
tion, is the resolution of the sensation into its elements.
A simple sensation, comprising only one element as to
peculiarity, is incapable of analysis; but a complex
sensation, comprising more than one element, is capable
of analysis. A complex sensation can sometimes be
analyzed by attentive reflection. Sensations may appear
simple to consciousness when in reality they are com-
plex. These ma}^ frequently be analyzed by calling to
our aid the methods of physical science, as in analyzing
94 PSYCHOLOGY,
the HcnsatioiiH of color and Round. Reversing the pro-
cesses of analysis, we may, by a synthetic process, re-
combine the elements, so as to reproduce a sensation
essentially like the oriii;inal sensation.
8. Relation, identification, and discrimination of sen-
sations. — Sensations are similar or dissimilar in kind^
according as they are acquired through the same sense,
or through different senses, and as such may be identi-
£ed or discriminated.
Sensations are similar or dissimilar in variety, accord-
ing as they involve similar or dissimilar qualities, as to
peculiarity, and as such may be identified or discrimin-
ated.
Sensations similar in kind may be similar or dissim-
ilar in variety; but sensations dissimilar in kind are
also dissimilar in variety.
Sensations similar in kind and variety may agree or
differ in degree of intensity, and may accordingly be
identified or discriminated.
Sensations similar in kind and variety, and agreeing
in degree of intensity, may agree or differ in temporal
relations, and may accordingly be identified or discrim-
inated.
Sensations similar in kind and variety, and agreeing
in intensity and in temporal relations, may agree or
differ in spatial relations, and may accordingly be iden-
tified or discriminated.
9. Classification of sensations. — Sensations are classi-
fied as to kind when referred to the senses or organs
through which they are acquired. They may be subdi-
vided, both as to quality and quantity. Sensations arc
general or special.
1st. The general sensations comprise all those con-
nected with the various portions of the organism, except
the five senses. They are the following:
SENSATION, 95
(1) The aensations connected with the muscular sys-
tem compriwe all those arisini^ from any posture or
movement of the })0(ly, involvin^^ the contraction or re-
laxation of the muscles, as in standing, walking, lifting,
pulling, pushing, striking, etc.
(2) The sensations connected witli the nervous system
comprise those arising from the state of the nervous
system — its general condition, not from a special ex-
citement. The nerves, are, however, concerned in all
sensation.
(3) The sensations connected with the nutritive and
circulatory systems are such as result from hunger or
thirst, or their opposites, and those resulting from an
unhealthy state of tlie organs of digestion.
(4) The sensations connected with the resjrlraiory
system are such as the exhilaration resulting from copi-
ous respiration in pure air, and the feeling of suffocation
resulting from bad air or from a lack of air.
(5) The sensations resulting from the general condition
of the body are such as result from the vigor or elastic-
ity of health, from the weakness of disease, from rest,
from fatigue, from the degree of temperature, etc.
2d. The special sensations are those which are acquired
through the special senses — smell, taste, touch, hearing,
and sight. These senses are the principal means for
acquiring a knowledge of external objects.
(1) The sensations of smell are known by conscious-
ness as located in the nostrils. They may be divided,
as to quality, into agreeable and disagreeable, each of
which may be subdivided, both with respect to qualit}^
and quantity, into an almost endless number of vari-
eties. It is, y)erha|)s, true that no two I'oses, even from
the same bush, have ])recisely the same odor, and that
no two things smell exactly alike. Since it is impos-
sible to apply names to all these varieties, so countless
96 PSYCHOLOGY.
in numbers, it is customary to designate them, either
by the effects which they cause in us, or by the objects
from which they proceed. Thus, we speak of agreeable
or offensive odors, of the odor of the rose, etc.
(2) The sensations of taste are known by conscious-
ness as located in the tongue, the palate, and a portion
of the pharynx. These sensations, as those of smell, are
divided with respect to quality into agreeable and disa-
greeable, and each of these may be subdivided into
numberless varieties. Perhaps no two dishes of food
have precisely the same flavor. The wonderful discrim-
inating power of taste is doubtless the reason why this
sense, which ministers to a gross appetite, gives name
to the power of appreciating the beautiful in Nature,
Literature, and Art. As it is impossible to devise names
lor all the varieties of flavor, they are designated, like
those of odor, by their eff'ects or by their causes.
(3) The sensations of touch may be experienced at
every point on the surface of the body, but especially
in the ends of the Angers, the lips, and the tip of the
toniJ-ue. The nature of these sensations can be learned
only from experience. The sense of touch is very im-
portant. In fact, certain philosophers regard touch as
the fundamental sense, and the other senses as its sj)ecial
modifications.
(4) The sensations of hearing are located in the ear.
Sounds, when classified, both as to quality and quantity,
exhibit a wonderful variety. They vary from low to
high, through all the intermediate degrees, and, in like
manner, from feeble to loud, from soft to harsh, from
smooth to rough, from light to heavy, and from musical
to discordant. ]^o two persons speak the same word
exactly alike, even though speaking on the same key;
for there will be a difference either in the qualities of
their voices, or in their manner of speaking.
SENSATION. 97
(5) The sensations of sight are acquired througli the
eye, and are classified botli with respect to quality and
quantity. Light varies from the faintest glimmer to
the most dazzling brightness. The primary colors, by
their possible degrees of intensity, and by their combi-
nations with one another, afford shades of color wonder-
ful in beauty, and countless in variety.
Light is supposed to be due to the vibrations of a
subtle medium called ether. According to Tyndall,
" The color of light is determined solely by its wave-
length. The ether-weaves gradually diminish in length
from red to violet. The length of a wave of red light
is about 3 9^0 of an inch ; that of the wave of violet
light is about 57^00 of an inch. The waves which pro-
duce the other colors of the spectrum lie between these
extremes."
The velocity of light is 192,000 miles per second,
which, reduced to inches, and multiplied, respectively, by
39,000 and 57,500, will give 474,439,680,000,000, and
699,494,400,000,000, the number of vibrations, per sec-
ond, respectively, of red and violet light.
White light is produced by a combination of all the
colors in due proportion. It may also be produced by
certain combinations of two colors. Any two colors
which, when mixed, will produce white, are called com-
plementary. The different white lights thus produced
cause sensations which are indistinguishable, though the
lights themselves are physically distinguishable by their
different reactions. Green is produced by combining
blue and yellow; and violet, by the blending of red
and blue.
Psy.— 9.
CHAPTER YIII.
PERCEPTION.
1. Perception defined as an act and as a faculty.
1st. As an act^ perception is that process of the intel-
lect by which it gains a knowledge of external objects.
It is sometimes called sense-perception^ to distinguish it
from other processes frequently called perception, as
when one says, "My perception of this truth is clear.''
We shall, however, for the sake of brevity, employ the
term perception in the technical sense of that of sense-
perception.
2d. As a faculty^ perception is the power to perceive
external objects by means of the senses. Thus, we say,
" Man is endowed with the power of perception."
2. Conditions of perception. — The conditions of per-
ception are an object to be perceived, a subject capable
of perceiving, and such a relation of object and subject
as to cause a sensation.
3. Elements of perception. — The elements involved in
the act of percei)tion are the sensational, the intuitional,
the inferential, and the ideational.
1st. The sensational element is the sensation accompa-
nying an excitement of the nerves, caused by the ac-
tion of an excitant upon the organism. This sensation
is experienced in consciousness, and is analyzed, com-
pared, identified or discriminated, and classified by re-
flection. Abstraction and voluntary attention are involved
in reflection as the first steps. Sensation, though in-
volved in the complex process of perception, is rather
(98)
PERCEPTION,— GENERAL VIEW, 99
the antecedent or condition of perception than perception
itself. As the beginning of perception it may be re-
garded as an element of the process. In fact, sensation,
original or revived, mingles more or less with the other
elements of perception.
2d. The intuitional element is subjective or objective.
The subjective intuitional element is the apprehension,
by rational intuition, of the conditional necessity of the
ego, with the faculties implied, as the subject of the per-
ception. This element being always present does not
attract especial attention. The objective intuitional ele-
ment is the apprehension, by rational intuition, of the
conditioned necessity of a cause of the sensation of which
we are conscious. Intuition, though apprehending the
conditional necessity of the cause of the sensation, does
not apprehend the cause itself.
3d. The inferential eleynent is the judgment based on
experience, or on investigation, or on information in any
way acquired, by which we infer what the cause of the
sensation is in reality. It is the conclusion which the
intellect reaches concerning the object which causes the
sensation.
4th. The ideational element is the construction by an
act of the imagination, of the appearance of the object
which causes the sensation. Thus, we look upon an
object, and see it with our eyes open. We then close
our eyes, and represent the same object. In the first
case, we construct the appearance under the stimulus of
sensation; but in the second case, we construct the ap-
pearance, by the aid of the memory, in the absence of
sensation. If we can picture the object in the absence
of sensation, we certainly ought to be able to do it
under the stimulus of sensation. The appearance is con-
structed in much the same way in the two cases, though
the object, w^hen presented to the sense, giving definite
100 PSYCHOLOGY,
sensations, followed by definite inferences, compels defi-
nite constructions. These constructions are more vivid
and rich in elements than the appearances constructed
in the absence of sensation. The construction of the
pictures, by the imagination, in the absence of the sen-
sation, is mainly an intellectual act. There may be re-
sidual sensations, as when spots are seen after pressing
the eye; or revived sensations, as the images which
Newton could recall, by act of the will, after looking at
the sun. But, more frequently, the image formed in
the absence of the object or when the sense is closed,
is purely the creation of the imagination, without sen-
sation. This is clear in case an object is represented
which has not been perceived or thought of for a long
time. No residuum of the sensation can be supposed to
remain, but the image formed by the imagination is
clear and distinct.
A percept is the knowledge of a quality of an object
gained through a single sense, as the cause of a sensa-
tion in that sense. A percept may be ideated^ that is,
developed into an idea, which may be committed to the
keeping of the memory, and recalled, as occasion may
require.
The combination of all the percepts relating to an ob-
ject, gained through all the senses, is the appearance of
the object, as acquired by the combined use of all the
senses ; but the combination of our ideas of these various
percepts is our idea of the object.
The combination of all the qualities of an object which
are known as the objects of all our percepts relating to
that object, constitutes the object as known by the act
of perception.
The combination of all the qualities of an object which
are known as the objects of all our percepts relating to
the object, together with all other qualities and pow-
PERCEPTION, — GENERAL VIEW. 101
ers in tliat objectj constitute that object as it is in it-
self.
The perceptions through the general sensations are
more or less vague. It is only those through the spe-
cial sensations that are clear and distinct, and these we
shall now proceed to consider.
4. Order of treatment. — Any one of the three fbUow-
ing orders might be adopted: We might begin with
touch, then pass to the consideration of the other senses,
regarding them as modifications of the general sense of
touch ; or we might begin with sight, the highest sense,
then descend through hearing, touch, and taste, to the
sense of smell; or we might begin with smell, the low-
est sense, then ascend, through the successive gradations,
to sight, the highest and most perfect sense. We have
adopted the latter order as being the most simple and
satisfactory.
CHAPTEE IX.
PERCEPTION THROUGH SMELL AND TASTE.
1. Perception through smell involves sensation, intui-
tion, inference, and ideation.
1st. Sensations of odor, as known by consciousness, are
located in the nostrils. They are analyzed, compared,
identified or discriminated, and classified by reflection.
2d. Rational intuition apprehends the conditional ne-
cessity of the subject and also of the cause.
(1) The sensation being given, intuition apprehends
the conditional necessity of the ego with the faculties
involved, as the subject of the sensation, and of the cor-
responding perception. This element is unobtrusive,
since the attention of the ego is directed, not to itself,
as being present in every phenomenon, but to the sen-
sation and its cause, especially to the sensation.
(2) Intuition also apprehends the conditional necessity
of the cause of the sensation, but not the cause itself
It apprehends that the sensation must have a cause, but
it does not apprehend what the cause is, nor decide
whether it is within or without the organism.
3d. The inference is the judgment derived from expe-
rience, investigation, or other sources, inferring the cause
of the sensation. This cause is not in the ego; for the ego
is passive in sensation, since sensations are experienced,
not only without special volition, but in spite of volition.
The cause is, therefore, objective to the ego, though it
is not necessarily objective to the organism.
From science we learn that the immediate cause of
(102)
PERCEPTION TITROUOH SMELL, 103
the sensation of odor is the excitement of the olfactory
nerves located in the nose; that the cause of the excite-
ment is some gaseous effluvium coming in contact with
the organ of smell; and that this effluvium is exhaled
from bodies, thence called odorous, since the sensation
follows the presence of such bodies, and ceases on their
removal.
The variety in the sensation of odor, in different cases,
is accounted for bv the difference in the remote cause,
though the peculiar nature of the cause is wholly un-
known. The reason why a certain effluvium should
excite one sensation rather than another can only be
conjectured.
Having learned by experience the nature of the sen-
sation excited by the exhalations of a given odorous
body, then, whenever that sensation is experienced, w^e
infer the presence of that body. There is a possibility
of mistake in this inference, since different objects may
excite sensations of odor scarcely distinguishable. Intu-
ition in affirming that the sensation has a cause, does
not err; but the judgment which affirms what the cause
is in itself, may err.
4th. Ldeation pictures to the mind the remote cause
of the sensation, after the judgment has inferred what
that cause is. In constructing the appearance, the body
from which the odor proceeds is usually represented as
it appears through the other senses, especially through
the sense of sight.
5th. The relative prominence of sensation, intuition, in-
ference, and ideation, is a matter of interest. In smell,
the sensation predominates, and mainly absorbs the at-
tention. The intuition of the conditional necessity of
the subject and object is unobtrusive, though perhaps
less so in case of the object than of the subject. The
inference relates to the object which causes the sen-
1 04 PSYCHOL OGY,
sation, and. is more prominent than the intuition, but
less prominent than the sensation. The idea of the im-
mediate cause of the excitement of the organ is vague,
since the nature of this cause is occult; but the idea of
the remote cause from which the exhalation comes, is
clear, derived as it is from sight.
6th. The utility of the sense of smell is threefold:
(1) It affords pleasure through the sensations of agree-
able odors, and thus adds to the enjoyment of life.
(2) It guards us, through the sensations of disagreea-
ble odors, against danger from deleterious exhalations or
from unwholesome food.
(3) It may sometimes be used as a chemical test in
identifying a substance.
7th. The sense of smell is in close sympathy with the
sense of taste, which is in immediate proximity. Savory
odors excite the appetite, while offensive smells occasion
disgust and disinclination for food.
2. Perception through taste involves sensation, intui-
tion, inference, and ideation.
1st. Sensations of flavor^ as given by consciousness, are
located in the tongue and palate, and a portion of the
pharynx. They are analyzed, compared, identified or
discriminated, and classified by reflection.
2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of
the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object
as the cause of the sensation.
3d. The inference is the judgment inferring the cause
of the sensation. This cause is not in the ego, which
is passive in sensation, and is, therefore, objective to the
ego, but not necessarily objective to the organism.
By experience, we learn that the cause of the sensa-
tion of taste is a sapid body brought in contact with
the organs of taste, producing in these organs an ex-
citement, which is the immediate cause of the sensation.
PERCEPTION THROUGH TASTE, 105
From science, we learn the structure and functions
of the organs of taste, and that a sapid body, to excite
the sensation of taste, must be in a liquid state, or un-
dergo, at least, a partial liquefaction.
What the nature of the cause of the sensation of taste
is, in itself, we know not, save that the cause must be
adequate to the production of the sensation. There is,
perhaps, chemical action between the sapid body and
the organ of taste; but why one element should pro-
duce one sensation, and another element another sensa-
tion, we know not. What the object is, and that it
produces the sensation, can be ascertained; but how it
produces the sensation, or why that sensation rather
than another, is a mystery.
Having learned by experience with what bodies cer-
tain sensations are connected, then whenever we identify
a sensation which we have learned is caused by an ob-
ject of a certain class, we infer the object which excites
the sensation. There is a possibility of mistake in this
inference, since different objects may excite sensations
scarcely distinguishable; but the mistake, if it occur, is
not in the intuition that there must be a cause, but in
the judgment inferring what that cause is.
4th,- Ideation pictures, not the occult quality which is
the real cause of the excitement of the nerves of taste,
but the object of which this cause is a quality, as it has
been found by experience to appear through the other
senses, especially sight and touch, and thus completes
the process of perception.
5th. As to the relative i^Tominence of these four elements,
it is to be observed that sensation, as the chief object of
attention, predominates, though not in so marked a de-
gree as in smell. The ego with the faculties involved is
implicitly assumed, but is not made the object of special
attention. The intuition of the conditional necessity of
106 PSYCHOLOGY.
the cause is more prominent. The inference is more
conspicuous than the intuition, but less conspicuous than
the sensation. The image formed by ideation is clear
and distinct.
6th. The utility of the sense of taste is threefold :
(1) It contributes to our enjoyment through the agree-
able sensations which it affords.
(2) It guards against danger through the disagreeable
sensations, which deleterious articles of food excite.
(3) It may be used as a chemical test in identifying
a given substance.
7th. Taste is intimately associated with touch, as the
organs of taste are also organs of touch. In general,
we may say, taste gives the sensations of flavor, and
touch the sensations of roughness or smoothness; yet in
certain cases, these sensations approach and seem to
blend. This fact suggests the inquiry whether taste is
not a special modification of touch — that is, touch trans-
formed and intensified, and located in proximity to the
sense of smell with which it acts in sympathy.
CHAPTEE X.
PERCEPTION THROUGH TOUCH AND HEARING.
1. Perception through touch involves sensation, intui-
tion, inference, and ideation.
1st. Sensations of touchy as given by consciousness, are
located at the extremity of the nerves terminating in
the skin, especially at the tips of the fingers, the lips,
and the tongue. They are analyzed, compared, identi-
fied or discriminated, and classified by reflection.
2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of
the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object
as the cause of the sensation.
3d. The iyiference is the judgment inferring the cause
of the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which
is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego. When
the sensation of touch is experienced, we infer that this
sensation is caused by some external body in contact
with the organ of touch. As the pressure increases, the
tactual sensation runs gradually into the muscular sen-
sation, and the acute perception of touch proper is trans-
ferred, by insensible degrees, into the perception of a
resisting body, as the cause of the muscular sensation.
From Anatomy and Physiology, we learn the structure
and functions of the organs of touch in their relations
to the muscular and nervous systems.
Through the sense of touch, especially in its relation
to the muscular sensation, we obtain unimpeachable ev-
idence of the existence of objects external to ourselves —
not external to our spirits only, but to our bodies.
(107)
108 PSYCHOLOGY,
We have already found that we are conscious of sen-
sations localized more or less definitely in the sensoriiim,
which is immediately known as the locus of sensation,
but not as the nervous system and the sense organs,
which constitute, as we learn from science, the material
apparatus of sensation. The sensorium, as the locus of
sensation, is immediately known to be extended, since
the sensations, as localized, are known to be reciprocally
external. Simultaneous sensations, not reciprocally ex-
ternal, especially if the same in quality, would blend
into one, and be indistinguishable. But the fact that
such sensations are distinguishable, is proof that they
are reciprocally external, and in fact, as such, they are
discriminated. Space is at once apprehended by rational
intuition as the necessary logical antecedent of the fact
that similar simultaneous sensations are discriminated.
If the tips of the fingers of one hand be moved along
the other hand, a double sensation is at once excited —
the sensation in the fingers touching, and the sensation
in the hand touched. The sensations in the two hands
are discriminated as situated in loci reciprocally exter-
nal. As the fingers move along the hand, the motion
is detected by the changing localities of the sensations
in the hand touched. The loci of these sensations are
noticed and constructed into unity, thus giving exten-
sion. On pressing the fingers the sensation becomes
muscular, a perception of resistance arises, and the hand
touched is known, not only as extended, but as resist-
ing. The belief in the correctness of this perception is
strengthened and confirmed by grasping one hand with
the other. The hand grasped is known to be extended
by the loci of the sensations within itself and within
the grasping hand; and it has the power of resistance,
and is therefore a solid, as is known by its opposing the
effort made to close the other hand.
PERCEPTION THROUGH TOUCIT, 109
If now the hand of another person be substituted for
the hand before grasped, the sensations in the grasping
hand will be simihxr to those before experienced, and
their loci will reveal extent, not only in the grasping
hand, but in the hand grasped, and the resistance will
reveal solidity. These perceptions will be confirmed by
those of the other person.
If another object be grasped by the hand, analogous
sensations will be experienced in the grasping hand,
followed, as before, by the perception of extension, form,
and resistance. The hand applied to a great variety
of objects will reveal, with respect to each, its size, form,
and power of resistance, and will enable us to decide
whether a given object is rough or smooth, hard or soft,
solid or fluid, sharp or blunt, in motion or at rest.
Having thus found that there are bodies external to
our organism, then, when encountering a resistance to
our locomotive energy, and not being conscious of caus-
ing the resistance ourselves^ but being conscious of en-
deavoring to overcome it, we judge that the power
causing the resistance is e:j^ternal to ourselves, and by
the application of the hand, learn other qualities of the
resisting object.
The sensations of jpain arising when the body is cut
or pierced by sharp tools, or burned by a hot body, are
not sensations of touch. Such sensations, by their
greater intensity, obscure those of touch, and are fol-
lowed by perceptions peculiar to themselves.
4th. Ideation pictures to the mind the nature of the
surface, according to the sensation^ as rough or smooth,
also the form of the body, and the appearance which it
would present to the eye.
5th. As to the relative jprominence of the four elements
connected with the sense of touch, it is to be observed
that the sensation, the intuition, the inference, and the
110 PSYCHOLOGY,
idea are, in average cases, in equilibrium. The tactual
sensation is sensibly experienced; the intuition of the
necessity of the subject and object is clear; the inference
that the sensation is caused by an external object in
contact with the organ is decided ; and the ideated pict-
ure distinctly embodies the inferential judgment, and
thus completes the process of perception.
In passing from smell, through taste to touch, we find
that, in average cases, the sensation diminishes, the in-
tuition remains constant, the inference becomes more
positive, and the idea more clear and distinct.
6th. The utility of the sense of touch will be manifest
when we reflect that it reveals the external world more
positively and certainly than any other sense. The
causes of the sensations of smell and taste, though their
necessity is apprehended by intuition, are in their nat-
ure occult. The cause of the sensation of hearing can
not, but by the aid of the other senses, especially of
touch, be positively known to be external to the ear
itself We may question whether the object supposed to
be seen be not an illusion; but when we touch it, and
handle it, and find it extended, figured, solid, and resist-
ing, we no longer doubt its external reality.
7th. The relation of touch to the other senses is inter-
esting. It is an opinion, ancient as the time of Democ-
ritus, that all the other senses are only modifications of
touch. This opinion, though rejected by Aristotle with
the assertion that its impossibility is manifest, was re-
vived by Telesius, an Italian philosopher of the sixteenth
century, and has been adopted by many philosophers of
modern times. All the senses involve touch, or contact
of something external with the organs of sense; but
smell and taste involve, perhaps, chemical action as well
as mechanical contact. The sensations given by the vari-
ous senses difi'er so widely, as is evident from a compar-
PERCEPTION THROUGH HEARING. Ill
ison of the sensations of odor, taste, touch, sound, and
color, that there is good reason for the popular classifi-
cation of the five special senses.
2. Perception through hearing, as through smell,
taste, and touch, involves sensation, intuition, inference,
and ideation.
1st. Sensations of sounds as given by consciousness, are
located in the ear. They are analyzed, compared, iden-
tified or discriminated, and classified by refiection.
2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of
the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object
as the cause of the sensation.
3d. The inference is the judgment inferring the cause
of the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which
is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego, but not
necessarily objective to the organism.
We learn from experiment that a vibrating body com-
municates vibrations to the air, which are propagated
to the ear, causing in this organ an excitement which
is the immediate cause of the sensation of which we are
conscious. From the sciences of Anatomy and Physiol-
ogy, we learn the structure and functions of the organ
of hearing.
4th. Ideation pictures the inference, and represents the
cause as it would appear through other senses, especially
sight, thus completing the act of perception.
5th. As to the relative prominence of the four elements
involved in hearing, it is to be observed that the sensa-
tion is noticeable, the intuition real, the inference prom-
inent, and the ideation clear and distinct. Let us notice
the working of these elements in the process of percep-
tion through hearing. We are conscious of a sensation
of sound, the attention is abstracted from other things,
and directed to the sensation, which is analyzed and
classified. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity
112 PSYCHOLOGY.
of the subject with the faculties involved. This element
is unobtrusive, since the ego is implied by every phe-
nomenon, and does not, therefore, attract special atten-
tion. Intuition also apprehends the conditional necessity
of the cause, but not what the cause is. Science informs
us that the immediate cause of the sensation is the ex-
citement of the auditory nerves, caused by the vibrations
of the air, which are, in turn, caused by the vibrations
of the sonorous body. The inference is the judgment
affirming the cause. The cause is objectified — that is,
the sound is judged to be caused by the vibrating body,
w^hich is more or less remote, the intermediate causes
being but obscurely recognized. The cause is ideated,
and we are said to perceive the object. The agitation
of the nerves, and the immediate and remote causes of
this agitation are the conditions of the sensation ; they
are the antecedents of the complex process- of the per-
ception, rather than elements of that process.
6th. It is not correct to say that we perceive an ob-
ject through its representative idea, as if we began with
the idea as a third thing intervening between the object
and the mind; for the idea is the last step in the pro-
cess of perception. It is the joint product of the action
of the objective cause and of the percipient mind, and
embodies our inference, or conclusion, concerning the
cause of the sensation.
7th. The utility of the sense of hearing is evident.
Sound not only reveals external objects, but, in certain
cases, w^arns us of danger, and, as employed in language,
is expressive of thought, feeling, or volition. To this
sense we are largely indebted for the pleasures of social
intercourse, and for the enjoyments derived from the
arts of music and oratory.
CHAPTER XL
PERCEPTION THROUGH SIGHT.
Perception through sight, as through the otlier senses,
involves sensation, intuition, inference, and ideation.
1st. The sensations of color ^ light ^ and shade are located
in*the eye. These sensations are given by conscious-
ness, and are analyzed, compared, identified or discrim-
inated, and classified b}^ reflection.
2d. Intuition apprehends the conditional necessity of
the subject with the faculties implied, and of the object
as the cause of the sensation.
3d. The inference is the judgment as to the cause of
the sensation. This cause not being in the ego, which
is passive in sensation, is objective to the ego.
By experience we learn that light is an essential con-
dition of vision; and, guided by touch, we infer that a
material object, more or less distant, from which light
comes to the eye, is the remote cause of the sensation,
and is the object of perception.
From Optics, as a branch of Physics, we learn the
nature and laws of light, and from Anatomy" and Phj^si-
ology, the structure and function of the eye.
Every point in the surface of an object sends out, in
all directions, rays of light in straight lines diverging
from that point From a single point in the visible
surface of an object, the rays of a diverging pencil in
the form of a cone whose vertex is at the point and
whose base fills the pupil of the eye, enter the eye
through the pupil, and are, by the lenses, brought to a
Psy.-lO. ( 113^)
114 PSYCHOLOGY.
focus at some point on the net-work of nerves, called
the retina, which lines the dark choroid coat of the
inner chamber of the eye. The focus of the rays of the
converging pencil is the vertex of an interior cone of
rays having a common base with the exterior cone.
The accommodation of the eye so as to secure distinct
vision, at different distances, needs attention. It is a
condition of distinct vision that the rays diverging from
a point, in a pencil, and entering the pupil of the eye
be brought, by the lenses, accurately to a focus on the
retina of the eye. Let us suppose a point at such a
distance from the eye that the diverging rays from it,
which enter the eye are brought exactly to a focus on
the retina. Now, if the point be removed a little farther
from the ej^e, the rays from this point, which enter the
eye, would be less diverging, and it would seem that
they would be brought to a focus before reaching the
retina, and crossing at this focus, and diverging back of
it, would be spread on the retina in a circle of diffusion
having the central ray for its axis. If the point be
moved nearer the eye than its first position, it would seem
that the interior pencil would reach the retina before
the rays are brought to a focus, giving, in this case, also
a diffusion circle. A circle of diffusion would actually be
formed whenever the point is at a greater or less dis-
tance than a certain distance, about eighteen inches in
normal cases, were it not for the power of accommoda-
tion which the eye possesses. The accommodation is
secured by a greater convexity of the anterior surface
of the lens as the point is brought nearer the eye, or a
less convexity, as the point is removed farther from the
eye. This change in convexity is eff'ected by a contrac-
tion of the ciliary muscle, when the point is brought
nearer the eye, and by a relaxation of this muscle,
when the point is removed to a greater distance.
PER CEPTION THE O UOH SIGHT. 1 1 5
In directing attention from a distant to a near object,
or the reverse, we are conscious of a feeling indicating
a change going on in the eye — in the first case, of ac-
tive accommodation; in the second, of relaxation. Both
the fact and the necessity of accommodation can be
shown by experiment. Fix two pins upright about 3
feet apart, and look at them with one eye nearly in
range w4th the pins, and about 2 feet from the nearest
pin. If attention be directed to either pin, the other
will appear blurred. Either j)in can, at w^ill, be made
to appear distinct, but not both at the same time.
We have seen that from a single point in the visible
surface of an object, rays of a diverging pencil enter
the eye, and are brought to a focus on the retina.
Rays of pencils from adjacent points in the surface of
the object are brought to foci, on the retina, in adjacent
points wdiich are symmetrically arranged with respect
to the corresponding points in the object. In like man-
ner, rays of pencils from all the visible j^oints of the
object, are brought to their proper foci in corresponding
points on the retina, thus forming on the retina an im-
age w^hich is a miniature picture of the object. The
cause of the sensation at each point of the image on the
retina is, by an act of judgment, objectified and located
in its proper position in the surface of the object. If
the lenses of the eye bring the rays to foci before reach-
ing the retina, or if they reach the retina before coming
to a focus, circles of difiusion will be formed, which by
overlapping one another and confusing the image, render
the perception of the object indistinct.
Near-sighted persons wear concave glasses to counter-
act the excessive convexity of the lenses of their eyes.
As persons grow old, they gradually lose the power of
adjusting their eyes to near objects, especially when
small, and are obliged to use convex glasses.
116 PSYCHOLOGY.
4th. Ideation combines and pictures in their true po-
sitions the objectified causes of the sensations at all the
points of the image on the retina, and thus constructs
the objective appearance so as to embody the conclusions
of the inferential judgment. The vivid pictures appear-
ing in vision are our ideas of the objects which cause
the sensations. These pictures embody our conclusions
respecting the objects, and as objectified, coincide with
the objects, though they are not the objects themselves,
as will clearly appear, while we pursue our investiga-
tions.
5th. As to the relative prominence of the four elements
of vision, it is to be observed that the sensation is un-
obtrusive, except in case of dazzling light, and brilliant
or finely-blended colors; the intuition of the conditional
necessity of the ego is implicitly assumed, while that of
the cause is explicitly recognized; the inference is clear
and definite; and the idea is distinct and vivid.
In passing from smell, through taste, touch, and hear-
ing to sight, in average cases, sensation decreases from
its maximum in smell to its minimum in sight; intuition
remains constant; inference and ideation increase from
their minimum in smell to their maximum in siii^ht. In
smell and taste, sensation is greater than intuition, intu-
ition than inference, and inference than ideation ; in
touch, sensation, intuition, inference, and ideation are in
equilibrium; in hearing and sight, sensation is less than
intuition, intuition than inference, and inference than
ideation.
6th. The physiological conditions of sight are the eye,
with its coats, the sclerotic, choroid, and retina, its cor-
nea, iris, and crystalline lens, its pupil, chambers, and
humors, also the optic nerve and higher centers.
Seeing is not consummated in the eye. The optic
nerve conveys the impressions made on the retina to a
PER CEPTION Tim O UGH SIGHT, 117
cluster of four tubercules, or ganglia, called tlie tubercula
quadrigemina,, where they are received and transmitted
to higher centers. These tubercules, by reflex action,
excite the iris, and thus automatically contract or ex-
pand the pupil, so as to regulate the amount of light
received by the retina. In like manner, by reflex action,
the direction of the optic axes are automatically adjusted
to an object near or remote.
The tubercula quadrigemina, perhaps reinforced by the
optic thalamic co-ordinate visual impressions with mus-
cular sensations, and thus preside over those muscular
efforts made in maintaining equilibrium or producing
motion, in all cases in which sight is essential to perfect
action. Let the experiment be made of balancing the
body on one foot with the eyes first open then closed.
The visual impressions made upon the retina, received
and co-ordinated by the tubercula quadrigemina and
optic thalami, are sent up to the angular gyms, a section
of the parietal lobe, where they are photographed and
still further elaborated, and forwarded to the frontal
lobes of the brain, where the judgment as to the cause
of the sensation is pronounced, the conclusion ideated,
and the process of vision consummated.
The following quotation from Dr. Clark's Visions, page
133, places the entire process of seeing, as viewed from a
physiological stand-point, in a clear light:
" When light waves from an uplifted dagger fall on
the retina, the eye records the facts of color, size, posi-
tion, motion, etc., and transmits an account of them to
the tubercula quadrigemina. This center carefully ad-
justs tlie mechanism of the eye, the iris, lenses, muscular
apparatus and the like, to the demands of careful obser-
vation, co-ordinates the general muscular system for any
movement the emergency may require, and makes its
visual report to the angular gyrus. The latter center
118 PSYCHOLOGY,
receives the report, perceives all the details of the dagger,
the hand grasping it, the face and action of the owner,
whatever constitutes an exact picture of the scene, and
transmits a corresponding pictorial re])ort to the frontal
lobes. Upon receiving this report — this pictorial repre-
sentation, — the lobes look at it, ascertain its significance,
determine whether the uplifted dagger is raised for in-
spection merely, or for a threatened or real plunge, or
for other purposes, communicate with the instincts and
emotions, and decide the will to act."
7th. The object 2)rimarily revealed in consciousness is
not the remote object, or cause of the sensation, nor the
waves of light reflected from the object to the eye, nor
the image formed on the retina, nor the excitement of the
nerves of the retina or of the optic nerve, or of the higher
centers, but the sensation of color or of light and shade,
obscurely located in the retina, though this sensation is
unobtrusive, except in case of strong light or brilliant
colors. The phenomena following sensation — the intui-
tion, the inference, and the ideation, are also objects of
consciousness.
The object known by rational intuition is neither the
sensation, nor the nature of the exciting cause, but the
conditional necessity of the ego as the subject of the sen-
sation, and the conditional necessity of the object as the
cause of the sensation.
The objects inferred by the judgment are the visible
qualities in the external object which excite sensation.
The idea is the picture, or appearance, embodying our
conclusions respecting the object. This idea, though
originally formed under the stimulus of sensation, can
be retained and recalled in the absence of sensation, in
which case it is less vivid but more indeterminate.
8th. To explain how we perceive the true 2)osition,
magnitude, and form of objects, let it be observed that
PERCEPTION TIIEOUOII SIOIIT. 119
the cause of a sensation at a point on the retina at the
vertex of an interior pencil, is objectified, ideated, and
located at the vertex of the corresponding exterior pen-
cil, the point from which the rays came, and the only
point from which they could come, having the direction
with which they meet at the focus. The objective poiut
is ideated, and thus seen in its true position.
The perception of the point in its true place ma}-, in
part, though this is not probable, be owing to a native
insight, analogous to the instinct of a young chick which
perceives a crumb in its true place, as is proved by the
fact that it picks it up. In man, however, the power
to perceive a point in its true place, is, no doubt, chiefly,
if not entirely, acquired gradually by experience, guided,
in some degree, by the sense of touch, which is tutor to
the eye; for, if the point be within reach, its location can
be verified by stretching out the hand and touching it, or
if a little farther off, by going to it. The location of
more distant objects can be only approximately deter-
mined by sight; but no correct estimate of the distance
of such remote objects as the stars can be made through
vision. The determination of these distances requires
the nicest measurements and accurate computation.
The causes of the sensations at all the points of the
image on the retina are objectified, ideated, and per-
ceived to be located, respectively, at the corresponding
points of the object, giving the assemblage of all the
visible points in their true ^^ositions, and thus the object
is seen in its proper place, form, and magnitude.
The movement of a visible point in space is detected
by the movement of the image of that point on the re-
tina, though of this movement we seemed to be uncon-
scious, since the attention is chiefly directed to the move-
ment of the objective point. The perception of a varie-
gated surface proves that the sensation at each point of
120 PSYCHOLOGY,
the image is referred to its special cause in the object.
The cause of the sensation at each point of the image
being objectified, located, and pictured at the vertex of
the corresponding exterior pencil, the point from which
the rajs came, the assemblage of all these objective,
pictured points gives a picture of the object, having not
onl}^ color, but outline and form; but since the points
of this picture coincide with the corresponding points in
the surface of the object, it follows that the object itself
has extent and form, and this is confirmed by the sense
of touch.
9th. Why does the object appear at full size when the*
image on the retina is a miniature picture? The axis,
or central ray of the pencil, from the objective point
through the center of the lens to the image of the point
on the retina, is not refracted, and is, therefore, a straight
line; that is, the axes of the two corresponding pencils,
exterior and interior, form one straight line. The ex-
terior pencil is longer than the interior, and hence the
divergence of the exterior pencil, as the rays come from
the point to the eye, is less than the convergence of
the interior. Now take an object, as a cane, and hold
it, in a vertical position, a few yards from the eye.
The axes of the pencils of rays from the extreme points
of the cane cross at the center of the crystalline lens;
and since the exterior pencils are longer than the in-
terior, the points at the extremities of the cane, which
are seen in their true position, are farther apart than
the images of these points on the retina; hence, the ob-
ject appears at full size, while its image on the retina
is only a miniature picture. Of this image we are un-
conscious, since the sensation is unobtrusive, and the
attention is directed to the objective appearance.
10th. Why is the image immrtedf and how is the ob-
ject seen erect? Since the axes of the pencils of rays
PER CEPTION Tim O UGH SIGHT. 121
from any two points cross each other at the center of
the lens, and when prolonged in straight lines^ fbrni the
axes of the corresponding interior pencils, the image of
the highest point of the object will be lowest on the ret-
ina, and the image of the low^est point of the object will
be highest on the retina. The images of the intermediate
points of the object are correspondingly^ arranged on the
retina, the image of the higher of two points being lower
on the retina; hence, the image is inverted. For like
reasons, the sides of the image are reversed; hence the
image is symmetrically arranged with respect to the
object.
How, then, is the object seen erect, and its sides in
their true position? Since the cause of the sensation at
the lowest point of the image is seen in its true posi-
tion at the vertex of the corresponding exterior pencil,
and hence at the highest point of the object, where it
actually is, and since the cause of the sensation at the
highest point of the image is seen where it is, at the
lowest point of the object, the object is inverted with
respect to the image, and since the image is inverted,
the object appears erect.
11th. Binocular vision^ or double vision through the
two eyes, demands attention. Why is it that we see an
object single, when an image of it is formed in each
eye? If we suppose two appearances for the same ob-
ject, one for each eye, giving to thought two appear-
ances, then, since each appearance is in coincidence with
the object, the supposed two appearances, coinciding
with the object, coincide Avith each other, and form but
one appearance, as we find in reality; but this one ap-
pearance is the combination of two appearances, as can
be proved by their separation on pressing one eye.
The two appearances blend, since for each point of the
image on the retina of one eye, there is a corresponding
Psy.— 11.
122 PSYCHOLOGY,
point of the other image, similarly situated on the ret-
ina of the other eye. The sensations at the two corres-
ponding points are referred to the same objective cause
in its true position, which is, therefore, seen as one
point; and as the same is true for every otlier point in
the visible surface of the object, it is evident that the
object ought to appear single, as is really the case.
To render this still clearer, let us consider the appear-
ance, though not the object itself, as the spontaneous
creation of the intellect, under the stimulus of the sen-
sation, objectifying the cause of the sensation, assigning
to it color, position, extent, and form, not as constitu-
ting the object, nor as representing all its qualities, since
it has other qualities as revealed by the other senses,
but as representing the qualities known in vision. Now,
the appearance in vision, considered as an external im-
age, constructed by the imagination under the stimulus
of sensation, as the product of the eifort of the intellect
to assign the true cause to the sensation, is in coinci-
dence with the object, as is verified by touch.
That the appearance is an objective image, a construc-
tion or creation of the mind, an idea embod^dng our
inference as to the objective cause of the sensation, and
not the object itself, is evident from the fact that if we
push one eye, moving it gently, we shall see two images
clearly separate, one at rest and the other in motion.
If the objective appearance is the object, there arc two
objects, one at rest and the other in motion; but there
is only one object under consideration, and that one at
rest; hence, the moving image is not the object. Neither
is the image at rest the object; for pushing the other
eye, this image moves as well as the other; but the ob-
ject is at rest, relatively, at least, as can be ascertained
from the testimony of a person touching it with his
hand; hence, neither image is the object, nor in this
I
PER CEPTION TIIU O UGH SIGHT. 1 23
ca.se in coincidence with the object, since the images are
moving while the object is at rest.
The reason why the objective image does not coincide
with the object, when the eye is pressed, is because the
internal image is thus moved to another part of the ret-
ina, where an image would be formed by an object in
the position of the external image, if the eye were not
pressed, and hence the objective image appears in that
position. Moving the eye moves the image on the ret-
ina the same as if the eye remained at rest, and the
object moved as the objective image appears to move;
hence, the appearance is constructed, when the eye is
pressed, as if the object moved.
If now the pressure be gradually removed from the two
eyes, the two objective images will approach and finally
coincide with each other and with the object, as can be
verified by the hand. The object is not now seen double,
though there is an image of it on the retina of each eye;
for the objective image, the appearance, seen through one
eye coincides with the object, and the appearance seen
through the other eye coincides with the object; hence,
these two appearances, or objective images, coinciding
with the same object, coincide with each other, or appear
as one objective image, though they maj^ be regarded as
two coincident images.
The creation of the image is, in popular language,
called "seeing the object," and this language is best for
common use. The spontaneous inference respecting the
cause of the sensation, and the ideation of the inference,
or the construction, by the imagination, under the stim-
ulus of the sensation, of the appearance embodying the
inference, is seeing the object. But the appearance seen,
when the eyes are open, is no more the object than is
the appearance imagined when the eyes are shut. The
appearance seen when the eyes are open is held, by the
124 PSYCHOLOGY.
sensation, to a correspondence with the reality, while the
appearance imagined when the eyes are shut, can be
changed at will.
Seeing with the two eyes aids in the perception of
reliefs by which a body appears to stand out from a
plane, or to have a third dimension, that is, depth, or
thickness, in addition to length and breadth. Thus,
when a small object, as a marble, is held near the face,
the part of the surface seen by either eye, is that hem-
isphere whose pole is the nearest e!xtremity of the di-
ameter which, when produced, would pass through the
pupil of that eye ; hence, with the two eyes, more than
half of the surface is seen. In seeing, as it were, par-
tially around the object, on opposite sides, the object ap-
pears raised, or stands out in space.
A point is not seen in the same direction with the two
eyes, though it is seen in the same position. Hold one
finger near the face, and look at it towards a wall, first
closing one eye, then opening that eye and closing the
other. It will be found that the range of the finger on
the wall has perceptibly changed. Open both eyes, and
look at the wall in the direction of the finger. Two
transparent images of the finger appear, through which
the wall is seen beyond. In looking at the wall, the optic
axes, or lines of vision, are adjusted for the distance of
the wall, and not for the distance of the finger, which
would require a greater convergence of the axes. Two
objective images of the finger appear, since the internal
images, with their sensations, have the same positions on
the retinas of the two eyes, as they would have if caused
by two objects, one for each eye, in the ranges of the re-
spective objective images, and the mind constructs the
images according to the usual interpretation of such sensa-
tions. The images appear transparent, neither concealing
the wall in the range with it and the eye with which it
FEB CEPTION THE O UGH SIGHT. 125
is seen, since that portion of the wall is seen through the
other eye. If one eye be closed, one image will vanish
and the other will become opaque. If that eye be opened
again, the image which vanished will reappear, and the
other will again become transparent. The two images
w^ill approach and finally coincide, as the attention is
withdraw^n from the w^all and directed to the finger, and
a spot on the wall in the direction of the finger w411
appear double.
12th. The material reality is the remote cause of the
sensation. The appearance is the spontaneous creation
of the mind, embodying its inference concerning the
cause. This ideated inference, however, is not the cause
itself The real objective, or remote cause is more than
an image — it is a material reality. But how do w^e
know that there is such a reality? The image which
embodies our ideas of the cause of a visual sensation,
combines the percepts of color, locality, extent, and form.
This combination of percepts, as a mere creation of the
mind, located in space, could not, in itself, afPect the
sense of touch, nor offer any resistance to our muscular
energy. It is absurd to supj)ose that the construction,
by the imagination, projected into space, of the combi-
nations of decisions that the cause of certain ocular
sensations has a certain color, position, extent, and form,
could also excite the sensation of odor, or flavor, or
sound, or touch, or oppose our locomotive energy. These
new sensations must have causes; and combining our
conclusions as to their causes, with our visual image,
we have a more perfect knowledge of the cause. The
material object which has qualities capable of exciting
ocular sensations has also qualities capable of exciting
sensations through the other senses. The combination
of qualities is the complex manifestation of the forces of
a common substance.
126 PSYCHOLOGY,
In perception, we infer what sort of an object that
must be which gives us certain sensations, and the
objective image, or ideated appearance, is the mental
construction embodying our conclusion. This image cor-
responds, more or less perfectly, with the object itself
In a geometric sense, the correspondence between the
image and its object may be perfect, as it is in normal
vision. The objective image in its position, magnitude,
and form, is the space conceived to be occupied by the
material object, and unless the perception is abnormal,
the image and the object are in coincidence. The image
represents correctly the geometric properties of the ob-
ject; but in other respects, we must take the words,
corresponds and represents^ with some latitude. Thus,
when we see a solid, we do not understand that the
objective image is a solid, in the physical sense, but
that the object is; that is, that it would offer a resistance
if we pressed it with the hand.
In seeing an apple, for instance, we perceive color,
size, and form, and construct an image which coincides
with the object. We experience a sensation of color,
and infer in the apple a power to excite this sensation,
and this power is localized, and has assigned to it extent
and form; and if our perception be correct, the locality,
size, and form of the image, coincide with the locality,
size, and form of the apple. But the apple is more than
the image constructed by the imagination, as colored,
located, extended, and figured; for it can manifest itself
through all the other senses; but it is more than the
combination of the percepts acquired through all the
senses. If the apple is simply a combination of all our
percepts concerning it — merely a complement of images
and notions, embodying our spontaneous inferences, then
it has no existence independent of our perceptions, and
would not exist if not perceived. Our notion of it is
I
1
PERCEPTION THROUGH SIGHT, 127
undoubtedly a combination of percepts or of their rep-
resentative ideas; but the apple itself is the combination
of all the causes of the sensations which it occasions in
us, together, perhaps, with other qualities altogether
unknown. This combination of qualities and causes is
not dependent on our perception for its existence, but
our perception of it implies its existence. The apple
does not exist because it is perceived, but it is perceived
because it exists and is brought into relation to our
powers of perception. It might even exist and not be
perceived. ]^o doubt many apples exist that have never
been perceived by any human being.
The appearance may be regarded as the joint product
of two factors — the underlying forces which are the
causes of the sensations, and the mind which interprets
the sensations by inferring and ideating their causes.
If either factor of the product be removed, the product
disappears. Take aw^ay the external forces, and the sen-
sations v/ill cease, and the appearance will vanish ; change
the forces, and the sensations will change and the ap-
pearance will also change; remove the mind, and there
will be neither sensation nor perception. The appear-
ance is not independent of the mind; but the apple, as
a substance involving a collection of forces, is independ-
ent of the mind. Neither is the appearance independ-
ent of the external forces — a mere creation of the mind ;
for then there w^ould be no cause of agreement in the
appearances as constructed by diiferent minds. But the
appearances to two minds of the same object are essen-
tially alike, which would not be the case if the appear-
ances were exclusively subjective representations; hence
the appearance, as a product, has an objective factor
independent of the mind, and this factor is common to
the appearances to the two minds, and is the cause of
their agreement.
128 PSYCHOLOGY.
That the objects whose qualities, as causes, excite sen-
sations in ns, are independent of the mind, is also
revealed by the fact that the mind can not create its
sensations at will, since these sensations are forced upon
the mind, which is passive in their reception. The laws
governing the combination and succession of sensations
are, therefore, the laws of a non-ego. Hence, there are
causes independent of ourselves, which produce in us
the sensations of which we are conscious. Strictl}^, sen-
sations are the joint products of the external causes and
the reactions of the internal sensibility. In perception,
we pass judgment on the external causes, and construct
our images so as to embody our notions of them as ex-
ternal objects independent of ourselves, which they are
in reality, unless our minds are false and deceive us in
their spontaneous, unprejudiced decisions. At the sum-
mit of thought, the conclusions of the Philosopher har-
monize with the inspirations of the Poet.
" Full many a gem of purest ray serene,
The dark, unfathom'd caves of ocean bear;
Full many a flower is born to blush unseen,
And waste its sweetness on the desert air."
13th. The utility of sight is evident: it opens to us a
world of marvelous beauty ; it is swift and delicate, and
far-reaching, taking in, at a glance, a wide spread land-
scape, locating its objects countless in number, marking
the wonderful variety of forms, and the nicest shades of
color; it reveals a multitude of worlds beyond our own,
giving us the most sublime conceptions of the grandeur
of Jehovah's empire. Indispensable is the information,
infinite are the blessings, and exhaustless the pleasures
which it confers.
CHAPTEE XII.
ACQUIRED PERCEPTION.
1. Original and acquired perception defined and il-
lustrated. — An original perception is a perception, through
a single sense, of the quality of an external object, which
is the appropriate cause of a sensation in the organ of
that sense.
An acquired perception is the perception of the quality
of an external object which would cause a sensation in
the organ of one sense, through the original perception
of a quality w^hich does cause a sensation in the organ
of another sense, from the knowledge gained by experi-
ence that these qualities are united in the same object.
The perception of the color of an extended object,
through the sensation which that object causes in the
eye, is an original perception ; so also is the perception
of a single quality of an external object, gained through
a sensation in the organ of any other sense.
The visual idea formed of the appearance of a person,
from hearing his voice, is an example of an acquired
perception. Thus, I hear a well-known voice in an ad-
joining room, and say that my friend is in that room;
and though I do not see him, yet I imagine how he
would appear if seen. In this case, the image is not
the person, who, by supposition, is not seen. This fact
accords with the doctrine of the last chapter, that the
appearance is an image constructed by the mind; for, if
the image, in the absence of the corresponding sensation,
that is, the sensation in the organ of the sense appro-
(129)
I
130 PSYCHOLOGY.
priate to that image, can be constructed under the
stimulus of another sensation, much more can it be con-
structed under the stimulus of the 23roper sensation.
The image constructed under the stimulus of a sensa-
tion not corresponding to the image, is less distinct and
more indeterminate than the image constructed under
the stimulus of the appropriate sensation. Thus, on
hearing the sound of the voice in the adjoining room,
the image constructed may be consistent with the sap-
position that the person is sitting or standing. Ho may
be in either posture, or in some other; but on going into
the room, the ocular sensations caused by the person, will,
by their definiteness, determine in what posture the im-
age constructed under the iiifluence of the sensation
shall appear. If the person change his posture, the sen-
sations will change, also the perception, thus revealing
the fact that there is a reality present independent of
our sensations; and this reality, by determining our
sensations, determines our perceptions. Our perceptions,
then, are not altogether voluntary, since, when the sen-
sations are present, they are spontaneously determined
by the mind informed by experience, and influenced by
habit.
There is a great variety of acquired perceptions.
Thus, I hear musical sounds, and know that they come
from a violin, a piano, or a guitar, as the case may be,
and imagine how the instrument looks. We say a
glowing coal of fire looks hot, imagining, by its appear-
ance to the eye, how it would feel to the hand. In like
manner, on seeing an apple, we imagine how it would
feel, or taste, or smell.
In original perception, the causes of the sensations
are known through the sensations themselves; but in
acquired perception, the cause of a sensation which
would be experienced, if the object were brought into
ACqUIBED FEECEPTION. 131
relation to a certain sense, is inferred, on occasion of an
original perception of the cause of another sensation ac-
tually experienced through another sense. Every act of
acquired perception, therefore, involves a sensation, an
original jDerception, an act of memory, and a represen-
tation by the imagination. The act, so far as the rep-
resentation is concerned, is regulated by the law of in-
tegration^ hereafter explained, by which the mind re-
peating any part of an entire process, tends to restore
the whole.
2. Acquired perceptions through smell. — Through
the sensation of smelly we not only perceive its cause,
but represent, by the imagination, the object of which
the cause of the sensation is a quality, as it would ap-
pear to the sight, touch, or taste. In this process, the
representation involves memory and is governed by the
law of association, guided by the light of experience.
Having learned by experience the peculiar odor ex-
haled from a given object, then whenever we experience
that odor, we not only infer its cause as an exhalation
from the object, but we imagine the object as it would
appear through the other senses.
3. Acquired parceptions through taste. — Through the
sensation of taste, we not only perceive the quality which
is its cause, but we imagine the object of which that
quality is a property, as it would appear to the other
senses. Thus, in tasting an article of food in the dark,
we know, for example, that it is an apple of a certain
variety, having a certain color and other properties not
originally known by taste.
4. Acquired perceptions through touch. — The orig-
inal perceptions through touch are accompanied by ac-
quired perceptions representing the objects as they would
appear to the other senses.
5. Acquired perceptions through hearing. — Through
132 PSYCHOLOGY.
hearing, we have a variety of acquired perceptions. We
hear a sound, and instantly know that it is, lor example,
the sound of a bell, and can, perhaps, tell what belL
We say that another sound comes from a drum, another
from a coach. We strike a barrel, and know from the
sound whether it is full or empty. We know from the
tones of a person's voice whether he is pleased or angry,
though we can not distinguish a word.
We are peculiarly liable to mistake in judging of the
cause of sound. The rumbling of a wagon over a bridge
may be mistaken for thunder; the hum of a musquito,
for the blast of a bugle; the rattling of a spoon in a tea-
cup, for sleigh-bells; the beating of the heart, for a rap
at the door. The noise made by a pet squirrel turning
the cylinder of its cage, was actually mistaken for the
noise made by burglars drilling into a safe, and the police
were called out to capture the thieves.
We judge the cause of any familiar noise, in the main
correctly; but any unusual noise is apt to mislead us in
our judgment concerning its cause; for we can learn
this cause only by experience.
6. Acquired perceptions through sight. — Through
sights we have acquired perceptions of objects, represent-
ing them as they would appear through smell, taste,
touch, and hearing. Thus, an orange at a short distance,
as an object of visual sense, is simply a yellow circle;
but by acquired perceptions it is represented as spher-
ical, with a rough surface, as capable of exciting certain
sensations of odor and taste, as naturally divisible into
spherical ungula, and as probably having seeds.
But the most important of the acquired perceptions
through sight are those relating to the magnitude, dis-
tance, and form of objects.
1st. The real magnitude of an object can be estimated
from its distance and apparent magnitude.
ACqUIEED PERCEPTION, 133
Let I denote a linear dimension of the real magnitude
of an object; d the distance; v tlie visual angle subtended
by Z, at the distance :ht into action.
What occurs in a paroxysm, is often forgotten by the
mind on recovering its natural state, and remembered
in a subsequent paroxysm.
Phantasms occurring in either waJicfulness or sleep,
take the forms of clairvoyance and visions.
PHANTASY. 239
Clairvoyance is the power of diHCOvering objects which
are supposed not to be perceptible through the senses.
Tliis state is analogous to liypnotism, or artificial som-
nambulism, if indeed it is not identical with it.
Tlie condition!^ of clairvoyance are: an excitable condi-
tion of the nervous system; certain external influences
acting upon the sensitive organism; a deficiency, for the
time being, of will power; a predominence, at least tem-
porary, of feeling over volition, and of rj^presentation
over the other cognitive acts.
As to form^ clairvoyance is involuntary^ when induced
in the subject without his consent, though not necessa-
rily against his will; or voluntary^ when the subject
yields himself up, of his own accord, to external influ-
ences or to the will of another.
As to the phenomena., it is claimed that the clairvoy-
ant can see, for example, the diseased parts in the in-
terior of his own body, or objects through a bandage or
a thick wall, or at a distance too remote for vision.
After allowing for exaggeration, guess-work, deception,
and the drawing of information from others by questions
or cautious generalizations, these f)henomena may perhaps
be explained, in part, at least, b}^ the condition of the
subject, and his relation to physical influences or to
other minds, if indeed there would be left any thing to
be explained.
The subject is in a highly sensitive condition, and his
representative power is abnormally active. In case of
internal disease in his own body, it is plain that the
sensations would sutciifcst the nature of the disease which
the activity of the representative power would vividly
picture. It would be very natural, in such a case, to
mistake representation for perception ; and this is prob-
ably done when objects at a great distance are supposed
to be seen, as cities on the otlier side of the globe.
240 I'S YCHQL OGY.
The condition of the subject renders him peculiarly
susceptible to magnetic or electrical influences. His
mind is in intimate sympathy with other minds, and in
some way, through mesmeric or higher spiritual influ-
ence, seems to participate in their knowledge.
The phenomena of clairvoyance and those of kindred
nature have by some been attributed to the influence of
disembodied spirits, as in modern spiritualism.
A vision is the appearance of something, as if seen,
when there is, through the eye, no corresponding per-
ception of an objective reality.
The conditions are a highly sensitive nervous system
and an intense activity of the representative power.
The forms are natural vision — that induced by natural
agency, — and supernatural vision — that induced by su-
pernatural agency. The truth of prophecy can not be
decided a priori, but must be determined a posteriori^ by
evidence, the same as that of historical questions.
i
DIVISION III.
ELABORATION AND THE ELABORATIVE FACULTIES.
CHAPTEE I.
ELABOKATION.
Elaboration is the process by which the intellect ar-
ranges objects into classes, and forms and applies gener-
alized concepts or notions of these classes.
The processes of elaboration are classification, concep-
tion, judgment, and reasoning.
The prorZw<^^,s of elaboration are classes, concepts, judg-
ments, and arguments.
The conditions of elaboration are the acquisitions through
consciousness, reflection, rational intuition, and percep-
tion, the acts and products of representation, also the
faculties implied in elaboration.
The faculty of elaboration is variously denominated,
thu^ The elaborative or discursive faculty^ since it is em-
plo3^ed lU working up, into higher forms, the materials
supplied by acquisition and reproduction; the logical
Jucidty, since it is the faculty employed in logical pro-
cesses; the comparative faculty^ since comparison enters,
as an essential element, into all its processes ; the faculty
of relations, since it deals with relations; the thought
faculty^ since its acts are styled thought; the rationed
facidty^ understanding^ or intelligence^ since it is the fac-
ulty which characterizes man as rational, and thus dis-
tinguishes him from inferior beings.
Psy.-21. (241)
242 PSYCHOLOGY,
Let us now give a brief recapitulation of the acts of
cognition :
Consciousness is the experience which the sonl has of
its phenomena. It is essential to cognition; for without
it, any supposed process would be to us as zero. Con-
sciousness involves judgment. To be conscious of a phe-
nomenon involves the judgment, usually informal and
unexpressed, of the existence of that phenomenon as
opposed to its non-existence. But consciousness is the
experience of a determinate phenomenon; hence, the
judgment involved in consciousuess is not that of bare
existence, but of a determinate existence, involving the
identity or peculiarity and particularity of the phenome-
non, and thus implying an act of comparison.
Uejiection is the turning back of our cognition to the
consideration of psychical phenomena. The processes
involved in reflection are abstraction, attention, analysis,
synthesis, comparison, identification or discrimination,
and classification. Though primarily applied to the
phenomena of consciousness, these processes are also
employed in the investigation of the properties and re-
lations of material things.
The classes formed by reflection consist of species, or
collections of individuals having a common attribute, and
of genera, or collections of species having more general
attributes than the attributes severally characteristic of
the species.
A class, as a collection of individuals or of species,
can be represented by the imagination, though inade-
quately, since a greater or less number of individuals
will, almost inevitably, fail to appear in the representa-
tion of the class; but a concept, as a generalized product
of the logical faculty, embracing only elements common
to all the members, can not, as will be shown more
fully hereafter, be imagined^ it can only be thought.
GENERAL VIEW. 243
Rational intuition is the apprehension of the necessity
of the conditions of phenomena. Tiius, a phenomenon
experienced in consciousness is, by rational intuition,
referred to the conscious subject or the ego^ which, as
tlie subject of consciousness, is discriminated from the
non-ego^ that is, from every thing else. By rational in-
tuition, the intellect apprehends the necessity of space
and time, as the universal conditions of phenomena; of
fundamental truth, as the condition of valid thought; of
substance, as the underlying power which manifests
conjoined attributes; of cause, or that which is efficient
in producing events; of laws, or the modes of the oc-
currence of events; and of consequences, or the effects
following. These intuitions play an important part in
the processes of elaboration ; and in all of them compar-
ison and judgment are involved.
Perception is the ^^I'ocess by which we gain a knowl-
edge of the properties of external objects. The elements
involved in perception are the sensational, the intuitional,
the inferential, and the ideational. Perception involves
comparison and judgment, and deals with the concrete.
Representation is the act by which the mind repro-
duces its acquisitions. It takes the form of memory,
imagination, or phantasy, according as it deals with past
realities, with ideals, or with phantasms.
Eepresentation involves comparison and judgment, and
deals with the concrete.
Elaboration generalizes its materials through the acts
of comparison and judgment, and thus deals with the
universal.
By an examination of the above processes, we dis-
cover that comparison is the typical act of thought, and
that the typical product is the judgment.
It is not to be supposed that any one of the above
processes takes place by itself, that is, in complete iso-
244 PSYCHOLOGY.
lation from the others. In fact, two or more of the
processes occur simultaneously.
We have used the word faculty to include both an
active power and a passive susceptibility, of the mind; but
some writers use the word faculty to denote a power of
the mind, and the word capacity to denote a susceptibil-
ity. Hamilton says : '^ We are surely entitled to say in
general that the mind has the faculty of exerting such
and such a class of energies, or has the capacity of being
modified by such and such an order of affections. We
here ex-cogitate no new, no occult, principle. We only
generalize certain effects, and then infer that common
effects must have a common cause; we only classify
certain modes, and conclude that similar modes indicate
the same capacity of being modified ^o accusation
can, therefore, be more ungrounded than that which has
been directed against philosophers, — that they have gen-
erally harbored the opinion that faculties are, like organs
in the body, distinct constituents of mind." Metaphysics,
pages 269, 272.
The faculties, then, are powers, active or passive, with
which the soul is endowed. Even the passive faculties,
the susceptibilities, or capacities, are powers in the sense
that the accompanying phenomena are due to their re-
sponse to stimuli, or to their reaction against impressions.
CHAPTEE 11.
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION.
Classification is the process of forming grou^DS of ob-
jects having common qualities.
In classification we may proceed by generalization —
the arrangement of individuals into species, and of these
species into genera; or by division — the resolution of
genera into species, and of species into sub-species or
individuals.
Conception is that process of elaboration by which
the intellect forms general notions of classes of objects
havino; common attributes.
The product of the act of conception is called a con-
cept or notion. The term concept denotes the combina-
tion of common attributes which is produced by the act
of conception; but the term notion denotes the marks or
signs, notce^ by which the individuals of a certain class
may be known.
Generalization embraces synthetic specification — the
formation of species from individuals, and generification
— the formation of genera from species.
The importance of generalization is obvious; for the
objects of the universe are countless in number, while
the mind is finite in its powers of comprehension. Were
it not for the fact of generalization, the finite powers of
the mind would be overwhelmed by the infinity of the
universe. But one aim of science is to reduce multiplic-
ity to unity; and in the realization of this aim, science
has been highly successful, and has thus enabled the
(245)
246 PSYCHOLOGY.
human mind to grapple with the innumerable facts of
the universe.
In generalization, we begin with an examination of
individual things, whether psychical phenomena or ma-
terial objects. By an examination of these things, we
learn what we can of them through consciousness, re-
flection, rational intuition, and perception. The qualities
thus discovered and represented in memory, if the ob-
jects be absent, can be predicated of these objects, thus
forming individual judgments; as, this apple is red, etc.
By comparison^ we find that many objects have simi-
lar attributes, — so far similar, that they may be regarded
as alike, and hence as common. The same objects that
possess similar attributes, may also j)ossess dissimilar
attributes. Abstracting our attention from the dissimilar
attributes, and concentrating it upon the similar, we
regard these objects as alike, since they possess similar
attributes, and class them together. These common at-
tributes are the marks or signs by which individual
objects may be known as belonging to this class; and
of any individual of this class, we may predicate any
of the common attributes. Our ideas of the common
attributes of a class, taken together as a combination,
constitute our notion or concept of the class. Other
classes, having other sets of attributes, may be formed in
a similar manner, and thus the universe of objects may
be formed into classes.
Strictl}^ speaking, we abstract our thoughts from those
attributes not common to the class, yet it is common to
say that we abstract the common attributes, since we
consider them apart from the other qualities possessed
by a part only of the individuals of the class. The ideas
of the common qualities thus said to be abstracted, are
called abstracts^ because they are considered apart from
the attributes not common to all the individuals of the
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION, 247
class. In like maimer, a single attribute of a single
object, considered apart from the other attributes of that
object, may be called an abstract. Thus, the form of a
particular chair, considered apart from the other attri-
butes of that chair, is an abstract.
If we should form abstract ideas, were it possible, of
all the objects of the universe, we should not only be
overwhelmed by their infinitude, but we should have
ideas of qualities apart from their objects, in which state
they do not exist in nature; and, viewing these qualities
thus separately, we should have no knowledge of their
mutual relation. Hence, we see the necessity of com-
parison, so that we may not only abstract but combine
the common qualities, thus forming concepts or notions,
by w^hich we recognize all the objects having the qual-
ities involved in the concept as a plurality of individu-
als embraced in the unity of a class.
By generification^ we form genera from species. We
do not rest at a first generalization by which we form
species from individuals, and the concepts of these spe-
cies; but comparing these concepts, disregarding their
differences, we observe their common elements, which
w^e abstract and combine into higher concepts of genera
embracing the subordinate classes as species.
By comparing the concepts of these genera, disregard-
ing their difPerences, abstracting and combining their
common attributes, which become fewer as we ascend,
we obtain still higher concepts, embracing a greater
number of subordinate classes and individuals. In like
4
manner, continuing the process, we arrive, at length,
practically, at the summit of our ascent — the concept
being^ the highest genus, embracing all reality, both
dynamical and non-dynamical.
By denomination J we assign names to the classes formed
by generalization, and tlius these classes, together with
248 PSYCHOL OGY,
the ideas, concepts, or notions of them become embodied
in verbal signs.
We have called being- the highest genus, and practi-
cally it is so; but as all thinking is relative, and implies
discrimination, it follows that every class or concept has
its negative; hence, in speculation, there is no highest
genus. Thus, being is discriminated from its negative,
non-being, and both being and non-being may be re-
garded as species of a higher genus, and so on. To
these higher genera, no names have been assigned, as
they are only objects of speculation. Though, absolutely,
there is no highest genus, yet, practically, for all reality,
being may be thus regarded; but, relatively to any
science, there is some class or concept, lower than being,
which may, for the special purpose of that science, be
regarded as the summum genus.
By division^ the reverse of generalization, we descend
to the subordinate classes and individuals. If some of
the objects of a class possess a quality not possessed by
other objects of that class, this quality is a difference
which divides the class into two species, — one character-
ized by the presence of this difference, and the other
by its absence, though perhaps possessing another differ-
ence which also would have served as a mark of dis-
crimination in dividing the class.
Beginning, then, at heing^ we divide and subdivide by
introducing at each division the differences w^hich* char-
acterize the species and enable us to discriminate them
from one another. We thus assign to each species a
less extent^ that is, fewer classes and individuals than
was assigned to the genus, but a greater content^ that
is, more attributes. The process of divjsion may be
continued till we reach the limit in the individuals.
Thus, w^e may divide being into dynamic being and
non-dynamic; dynamic, into matter and spirit; matter,
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION. 249
into organic being and inorganic; organic, into animal
and vegetable ; animal, into vertebrates and invertebrates,
and so on, till we reach dog, spaniel, and the individual
Wag, Each logical division is bifurcate^ having two
branches, that is, a dichotomy^ having two members.
The lowest species^ practically, is that whose division
will give individuals; yet, strictly, since we can continue
the division so long as there is any diiference, however
minute, it would be difficult to find a species which
could not be subdivided into lower species. We reach
the lowest species, then, when practically we do not care
to discriminate more minutely, nor to carry our sub-
divisions farther, though, strictly, the infima species has
no existence except in speculation.
For the purposes of Psychology, every class containing
sub-classes is regarded as a genus of which the sub-
classes are the species; hence, the same class may be
both a genus and a species; it is a genus in regard to
the classes contained under it, and it is a sj)ecies in
reference to the class under which it is contained. But,
for the purposes of Natural Science^ the degree of subor-
dination in the series is designated by a name. Thus,
X/innceus introduced five grades of subordination — class,
order, genus, species, variety. With the progress of
science, intermediate and additional grades have been
introduced. The Botanical Congress held at Paris in
August, 1867, recognized twenty-one grades — kingdom,
division, subdivision, class, sub-class, cohort, sub-cohort,
order, sub-order, tribe, sub-tribe, genus, sub-genus, sec-
tion, sub-section, species, sub-species, variety, sub-variety,
variation, sub-variation. Even this list is probably not
complete. The important thing to be observed is the
order of the subdivision; but the degree of importance
assigned to any grade varies with the opinion of diflPer-
ent minds.
250 PSYCHOLOGY.
A definition is such a description of a thing as will
distinguish it from all other things. A thing is defined
by referring it to the class immediately containing it,
and distinguishing it from other things of the class by
means of its characteristics. Thus, a triangle is a poly-
gon of three sides.
A property^ of a class is an attribute which belongs to
every object of the class, though it does not enter into
the definition^ since it may belong also to other classes.
Thus, it is a property of a rectangle that its angles are
equal, but this is also true of any regular polygon.
A generic property is one which is common to all the
species of a genus. Thus, the sum of the three angles
of every plane triangle is equal to two right angles.
A specific property is a property which is common to
all the individuals of a species. Thus, two angles are
equal in every isosceles triangle.
A peculiar property of a class is a property which is
not found in any object of any other class. Thus, it is
a peculiar property of the circle that, for a given peri-
meter, it contains the maximum area.
A constant property is a property which is always
and every-where the same. Thus, inertia is a constant
property of matter.
A variable property is a property subject to change
in degree. Thus, density, elasticity, etc., are variable
properties of matter. •
An accident is a quality which may or may not be-
long to certain objects. Thus, the magnitude of a body
is an accident.
Denomination embraces nomenclature and terminology.
Nomenclature is the collection of the names of the
classes in a science. The number of natural groups is,
however, so large that it is impracticable to devise or
to remember names for all of them. Thus, the number
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION 251
of known species of plants is at least 60,000, to say
nothing of the sub-species, varieties, and sub-varieties.
Some artifice is, therefore, requisite to secure a practical
nomenclature. In Eotany, the higher groups, down to
genera, have distinct names; but the species take the
name of the genus modified by that of some attribute,
as geranium sanguineum. In Chemistry, we have an ex-
ample of a nomenclature in which the prefixes and
suffixes used in names are significant of the nature of
the substance, as perchloric acid.
Terminology is the collection of the names of the parts
and properties of individual objects in the province of
a science. Thus, included in the terminology of Botany,
are the names calyx ^ corolla^ etc., expressive of parts of
plants; also the names, pinnatifid, palmatifid, etc., ex-
pressive of the shape of the leaf.
CHAPTEE III.
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION.
Classification is the formation of groups of objects
having common qualities. It embraces both generaliza-
tion and division.
Generalization is the formation of classes from objects
having common attributes. It embraces both synthetic
specification and generification.
Synthetic specification is the formation of species from
resembling individuals.
Let Aj JBj (7, be individual objects having the common
attributes, a, 6, e, d, e, f, found by examination and com-
parison, — A having the additional attributes, g, h, pe-
culiar to itself; and B and C, respectively, the additional
attributes, i, j, and J, k.
Disregarding the attributes not common to A, B. (7,
and abstracting and combining the common attributes
giving them special prominence, we attribute to them a
kind of separate existence, objectively fictitious, though
subjectively real, and thus form the concept, which we
shall call C\ of the class, which we shall call Jf, em-
bracing the individuals, A, B, 0, having the common at-
tributes, a, b, e, d, e, /.
In the concept C\ no attribute can enter which is
not common to all the objects of the class; hence, all
the attributes peculiar to an individual, or common to
any number of individuals, less than the whole number,
must be excluded.
The concept, in its pure form, can not be represented
(2e52) ■
GENERAL DISCUSSTON, 253
by the imagination; yet it can be rej)resented, with in-
dividual attributes, in a concrete form, by calling up
one or more of the individuals, A.^ B^ C. But in calling
up an individual, we introduce qualities peculiar to the
individual, as well as the qualities common to all the
individuals of the class, though we banish, as completely
as possible, the qualities peculiar to the individual, and
give to the common qualities special prominence.
The image thus obtained is individual ; but It has a
potential universality in the fact that we may vary it so
as to represent any individual of the class, by droj)ping
the j)eculiarities of one individual and incorporating
those of another. But if we drop the peculiarities of
one individual without incorporating those of another,
the image itself would vanish. In attempting, for ex-
ample, to represent, by the imagination, the concept of
the class horse, we should call up the image of a horse
of a particular color, form, size, etc., introducing not
only the qualities common to all horses, but also those
peculiar to some of the individuals of the class. We
thus have an image of an individual, real or imaginary,
but not the concept of the class. If we should drop all
attributes not belonging to the concept, the image itself
would vanish, since we could not construct the image,
unless we assign to it some particular color, form, size,
etc. Hence, a concept, in its pure generality, can not
be reiiresented b}^ the imagination.
On the other hand, if we should drop from the image
all that is characteristic of the class horse, retaining, at
the same time, the other elements, it would no longer
be recoo-nized as the imas-e of a horse, but it would still
have the elements common to animal, or, dropping these,
the elements common to organic being, then the element
common to being, dropping this, the image would vanish.
Hence, every image must contain both particular and
254 PSYCHOLOGY,
universal elements, and will vanish whenever either
kind is dropped. The universal and the particular are,
therefore, not two kinds of ideas, but the two elements
of every idea. An idea that is exclusively general or
exclusively particular can not be realized, but can only
be approached by directing the attention especially to the
one kind of elements or the other. " The common element
that enters into every cognition is that of being; but
with this, there is also always present, the subjective
intuition of the conditional necessity of the ego, as the
subject of the cognition.
Though the general concept can not be represented,
as a pure universal, by the imagination, yet it is possi-
ble to represent the class as a collection of individuals.
Thus, the class denoted by X is the collection of the
individuals, A^ B^ (7, and as such, it is capable of repre-
sentation. A class consisting of a vast multitude, as the
class man, can not be represented in its totality, since
great multitudes of individuals are unknown. Thus,
many human beings have died, many are not yet born,
yet such a number and variety can be represented, as
will do fair justice to the entire class.
We have formed the individuals A, 5, (7, having the
common attributes, a, 6, c, d, e, /, into the class X, of
which the concept C\ is the combination, abcdef of
these common attributes.
IN'ow, let Jj, Mj iV, be individuals having the common
attributes, b, c, f] I, m, n, — L having the additional attri-
butes, t, u, peculiar to itself; and M and iV, respectively,
the additional attributes, v, w\ and iv, x. We thus form
the concept (7", of the class which we shall call Y, con-
taining the objects X, Jf, iV, having the common attri-
butes, 6, c, /, ?, m, n.
Generification is the formation of higher classes from
species. These classes are called genera (sing, geyius).
GENERAL DISCUSSION. 255
Taking the results obtained under synthetic specifica-
tion, denoting the sum of the attributes by the proper
letters, without the sign of addition, and writing the
attributes of the individuals, and the concepts of the
classes, as subscripts, we have
A ahcdef gh
BahcdefiJ )- ^= X abode f ■= C
Cabcdefjk
Lbcflmntu
Mbcflmnviv V ^=^ Ybcflr)in=^ C"
Nbcfl
mnwx
The expression, Ahcdef gh^ is read the individual A,
whose attributes are a^h^ c^ d^e^f^g ; and Xabcdef = c'
is read the class JT, whose concept, ah cd ef^ equals C\
l^ow, if we wish, by a higher generalization, to form
a higher class containing the classes X and Y, we dis-
regard the attributes a,d,e, peculiar to the concept, C",
of the class Jl, also the attributes, I, m, n, peculiar to the
concept, (7'', of the class Y, and, by abstracting and com-
bining the attributes, 6, c,/, common to (7' and C'\ we
' form the concept, C^^\ of the genus which we shall call
Z, embracing the classes, X and Y, as species.
The process of generification is thus exhibited :
JLabcdef=C'l ^x. ^
1 bcjlmn=^ C" )
tn
In like manner, having formed another genus con-
taining attributes in common with Z^ we form a still
higher genus, and so on.
Division is the resolution of a class into sub-classes or
individuals. Comparing the objects embraced in Z^ we
find, not only that they possess the attributes, 6, c,/, in
256 PSYCHOLOGY,
common, but that some of them possess the attributes,
a, d^ e, not possessed by the remaining objects of the
class, and that the remaining objects possess the attri-
butes, I. m, n, not possessed by the first. We disregard
the attributes, b, c, /, common to all the objects of the
genus Zj and direct attention to the attributes, a, r/, e,
and I, m, n, respectively common to the two parts of the
genus ^. Either of the groups of attributes, a, d, e, and
I, m, /I, is sufficient to divide the genus into two species,
one containing the group of attributes under considera-
tion, and the other not containing this group. We may,
if we choose, take both groups into consideration in the
division. We then divide the genus Z into the two
species, designated, respectively, by ^ and Y, which,
though containing the attributes, Z>, c, /, characteristic of
the genus, and hence common to JT and Y, are charac-
terized, respectively, by the attributes, a, d, e, and I, m, n.
This division of the genus, Z^ into the two species, -Z
and Y, is called analytic specification, to distinguish it
from synthetic specification, in which a species is formed
from similar individuals.
In discriminating ^ and Y, as species of the genus Z,
the attributes, a, d, e, and I, m, n, respectively character-
istic of JT and Y, are made especially prominent, while
the attributes, 6, c, /, characteristic of the genus Z, and
hence common to JC and Y, are obscurely recognized.
In generalization, similarities play the important part,
but differences in division. Similarities are detected by
identifivcation, and differences by discrimination.
The discrimination of differences, unchecked by the
identification of similarities, would individualize and iso-
late every tiling, and render science impossible; but the
identification of similarities leads to generalization, in-
duction, and the comprehensive truths of science.
The division of X gives the individuals. A, B, (7, each
GENERAL DISCUSSION. 257
of which, though containing the attributes, a^ d, e, char-
acteristic of JC, also the attributes, 6, , /, characteristic
of Z, and hcDce common to JC and F, is especially char-
acterized by attributes peculiar to itself In like manner,
the division of Y gives the individuals, X, M, N, each
of which, though containing the attributes, /, ???, n^ and
6, c, /, respectively characteristic of Y and Z^ is also
characterized by attributes peculiar to itself This pro-
cess is called individualization. The processes of divis-
ion, including both analytic specification and individual-
ization is thus exhibited:
Aabcdefgh
X c'^abcdef \ B ab cdefij
Zc" — bef <
C abed efj k
Lbcflmn tu
Y Qff = b cflm n -^ il^ bcfl m nvw
Nbcflimnwx
Each higher class embraces all the subordinate classes
and individuals, and each lower class or individual con-
tains all the attributes of the higher class, together with
those attributes peculiar to itself Hence, the higher the
class the greater the number of objects, and the less the
number of attributes; and the lower the class the less
the number of objects, and the greater the number of
attributes.
In generalization, by synthetic specification, we form a
species from resembling individuals by a comparison of
the individuals; but in generalization by generification,
we form a genus from resembling species by a compar-
ison of the concepts of the sj)ecies.
In division, we find the subdivisions of a class by a
comparison of the objects of the class, and not by the
analysis of its concept. Hence, in division, we divide
Psy.— 22.
258 PSYCHOLOGY,
classes, that is, genera and species, not their concepts;
for the concept of a class contains fewer attributes than
the concepts of its subdivisions, and these concepts con-
tain more attributes as we descend.
The rules for the process of division are the following:
1st. Every division should be made in reference to
one principle and only one. .
2d. The principle of division should be a determinate
attribute of one of the members of the class divided.
3d. The principle of division should be selected in
view of the objects to be accomplished.
4th. Each member must be less than the class divided.
5th. The sum of the members must be equal to the
class divided.
6th. The members must be co-ordinate and mutually
exclusive.
7th. The divisions must proceed continuously, each
member being immediately subordinate to the class un-
der which it is placed.
Denomination^ as the naming of individuals, species
and genera, constitutes the nomenclature of a science;
but as the naming of the parts and properties of indi-
viduals, it constitutes the terminology.
The name of a class denotes all the subdivisions of
that class, whether species or individuals, and connotes
their common attributes. In connection with the pro-
cess of classification, names are usually applied to des-
ignate the classes, individuals, or attributes.
The names of classes are subject to two contrary
changes, as influenced b}^ generalization or division. In
generalization, the name of a species is often generalized,
or extended to its genus, thus increasing its denotation,
and diminishing its connotation. Thus, the name coal,
which originally denoted charred wood, was extended to
a miDeral substance resembling it. The new coal, at
GENERAL DISCUSSION, 259
first designated as pit-coal or sea-coal^ becoming the
more common, is now iisuall}^ designated simply as coal^
while the original coal is called charcoal. In division,
the name of the genus is often specialized or restricted
to owe of its species, thus decreasing its denotation and
increasing its connotation. Thus, the name physician^
originally signifying one wdio studies nature, now signi-
fies one who applies his knowledge of the human system,
to the practice of medicine. One who studies nature is
called a p)liysicist ; and one who studies animate nature
is called a naturalist.
Though a subordinate act, denomination is yet a matter
of great importance, since it embodies the products of
thought in verbal signs, and thus affords the requisite
facilities for thinking.
A definition is such a description of a thing, w^hether
an object or a class, as will distinguish it from all other
things. A thing is defined by affirming it to belong to
the class immediately containing it, and distinguishing
it from other things of that class by means of its es-
sential characteristics. Thus, let Z be the genus embrac-
ing the species X and F, — X characterized by a d e,
and y by I m n. Then X is that sjoecies of the genus
Z^ which is characterized by a d, e. Hence, a definition
of a thing gives both its denotation and connotation,
otherwise called its extension and comprehension, or
sphere and matter, or breadth and depth, or genus and
differentia.
A definition should also exhibit the following qualities:
(1) The subject and predicate of a definition are co-
extensive and interchangeable. Thus, ''A rectangle is a
right parallelogram," and ''A right parallelogram is a
rectangle." The proposition, "Horses are four-footed
animals," though true, is not a definition, since the predi-
cate is greater in extent than the subject.
260 PSYCHOLOGY.
(2) A definition should not be circular; that is, the
predicate should not contain the name of the thing de-
fined, nor any derivative of that name, nor any term
whose definition involves that name. Thus, the follow-
ing definitions are circular: ''Law is a lawful command."
'• Mathematics is the science of quantity," and " Quantity
is the object of mathematical investigation."
(3) A definition should be clear and precise. Thus,
Dr. Johnson's definition, ''Net-work is any thing decus-
sated or reticulated, with interstices between the inter-
sections," is not clear. " Parallel lines are those which
never meet," wants precision, since it is defective, as
j)arallel lines also lie in the same plane. '^Parallelograms
are quadrilaterals whose opposite sides are parallel and
equal," wants precision, since it is redundant. The
words "and equal" should be omitted.
(4) A definition should be affirmative rather than neg-
ative. Thus, "Industry is not honesty," does not tell
what industry is, but what it is not. A negative defi-
nition is, however, allowable when a positive one can
not be given.
(5) A definition admits of no exception. For an ex-
ception would invalidate the definition.
A genetic definition is one which exhibits the mode
of producing the thing defined. Thus, a sphere is a
solid generated by the revolution of a circle about a
diameter.
CHAPTEE lY.
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION.
1. Names. — A name is the verbal designation of a
class or an individual, or of a part or an attribute of
an individual.
Species and genera uniformly receive names, also in-
dividuals in cases of importance, as human beings, cer-
tain domestic animals, geographical objects, etc. ; but in
other cases, individuals are not named, otherwise than
by the common name of the class to which they belong.
In fact, it would be impossible to name every individual,
as in case of plants, leaves, birds, fishes, insects, etc.
The parts and qualities of individuals are named in
the terminology of the sciences, though the individuals
themselves are not designated by proper names. But
the names of parts and qualities of individuals are com-
mon nouns, and apply to the similar parts of resembling
individuals.
Xames, as originally applied, were expressive of some
quality of the objects named, and the same names were
afterwards api^lied to other objects possessing similar
qualities, thus aiding classification. As knowledge ad-
vances, other qualities are discovered in the objects of a
class, perhaps more important and fundamental than
that signified by the name, but the name is not usually
changed, though its signification varies. Hence, a con-
cept may be variable, while the name and the class as
inclusive of all its subordinates, known or unknown,
actual or possible, may be constant.
(261)
262 PSYCHOLOGY,
The variability of a concept, however, differs greatly
from the variability of the image of an individual; for
the variability of the image is a consequence of the va-
riable character of its peculiar elements, since these may
so change that the image may represent, in rapid suc-
cession, many different individuals of the class; but the
variability of the concept is a consequence of a change
in our opinion as to what is essential to the class, and
this change is usually of slow growth. With the excep-
tion of the change growing out of maturer views, a
concej)t is practically invariable.
A name denotes the objects of a class, and connotes
their attributes. But what attributes are connoted?
Strictly and scientifically, the name should connote only
essential attributes, — those conceived as constituting the
concept of the class ; but the concept is, as we have seen,
variable for the same mind, and differs for different
minds, and is always represented in connection with the
peculiarities of an individual. A name, then, practically
connotes all the attributes, essential and accidental, which
it calls up to the individual mind. Hence, the connota-
tion of a name may be variable, while its denotation
may be constant.
The expression, constant denotation^ needs qualification.
Thus, the words Chinese railway may, in the year 1882,
denote, in our thought, the one short railway in China;
but, virtually, it denotes all the railways that shall ever
be constructed in the Celestial Empire. Likewise, the
name man denotes not only living human beings, but
also those of past and future generations. The extent
which a term denotes to an individual mind, varies with
its knowledge.
In consequence of the variability in the connotation
of common names, technical terms are employed in
science, which shall not only denote the objects of the
NAMES, CLASSES, CONCEPTS. 263
respective classes, but also connote exclusively their es-
sential attributes. Though a common name or a tech-
nical term, denotes all the objects of the class designated
by it, yet the mind, when employing either, does not
actually represent in memory all the objects of the class;
for a multitude of these objects are wholly unknown,
and others, though once known, are now, perhaps, alto-
gether forgotten.
2. Nature of classes and concepts. — What is the nat-
ure of classes, — -the species and genera, and their rela-
tion to their concepts? What is the object of thought
when we employ a common noun, as man or horse?
Three theories have been proposed in answer to these
questions — Eealism, I^ominalism, and Conceptualism.
1st. Realism, not as opposed to Idealism in Perception,
but to Nominalism and Conceptualism in Conception,
is the doctrine that a species or a genus has a real ob-
jective existence, independent, both of the individual
objects of the class, and of the act of conception; that
it embraces the elements common to all the individuals
of the class; that it is the object of which the concept is
the counterpart; and that it is the perfect pattern ac-
cording to which the individuals of the class are fash-
ioned, and in comparison with which they must forever
remain imperfect and inferior. This is the doctrine of
Plato, as understood by Aristotle. The formula, as after-
wards given, is universalia ante rem. In this extreme
form, Eealism has long since been exploded.
A modified realism, is, however, possible. A universal
is not a kind of being or kind of idea, but an element
of both being and idea, the other element being partic- ,
ular; but the universal, apart from the particular, can
neither exist nor be represented. But if we regard a
species as a collection of resembling individuals, and a
genus as a collection of resembling species, then both
264 PSYCHOLOGY,
species and genera have an objective existence, independ-
ent, not of the objects, but in a certain sense, of the
human mind, which has only discovered the classes ex-
isting in nature. The formula of modified realism is,
universalia in re.
Eoth nature and the human mind perform their part
in classification. In some cases, nature performs the
more conspicuous part, leaving to the human mind the
easy part of recognizing obvious resemblances and diff'er-
ences. This is especially true of the organic kingdoms.
In other cases, the classes appear to be the creations of
the human mind; but the resemblances, though occult
to the common observer, are still in nature, and, as nat-
ural distinctions, are recognized by the eye of science.
Since an individual can be represented by the imag-
ination, a species, as a collection of individuals, can be
rej^resented, though imperfectly, since but a portion of
the individuals will, in general, be represented ; yet a
sufficient number and variety of specimens may be
chosen as fairly to represent the class. In like manner
a genus, as a collection of species, can be represented.
2d. Nominalism is the doctrine that only individuals
have a real existence; that all our ideas are particular;
that universals exist only as names of resembling indi-
viduals; that the concept, in its pure generality, can not
be represented by the imagination; that only the indi-
vidual can be represented ; that the idea of an individual
has a potential universality by which it can be made to
represent any individual of the class, by dropping the
peculiarities of one individual and incorporating those
of another; and that, as soon as all peculiarities are
dropped, the idea itself will vanish. The formula for
Nominalism is, universalia post rem.
The name man, for example, is applicable to every
individual of the class, and in this sense is universal.
NAMES, CLASSES, CONCEPTS. 265
The class man embraces the various races, — white, black,
red, yellow, and copper colored, divided into nationali-
ties, ranks, and individuals, of past, present, and future
generations, with all their peculiarities. The concept
man, in its pure generality, embraces those elements,
and those only, which are common to all the individu-
als of the class.
-Now, can the concept man be represented by the im-
agination? Let us tr^^ to represent it. On trial, we
find that the image which we form is, in every instance,
an idea of an individual, actual or imaginary, having a
certain size, form, color, and other peculiarities, but the
image is not the concept of the class. This image has,
however, a potential universality, since it can be varied
by dropping the peculiarities of one individual and in-
corporating those of another, and so on, so as to make
it represent any other individual of the class; but as
soon as we drop all peculiarities, the image itself van-
ishes, since we can not have an image which does not
exhibit some definite size, form, color, etc.
3d. Conceptualisjn is the theory that a universal has
an existence in the mind of the thinking subject, as a
pure concept embracing those elements only w^hich are
common to all the individuals of the class; that it is
formed by comparing resembling individuals, disregard-
ing their peculiarities, anJ abstracting and combining
their common qualities ; and that, after it has once been
formed from a comparison of resembling individuals, it
can be reproduced without reference to these individuals,
though it may be predicated of any of them.
If the pure concept can not, as we . have shown in
discussing ^Nominalism, be represented by the imagina-
tion, what kind of an existence has it, and how can it
be distinguished from an image of an individual? To
illustrate, take the idea of an individual of a class, and
Psy.— 23.
266 PSYCHOLOGY,
vary it by dropping the peculiarities of that individual
and incor^^orating those of another, and 80 on, till the
idea has represented, in succession, at least a considera-
ble number of the objects of the class. Now, in this
varying idea, we have two classes of elements — varia-
bles and constants. The variable elements form no part
of the concept, though some one or more of them are
necessary to the idea of a specified individual. The con-
stant elements can be ascertained as those which enter
the idea formed of every individual of the class, and
these elements alone^ taken together, constitute the pure
concept, which is^ therefore, not zero to thought, though
it is zero to the imagination, since it vanishes whenever
all variable elements are dropped.
The idea of an individual embraces the constant com-
mon elements of the concept, plus the variable peculiar-
ities of the individual.
In assigning an individual to its class, the common
elements of the concept are especially considered; but,
in identifying an individual, the peculiarities which dis-
tinguish the individual receive the chief attention.
The error of Eealism is the assumption that the uni-
versal has an objective existence, apart from the partic-
ular.
The error of ISTominalism is the assumption that an
idea can be merely particular, and that the only thing
universal is the name.
The error of Conceptualism is the assumption that
an idea can be merely general.
These errors have their origin in the common assump-
tion that the universal and the particular, which are
elements, both of things and of ideas, are either kinds
of things or kinds of ideas.
The following Propositions concerning Universals was
contributed by Mr. B. A. Hinsdale.
NAMES. CLASSES, CONCEPTS. 267
1. Metaphysical Universals. — These are arehitypical
forms ill the Divine mind. They are the patterns ac-
cording to which God wrought in the creation, and may
be said to correspond to the ''ideas" of Plato. In this
sense, universals ave before things: \miversalia ante rem.
2. Natural Universals. — These are the common nat-
ures belonging to different species, as rationality be-
longs to men. In this sense, universals are in things:
universalia in re,
3. Logical Universals. — These are general notions or
concepts framed by the human mind; they are based
on the common natures possessed by the species. In
this sense universals are after things: universalia post
rem.
4. Universal terms or names. — These stand for log-
ical universals; they are both after things and after
concepts.
See the Krauth- Fleming Vocabulary.
From these four propositions certain others flow.
. 1st. There are such things as species.
2d. These species existed in ideas before things; they
exist in substance in things; they exist in concepts and
names after things.
3d. The extreme Eealist is right in the sense of the
first proposition; the moderate Eealist in the sense of
the second; the Conceptualist is right in emphasizing
the subjective nature of the concept; and the extreme
Kominalist wrong in holding that names are the only
universals.
CHAPTEE V.
CLASSIFICATION AND CONCEPTION.
In classification, does the mind first ascend by gen-
eralization, from individuals to species, and from species
to genera, then descend, by division, from genera to
species, and from species to individuals, or does it pro-
ceed in a reverse order, that is, first descend, and then
ascend? In the formation of language, in its acquisition
by children, do proper nouns precede common, or do
common nouns precede proper?
Three theories have been proposed by philosophers
in their attempts to answer these questions ;
1st. Particulars are before generals^ and proper nouns
are before common. This view is held by Yives, Locke,
Eousseau, Condillac, Adam Smith, and others. Hamilton
translates from Yives thus: "The order of learning is
from the senses to the imagination, and from this to the
intellect; — such is the order of life and of nature. We
thus proceed from the simple to the complex, from the
singular to the universal. This is to be observed in
children, who first express the several parts of different
things, and then conjoin them. Things general they call
by singular names; for instance, the}^ call all smiths by
the name of that individual smith whom they have first
known, and all meats, beef or pork^ as they have hap-
pened to have heard the one or the other first, when
they began to speak. Thereafter, the mind collects uni-
versals from particulars, and then again reverts to par-
ticulars from universals." Metaphysics^ page 493.
(268)
ORDER IN CLASSIFICATION, 269
Locke expresses the same opinion in nearly the same
words as those used by Yives.
Adam Smith says : " The assignation of particular
names to denote particular objects, — that is, the institu-
tion of nouns substantive, would probably be one of the
first steps towards the formation of language. Two
savages, who had never been taught to speak, but had
been bred up remote from the societies of men, would
naturally begin to form that language by which they
would endeavor to make their mutual wants intelligible
to each other, by uttering certain sounds whenever they
meant to denote certain objects. Those objects only
which were most fiamiliar to them, and which they had
most frequent occasion to mention, would have particu-
lar names assigned to them. The particular cave whose
covering sheltered them from the weather, the particular
tree whose fruit relieved their hunger, the 23articular
fountain whose water allayed their thirst, would first be
denominated by the words cave^ tree, fountain, or by
whatever appellations they might think proper, in that
primitive jargon, to mark them.
"Afterwards, when the more enlarged experience of
these savages had led them to observe, and their necessary
occasions obliged them to make mention of other caves and
other trees and other fountains, they would naturally be-
stow upon each of these new objects the same name b}^
which they had been accustomed to express the similar ob-
ject they were first acquainted with. The new objects had
none of them any name of its own, but each of them exactly
resembled another object which had such an appellation.
It was impossible that those savages could behold the
new objects without recollecting the old ones, and the
names of the old ones to which the new bore so close a
resemblance. When they had occasion, therefore, to
mention or to point out to each other any of the new
270 PSYCHOLOGY.
objectSj thej would naturally utter the name of the cor-
respondent old one, of which the idea could not fail, at
that instant, to present itself to their memory in the
strongest and liveliest manner. And thus those words
which were originally the proper names of individuals,
would each of them insensibly become the common name
of a multitude.
^'A child that is just learning to speak, calls every per-
son who comes to the house its papa or its mam^ma;
and thus bestows upon the whole species those names
which it had been taught to apply to two individuals. . . .
"We say of a hero, that he is an Alexander; of an
orator, that he is a Cicero ; of a philosopher, that he is a
Newton. This way of speaking demonstrates how much
all mankind are naturally disposed to give to one object
the name of any other which nearly resembles it, and
thus to denominate a multitude by what originally was
intended to express an individual.
"It is this application of the name of an individual to
a great multitude of objects whose resemblance natu-
rally recalls the idea of that individual, and the name
which expresses it, that seems originally to have given
occasion to the formation of those classes and assort-
ments which, in the schools, are called genera and spe-
cies." Theory of Moral Sentiments — Appendix. ^
2d. Generals are before particulars and common nouns
before proper. This view was held by many of the school-
men, by Leibnitz, Turgot, and others. Leibnitz says:
"General terms serve not only for the perfection of
languages, but are even necessary for their essential f
constitution. For, if by particulars be understood things
individual, it would be impossible to speak if there were
only proper names and no appellatives; that is to say,
if there were only names for things individual, since,
at every moment, we are met by new ones, when we
ORDER IN CLASSIFICATION, 271
treat of persons, of accidents, and especially of actions,
which are those that we describe the most; but if by
particulars be meant the lowest species, besides that it
is frequently very difficult to determine them, it is
manifest that these are already universals founded on
similarity.
'■^ Now, as the only difference of species and genera
lies in a similarity of greater or less extent, it is nat-
ural to note every kind of similarity or agreement, and
consequently to employ general terms of everj^ degree;
nay, the most general being less complex with regard to
the essences which they comprehend, although more ex-
tensive in relation to the things individual to which
they apply, are frequently the easiest to fcrm, and are
the most useful.
^' It is likewise seen that children, and those who know
but little of the language which they attempt to speak, or
little of the subject on which they would employ it, make
use of general terms, as thing ^ plant ^ animal^ instead of
using proper names of which they are destitute.* ....
" I would add, in conformity to what I have previously
observed, that proper names have been originally ap-
pellative, that is to say, general in their origin, as
Brutus, Caesar, Augustus, Cicero, Alps, etc
" Thus, I would make bold to affirm that almost all
words have been originally general terms, because it
would happen very rarely that men would invent a
name, expressly and without reason, to denote this or
that individual. We may, therefore, assert that the
names of individual things were names of species, which
w^ere given par excellence^ or otherwise, to some individ-
ual
"It is thus, likewise, that men give the names of genera
to species, that is to say, that they content themselves with
a term more general or vague to denote more particu-
272 PSYCHOL OGY.
lar classes, when they do not care about differences."
Nouveaux JEssais, Lib. iii. Ch. i., page 297.
3d. Either order is followed indifferently. Hamilton
says: ''Here are two opposite opinions, having nearly
equal authority in their favor, maintained, on both sides,
with equal ability and apparent evidence. Either doc-
trine w^ould be held established w^cre w^e unacquainted
with the arguments in favor of the other. . . . .
"But I have now to state to you a third opinion in-
termediate betw^een these, which conciliates both, and
seems, moreover, to carry a superior probability in its
statement. This opinion maintains, that as our knowl-
edge proceeds from the confused to the distinct, — from
the vague to the determinate, — so, in the mouths of
children, language at first expresses neither the precisely
general, nor the determinately individual, but the vague
and confused; and that, out of this, the universal is
elaborated by generification, the particular and singular
by specification and individualization
'' Instead of commencing with minima, perception com-
mences with masses. Though our capacity of attention
be very limited in regard to the number of objects on
which a fiaculty can be simultaneously directed, yet these
objects may be large or small. We may make, for ex-
ample, a single object of attention, either of a w^hole
man, or of his face, or of his eye, or of the pupil of his
eye, or of a speck upon the pupil. To each of these
objects there can only be a certain amount of attentive
perception applied, and we can concentrate it all on
any one.
*' In proportion as the object is larger and more com-
plex, our attention can, of course, be less apj)lied to any
part of it, and consequently, our knowledge of it, in de-
tail, will be vaguer and more imperfect. But, having
first acquiix'd a comy)re1ionsive knowledge of it, as a
ORDER IN CLASSIFICATION. 273
whole, we can descend to its several parts, consider
these, both in themselves and in relation to each other,
and to the whole of which they are constituents, and
thus attain to a complete and articulate knowledge of
the objects. We decompose, and then we recompose. . . .
''I say, then, that the first procedure of mind, in the
elaboration of its knowledge, is always analytical. It
descends from the whole to the parts, — from the vague
to the definite. Definitude, that is, a knowledge of
minute differences, is not, as the oj)posite theory sup-
poses, the first, but the last term of our cognitions.
Between two sheep, an ordinary spectator can probably
apprehend no difference, and if they were twice pre-
sented to him, he would be unable to discriminate the
one from the other. But a shepherd can distinguish
every individual sheep; and why? Because he has de-
scended from the vague knowledge which makes every
sheeji, as it were, only a repetition of the same undiffer-
enced unit, — to a definite knowledge of qualities by
which each is contrasted from its neighbor. Now, in this
example, we apprehend the sheep by marks not less indi-
vidual than those by which the shepherd discriminates
them; but the w^hole of each sheep being made an ob-
ject, the marks by which we know it are the same in
each and all, and can not, therefore, afford the jmnciple
by which we can discriminate them from each other.
''I^ow, this is what appears to me to take place with
children. They first know, — they first cognize the
things and persons presented to them, as wholes. But
wholes of the same kind, if we do not descend to their
parts, afford us no difference, — no mark by which we
can discriminate the one from the other. Children, thus
originally perceiving similar objects, — persons, for exam-
ple, — only as wholes, do at first hardly distinguish them.
They apprehend first the more obtrusive marks that
274 PSYCHOLOGY.
separate species from sjoecies, and in consequence of the
notorious contrast of dress, men from women; but they
do not as yet recognize the finer traits that discriminate
individual from individual.
"But though thus apprehending individuals only by
what we now call their specific or their generic qualities,
it is not to be supposed that children know them by
any abstract, general attributes, that is, by attributes
formed by comparison and attention. On the other
hand, because their knowledge is not general, it is not
to be supposed to be particular or individual, if by par-
ticular be meant a separation of sjoecies from species,
and by individual, the separation of individual from in-
dividual; for children are apt to confound individuals
together, not only in name, but in reality." Page 497.
It may be remarked, on account of its bearing on
education, that though the order of procedure is, in gen-
eral, the collection of facts, the classification of facts,
and the reasoning on the facts, yet we are not to re-
frain from classifying till we have collected all possible
facts relating to all possible subjects, or from reasoning
till we have made all possible classifications. As soon
as we have collected the facts pertaining to a special
subject, we can classify, and as soon as we classify, we
can reason.
It is true that in a particular investigation the order
of thought is first acquisition, then representation, then
elaboration ; yet it is not true that the perceptive facul-
ties should first be educated, then the re23resentative,
then the elaborative. These faculties ought to be edu-
cated together. Children not only perceive, but imag-
ine and reason.
CHAPTBE VI.
QUANTITY OF CONCEPTS.
The quantity of a concept is of two kinds — compre-
hensive^ when referring to tlie number of common qual-
ities of a class, thus corresponding to the connotation of
the name, and extensive^ when referring to the number
of subdivisions of the class, thus corresponding to the
denotation of the name. Thus, the quantity of a con-
cept emerges, when the concept is viewed with refer-
ence to its objects — that is, to its content, or common
qualities involved, and to its extent, or the subdivisions
of the class.
1st. The comprehension of concepts. The comprehension
of a concept is that kind of quantity which is expressed
by the number of qualities, attributes, or characteristics,
as they are variously called, of which the concej)t is the
sum. It is also called its content, matter, depth, or in-
ternal or intensive quantity. In reference to its compre-
hension, a concept is, therefore, regarded as a whole of
which the constituent parts, or elements, are the com-
mon qualities of resembling individuals or classes.
The comprehension of the concept of a class is prima-
rily known in the act of its formation, that is, in com-
paring all the objects of a class, or a sufficient number
of them, and ascertaining and combining their common
qualities. It is secondarily known by analysis, that is,
by resolving the concept into its constituent elements.
Thus, the concept man is found to comprehend the ele-
ments connoted by the words rational and animal, the
(275)
276 PSYCHOLOGY.
word rational connoting the faculties of rational intni-
tion, conceiving, judging, and reasoning, and the word
animal connoting the common qualities possessed by liv-
ing sensitive beings. The concept man immediately
comprehending the concepts rational and animal, me-
diately comprehends all their parts, and the pai'ts of
these f)Jii^t^? ^i^lique; hence, triangles are divided into right tri-
Q UA XTITY OF CONCEPTS. 277
angles and oblique triangles. This division gives a di-
chotomy, of which the two parts are- contradictories,
since they are niiittially repugnant, and together univer-
sallv inchisive of all trianades. Btit shotild we divide
triano'les into rio-ht triano'les, acute triano:ies. and obtuse
triano'les, we should have a trichotomv. whose members
are contraries, since thev are mtituallv reptici:nant. but
no two of them universallv inclusive.
The definition of a sj^ecies refers it to its genus, and
characterizes it bv its content, and hence determines its
extent and distingtiishes it from the other species of the
genus.
Analysis gives content: division, extent: and definition,
both content and extent.
The comprehension of a concept can not be repre-
sented by the imagination, a2:)art from the extension,
nor the extension apart from the comprehension : btit
the class can be represented, as having both comji^rehen-
sion and extension, as found in the realities of nattire.
3d. jRelation of t?ie comprehension and the extension of
concepts.
(l^ The comprehension of a concept varies inversely
as its extension, that is. the o-reater the extent the less
the content, aiul converselv: for the hio-her the o-entis.
the greater the extension, and the less the comprehen-
sion : and the lower the species, the less the extension
and the greater the comprehension. Thtis. the compre-
hension of the concept animal is less than that of the
concept horse, since it contains those attributes only
which are common to all the subordinate sjiecies. whereas
the concept horse contains all the attribtites common to
all these species, and to all the species of the gentis con-
tainino- horse, toa'ether with what is characteristic of it-
self Btit the extension of the concept animal is greater
than that of the concept horse, since it contains the class
278 PSYCHOLOGY,
horse, as a subdivision, together with a great variety of
other subdivisions.
(2) The simple concept being is a minimum as to com-
prehension and a maximum as to extension. It is a
minimum as to comprehension, since it contains in it no
essential attribute which is not an attribute of every
class, sub-class, and individual contained under it, and
the only attribute thus common is existence. It is
a maximum as to extension; for, since being is the high-
est genus, it contains under it all other classes, sub-
classes, and individuals. It is, therefore, extensive rather
than comprehensive.
(3) The class being is incapable of definition, the com-
prehension of its concept is incapable of analysis, but
the extension is capable of division. The class is inca-
pable of definition, since it is not contained under a
higher genus, neither has it a difi*erential attribute. The
comprehension of its concept is incapable of analysis,
since it contains but one element — existence. The ex-
tension of its concept is capable of division, since by an
analysis of the comprehension of the parts of the exten-
sion, they are found to possess qualities peculiar to each;
hence, the class being can be resolved into classes, sub-
classes, and so on, down to individuals.
(4) An individual concept is a maximum as to com-
prehension and a minimum as to extension. It is a
maximum as to comprehension, since it contains all the
attributes common to all the individuals of its class, to-
gether with what is peculiar to itself It is a minimum
as to extension, since it contains no classes or individu-
als under it. It is, therefore, comprehensive rather than
extensive.
(5) An individual is capable of definition, the compre-
hension of its concept is capable of analysis, but the
extension is incapable of division. An individual is ca-
Q UANTITY OF CONCEPTS, 279
pable of definition, since it is contained under a class,
and has peculiar qualities. The comprehension of its
concej^t is capable of analysis, since it involves a plural-
ity of attributes. The extension of its concept is inca-
pable of division, since it contains neither classes nor
individuals undei* it.
(6) A concept neither simple nor individual is neither
a maximum nor a minimum, either as to comprehension
or to extension. Since it is neither the highest genus
nor an individual, it is neither a maximum nor a mini-
mum as to comprehension; for, the lower the species,
the greater the comprehension, down to the individuals,
and the higher the genus, the less the comprehension,
up to the highest genus. For like reason, it is neither
a maximum nor a minimum as to extension; for the
higher the genus, the greater the extension, up to the
highest genus, and the lower the species, the less the
extension, down to the individuals.
(7) A class, not the highest genus, is capable of defi-
nition, the comprehension of its concept is capable of
analysis, and the extension is capable of division. The
class is capable of definition, since it is contained under
a higher class, and has characteristic qualities. The
comprehension of its concept is cajDable of analysis, since
it involves a plurality of attributes, and the extension
is capable of division, since the class contains other
classes or individuals under it.
It will be observed that a class may be defined unless
it is the highest genus; that an individual may be de-
fined; that a concept is identified by naming the class
of which it is the concept; that the comprehension of a
concept is analyzed but not divided ; that the extension
of a concept is divided but not analyzed; that the com-
prehension of the concept being, does not admit of anal-
ysis, though its extension admits of division ; that the
280 PSYCHOLOGY,
extension of the concept of an individual does not admit
of division, though its comprehension admits of analysis;
that the class beino- contains but one universal attribute
— existence^ though all actual attributes are contained in
its parts; and that being is divided by analyzing the
contents of its parts.
In rising, by generalization, from individuals to spe-
cies, we abstract our thoughts from the peculiarities of
the individuals, and overlook their idiosyncrasies. Thus,
the concejDt of the species is less rich in attributes than
the idea of the individual. In like manner, in rising
from species to genera, and from these to still higher
genera, the ascending hierarchy of concepts become
more and more meager in content, till we reach that of
being, which is characterized by no attribute but that
of existence. Thus, the higher we rise, the greater the
poverty of our concepts in content, till they terminate
in the minimum of knowledge, if not in utter nescience.
There are two remedies for this undesirable result:
(1) The tendencies of abstraction and generalization
are counteracted by those of division and discrimination.
As we may rise higher and higher, and thus drop at-
tributes continually, so we may descend deeper and
deeper, and thus multiply attributes indefinitely. Though,
as we ascend towards the summit, the general concepts
of the higher classes necessarily contain fewer and fewer
elements, yet the classes themselves contain, not as uni-
versally diffused, but somewhere in their subdivisions,
every actual attribute. As we rise, though we drop the
elements not common from the contents of the general
concept, 3^et we retain them as elements of parts of the
extent. Thus being, though indeed containing but one
universal attribute, that of existence, contains in its sub-
divisions all attributes, and thus the division of being,
not of the concept, but of the class, gives all reality.
QUANTITY OF CONCEPTS. 281
(2) The intuition of reason declares the necessity of
the conditions of whatever exists, thus giving to every
thing its expUmation and law, and uniting all realities
by their common dependence on the Absolute First
Cause.
4th. Other forms of quantity. In addition to the two
forms of quantity, the comprehension and extension of
concepts, called the logical luJtoles, there are other wholes
of which the following are specimens:
(1) The dianoetic ivhole — the lohole of thought. Every
thing has its negation, and the two comprise the uni-
verse, — thus B and non-^. Then, we can say, A is B
or non-^.
(2) The mathematical whole — the whole of necessary
form. Of this species, there are two varieties: The
arithmetical ivhole, as a collection of objects, involving
time in their reckoning. The geometric ichole, as a cubic
foot of wood, a barrel of water. This is a mass whole,
and space is involved.
(3) The essential whole — the whole of being. Of this
S23ecies there are two varieties : T/ie substantial whole —
the substance with its attributes. The causal ichole — the
cause and its effects. The substantial Avhole and the
causal whole are the complementary parts of the essen-
tial whole.
(4) The corporate whole — the formal or aesthetic whole.
This is the idea revealed in the matter by the form.
(5) The accidental whole — the whole by accident. Of
this species there are three varieties — Of degree^ as man-
kind comprises the rich and the poor. Of position^ as
the upper and the lower, the right and the left, etc.
Of affinity^ as the family comprises the parent and the
children.
Psy.~24.
CHAPTEE YTI.
QUALITY OF CONCEPTS.
The Quality of a concept has relation to the subject
mind, and is chiefl}^ found in the pairs of opposites —
clearness and obscurit}^, distinctness and indistinctness.
1st. Clearness and obscurity. A concept is clear when
it is discriminated, as a whole, from other concepts. A
concept is obscure^ when it is confounded with other
concepts. Clearness is attained and obscurity avoided
by definition of the class.
The degree of clearness or obscurity of a concept is
variable. Perfect clearness, obviating all confusion, is a
possible, though a rare attainment. Total obscurity, ob-
literating all distinction, would, when reached, cause the
concept itself to vanish. The degree of obscurity, there-
fore, varies between the limits, perfect clearness and
total obscurity. A concept is characterized as clear or
obscure, according to its prevailing quality.
2d. Distinctness and indistinctness. Distinctness and
indistinctness have two varieties — comprehensive and
extensive. A concept has comprehensive or extensive
distinctness or indistinctness, according as the attributes
involved in its content, or the subdivisions embraced by
its extent, are discriminated or confounded. Compre-
hensive distinctness is attained, and comprehensive in-
distinctness is avoided, by analysis. Extensive distinct-
ness is attained, and extensive indistinctness is avoided,
by division.
The degree of distinctness, in general, varies between
( 282 )
q UALITY OF CONCEPTS. 283
the limits perfect distinctness and com2:)lete indistinct-
ness. A concept is characterized as distinct or indistinct,
according to its prevailing quality.
A concept may be clear, that is, be discriminated, as
a whole, from other concepts, and yet be more or less
indistinct. Thus, our concept of the genus animal may
be clear, and still be far from having either comprehen-
sive or extensive distinctness ; but a concept having both
comprehensive and extensive distinctness, has also the
quality of clearness. Distinctness is, therefore, a higher
virtue than clearness, and its attainment is a higher
achievement.
3d. Concepts admitting of distinctness. Since compre-
hensive distinctness signifies a clear apprehension and
discrimination of the attributes involved in the content
• of a concept, and extensive distinctness, a clear apj)re-
hension and discrimination of the classes and individu-
als embraced in the extent, and bound together into
unity by the nexus or content, it follows,
(1) That the concept being — the highest genus, since
it is a maximum as to extent, and a minimum as to
content — is capable of extensive distinctness, but incaj)a-
ble of comprehensive.
(2) That an individual concept, being a maximum as
to content, but a minimum as to extent, is capable of
comprehensive distinctness, but inca])able of extensive.
(3) That a concept neither the highest genus nor in-
dividual, since it is not a minimum either as to content
or extent, is capable both of comprehensive and exten-
sive distinctness.
4th. Rules for distinctness. These are the following:
(1) To secure comprehensive distiiictness, analyze the
content of the concept, noting especially the positive,
intrinsic, and essential elements, rather than the nega-
tive, extrinsic, and accidental.
284 PSYCHOLOGY.
(2) To secure extensive distinctness, divide the extent
of the concejDt, according to the peculiar, positive char-
acteristics of the parts.
5th. Sources of indistinctness. These are of two kinds:
(1) The nature of the concept itself, which is multi-
plicity, either as to content or extent, bound by a men-
tal act, into unity.
(2) The dependence of the concept on language, as the
condition of its continuance. The name becomes a sym-
bol for the concept, and frequently the mind is content
to employ the word without taking the trouble to call
up the concept. This may be well when we are able
to call up, at pleasure, the meaning of the word, in a
clear and distinct concept, thus relieving the mind of
an unnecessary burden. But when the mind employs a
word without the ability to call up the corresponding
concept, indistinctness and confusion of thought are sure
to follow. Use no word whose meaning; is not clear.
6th. Illustrations of clearness and obscurity^ distinctness
and indistinctness. Hamilton says : '' The expressions,
clearness and obscurity, distinctness and indistinctness,
as applied to concepts, originally denoted certain modi-
fications of vision; from vision, they were analogically
extended to the other senses, to imagination, and finally
to thought. It may, therefore, enable us the better to
comprehend their secondary application to consider their
primary.
" To Leibnitz we owe the precise distinction of con-
cepts into clear and distinct, and from him I borrow the
following illustration: In darkness — the complete ob-
scurity of night — we see nothing — there is no percep-
tion, — no discrimination of objects. As the light dawns,
the obscurity diminishes, the deep and uniform sensation
of darkness is modified, — we are conscious of a change,
— we see something, but are still unable to distinguish
QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS. 285
its features, — we know not what it is. As the light in-
creases, the outlines of wholes begin to appear, but still
not with a distinctness sufficient to allow us to perceive
them completely; but when this is rendered j)ossible by
the rising intensity of the light, we are then said to see
clearly. We then recognize mountains, plains, houses,
trees, animals, etc. ; that is, we discriminate these objects
as wholes, as unities, from one another. But their parts,
— the manifold, of which these unities are the sum —
their parts still lose themselves in one another; they
are still but indistinctly visible.
^'At length, when daylight has fully sprung, we are
enabled likewise to discriminate their parts; we now
see distinctly what lies around us. But still we see as
yet only the wholes which lie proximately around us,
and of these only the parts which possess a certain size.
The more distant wholes, and the smaller parts of the
nearer wholes, are still seen by us only in their conjoint
result, only as they concur in making up that whole
which is for us a visible minimum. Thus it is, that in
the distant forest, or on the distant hill, we perceive a
green surface; but we see not the several leaves, which
in the one, nor the several blades of grass, which in
the other, each contributes its effect to produce that
amount of impression which our consciousness requires.
Thus it is, that all which we do perceive is made up
of parts which we do not perceive, and consciousness is
itself a complement of impressions which lie beyond its
apprehension.
'' Clearness and distinctness are thus only relative.
For, between the extreme of obscurity and the extreme
of distinctness, there is in vision an infinity of inter-
mediate degrees. Now, the same thing occurs in thought.
For we may either be conscious only of the concept in
general, or we may also be conscious of its various con-
286 ' PSYCHOLOGY,
stituent parts, or both the concept and its parts may be
lost in themselves to consciousness, and only recognized
to exist by effects which indirectly evidence their exist-
ence." Logic ^ page 112.
7th. Other qualities of concepts. These are as follows:
(1) Valid concepts are those which are known to cor-
respond to their objects. Yalidity depends on evidence.
(2) Invalid concepts are those which are not known to
correspond to their objects. Invalidity implies want of
evidence.
(3) True concepts are those which correspond to their
objects. True concepts may be valid or invalid accord-
ing as there is a presence or absence of evidence. Valid
concepts are always true, but true concepts are not al-
ways valid. It is possible to assume the truth without
evidence. A concept is true or false, since it is an im-
plicit judgment, which is true or false.
False concepts are those which do not correspond to
their objects. False concej)ts are alwaj^s invalid, but
invalid concepts are not always false.
A concept, therefore, to be both true and valid must
correspond to its object, and must be also known to
correspond to its object. The correspondence must hold
as far as the concept goes, though the concept may not
do full justice to the object.
(5) Congruent concepts are those in which all the ele-
ments harmonize, that is, run together without conflict.
(6) Incongruent concepts are those which embrace con-
flictive elements — contrary or contradictory elements.
Incongruity is a mark of invalidity, and indicates that
some element has been assumed without warrant. Ya-
lidity implies congruity ; but congruity does not imply
validity, since there may be absence of evidence.
(7) Complete concepts are those which involve all the
common elements, and embrace all the divisions and sub-
QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS, 287
divisions of the class down to the individuals. Com-
pleteness is, in general, an ideal perfection. Yery few,
if any, of our concepts are complete.
(8) Incomplete concepts are those which embrace only
a part of the elements or objects of the class. Incom-
pleteness characterizes- most, if not all, of our concepts.
Most objects have qualities which have escaped our ob-
servation ; and most classes have individuals altogether
unknown to us. Different persons may form different
concepts of the same class, since one ]3erson may com-
bine one set of attributes, and another person, another
set. The same person may, at different times, form
different concepts of the same class. The concept may
change with advancing knowledge.
8th. Symbolic and intuitive knowledge. To illustrate
this distinction, we quote from Leibnitz and from Taine.
(1) Leibnitz says, as quoted by Hamilton: ''For the
most part, however, especially in an analysis of an^^
length, we do not view, at once, the whole characters
or attributes of the thing, but in place of these we
employ signs, the explication of which into what they
signify, we are wont, at the moment of actual thought,
for the sake of brevity, to omit, knowing or believing
that we have this explication always in our poAver.
Thus, when I think of a regular chiliagon, I do not al-
ways consider the various attributes of the sides, of
their equality, and of the number, a thousand, but I
use these words, whose meaning is obscurely and im-
perfectly presented to the mind, in lieu of notions which
I have of them, because I remember that I possess the
signification of these words, though their application and
explication, 1 do not, at present, deem necessary. This
kind of thinking, I am used to call blind or symbolic. We
employ it not only in algebra and arithmetic, but in fact
universally. And certainly, when the notion is very com-
288 PSYCHOLOGY.
plex, we can not think, at once, all the ingredient no-
tions; but when this is possible — at least, inasmuch as
it is possible — I call the cognition intuitive.
" Of the primary elements of our notions, there is
given no other knowledge than the intuitive; as of our
composite notions, there is, for the most part, possible
only a symbolic. From these considerations, it is evi-
dent that of the things which we distinctly know, w^e
are not conscious of the ideas, except so far as we em-
ploy an intuitive cognition. Indeed, it happens that we
often falsely believe that we have in our minds the ideas
of things, erroneously supposing that certain terms
which we employ had been applied and explicated ;
and it is not true, at least it is ambiguously expressed,
what some assert, — that we can not speak concerning
any thing, understanding what we say, without having
an idea of it actually present. For we frequently ap-
ply any kind of meaning to the several words, or we
merely recollect that we have formerly understood them;
but because we are content with this blind thinking,
and do not follow out the resolution of the notions, it
happens that contradictions are allowed to lie hid, which
perchance the composite notion involves." Logic, page
128. Symbolic and intuitive knowledge thus clearly differ.
(2) Taine says : " My garden is surrounded b}^ a hedge,
and my fruit is stolen ; I determine on enclosing it with
a wall. I get wdiat workmen I can in the village —
lour, for instance — and at the end of the day, I find
they have built twelve meters of wall. This is not fast
enough; I send to the next village for six other work-
men, and ask myself how many meters a day will be
added to the wall. To find out this, I no longer picture
to myself workmen, with their blouses and trowels —
the wall with its stones and mortar, — but replace my first
workmen by the figure four, the first amount of work
QUALITIES OF CONCEPTS, 289
by the figure twelve, the whole number of workmen by
the figure ten, the amount of work they will do by the
symbol x^ and write down the following proportion,
12 X 10
4.:l2::\{):x = =3 30.
4
^'Henceforth, barring accident or drunkenness, if the
new men work like the old, and all continue to work
together, as the first four began, my ten men will build
thirty meters a da^^. Operations of this kind occur
daily, and all practical calculations are made in this
way.
''For the real objects first imagined, figures are substi-
tuted which replace them partially; they replace them
in the only point of view in which we need consider
them, that is, in point of number. This once effected,
we forget the objects represented; they recede into the
background; we only consider the figures; we assemble,
compare, transpose, and manij^ulate them as more con-
venient equivalents; and the figure we finally arrive at,
indicates the object or group of objects at which we
wish to arrive.
"Substitution goes further than this, and figures sub-
stituted for things have in turn letters substituted for
them. After several similar calculations, I observe that,
in all such cases, the proportion is written in the same
way — that the first figure always represents the first
workmen; the second figure, their work; the third, the
whole number of workmen; the fourth, the unknown
work; and I thus pass from arithmetic to algebra.
Henceforth, I replace the first figure by A^ the second
by B^ the third by (7, and write down as follows:
^X G
A: B : : C :x =
A
•'I see tluit, in every such case, if I want to know
Psy.~2.5.
290 PSYCHOLOGY.
the amount of work which will be done by all the work-
men^ it will be sufficient to multiply their number by
that representing the work done by the first lot^ and
then to divide the product by the number of workmen
first employed.
"Instead of this simj)le case, let us consider the labor
of an analyist, who Writes equations by the hour. He
lays aside the figures, but indirectly he is working on
them, just as an arithmetician lays aside the facts, but
works indirectly on the facts. Each of them arranges
and combines symbols, and these symbols are substitutes.
The fact is, they are not like proper names, substituted
for the whole of the object they represent, but merely
for a portion or an aspect of such object. The letter
used in Algebra does not fully replace the arithmetical
figure with its precise quantity, but only as regards its
function and place in the equation it enters into. The
arithmetical figure does not fully replace the thing it
stands fi^r, with all its qualities and characters, but only
as regards quantity and number. Each replaces a part
only of the imagined object; that is to say, a fragment
— an extract; the figure, a more complex extract; the
letter, a less complex one; that is to say, an extract from
the first extract. But the substitution, though partial,
is none the less actual. Two complete and infinitely
fertile sciences depend on it, and .derive their efficiency
from it." Taine on Intelligence^ page 4..
^
CHAPTEE VTII.
RELATION OF CONCEPTS.
The reciprocal relation of concepts may be considered
with respect to their comprehension and to their exten-
sion, thus giving two independent classifications.
1. As to comprehension, we may consider identity
and diversity, congruity and incongruity, the intrinsic
and the extrinsic, subordination and co-ordination.
Ist. Identity and diversity. Two concepts, when com-
pared, are found to comprise eitlier the same elements
or different elements, giving rise to the distinctions of
identical concepts and different concepts, or, in general,
of identity and diversity.
(1) Identity. Identical concepts are either absolutely
identical or relatively identical.
a. Absolute identity. No two concepts are absolutely
identical; for, if so, they could not be distinguished as
two, since they would have no difference by which they
could be discriminated. This class of concepts, therefore,
has not a real^ but only an ideal existence, and consti-
tutes an imaginary member in the division of identical
concepts. Even the concepts relating to the same class,
formed by different minds, or by the same mind at dif-
ferent times, which make the nearest approach to abso-
lute identity, are distinguishable ; for, we can say, that
the one w^as formed by this mind, and the other by
that, or that one was formed by a mind at one time,
and the other by the same mind at another time. These
concepts, if otherwise identical, are numerically differ-
( 291 )
292 PSYCHOLOGY.
ent — one can be distinguished as the first, and the other
as the second. The difference is not intrinsic, but ex-
trinsic; not essential, but accidental.
b. Relative identity. Concepts relatively identical are
of two kinds — reciprocating, or convertible, and similar,
or cognate.
«. Concepts relatively identical are reciprocating^ or
convertible^ when they relate to the same class, but des-
ignate it, in the one case, by one set of attributes, and,
in the other case, by another set. Thus, the concept of
the class denominated equilateral triangles, designates
the class by the equality of the sides, while the concept
of the class denominated equiangular triangles, designates
the class by the equality of the angles. But since, in
the case of triangles, the equality of the sides involves
the equality of the angles, and conversely, the class of
triangles denominated equilateral is identical with the
class denominated equiangular; hence, the concepts of
this class corresponding to the expressions, equilateral
triangles and equiangular triangles, though not abso-
lutely identical, since in the one case, the equality of
the sides is made prominent, and, in the other, the equal-
ity of the angles, jai are relatively identical, or more
specifically, reciprocating, or convertible, since one in-
volves the other.
^. Concepts relatively identical are similar^ or cognate^
when they belong to the same family, and having the
same origin are thus kindred. Certain languages are
said to be cognate, and the same may be said of certain
virtues or vices.
(2) Diversity. Different concepts are either absolutely
different or relatively different.
a. Absolute difference. No two concepts are absolutely
different; for, if not subordinate to an}^ lower genus,
they are, at least, subordinate to being, the highest
RELATION OF CONCEPTS.
293
genus, and hence agree in possessing existence^ the attri-
bute of this genus, though they differ in other respects.
Absolutely different concejits, therefore, constitute an
ideal or imaginary member of the class different con-
cepts, and merely give symmetry to the classification.
h. Relative difference. Concepts relatively different are
distinguished by the fact that they possess diverse at-
tributes, though they have other attributes in common.
The laws of resemblance and difference are as follows :
(1) The law of homogeneity. However different two
concepts, they m.ust, in some respect, at least in that of
existence, be alike; for, every other concept is subordi-
nate to that of being. Hence, things most dissimilar
must, in one respect at least, be similar.
(2) The laiv of heterogeneity. Every concept contains
other concepts under it. In thought, therefore, the di-
vision of concej^ts gives concepts, not individuals. Hence,
things most similar, must, in certain respects, be dissim-
ilar. Thus, take any two concepts with a small differ-
ence. Now, this difference can be divided, thus giving
new concepts distinguished by this partial difference,
and so on, ad infinitum. But the infinite divisibility of
concepts, like the infinite divisibility of space, time, or
matter, exists only in speculations.
To illustrate, let us classify angles, thus:
Angles
liight
<
Oblique
V
Acute
Obtuse
Here we pause, not because it is impossible to pursue
294 PSYCHOLOGY,
the divisions further, but because it is not called for.
But we can conceive these angles to be situated in a
horizontal, a vertical, or an oblique plane, giving hori-
zontal, vertical, or oblique angles. These angles may
have any position in these planes, and the sides may
take an infinite number of directions for each position
of the vertex. The acute angle may vary through an
infinite number of values, between the limits 0^ and 90^,
and the obtuse angle may vary, in like manner, between
the limits 90° and 180°.
2d. Congruity and incongruity. Again, as to compre-
hension, two concepts are either congruent or conflictive.
(1) Congruity. Two concepts are congruent, if they
can be united in thought, so that one can be afiirmed
of the other, or both can be afiirmed of the same object.
Thus, triangles are polygons. A single concept is con-
gruous if all its elements harmonize, as a square field.
(2) Incongruity. Incongruous concepts are conflictive,
since they involve inconsistent attributes. They are of
two kinds — contraries and contradictories.
a. Contrary concepts are mutually repugnant, though
not universally inclusive of their genus. Thus, the con-
cepts of the classes triangles and quadrilaterals are con-
» trary, since they do not include all the divisions of the
genus polygon.
h. Contradictory concepts are mutually repugnant and
universally inclusive of the genus of which they are
species. Thus, right triangles and oblique triangles are
contradictories within the sphere of the genus triangle.
Any triangle is either right or oblique; if it is one, it
is not the other; and if it is not one, it is the other.
But within the sphere of another genus, as polygon, right
triangles and oblique triangles are not contradictories.
Hence, contradictories in a restricted sphere are not
necessarily contradictories when the sphere is enlarged.
RELATION OF CONCEPTS, 295
Thus, honest and dishonest are contradictories within
the sphere of moral beings, but not within the sphere
of beings. Thus, vertebrate and invertebrate are con-
tradictories within the spliere of animals; organic and
inorganic, within the sphere of beings; the ego and the
non-ego, A and not-^1, being and non-being, are univer-
sally contradictories, since their sphere is absolutely un-
limited, the two members together comprehending every
thing, existent and non-existent,
A single concept is incongruous, when it involves con-
flictive elements, as a round square.
Identity is to be distinguished from congruity, and
diversity from confliction. All identical concepts are
congruent, but all congruent concepts are not identical.
Thus, the concej)ts of the classes, equilateral triangles
and equiangular triangles are relatively identical and
congruent; learning and virtue are congruent, but not
identical. All conflictive concepts are diverse, but all
diverse concepts are not conflictive. Thus, virtue and
vice, beauty and ugliness, are conflictive and diverse;
but virtue and beauty are diverse but not conflictive.
od. The intrinsic and extrinsic. As to comprehension,
we may also regard concepts as intrinsic or extrinsic.
- (1) Intrinsic concepts are those which involve the
qualities necessary to the existence of the class — they
contain essential elements. Thus, the concept of a tri-
angle involving three sides and three angles, is intrinsic.
(2) Extrinsic concepts are those which consist of ac-
cidental qualities — those not essential to the existence
of the class. Thus, the concept of a triangle involving
the equality of its sides, is extrinsic.
4th. Subordination and, co-ordination. As to compre-
hension, we may regard concepts in the relation of sub-
ordination or co-ordination.
(1) One concept is subordinate to another, as to com-
296 PSYCHOLOGY.
prehension, when the first forms a part of the sum total
of the elements which together constitute tlie compre-
hension of the second. The concepts of sides, angles,
and area of a triangle are involved in the concept of
the class triangle.
(2) Two or more concepts are co-ordinate^ as to com-
prehension, when they are exclusive and both are im-
mediately comprehended as elements of the same con-
cept. . Thus, the concepts of the sides, angles, and area of
a triangle, are co-ordinate with one another, though
alike subordinate to the concept triangle.
2. As to extension, we may consider co-extension,
subordination, exclusion, and intersection.
1st. Co-extension. One concept is co-extensive with an-
other, when they relate to the same class, and thus have
the same sphere. Thus, equilateral triangles and equi-
angular triangles are co-extensive. In comprehension,
these concepts are called reciprocating or convertible.
Of the two elements, the equality of the sides, and the
equality of the angles, that which is explicitly enounced
in the one is implicitly involved in the other, and con-
versely. The subject and j^redicate of a definition are
co-extensive. Thus, in the definition, a triangle is a
polygon of three side, the concepts, triangle, and a
polygon of three sides, are co extensive.
Co-extension may be symbolized by two
equal co-incident circles, which appear as
one, though indicated as two by two letters
placed within, thus:
2d. Subordination. One concept is subordinate to
another, when, as to extension, the former is contained
under the latter, as an individual under a species, or a
species under a genus. If one concept is subordinate to
another, it is subordinate to any higher concept em-
bracing the other. Thus, since horse is subordinate to
RELATION OF CONCEPTS, 297
the genus equus, it is subordinate to quadruped, verte-
brate, animal, organized being, being.
Subordination may be symbolized by one
circle within another, the inner circle de-
noting the subordinate concept. Thus, A is
subordinate to JB.
3d. Exclusion. One concept is excluded from another,
when they have nothing in common as to extension.
Thus, the concepts of the classes horse and dog, aiford
an example of exclusion, as to extension, since they
have neither species nor individuals in common.
Exclusive concepts may be either co-ordinate or non-
co-ordinate, — co-ordinate, when each is subordinate to
the same concept, as acute angles and obtuse angles,
which are immediately subordinate to oblique angles, —
non-co-ordinate., when one, but not the other is immedi-
ately subordinate to a third concept, as right angles
and acute angles, right angles being immediately subor-
dinate to angles, and acute angles to obliqe angles.
Exclusive concepts are conflictive, as to comprehension,
and are either contrary or contradictory, — contrary,
when they are not universally inclusive of their genus,
— contradictory, when they are universally inclusive of
their genus. Thus right angles and acute angles are
contraries, while right angles and oblique angles are
contradictories.
The exclusion of contraries may /^ X /^ ^
be symbolized by two exclusive cir- I A \ I B j
cles. Thus, the circles A and B. V.__^ V__^
The exclusion of contradictories
may be symbolized by one circle and the indefinite
surrounding space in the plane of the circle y^ \
— the circle denoting one of the contradicto- (a ]B
ries, and the indefinite space the other, as V__^
A and B in the annexed figure.
298
PSYCHOLOGY.
4th. Intersection. Two concepts intersect, when their
extensions have a common part, and the extension of
each a j)art not common with the other. Thus, the
concepts men and liars intersect. For, some men are
liars; some liars are men; some men are not liars; and
some liars are not men.
Intersection may be symbolized by two
intersecting circles. The concepts sym-
bolized by A and B^ intersect.
This method of representing the rela-
tion of the concepts of classes, as to extension, is due
to Euler. The circles do not, of course, resemble the
concepts, but the relation of the circles does correctly
represent the relation of the extension of the concepts.
CHAPTBE IX.
JUDGMENT.
1. A judgment is the decision that a certain relation
exists between two objects of thought.
It has already been seen that every act of cognition
involves a judgment. A concept itself is an implicit or
undeveloped judgment. This is evident from an analy-
sis of the act of conception, for, in conception certain
attributes are regarded as belonging to all the objects
of a class, thus involving the judgment that each object
of the class has these attributes.
The judgments involved in a concept are called pri-
mary or psychological. They have individual objects
for their subjects, and attributes or concepts for their
predicates. Judgments in which concepts are predicated
of concepts are called secondary or logical.
2. A proposition is the expression of a judgment. For
the purposes of logic, a proposition is considered as con-
sisting of three parts — a subject, always a substantive
or a substitute for a substantive, that of which some-
thing is affirmed or denied, a predicate, also a substan-
tive or its substitute, that which is affirmed or denied
of the subject, and the copula, is or is not, or in the
plural, are or are not, which affirms or denies the predi-
cate of the subject. Thus, horses are animals , lying is
not a virtue.
Such propositions as, trees grow; birds are beautiful,
are put into the requisite form by saying, Trees are
things which grow. Birds are beautiful animals.
(299)
300 PSYCHOLOGY.
A proposition does not necessarily imply the real ex-
istence of the object denoted by the subject; for this
object may be imaginary, as in the proposition, A cen-
taur is half horse and half man. Whether the subject
denotes a real or an imaginary object is to be deter-
mined by considerations independent of the proposition.
3. The terms of a proposition, from termini^ limits or
boundaries, are the subject and predicate, which limit or
mark the extremes of a proposition. A term expresses
an individual or a group of individuals, an attribute or
a group of attributes.
Ist. A singular term is expressive of an individual.
Thus, Plato, George Washington, this boy, etc., are sin-
gular terms.
2d. A common term is expressive of each individual of
a class, as well as the class itself. Thus, man, horse,
tree, etc., are common terms.
3d. A collective term is expressive of a group, but not
of each individual of the group. Thus, the senate, the
convention, the army, etc., are collective terms, since
we can say this body of men is the senate, but not that
Sherman is the senate, etc.
4th. An attributive term is an adjective or a partici]3le
expressing an attribute or a group of attributes. Thus,
white, human, etc. For logical purposes, a noun is un-
derstood when an attributive is the predicate. Thus,
Plato is human, is logically equivalent to, Plato is a
human being. An attributive can not by itself be used
as the subject, but only in connection with a noun, as
this human being is Plato.
5th, An abstract term is a noun expressive of an at-
tribute or a group of attributes considered apart from
the object to which it belongs. Thus, humanity, virtue,
form, color, etc. An abstract term may, b}^ itself, be
either the subject or the predicate of a proposition.
GENERAL VIEW. 301
4. The modality of a proposition is the view of it
taken by the mind as influenced by the degree of evi-
dence. It is expressed by an adverb in connection Avith
the copula. Thus, This is certainly the boy who stole
the fruit; this is probably the boy w^ho stole the fruit, etc.
These propositions may be expressed in the usual logi-
cal form, thus. That this is the boy who stole the fruit
is a certainty, etc.
5. The classification of judgments may be with ref-
erence to logical quantity, origin, validity, truth, or form.
1st. As to logical quantity^ judgments are comprehen-
sive or extensive, according as the quantity of the predi-
cate is comprehensive or extensive.
(1) A comprehensive judgment is one in which the
predicate is considered in reference to its content. Thus,
these houses are white.
(2) An extensive judgment is one in which the predi-
cate is considered in reference to its extent. Thus, a
horse is an animal.
A comprehensive judgment may be turned into an
extensive judgment. Thus, these houses are white, is
equivalent to these houses are white objects.
In a comprehensive judgment, the subject is the whole
of comprehension of which the predicate is affirmed or
denied to be a part. The copula is or is not, signifies
comprehends or does not comprehend.
In an extensive judgment, the predicate is the whole
of extension of which the subject is affirmed or denied
to be a part. The copula, is or is not, signifies is con-
tained under or is not contained under.
A definition is both an extensive and a comprehensive
judgment; for the predicate as the genus of the subject
is extensive, while the differential quality is comprehen-
sive, and thus limits the extent of the subject to that
part of the predicate characterized by this quality.
302 PSYCHOLOGY,
2d. As to origin^ judgments are primitive or derivative,
according as they are original or derived.
(1) A primitive judgment is assumptive or intuitive,
according as the relation of the subject and predicate is
an assumption or an intuition. Thus, Mars is inhabited,
is a primitive judgment, since it is not derived from
other judgments; and is assumptive, since it is not
known to be true. Either of two equal quantities is a
substitute for the other, is both a primitive and an intui-
tive judgment.
(2) A derivative judgment is demonstrative or proble-
matical, according as it is capable or incapable of proof
A judgment which is strictly demonstrative may be re-
garded as problematical till it is proved true.
3d. As to validity^ judgments are valid or invalid.
(1) A judgment is valid ^ when the concepts are valid,
and the relation is intuitive or demonstrative. It is
valid, if its truth is known. A valid judgment is true.
(2) A judgment is invalid^ when the law of validity
is not complied with. It is invalid, if its truth is not
known. An invalid judgment is true or false.
4th. As to truths judgments are true or false.
(1) A judgment is true^ when the relation expressed
corresponds to the reality. A true judgment is valid or
invalid according to evidence.
(2) A judgment is false ^ when the relation exj)ressed
does not correspond to the reality. A false judgment is
invalid.
Validity depends on evidence, and implies truth, but
truth on correspondence, with or without evidence.
5th. As to form^ judgments are either categorical or
conditional.
(1) A categorical judgment is one. in which the rela-
tion expressed is not qualified by a condition. Thus,
horses are animals; some men are liars; >§ is P.
GENERAL VIEW. 303
(2) A conditional judgment is one in which the rela-
tion expressed is qualilied by a condition.
There are three varieties of conditional judgments —
hypothetical, disjunctive, and dilemmatic.
a. A hypothetical judgment is a conditional judgment
in which the qualifying condition is an hyj)othesis. Thus,
if ^ is ^, is D.
h. A disjunctive judgment is a conditional judgment in
which the qualifying condition is an alternative. Thus,
J. is £ or C, which is equivalent to, if A is not (7, A
is -B, or if A is not B, A is C.
c. A dilemmatic judgment is a conditional judgment in
which there are two qualifying conditions — an hypoth-
esis and an alternative. Thus, if J. is B, C is D or E.
6. The principles of expression are those warranting
aflSrmation, negation, hypothecation, or disjunction.
1st. Affirmation is either immediate or mediate.
(1) Immediate affirmation is warranted by knowledge
gained by empirical intuition, as in consciousness, or by
rational intuition, as the fundamental axioms of thought
or the special axioms of the various sciences.
(2) Mediate affirmation is warranted in several ways:
a. By the law of contradictories. Thus, we can af-
firm either of two contradictories, if we know the other
is false.
h. By valid inference from a single ^proposition. Thus,
if I know that all S is P, I can affirm that some 8
is P, or that some P is S.
c. By logical deduction from valid premises. Thus, if
I know that all M is P, and that all >S' is M, I am
warranted in affirming that all S is P.
2d. Negation is either immediate or mediate.
(1) Immediate negation is warranted by the principle
of identity — a thing is not any thing other than itself
(2) Mediate negation is warranted in several ways:
304 PSYCHOLOGY,
a. By the law of conflictives. Thus, knowing the
truth of either of two conflictives, we are warranted in
denying the other.
h. By a valid inference from a single proposition.
Thus, knowing that no S is P, we can afSrm that some
S is not P, or that no P is aS'.
c. By logical deduction from valid premises. Thus,
knowing that no M is P, and that all S is M^ we are
warranted in affirming that no S is P.
3d. Hypothecation is warranted, if the condition is a
valid reason for the consequent, thus, if A has the fever,
he is sick.
4th. Disjunction is warranted by two reasons:
(1) When the parts of the predicate are contradicto-
ries. Thus, a triangle is right or oblique.
(2) When the parts of the predicate are all of the
contraries. Thus, an angle is right, acute, or obtuse.
'M\
CHAPTER X.
CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS.
1. Categorical judgments are classified as to quantity
and as to quality.
Ist. As to quantity^ categorical judgments are univer-
sal or particular — universal^ when the predication, that
iSj the affirmation or denial, is made of all the subject,
as all S is P, no >S is P ; particular, when the predica-
tion is made of only a part of the subject, as some S is
P, some S is not P.
2d. As to quality, categorical judgments are affirmative
or negative — affirmative, when the predicate is affirmed
of the subject, as all S is P, some S is P; negative, when
the predicate is denied of the subject, as no S is P, some
S is not P.
An individual proposition, as John is a man, is to be
regarded as a universal.
An indefinite proposition, one devoid of any mark of
quantity, is to be interpreted, either as a universal or
as a particular, according to the matter, but this inter-
pretation is extra-logical, since logic deals with the form
of thought and not with the matter. Thus, planets are
subject to the law of gravitation, is interpreted as a uni-
versal — all planets are subject to the law of gravitation.
Metals are useful is inter j)reted as a particular — some
metals are useful.
Dividing w4th respect to quantity, and subdividing
with respect to quality, denoting the universal affirma-
tive by (A), the universal negative by (E), the particu-
Psy.-26. ( 305 )
306
PSYCHOLOGY,
lar affirmative by (1). and the particular negative by
(O), we have the following summary classification of
categorical judgments:
Universal
Particular
Affirmative (A) All 8 is P.
Negative {E) ]N"o S is P.
Affirnia'tive (/) Some S is P.
Negative (0) Some S is not P.
2. The laws of trutli are the following:
1st. {A), All S is P, is true, if
8 is subordinate to P, or if 8 is
co-extensive with P
2d. (^), No >S is P, is true, if
8 is excluded from P.
3d. (/), Some 8
is P, is true, if {A)
is true, as above,
also if 8 intersects
P, or if P is sub-
ordinate to 8.
4th. (O), Some /S
is not P, is true,
if (^) is true, as
above, also if 8 in-
tersects P, or if P
is subordinate to 8.
3. The relation of the propositions, (J), (^), (/),
(0), or as it is commonly called, their opposition^ is thus
shown:
CATEGOEICAL JUDGMENTS.
307
A Contraries E
I 8ub-oontraries Q
Ist. In relation to agreement or disagreement in quantity
or quality.
(1) (A) and {E) agree in quantity, both being univer-
sal; they disagree in quality, (A) being affirmative, and
{E) negative.
(2) (/) and (0) agree in quantity, both being partic-
ular; they disagree in quality, (/) being affirmive, and
(0) negative.
(3) (J.) and (Z) agree in quality, both being affirma-
tive; they disagree in quantity, (A) being universal, and
(7) particular.
(4) {E) and (0) agree in quality, both being nega-
tive; they disagree in quantity, (^) being universal, and
(0) particular.
(5) (A) and (0) disagree both in quantit}^ and in qual-
ity, (A) being universal and affirmative, and (0) par-
ticular and negative.
(6) (jK) and (7) disagree both in quantity and in qual-
ity, (7i^) being universal and negative, and (7) particular
and affirmative.
2d. As to agreement or disagreement in truth or falsity.
Let it be observed tliat there are five diiferent rela-
tions possible between S and P, — S is subordinate to P,
308 PSYCHOLOGY.
S is co-extensive with P, 8 is excluded from P, .8 inter-
sects Pj and P is subordinate to ;S^.
(1) (^) and (^E) are mutually repugnant, since neither
relation, 8 is subordinate to P, or 8 is co-extensive with
P, included in (^), is found in (P), nor is the relation, 8
is excluded from P, which is expressed by (P), found in
(J.); hence, having no relation common, they can not both
be true, and therefore the truth of either implies the
falsity of the other. If it is true that all 8 is P, it is
false that no 8 is P, and if it is true that no 8 is P,
it is false that all 8 is P.
(2) (J.) and (P) are not universally inclusive of all
possible relations of 8 and P, since there are other re-
lations, as 8 intersects P, P ij subordinate to 8, not
found in either; hence, not including all possible rela-
tions, they may both be false, and therefore the falsity
of either does not imply the truth of the other.
(3) Hence, (^) and (P) are called contraries, since
they are mutually repugnant, but not universally in-
clusive. Other relations are possible.
(4) Since the relations in (4) are found in (7), the
truth of (^) involves the truth of (7). For this reason,
{A) and (7) are called subalterns, though, strictly, (7) is
the subaltern of (A).
(5) Since (7) contains relations not found in (A), as
well as those in (J), the falsity of (A) does not imply
the falsity of (7), nor does the truth of (7) imply the
truth of (yl), but the falsity of (7) implies the falsity
of (A), since the relations in (A) are in (7).
(6) For like reasons, (0) is the subaltern of (P), the
truth of (P) implies the truth of (0), the falsity of (P)
does not imply the falsity of (0), nor does the truth of
(0) imply the truth of (P), but the falsity of (0) im-
plies the falsity of (P).
(7) Since (7) and (O) contain the common relations,
CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS. 309
S intersects P, and P is subordinate to S^ both may be
true; hence, the truth of either does not imply the
falsity of the other.
(8) Since (/) and (0) are universally inclusive of all
possible relations of S and P, both can not be false;
hence, the falsity of either implies the truth of the other.
(9) Since (/) contains relations not found in (0), and
(0) a relation not found in (/), either may be true and
the other false; hence, the truth of either does not im-
ply the truth of the other.
(10) (7) and (0) are subordinate to (^4.) and (^E^^ re-
spectively, and hence are called sub-contriries.
(11) (A) and (0) are mutually repugnant, since they
contain no common relation ; hence, they can not both
be true, and therefore the truth of either implies the
falsity of the other; and since they are universally in-
clusive of all possible relations of S and P, both can
not be false, and therefore the falsity of either implies
the truth of the other. Hence, (A) and (0) are called
contradictories, since they are mutually repugnant and
universally inclusive.
(12) For like reasons, (^E) and (7) are contradicto-
ries; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of the
other, and the falsity of either, the truth of the other.
3d. These relations may likewise be thus expressed:
(1) The truth of (A.) implies the truth of (7) and the
falsity of (7^) and (O); but the falsity of (A) implies
the truth of (0).
(2) The truth of (E) implies the truth of (O) and
the falsity of (A) and (7) ; but the falsity of (E) im-
plies the truth of (7).
(3) The truth of (7) implies the falsity of (E) ; but
the falsity of (7) implies the truth of (E) and (0) and
the falsity of (J).
(4) The truth of (O) implies the falsity of (A); but
310 PSYCHOLOGY.
the falsity of (0) implies the truth of {A) and (J) and
the falsity of {E).
Let the student answer the following questions:
(1) What does the truth of (J.) imply? What the
falsity of {A) imply?
(2) What does the truth of (^) imply? What does
the falsity of {E) imply?
(3) What does the truth of (/) imply? What does
the falsity of (/) imply?
(4) What does the truth of (0) imply? What does
the falsity of (0) imply?
(5) What implies the truth of (A) ? the falsity of {A) ?
(6) What implies the truth of {E)l the falsity of (^)?
(7) What implies the truth of (/)? the falsity of (/)?
(8) What implies the truth of (0)? the falsity of (0)?
(9) Show in three ways that the falsity of (/) im-
plies the truth of (0).
(10) Show in three ways that the falsity of (0) im-
plies the truth of (7).
4th. These relations may receive a more general ex-
pression :
(1) The truth of a universal implies the truth of its
particular; but the falsity of a universal does hot imply
the falsity of its particular.
(2) The falsity of a particular implies the falsity of
its universal; but the truth of a particular does not im-
ply the truth of its universal.
(3) The contraries can not both be true, but may both
be false; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of
the other; but the falsity of either does not imply the
truth of the other.
(4). The sub-contraries can not both be false, but may
both be true ; hence, the falsity of either implies the truth
of the other ; but the truth of either does not imply the
falsity of the other.
CA TEG ORICAL JUl) GMENTS. 31 1
(5) Two contradictories can not both be true nor both
false; hence, the truth of either implies the falsity of the
other, and the falsity of either the truth of the other.
In the above discussion, we have considered the form
of the proposition but not the matter.
5th. The following statements, though extra-logical,
may be found to be useful.
(1) In necessary matter, the affirmatives, {A) and (J),
are both true, and the negatives, {E) and (0), are both
false. Thus, all triangles have three sides, and some
triangles have three sides, are both true; but no triangles
have three sides, and some triangles have not three sides
are both false.
(2) In contingent matter, the particulars, (/) and (0),
are both true, and the universals, {A) and (J5/), both
false. Thus, some triangles are right, and some triangles
are not right, are both true; but all triangles are right,
and no triangles are right, are both false.
(3) In impossible matter, the negatives, {E) and (0),
are both true, and the affirmatives, (^) and (7), both
false. Thus, no triangles have four sides, and some tri-
angles have not four sides, are both true; but all tri-
angles have four sides, and some triangles have four
sides, are both false.
CHAPTEE XL
CATEGORICAL JUDGMENTS.
1. Distribution of terms. — 1st Definition and remarks.
A term is distributed when it is applied to all the in-
dividuals denoted by the name. Thus, in the expres-
sions, all men^ no nien^ the term men is distributed.
A term is undistributed when it is applied only to some
of the individuals denoted by the name. Thus, men is
undistributed in the expression some men.
It would seem that distribution is applicable only to
common terms; but as singular^ collective^ and abstract
terms are, as \\q have seen, regarded as universal, they
are regarded as distributed.
When an attribute is used as a predicate, the noun un-
derstood is to be supplied before the rule for distribu-
tion is to be applied. Thus, the proposition, the bird is
beautiful, is changed to, the bird is a beautiful animal.
When an abstract term or an attributive Jms come to
be regarded as a common noun, as virtue^ color ^ fig^^'^e,
the good^ etc., its distribution or non-distribution is reg-
ulated by the rules for common terms.
2d. Rules for the distribution and. non-distribution of the
terms of a proposition.
(1) The subject of every universal j)roposition is distrib-
uted. Thus, the subject is distributed in the following
propositions: Every man is liable to accident; All S is
P; No selfish action is praiseworthy; No S is P; Any
coward is contemptible. The distribution of the subject
is shown by one of the words, every., all^ no, any.
(312)
CA TEG ORICAL JUD GMENTS. 313
(2) The subject of every particular projjosition is undis-
tributed. Thus, the subject is undistributed in the fol-
lowing propositions: Some men are liars; Some Sis F;
Some men are not liars; Some S is not P. The non-
distribution of the subject is indicated by the word some.
It will b# observed that the distribution or non-distri-
bution of the subject depends upon the quantity of the
proposition — the subject is distributed in universals, and
undistributed in particulars.
(3) The predicate of every negative proposition is distrib-
uted. Thus, the predicate is distributed in the following
j)ropositions : ISTo horse is a ruminant; Some apples are
not red; No S is P; Some S is not P; for every indi-
vidual of the class ruminants is excluded from the class
horse; every red object, from the class some apples; and
every P, from S.
(4) The predicate of an affirmative is undistributed^ unless
the subject is co-extensive vjith the predicate^ or the p)redicate
is subordinate to the subject. Thus, the predicate is un-
distributed in the propositions, All horses are animals;
Some Americans are poets; All S is P; Some S is P;
for all animals are not horses; all poets are not Ameri-
cans; nor is it certain that all P is S.
It will be observed that the distribution or non-distri-
bution of the 23redicate depends on the quality of the
proposition — the predicate is distributed in negatives,
and is, in general, undistributed in affirmatives.
It may, indeed, be true, in fact, that the predicate of
an affirmative is distributed, as in case of co-extension
in (^) or (7), or when, in (Z), P is subordinate to S ;
but this is extra-logical, since it is not indicated by the
form^ with which alone logic has to deal. It is impor-
tant, however, to note that co-extension is found in case
of definitions, equations, identical propositions, and when
S and P designate, by different properties, the same
Psy.— 27.
314 PSYCHOLOGY,
class. ThuSj A decagon is a polygon often sides; J ==:
B ; A is A; All equilateral triangles are equiangular. P
is subordinate to S in (7)^ when S is the genus of which
P is a species, as some animals are horses.
HencCj the rules for distribution may be thus stated:
(1) All universals distribute their subject, •
(2) All negatives distribute their predicate,-
(3) No particular distributes its subject.
(4) An affirmative does not, in general, distribute its
predicate.
2. Conversion of propositions — definitions, rule, clas-
sification. — The conversion of a proposition is the trans-
position of its termSj or the interchange of the places of
the subject and predicate. Thus, the conversion of the
proposition, S is P, gives the proposition, P is S,
The convert end, or exposita, is the original poposition to
be converted.
The converse is the proposition obtained by conversion.
The general rule to be observed in conversion is the
following: A term must not be distributed in the converse
which is not distributed in the convertend.
Conversion is divided into immediate and mediate^ and
each of these into simple and by limitation, or per acci-
dens, as it is also called.
Conversion is immediate when the convertend is con-
verted, without preliminary change of form; that is, the
original proposition is itself converted.
1st. Immediate conversion is simple, when the converse
has the same quantity and quality as the convertend, and
is denoted by the same vowel.
(1) (E) always admits of immediate simple conversion.
{E) No 8 is P.
.-. \e) ]Sro P is S.
CATEGOBICAL JUDGMENTS,
315
P.
(2) (7) always admits of immediate simple conversion.
(J) Some S is
...(/) Some FiJ^'^^' ^^ ^^ ' '^'' ^ ' ^'
8.
(3) (A) arim?:?^5 of immediate simple conversion in case S
and P are co-extensive, as in definitions, etc., but not in
general.
(A) All S is P.
.-, (A) All P is S.
(4) (0) admits of immediate simple converse in case of
exclusion or intersection, but not in general.
(0) Some S
is not P.
.-, (0) Some P
is not aS.
It thus appears that (J5) and (J) universally admit
of immediate simple conversion; and (A) and (0) in
special cases — (J.) in case of co-extension, and (0) in
case of exclusion or intersection. To convert (JL) by im-
mediate simple conversion, in case 8 is subordinate to
P, is to distribute P in the converse when it is not dis-
tributed in the convertend, and thus to violate the gen-
eral rule, that a term is not to be distributed in the
converse which is not distributed in the convertend. In
like manner, to convert (0) by immediate simple con-
version, in case P is subordinate to 8, is to distribute
8 in the converse, when it is not distributed in the con-
vertend, and thus to violate the rule.
2d. Immediate conversion is by limitation, when the
316
PSYCHOLOGY,
quantity is reduced, the convertend being universal^ and
the converse particular.
(1) (A) always admits of immediate conversion by limi-
tation.
(A) All S is P.
.-. (Z) Some P is S,
(2) (i?) always admits of immediate conversion by limi-
tation.
{E) ISTo 8 is P.
.*. (0) Some P is
not >S.
(7) and (0) having already reduced quantity^ can not
be converted by limitation.
Conversion is mediate when the convertend is con-
verted through a preliminary change of form; that is,
the original proposition itself is not converted, but is
changed to another which is converted. Mediate con-
version, when applied to (J.), or (JS^) is called conversion
by contraposition, and when applied to (0), conversion
by negation.
3d. Mediate conversion is simple when the converse
has the same quantity and quality as the proposition
into which the original is changed, and hence is denoted
by the same vowel.
(1) {A) can always be changed to {E) which may be
converted simply.
{A ) All S is P.
=Ie) No S is non-P.
.\ {E ) No non-P is S.
(2) (J57), in case S and P are' contradictories, can be
CA TEG OEICA L JUD G ME NTS.
317
changed into co-extensive (A) or (/) either of which may
be converted simply.
{E)m s i^ p= \ (^) ^^^ ^ ^^" ^^^-^- ^
(.(/) Some S is non-F. [ s
.-. {A) All no/2-P is >?. (/) Some non-P is aS.
(3) (/) does not admit of mediate simple conversion.
(4) (0) can always be changed to (Z), which may be con-
verted simply.
(0) Some
S is not P.
= (/) Some
S is non-P.
.'. (7) Some
non-P is S.
Mediate conversion is by limitation^ when the quantity
is reduced, the original proposition and the proposition
into which the original is changed, being universal^ and
the converse particular.
(1) {A) cayi alicays be changed to (^), which may be con-
verted by limitation.
{A) All .9 is P.
= (^) ISTo /S is non-P.
.*. (0) Some non-P is not S.
(2) {E) can always be changed into {A), which may be
converted by limitation.
(E) No S is P.
= (A) All S is non-P.
.-. (/) Some non-P is S.
(3) (7) and (0), being particular, that is, already in re-
duced quantity, can not be converted by limitation.
CHAPTEE XII.
CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS.
Conditional Judgments are, as we have seen, of three
kinds — hypothetical, disjunctive, and dilemmatic.
1. Hypothetical judgments may be divided into five
groups, each containing four forms. Let the laws of
truth of each be exhibited by Euler's notation of circles,
thus:
If A is B, A is C,
True, if B is C.
1st. The subject of the condition is the subject of the con-
sequent.
(1) If A is B, A is a True, if B is C.
(2) If Ais B, A is not C. True, if B is not C.
(3) If A is not 5, A is C. True, if B and G are con-
tradictories.
(4) If A is not B, A is not C. True, if C is B.
2d. The subject of the condition is the predicate of the
consequent.
(1) If ^ is 5, is A, True, if C is B, and A is co-
extensive with B.
(2) If ^ is ^, is not A. True, if G is not B.
(3) If A is not B, G is A. True, if G is not B, and A
and B are contradictories.
(4) If A is not J?, G is not ^. True, if G is ^.
(318)
CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS. 319
3d. The ^predicate of the condition is the subject of the
consequent.
(1) If ^ is B^ B m C. True, if A m (7, and is co-ex-
tensive with B.
(2) If A is Bj B is not C. True, if A is not C, and is
co-extensive with B.
(3) If A is not B, B is C. True, if A and C are con-
tradictories.
(4) If A is not B, B is not C. True, if C is A.
4th. The predicate of the condition is the predicate of the
consequent.
(1) If Ais B, C is B. True, if C h A.
(2) If A h B, C is not B. True, if C is not A, and ^
is co-extensive with B.
(3) If A is not B, C is B. True, if (7 is not A, and J.
and B are contradictories.
(4) If A is not ^, (7 is not B. True, if C is A.
5th. T/i6 subjects and predicates are different in the an-
tecedent and. consequent.
(1) If A is J5, C is D. True, if C is A and B is D.
(2) If A IS B, C is not D. True, if C is J and B is
not J).
(3) If A is not J5, (7 is D. True, if A and 5 are con-
tradictories, and either A or B is in _D, and C is not in
the other.
(4) If A is not B, C is not D. True, if C is either A
or B, and D is the other.
2. Disjunctive judgments are those which present al-
ternatives. These alternatives are either unexclusive or
exclusive.
1st. Unexclusive alternatives are of two kinds:
(1) When the alternatives are simply different words
for the same thing. In this case, the judgment is dis-
junctive only in expression. Thus, this electricity is
vitreous, or positive.
320 PSYCHOLOGY,
(2) When the alternatives are different but congruent
tilings. Tims, this man is a knave or a fool; he may be
both. Augustine was a saint or a philosopher; he was
both.
2d. Exclusive alternatives have two forms, expressed,
(1) In the copula. Thus, >S either is or is not P. This
is equivalent to the proposition S is either P or non-P^
which, as pure contradictory opposition, is true by the
law of contradictories.
(2) In the terms, a. In the subject. Thus, either P or
>SisP
b. hi the predicate. S is either P or Q.
If R and 8 or P and Q are contradictories, we have
contradictory opposition, and the judgment is true by
the law of contradictories.
If P and S or P and Q are contraries, we have con-
trary opposition, and hence can not affirm the judgment
a priori^ but only a posteriori^ by showing that all other
contrary judgments are false. Then, the same inferences
follow as in contradictory opposition ; that is, one of the
alternatives is true; if either is true, the other is false;
if either is false, the other is true.
Such a proposition as angles are right or oblique is
divisive. It does not mean that all angles are right or
all angles are oblique; but that angles are divided into
right angles and oblique angles; that is, that some angles
are right and some oblique, or that any angle is either
right or oblique, which is disjunctive, not only in ex-
pression, but in thought, and the alternatives are contra-
dictories in the genus angles.
Alternatives may be contradictories within a limited
sphere, but only contraries if the sphere be extended.
Thus, Vertebrates and invertebrates are contradictories in
the sphere of animals; but only contraries in the sphere
of organic beings. Any animal is either a vertebrate or
CONDITIONAL JUDGMENTS. 321
an invertebrate, but it will not do to say that every
organic being, much less, that every thing, is either a
vertebrate or an invertebrate animal.
3. The dilemmatic judgments are divided into two
groups, each containing four forms. Let the law of truth
be given for each and illustrated with circles, according
to Euler's notation.
1st. When the condition is simple,
(1) If A is B, S is either P or Q.
(2) If A m B, S is neither P nor Q.
(3) If A is not B, S is either P or Q.
(4) If A is not B, S is neither P nor Q.
2d. When the condition is compound.
(1) If either A m B or C is D, >S is either P or Q.
(2) If either A i^ B or C is D, S is neither P nor Q.
(3) If neither A is B nor C is D, S is either P or Q.
(4) If neither A is B nor C is P, S is neither P nor Q.
The disjunctive consequent is in contrary opposition;
for if in contradictory opposition, then, in either group,
the consequents of (1) and (3) would be true and the
consequents of (2) and (4) would be false by the law
of contradictories, and the reason in the conditional
clause woald be redundant. Thus, it would be super-
fluous to say, if A is B, S is either P or non-P, for J3
is either P or non-P, whether A is B or not.
CHAPTEE XIII.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
Reasoning is the process by which the truth or falsity
of a proposition is proved.
An argument is the derivation of a judgment from
another judgment or from other judgments. It infers,
in the final proposition, what was virtually contained in
the preceding.
An immediate argument is an argument in which the
relation of the terms of the derived proposition is inferred
from another proposition, or from other propositions, with-
out the intervention of a middle term.
The varieties of immediate arguments are the follow-
ing:
1st. Inferences from the relation of the four propositions^
{A), (E), (Z), (0). See Chapter X.
(1) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of
the proposition, (A), All S is P? from the falsity of (A)f
(2) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of
the proposition (^), :N'o ^ is Pf from the falsity of (E)? ^
(3) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of
the proposition (J), Some S is Pf from the falsity of
(I)f
(4) What inferences can be drawn from the truth of
the proposition (0), Some S is not P? from the falsity
of(0).^
2d. Inferences from the conversion of the propositions, (A),
(E) (/), (0). See Chapter XI.
(1) What inferences from conversion can be drawn
(322)
I MM EDI A TE ARG VMENTS, 323
from the proj)osition {A)^ in case of co-extension? in
case of subordination? What from the 2)roposition, Pen-
tagons are polygons of five sides? What from the prop-
osition, Pentagons are polygons?
(2) What inferences from conversion can be drawn
from the proposition (^).^ What from the proposition,
No knowledge is useless?
(3) What inferences from conversion can be drawn
from the proposition (/).^ What from the proposition,
Some men are liars?
(4) What inferences from conversion can be drawn
from the proposition (0),^ What from the proj)osition,
Some men are not liars?
(5) State the contrary, the subaltern, and the contra-
dictory of the proposition. All criminals deserve punish-
ment.
(6) Classify the proposition. All just acts are expedi-
ent. What inferences can be drawn from it, by means
of relation? What b}^ means of conversion? Classify
and convert these inferences.
(7) State and classify the propositions incompatible
with the proposition. All liars are detestable. Convert
each.
3d. Inferences from model restriction. The necessary, im-
plies the actual; the actual, the probable; the probable,
the possible. What inferences can be drawn from the
proposition. Space is necessarily infinite?
4th. Inferences from composition. Thus, A is in C ; B
is in C ; therefore, A and B are in C.
' 5th. Inferences from divisive judgments. Thus, S is P,
Q, or R ; therefore, the P of S is neither the Q nor the
P of S; the non-P of S is either the Q or the R of S;
the neither P nor Q of aS is the R of S.
Gth. Inferences by means of privatives.
(1) All S is P; therefore, ISTo S is non-P, and all
324 PSYCHOLOGY,
non-P iis non-S. Also, from the proposition. All non-S is
no7i-Pj we infer, T^o non-S is P, and all P is /S.
(2) Infer, by means of privatives, the conclusion from
the proposition, JSTo /S is P; from, No non-8 is non-P.
(3) What inference, by means of privatives, can be
drawn from the proposition, Some >S is Pf From, Some
non-S is non-Pf
(4) What inference, by means of privatives, can be
drawn from the proposition, Some S is not Pf From,
Some non-S is not non-Pf
7th. Inferences by means of determinants. This class of
inferences consists in joining the same modifier to both
subject and j)redicate. Thus, An Indian is a fellow creat-
ure; therefore, A happy Indian is a happy fellow creat-
ure. Inferences of this kind are often fallacious. Thus,
A president is a man ; therefore. An incompetent presi-
dent is an incompetent man. A dwarf is a man ; there-
fore, A big dwarf is a big man- The inference is valid
in case of co-extension, or when the modifier does not
afiect the characteristics of the subject.
8th. Inferences by means of complex conceptions. This
class is clearly allied to the last. Thus, Metals are ele-
ments; therefore, A mixture of metals is a mixture of
elements. Inferences of this kind are often fallacious.
Thus, Americans are human beings; therefore, A major-
ity of Americans is a majority of human beings.
CHAPTER XIV.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
A mediate argument is an argument in which the re-
lation of the terms of the derived proposition is inferred
from other propositions through the intervention of a
middle term.
The derived proposition is called the conclusion. The
propositions from which the conclusion is inferred are
called the premises.
A syllogism is an argument in regular form.
f All M is P.
Thus, \ All S is M.
.'. All S is P.
A syllogism contains three terms : two extremes — -the
major term and the minor term — and the middle term.
The major term, P, is the predicate of the conclusion ;
the minor term, S, is the subject of the conclusion ; and
the middle term, M, is the medium of comparison.
A syllogism contains three propositions: two premises
— the major premise and the minor premise — and the
conclusion.
The major premise is the premise which expresses the
relation of the middle term, M, to the major term, P.
The minor premise is the premise which expresses the
relation of the minor term, S, to the middle term, M.
The conclusion is the proposition which expresses the
(325)
326 PSYCHOLOGY.
relation of the minor term to the major, as inferred from
the premises.
As an illustration of an argument, take the following :
All responsible agents are free agents.
Man is a responsible agent.
.-. Man is a free a^ent.
Man and a free agent, the subject and the predicate of
the conclusion, are the extremes, — a free agent, the pred-
icate, is the major term, and man, the subject, is the
minor. The term, resj^onsible agents, with which the
extremes are separately compared in the premises, is the
middle term, and is in both premises, but not in the
conclusion.
All responsible agents are free agents, the premise
which expresses the relation of the middle term to the
major term, is the major premise Man is a resj^onsible
agent, the premise which expres.Hes the relation of the
minor term to the middle, is the minor jDremise.
In extensive quantity^ the class res23onsible agents is
subordinate to the class free agents; the class man is sub-
ordinate to the class responsible agents; hence the class
man is subordinate to the class free agents, according to
the principle, a subordinate to a class is subordinate to
any genus embracing that class, or, as it may be stated,
a part of a part is a part of the whole.
In comprehensive quantity^ the class responsible agents
comprehends free agency as an element of resj)onsibility;
the class man comprehends responsibility as one of its
attributes; hence, the class man comprehends free agency
as an attribute, on the principle that the whole compre-
hends a part of a part.
It is to be observed that the term ccreatest in exten-
sion is least in comprehension; and that the term least
in extension is greatest in comprehension.
MEDIA TE AE G UMENTS. 327
The names, major and minor terms, are significant
only in extensive quantity; but even in this quantity,
the major term, as a matter of fact, as we shall hereafter
see, is frequently less in extension than the minor term.
These names are, therefore, to be regarded as mere
technical expressions, the major term denoting the 2:>red-
icate of the conclusion, and the minor, the subject.
The expressions, major and minor premises, are also
to be regarded as technical expressions, the major 2:)rem-
ise being the premise containing the major term, and
the minor premise the premise containing the minor
term.
The order of the premises is not essential, though the
major premise generally stands first. The conclusion
may even stand before the premises.
The function of an argument is to prove that a certain
relation exists between two terms, when that relation is
not self-evident.
In mediate arguments, this is accomplished by select-
ing, as the medium of comparison, a third term, called
the middle term, with which the other terms are sepa-
rately compared. The • relations of the extreme terms
to the middle term prove the relation of the extremes
to each other.
The conclusion must not only be compatible with the
premises, but must be necessitated by them, otherwise
the argument is a fallacy.
This is shown in the following argument and illustra-
tions. The conclusion may be accidentally true, as
shown in the first set of circles, but it is not necessi-
tated by the premises, as shown by the second set.
'^o M is P.
No S is M,
..-. No S is P.
328 PSYCHOL OGY.
The same relations may have different expressions:
]^o 3f is P. /^7C\ /^~^ ^o P is M.
All >S is .¥. ( ® i ( -^ ) All S is i¥.
.-.JSTo /? is P. V_^ V_y .-.ISro S is P.
These arguments are identical in thought, as is seen
by the circles, with an accidental difference of expression.
Does the syllogism beg the question? It has been as-
serted, by John Stuart Mill and others, that the syllo-
gism involves the fallacy called petitio principii, the beg-
ging of the question. This charge is made, not in the
sense that in all valid syllogisms the premises virtually
assert the conclusion, — for this they must do, otherwise
the argument is a fallacy, — but, in the sense that the
conclusion, so far from being deduced from the premises,
must be known to be true before the major premise can
be established; but as the conclusion is not known to
be true, the very thing to be proved is begged in the
major premise, thus:
All men are mortal.
Gabriel is a man.
.-. Gabriel is mortal.
Mill says : '' That we can not be assured of the mortal-
ity of all men, unless we were previously certain of the
mortality of every individual man; that if it be still
doubtful whether Socrates, or any other individual you
choose to name, be mortal or not, the same degree of
uncertainty must hang over the assertion, All men are
mortal."
The warrant for the major premise, All men are mor-
tal, is not found in the fact that Gabriel is mortal; for
we may be totally ignorant even of the existence of
Gabriel. Much less is the major premise a case of so-
MEDIATE AEGmiENTS, 329
called perfect induction, established by an examination
of every individual man, which is impossible in the nat-
ure of the case; and, yet, after examining a multitude of
cases, we are warranted in asserting that all men are
mortal, as an induction of a very high degree of prob-
ability.
Neither is the warrant for the conclusion, Gabriel is
moi'tal, found only in the inajor premise, All men are
mortal; for Gabriel may be an angel. We must also
know that Gabriel is a man. Then, without begging the
question, the conclusion, Gabriel is mortal, follows logi-
cally from the premises, but with no higher probability
than the major 2:)remise.
The syllogism is based on classification ; and classifica-
tion, on the law of Eeasoii and Consequent. An examin-
ation of a great number of individuals of the human
race reveals sufficient reason for concluding that, in the
present condition of man, mortality is the law, or gen-
eral fact, of humanity.
Again, suj)pose I find a plant of a class v^hich I have
never before seen, and am desirous of knowing the char-
acter of its fruit, if indeed it bear fruit, not at present
having any. I examine the plant according to the meth-
ods of botany, and find it to belong to a certain class.
Heading a further description of the class, I find the
character of the fruit which plants of this kind bear. I
then reason thus:
Plants of this class bear a certain kind of fruit.
This plant belongs to this class.
.-.This i^lant bears this kind of fruit.
This process is legitimate, and the conclusion is an im-
portant extension of my knowledge.
But how do botanists know that plants of this kind
bear such fruit? Surely not because they have seen
Psy.— 28.
330 PSYCHOLOGY,
this plant bear such fruit; but because they have seen a
great many specimens of this kind of plants bear such
fruit, and have found no exceptions; that is, they have
found no plants of this kind bearing a different species
of fruit.
Again, suppose we wish to know how many diago-
nals can be drawn in a chiliagon, a polygon of a thousand
sides. It would not be practicable to draw all the diag-
onals and then count them; for they are too numerous;
but the proper thing to do is to find a general formula
for the number of diagonals that can be drawn in a
polygon of n sides. This formula is not found by in-
duction, that is, by finding the number of diagonals
that can be drawn in polygons of four, fiYe, six, etc.,
sides; bat by reasoning thus:
Since the polygon has n sides, it has n vertices. Now,
from any vertex, a diagonal can be drawn to any ver-
tex except itself and the two adjacent vertices; hence,
from each vertex, n-3 diagonals can be drawn, and
therefore from the n vertices, n times n-3, or n (n-3)
diagonals can be drawn ; but in this w^ay, each diagonal
is counted twice; hence the number of diagonals is
I n (n-3.) •
This formula has been established without any refer-
ence to the chiliagon. Now, we reason thus : The num-
ber of diagonals that can be drawn in a polygon of n
sides is Jn(n-3), whatever be the value of n; but, in a
chiliagon, n := 1000; hence, the number of diagonals that
can be drawn in a chiliagon is 500x997 = 498500.
Where is there even a shadow of petitio principu here?
Again, suppose I stand on the lake shore and see a
vessel sink w4th all on board. Now, need I know that
John Jones was drowned to know that all on board
were drowned? I may not even know that John Jones
was aboard. The next da}^, however, I learn from wit-
MEDIA TE AEG UMENTS, 331
nesses who saw the vessel leave a neighboring port that
John Jones was aboard. Then I reason thus:
All on board a certain vessel at a certain time were
drowned.
John Jones was on board that vessel at that time.
.-. John Jones was drowned.
There is no begging of the question here, since I
knew the truth of the major premise before knowing
the truth of the conclusion. The minor premise is as
essential to the truth of the conclusion as the major;
but if the tw^o j^remises be admitted, the conclusion can
not logically be denied.
An enthymeme is an argument w^ith one proposition,
either of the premises or the conclusion, suppressed, thus:
All men are mortal. .*. You are mortal.
You are a man. .-. You are mortal.
All men are mortal. You are a man.
Such reasonings are common. The last form is im-
pressive, as it leaves the hearer to draw his own con-
clusion.
CHAPTER XV.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
Categorical syllogisms are those in which the propo-
sitions — the two premises and the conclusion — are cate-
gorical. They are simple or compound.
1. Simple categorical syllogisms are those which con-
tain only three terms and three propositions. The three
terms are the two extremes — the major term, or the
predicate of the conclusion ; and the minor term, or the
subject of the conclusion; and the middle term, or the
medium of comparison. The three propositions are the
two premises — the major premise, or the premise con-
taining the major term and the middle term; and the
minor premise containing the minor term and the mid-
dle term; and the conclusion containing the major term
and the minor term.
Laws warranting the conclusions, (J.), {E^^ (7), (0).
1st. The universal affirmative conclusion (^) is warranted^
if all the middle term is contained in the major, and all the
minor in the middle.
This general principle holds whether the relations ex-
pressed be those of subordination or co-extension, as
thus shown:
All M is P.
All S is M.
.-. All S is P.
2d. The universal negative conclusion (E) is ivarranted,
(332)
CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS. 333
if all of either extreme is contained in the middle and all
of the other is excluded from the middle.
This general principle holds whether the relation in
the affirmative premise be one of subordination or co-
extension, and whether the terms in the negative prem-
ise are contraries or contradictoi^ies. Illustrate by circles.
All P is M. No P is M.
ISTo S is M. All S is M,
.-.No S is P. .-.No S is P.
3d. The jyarticular affirmative conclusion (7) is warranted,
if all the middle is contained in both extremes, or if all the
middle is contained in either extreme, and a part of the mid-
dle in the other.
In both cases, the same thing — either all or the same
part of the middle — is contained in both extremes ; hence,
the extremes must, in part at least, coincide with each
other, or a particular affirmative conclusion, at least, is
warranted.
These princij)les hold, whether the relations in the
universal premises be those of subordination or co-exten-
sion, or the relation in the particular premise be that
of co-extension, or intersection, or subordination, which-
ever term be subordinate to the other. Illustrate:
All M is P All M is P. Some M is P.
All M is S. Some M is S. All M is S.
.'. Some S is P. .*. Some S is P. .-. Some S is P.
If both premises be particular, that is, if some of the
middle is contained in the major term, and some in the
minor, it will not be known that it is the same some ;
the same thing, then, will not be known to be in both
extremes, and there will be no w^arrant for the conclu-
sion. The argument will then be a fallacy, thus:
334 PSYCHOL OGY,
So mo 21 is P.
Some ilf is S.
.'. Some S is P.
If. however, a part of the middle is contained in one
extreme, and more tlian the complementary part in the
other, the same thing — a part of the middle — is con-
tained in each extreme, and the argument is valid,, thus:
Two thirds of M is P.
More than one third of M is S. '
.'. Some S is P.
If, at a certain election, a majority of the electors
voted for A, and a majority voted for 5, then some
who voted for A, voted for B.
4th'. The particular negative conclusion (0) is warranted
if all the major term is excluded from the middle, and some
of the minor is contained in the middle; or, if all the major is
contained in the middle, and some of the minor is excluded
from the middle; or, if all the middle is contained in the
minor, and some of the middle is excluded from the major.
These principles hold for all possible relations of the
terms in the premises, and in each case some of the
minor, at least, will be excluded from the major. Illus-
trate :
No P is M. All P is M. Some M is not P.
Some S is M. Some S is not M. All M is S.
.'. Some S IS not P. .-. Some S is not P. .'. Some S is not P.
2. A compound syllogism is a combination of simple
syllogisms. There are several varieties.
1st. The compound syllogism, composed of a prosyllo-
gism and an episyllogism — the conclusion of the prosyl-
logism being one of the premises of the episyllogism,
thus :
CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISM. 335
r All B is A.
Prosyllogism } All C \^ B.
(..-.AH (7 is ^. -)
All D is (7. > Episyllogism.
.-. All D is A. )
2d. An epichirema is a syllogism in which the reasons
for the premises are stated in connection with them,
thus:
(1) All true patriots are friends to religion, because
religion is the basis of national prosperity. Some great
statesmen are not friends to religion, because their lives
are not in accordance with its precej)ts. Therefore, some
great statesmen are not true patriots.
!A is B, for A h C and C is B.
D is A, for D is LJ and E is A.
..D'mB.
3d. The sorites^ or chain syllogism, is a compound ar-
gument which may be indefinitely extended. There are
several varieties which may be illustrated by circles.
(1) When the predicate of each premise is the subject
of the next.
r All A is B. ( All A \s B.
All B is 0. ^^ ,. I All B is a
'^^^^ 1 Ml n ' T^ Negative < at ^ • ,
j All (7 IS D. ^ j No (7 IS If.
I -.All A is D. I -.No A is n.
(2) When the subject of each premise is the predicate
of the next.
f
All B is A.
All C is B.
No B is A.
All C is ^.
Atnrmative -< , ,, -r^ - ^ Negative^ . n t^ . /^
All D IS (7. ^ AH i) IS C.
I .-.All D is A I .-.No i) is A
336
PSYCHOLOGY,
(3) When the first and second varieties are combined.
Negative <
All A is B,
All B is C,
No G is D,
All E is D.
All F is JS'.
All G^ is F.
.-. No ^ is G.
Negative <
V
All A is 5.
All B is (;
All (7 is D.
No i; is D,
All i^^ is ^.
All G is i^.
.*. No A is ff.
The laws of the sorites are the following:
(1) Only one premise can be particular — the first in
the first variety, the last in the second j and the first or
last in the third — and the subject of the particular prem-
ise is the subject of the conclusion.
(2) Only one premise can be negative — the last in
the first variety, or the first in the second variety.
(3) In the third variety, one premise must be negative
— the last in the first series, or the first in the second
series.
The expansion of the sorites is thus effected,
trate by circles.
lllus-
(1) ^
' All A is B,
All B is G
^
All C is B.
.: All A is D.
V
All A is 5.
All B is G.
.-. All A is G.
All G is D.
All A is G.
.-. All A is D.
It will be observed that the minor premise stands
first in the first simple syllogism, and the major in the
second.
This order might, in either or both cases, have been
reversed; hence, the order of the premises is not essen-
tial.
CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS, 337
(2) Expand each of the examples above given to il-
lustrate the varieties.
(3) Expand the following concrete example:
The mind is a thinking substance.
A thinking substance is a spirit.
A spirit has no composition of parts.
That which has no composition of parts is indissoluble.
That w^hich is indissoluble is immortal.
Therefore, the mind is immortal.
Psy.-^29.
CHAPTEE XVI.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
Conditional Syllogisms are divided into three classes
— Hypothetical, Disjunctive, and Dilemmatic.
1, The hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism having
an hypothetical major premise and a categorical minor.
Its form is, therefore, determined by the law of Reason
and Consequent.
The hypothetical syllogism is said to be constructive,
or modus ponens, the mood which posits or affirms, when
the minor premise affirms the condition, and the conclu-
sion the consequent, — and destructive, or modus tollens,
the mood which removes or denies, when the minor
premise denies the consequent, and the conclusion the
condition. .
The rule to be observed is that the antecedent condi-
tion is to be affirmed in the minor premise and the
consequent in the conclusion, or the consequent is to be
denied in the minor premise and the condition in the
conclusion. The following are illustrations:
r If ^ has the fever, he is sick.
Constructive I But A has the fever.
C Therefore, A is sick.
!If A has the fever, he is sick.
But A is not sick.
Therefore, A has not the fever.
If the rule be violated, by either denying the antece-
(338)
CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS, , 339
dent in the minor premise or affirming the consequent,
nothing follows, thus:
If A has the fever, he is sick.
But A has not the fever.
It does not follow that A is not sick; for he may have
some other disease, and hence be sick. It would, how-
ever, follow that A is not sick, if fever were co-extensive
with sickness.
If A has the fever, he is sick.
But A is sick.
It does not follow that A has the fever; for his sick-
ness may be the result of some other disease. It would,
however, follow that A has the fever, if fever were co-
extensive with sickness.
The analysis of the hypothetical syllogism, therefore,
gives the following results:
1st. The major premise is an hypothetical proposition,
enouncing the dependency between a conditioning ante-
cedent and a conditioned consequent, but affirming noth-
ing in regard to the actual existence of either.
2d. The minor premise is a categorical proposition,
either affirming the conditioning antecedent or denying
the conditioned consequent.
3d. The conclusion is a categorical proposition, affirm-
ing the consequent, if the antecedent is affirmed in the
minor premise, or denying the antecedent if the conse-
quent is denied in the minor premise.
4th. There is no conclusion, when either the anteced-
ent is denied in the minor premise, or the consequent is
affirmed, unless the predicate of the antecedent is co-
extensive with the predicate of the consequent.
The reduction of hypothetical syllogisms to categorical
340
PSYCHOL OOY,
is effected by substituting for the major premise the
condition of its truth, as determined in Chapter XII.
Thus, the condition of the truth of the proposition, If A
is B^ A is (7, is the proposition, B is C. Hence the
reduction :
r If A is B, A is a
Constructive I But A is B,
(..-. A is G.
r B is a
= \ A i& B,
.'. A is C.
Illustrate the above by circles, also the following:
Destructive
r If A is B, A is C.
} But A is not C.
L .'. A is not B,
B is a
A is not G,
.-. A is not B.
Clf A is B, G is JD.
Constructive -j But A is B,
(-.•. (7 is D.
A is jB.
G is ^.
.-. C is B.
B is B.
^} G is B.
.'. G is D.
rlf^is^, (7isi).
Destructive < But (7 is not D.
L.-. J- is not J5.
r
= <
B is D.
G is not Z).
.-. G is not jS.
(7 is A.
G is not J5.
.-. Some A is not B.
The last constructive syllogism may be thus reduced
The case of A being B, is the case of G being D.
The present case is the case of J^ being B.
.*. The present case is the case of C being 7).
CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS. 341
Construct hypothetical syllogisms having for major
premises the hypothetical propositions of Chapter XII.
Eeduce them to categorical by employing the conditions
of their truth as premises.
2. The disjunctive syllogism is a syllogism having a
disjunctive major premise, and a minor premise in which
the number of alternatives is reduced.
1st When there are only two alternatives. In this case,
the form is determined by the law of contradictories.
There are two moods: — -the affirmative, or modus po-
nendo tollens, the mood which by affirming denies, when
the minor premise affirms one of the alternatives, and
the conclusion denies the other, — and the negative, or
modus tollendo ponens, the mood which, by denying, af-
firms, when the minor premise denies one of the al-
ternatives, and the conclusion affirms the other:
The following is the modus ponendo tollens:
A is either B or C.
But A is B.
.-. A is not C. '^
The modus ponendo tollens proceeds on the supposition
that there is opposition, contradictory or contrary, be-
tween the alternatives. If the opposition is contradictory,
the major premise is known, a priori, to be valid; but if
the opposition is contrary, the truth of the major prem-
ise is determined a posteriori. In either case, if one al-
ternative is affirmed, the other must be denied.
If there is no opposition between the alternatives, the
affirmation of one does not involve the denial of the
other. Thus, if we say : "A good book is valued either
for the usefulness of its contents or the excellence of its
style," it does not follow that if valued for the useful-
ness of its contents, it is not valued for the excellence
342 PSYCHOLOGY,
of its style. These alternatives are not in opposition,
and the book may be valued both for the usefulness of
its contents and for the excellence of its style.
The alternatives are always diverse, but may be either
congruents or conflictives, which are the two species
embraced by the genus diverse things.
The following is the modus toUendo ponens:
A is either B or (7,
But A is not B,
• r,A is a
The book is valued either for the usefulness of its
contents or the excellence of its style. But it is not
valued for the usefulness of its contents; therefore, it
is valued for the excellence of its style. This will be a
true conclusion, if the major premise be true, whether
there is opposition between the alternatives or not.
The analysis of the disjunctive syllogism in the case
considered, therefore, gives the following results:
(1) The major premise is a disjunctive proposition ex-
pressing two alternatives.
(2) The minor premise is a categorical proposition af-
firming or denying one alternative.
(3) The conclusion is a categorical proposition deny-
ing one alternative, if the minor premise affirms the
other, and if the alternatives are conflictives, or affirm-
ing one alternative, if the minor premise denies the other,
whether the alternatives are congruents or conflictives.
(4) If the alternatives are not conflictives, the modus
ponendo tolleiis fails, but the modus tollendo ponens is still
valid.
2d. When there are more than two alternatives. In this
case the minor premise may be either categorical or
disjunctive, thus:
CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS.
343
r
Affirmative ^
( A is either J5, C\ D, or ^.
] But A is 5.
L.-.A is neither C, J), nor U.
iui is either B, C, D, or ^\
But J is either B or C.
.-.A is neither D nor LJ.
Negative -^
A is either B, C, D, or K
But J. is neither B, C, nor -D.
.-. A is ^.
A is either B, C, D, or U.
But J. is neither B nor (7.
.-.J. is either D or ^.
The laws aj^plying to more than three conflictive al-
ternatives are the following:
(1) Affirming a j^art of the disjunctives, determinately
or indeterminately, in the minor premise, denies all the
others in the conclusion if the alternatives are conflict-
ives, but not if the alternatives are congruents.
(2) Denying a part of the alternatives in the minor
premise, affirms the rest, in conclusion, determinately or
indeterminately, according as one or more remain, whether
the alternatives are conflictives or congruents.
If the minor premise neither affirms nor denies an al-
ternative, but affirms something to be contained in the
subject, the conclusion is disjunctive, thus:
•
B is either C or D.
Ah B.
.'.A is either C or D.
This syllogism is, in thought, categorical.
3. The diiemmatic syllogism is a syllogism having
an hypothetical major premise and a disjunctive minor.
344
PSYCHOLOGY,
There are at least four forms, as follows:
1st. The simple constructive dilemma. The major prem-
ise has different antecedents and the same consequent;
the minor j)remise disjunctively affirms the antecedents;
and the conclusion affirms the consequent, thus:
If A is B. X is Y.
cA\^B,
it A IS a, Ji \^ l.~\ CA IS i/, ^
If (7 is i), Jr is y. [ But either] or (7 is D, [ .-. X is T.
If E is F, X is Y. J (or ^ is i^. 3
If the minor premise had been, X is not F, the con-
clusion would have been, A is not ^, G is not D, and E
is not F, This is virtually a destructive hyj)othetical
syllogism, but is not strictl^^ dilemmatic, since the minor
premise is not a disjunctive proposition.
2d. The simple destructive dMemma. The major prem-
ise has the same antecedent and different consequents;
the minor premise disjunctively denies the consequents;
and the conclusion denies the antecedent, thus:
If A is -S, (7is Z). ^ r G is not D, ^
If A is B, E is F. V But either \ or ^ is not F^ V .\ A is not B,
If^isi?, G^isJyJ (.orG^isnotll.J
If the minor premise had been A is B^ the conclusion
would have been, (7 is D^ E is i^, and G is H^ which is
virtually a constructive hypothetical syllogism but not
dilemmatic.
3d. The comj)lex constructive dilemma. The major prem-
ise has different antecedents and different consequents;
the minor premise disjunctively affirms the antecedents;
and the conclusion disjunctively affirms the consequents,
thus :
If A is 5, G is H. \
If G is B,J is K. [But either
If E is F. E \s M.)
A is B,
or G is D,
or E is F,
. Either G is //, J is K. or X is M.
CONDITIONAL SYLL O GISMS. 345
4th. The complex destructive dilemma. The major prem-
ise has different antecedents and different consequents;
the minor premise disjunctively denies the consequents;
and the conclusion disjunctively denies the antecedents,
thus:
If A is B, am H.\ rG is not H,
If is D, J is X. y But either ^ or J" is not K,
If E is F, L is M. ) ( or X is not M.
.-.Either A is not J5, is not D, or E is not F.
To which class does the following dilemma belong?
If a science furnishes useful facts, it is worthy of cul-
tivation ; if the study of it exercises the reasoning pow-
ers, it is worthy of cultivation; but a science either fur-
nishes useful facts, or its study exercises the reasoning
powers; therefore, it is worthy of cultivation.
4. The reductio ad absurdum is an indirect argument
which, by employing some form of the conditional syl-
logism, proves a proposition to be true by showing that
the supposition that it is false involves an absurdity.
It is based on the harmony of truth.
There are two cases of the reductio ad absurdum:
1st. When only two relations are possible — one ex-
pressed by the given proposition, and the other by its
contradictory.
In this case, either the given proposition or its con-
tradictory is true. The given proposition is proved
true by assuming that it is false, or, which is virtually
the same, that its contradictory is true. We then rea-
son on this assumed proposition till we reach a conclu-
sion conflicting with a known truth, and hence absurd.
Therefore, the assumed proposition, which led to this
absurdity, is false, and if false, its contradictory, or the
given proposition, is true, and is hence demonstrated.
346 PSYCHOLOGY.
Thus, of two unequal quantitieSj a and 6, we can prove
that ay>h^ if we can show that the supposition, aKb,
involves an absurdity.
2d. When more than two relations are possible — one
expressed by the given proposition, and the others by
its contraries. In this case, the given proposition, or
some one of its contraries, is true. The given proposi-
tion is proved true, by assuming that it is false, or, which
is virtually the same, that some one of the contraries is
true. We then show that each of these contraries is
false, because involving an absurdity; but the falsity of
all the contraries implies the truth of the given propo-
sition, which is, therefore, demonstrated. Thus, we can
prove that a = ^, if we can show that each of the sup-
positions, a > 6 and a < ^, involves an absurdity.
In dealing with the second case, care must be taken
that all possible contraries are considered. If a possible
contrary is omitted, the conclusion is vitiated.
As an example of this method, prove that the side
opposite the greater of two unequal angles of a triangle is
greater than the side opposite the less, — having first proved
that the angles opposite the equal sides of an isosceles tri-
angle are equal, and that the ayigle opposite the greater of
two unequal sides of a triangle is greater than the angle
opposite the less.
CHAPTEE XVII.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING,
A formal fallacy is a fallacy which, in its form, vio-
lates some law of thought. It is also called a paralogism^
or a fallacy in dictione or in voce.
1. Classification and Illustrations. — There are several
varieties.
1st. A paradox^ or violation of a fundamental law of
thought. It is self-contradictory, and, when explicitly
stated, is at once detected. Thus, A is non-A. A part
is greater than the whole, etc.
2d. Fallacies in immediate inferences. The varieties are :
(1) Fallacies in the relation of the propositions, (J.), (F),
(J), (0). Thus, inferring from the falsity of either (J.)
or (^),the truth of the other; from the truth of either
(7) or (0), the falsity of the other; from the falsity of
(J.), the falsity of (I) ; from the truth of (7), the truth
of (A) ; from the falsity of (JS"), the falsity of (0); from
the truth of (0), the truth of (^).
(2) Fallacies in conversion. Thus, All S is P; .-.All
P is S. All seeds come from plants; .*. All plants come
from seeds. Some S is not P; Some P is not S. Some
animals are not horses; .-.Some horses are not animals.
(3) Fallacies in extending modal restriction. Thus, ;S' is
possibly P; .-. S is probably P. S is probably P; .-. S
is actually P. aS^ is actually P; .-. S is necessarily P.
(4) Fallacies from composition. Thus, A and B are C ;
.'.A is C. In numbers, this fallacy is apparent, as 3
and 2 are 5; .-. 3 is 5.
( 347 )
348 PSYCHOL OGY.
(5) Fallacies from determinants. Thii8j a pony is a
horse; .-.A big pony is a big horse.
3d. Fallacies in mediate inferences. There are several
varieties :
(1) Undistributed middle. This fallacy consists in com-
paring each of the extremes with a part of the middlCy
and, as it is not certain that it is the same part, the
extremes are not known to be compared with the same
thing, and hence there is no warrant for inferring their
relations to each other. It will suffice, however, if the
middle term be distributed in one of the premises.
Let it be remembered that a term is distributed, if it
is either the subject of a universal proposition or the
predicate of a negative; and that a term is to bo re-
garded as undistributed, if it is either the subject of a
particular proposition or the predicate of an affirmative.
In a valid argument, the conclusion is not only com-
patible with the premises, but is necessitated by them,
otherwise the argument is a fallacy.
Take an argument with an undistributed middle:
All P is Jf.
All S is M.
.'. All S is P.
The middle term is undistributed, since in each term
it is the predicate of an affirmative. The conclusion
does not necessarily follow from the premises, as seen
from the first diagram; but it may be accidentally true,
as seen from the second, yet the argument is no less a
fallacy, since the conclusion is not necessitated.
If the relation in the major premise is known to be
that of co-extension, in which case the conclusion is
true, the argument can be relieved from the appearance
FORMAL FALLACIES. 349
of fallacy by converting the major premise, as is ad-
missible in case of co-extension, thus:
All M is P.
All S is M,
.'. All S is P.
What is the fallacy in the following argument?
Every country under a tyranny is distressed.
This country is distressed.
.-. This country is under a tyranny.
(2) Illicit process. This fallacy consists in distributing
either the major or minor term in the conclusion, when
it is not distributed in its premise. Take the following
argument :
All M \^ P P is distributed in the conclusion, since
No S is M. it is the predicate of a negative, but is
.-. No S is P. undistributed in the major premise, since
it is the predicate of an affirmative;
hence, we have an illicit process of the major term.
Show the fallacy by circles. Take also the following:
All M \^ P. S is distributed in the conclusion, since
All M is S. it is the subject of a universal, but it is
.*. All S is P. undistributed in the minor premise, since
it is the predicate of an affirmative;
hence, we have an illicit process of the minor term.
Show the fallacy by circles.
(3) Farticular premises. This name aids in detecting
certain fallacies, since we know at once that there is a
fallacy, when each of the premises begins with the word
some; but this case is not another class of fallacies, since,
it involves either the undistributed middle, or an illicit
350 PSYCHOLOGY,
process. Show this in the following, and illustrate by
circles:
Some P is M, Some M is P.
Some /S is ilf. • Some 8 is not M.
.'. Some S is P. .*. Some S is not P.
(3) A universal conclusion and one particular premise.
This involves either an undistributed middle or an illicit
process. Show this in the following, and illustrate by
circles:
Some M is P. All M is P.
All S is M. Some S is not M.
.', All S is P. .-. Some aS is not P.
Some Jf is not P. Some ilf is not P.
All If is 8. . All >S is M.
.-.No >S is P. .-.ISro aS is P.
(5) Negative premises. In this case, no conclusion is
warranted; for the denial of certain relations between
the middle term and the extremes, warrants neither the
affirmation nor denial of any relation between the ex-
tremes. Thus, show the fallacy of the following b}^ cir-
cles:
No P is M. Some M is not P.
No 8 is M. No 8 is M.
.'. No 8 is P. .*. Some 8 is not P.
(6) ^n affirmative conclusion and one negative premise.
The affirmative premise expresses the agreement, in
whole or in part, of one of the extremes with the mid-
dle; and the negative premise, the disagreement of the
other extreme with the middle; hence, if any relation of
the extremes follows, it is that of disagreement, or the
FORMAL FALLACIES, 351
conclusion is negative. Show the fallacy of the follow-
ing by circles:
No M is P. No M is P.
All 8 is M, . Some >9 is M.
.-. All >S is P. .-. Some 8 is P.
(7) A negative conclusion from affirmative premises. Both
extremes agree in whole or in part with the middle,
and hence if any relation is warranted, the extremes
must agree with each other, or the conclusion is affirm-
ative.
Show the fallacy of the following by circles :
All ilf" is P. All M is P.
All 8 is M. Some 8 is M.
.-.No 8 is P. .-. Some 8 is not P.
(8) Fallacies in hypothetical syllogisms. This fallacy
arises either when we deny the condition in the minor
premise, and the consequent in the conclusion, or when
we affirm the consequent in the minor premise, and the
condition in the conclusion.
The following is an example of the first kind:
If this man has stolen, he is immoral.
But he has not stolen.
.-. He is not immoral.
The following is an example of the second kind:
If this man has stolen, he is immoral.
But he is immoral.
.-. He has stolen.
(9) Fallacies in disjunctive syllogisms. This fallacy
arises when, in case there is no conflict between the al-
352 PSYCHOLOGY,
ternatives, we affirm one in the minor premise and deny
the other in the conclusion.
The following example will illustrate :
This science i& valued either for knowledge or for
discipline.
It is valued for knowledge.
.*. It is not valued for discipline.
It may be valued for both knowledge and discipline.
(10) Fallacies in dilemmatic syllogisms. These are
analogous to those in the hypothetical syllogism, and
consist in denying the condition, and hence the conse-
quent, or in affirming the consequent, and hence the
condition.
(11) Fallacy of four terms. The use of four terms in
a syllogism involves a fallacy nicknamed the logical
quadruped. In this case, there are either two middle
terms, and the extremes are separately compared with
diiferent things, thus affording no warrant for inferring
their relations to each other, or thei:e is a term in the
conclusion not found in either premise, in which case
one extreme is not compared with the middle, and hence
its relation to the other extreme can not be inferred.
The fallacy in this form is too glaring to deceive;
hence, it generally assumes the form called the fallacy
of equivocation — the same word being used with two
distinct meanings. There are apparently but three terms,
though in reality four.
Any one of the three terms, the major, the minor, or
the middle, is liable to be equivocal, but it is more fre-
quently the middle term which is thus used in a double
sense. In this case, the fallacy is called the fallacy of
the amMguous middle. The following are illustrations:
Light is contrary to darkness.
FORMAL FALLACIES. 353
Feathers are light.
.-. Feathers are contrary to darkness.
All criminal actions ought to be punished by law.
Prosecutions for theft are criminal actions.
.-. Prosecutions for theft ought to be punished by law.
(12) Fallacy of amphibology. This fallacy consists in
the use of an ambiguous grammatical construction.
Thus, the conclusion depending on the interpretation
of the proposition, '^ The duke yet lives that Henr^^
shall depose," would be doubtful, since, from the con-
struction, it is uncertain whether Henry is to depose
the duke, or the duke, Henry.
(13) The fallacy of composition. This fallacy occurs
when the middle term is used distributively in the
major premise and collectively in the minor, as in the
following example:
Three and four are two numbers.
Seven is three and four.
.-. Seven is two numbers.
(14) The fallacy of division. This fallacy occurs when
the middle term is used collectively in the major prem-
ise and distributively in the minor, as the following:
Seven is one number.
Three and four are seven.
.-. Three and four are one number.
(15) The fallacy of accent or emphasis. This fallacy
consists in misplacing the accent or emphasis. In the
proposition, "The study of Logic is not supposed to
communicate a knowledge of many useful facts," place
the emphasis first on supposed^ then on 7nany, then on
useful^ and state the sense expressed in each case.
Psy.— 30.
354 PSYCHOL OGY,
(16) The fallacy of figure of speech. Thus, the follow-
ing will illustrate:
A hero is a lion.
A lion is a quadruped.
.-.A hero is a quadruped.
Designing persons are untrustworthy.
Every body forms designs.
.-. Ever}^ body is untrustworthy.
2. Bules guarding against fallacy. — These are.
1st. Every syllogism must have three, and only three,
terms — the major term, the minor term, and the middle
term, and these terms must not be ambiguous.
2d. Ever}^ syllogism must have three, and only three,
propositions — the major premise, the minor premise,
and the conclusion, and these propositions must not be
ambiguous.
3d. The middle term must be - distributed at least in
one of the premises.
4th. A term must not be distributed in the conclusion,
unless it is distributed in one of the premises.
5th. If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion
is affirmative.
6th. If one premise is affirmative and the other neg-
ative the conclusion is negative.
7th. If both premises are negative there is no con-
clusion.
8th. If the conclusion is universal, both premises are
universal.
9th. If one premise is universal and the other partic-
ular, the conclusion is particular.
10th. If both premises are particular, there is no con-
clusion.
3. General laws of the syllogism. — These laws, on the
FORMAL FALLACIES, 355
supposition that no formal fallacy is involved, are the
following :
1st. The truth of the premises involves the truth of
the conclusion ; for the premises necessitate the conclu-
sion.
2d. The falsity of the conclusion involves the falsity
of one of the premises; for if the premises were true,
the conclusion would be true.
3d. The falsity of a premise does not necessitate the
falsity of the conclusion.
4th. The truth of the conclusion does not involve the
truth of the premises.
The third and fourth laws are thus illustrated:
Every month has thirty days
April is a month.
.-. April has thirty days.
4. Miscellaneous examples of fallacies. — Character-
ize the following fallacies, stating the irregular examples
in due form :
1. All good fathers provide food and clothing for their
children. Mr. B provides food and clothing for his
children. Therefore, Mr. ^ is a good father.
2. All moral beings are accountable. IN^o brute is a
moral being. Therefore, no brute is accountable.
3. No Pagan is a Christian. Every villager is a Pa-
gan. Therefore, no villager is a Christian.
4. Nothing is better than wisdom. Dry bread is better
than nothing. Therefore, dry bread is better than wis-
dom.
5. His imbecility of character might have been in-
ferred from his proneness to favoritism; for all weak
princes have this failing.
6. The express trains do not stop at this station. The
356 PSYCHOLOGY.
train that has just passed did not stop at this station.
Therefore, the train that just passed is an express train.
7. A successful author must be very industrious or
very talented. Gibbon was a successful author and
was very industrious. Therefore, Gibbon was not very
talented.
8. Who is most hungry eats most. Who eats least is
most hungry. Therefore, who eats least eats most.
9. The end of a thing is its perfection. Death is the
end of life. Therefore, death is the perfection of life.
10. He who believes himself to be always in the right
in his opinions lays claim to infallibility. You always
believe yourself to be right in your opinion. Therefore,
you lay claim to infallibility.
11. Improbable events happen every day. But what
happens every daj^ is probable. Therefore, improbable
events are probable.
12. The ancient Greeks produced the greatest master-
]3ieces of eloquence and philosophy. The Lacedemonians
were ancient Greeks. Therefore, the Lacedemonians
produced the greatest masterpieces of eloquence and
philosophy.
CHAPTEE XVIII.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
A material fallacy is a fallacy in the matter of
thought. It is said to be a fallacy in re, and is, there-
fore, extra dictionem, and, in fact, extra logical, unless it
is also faulty in form.
Material fallacies can be detected only hj those ac-
quainted with the subject-matter, or with the special
science under consideration. Thus, to settle matters of
fact pertaining to plants, we appeal to botany; facts
pertaining to the stars, fall within the province of as-
tronomy, and so on.
Though material fallacies can not be detected purely
by the methods of logic, yet it is important to point
them out and classify them, thus rendering the mind
alert, and diminishing the liabilities of falling into error.
We shall consider eight varieties of material fallacies:
1. Assumptions. — An assumption is that which is
taken to be true without evidence. It may be true or
false; but, resting on no basis of evidence, it is, in either
case, invalid, not because known to be false, bat because
not known to be true. To assume an assumption false
on account of its lack of evidence, is a procedure as in-
valid as to assume it true. There are several varieties
of assumptions :
1st. The want of attention results in non-observation or
mal-ohservation. Failing to notice many things, we are
likely to assume their non-existence. Other things, not
wholly overlooked, are, from inattention, misapprehended,
( 357 )
358 PSYCHOLOGY.
and assuming them to be what they are not, we are in-
volved in confusion.
2d. Prejudice is a fruitful source of assumptions. JSTor
is it easy to divest ourselves of its influence, though we
are loath to admit that we are, in any degree, subject to
its control. Prejudice which leads to assumptions vitia-
ting our judgments and involving us in error, may arise
from too high an opinion of ourselves, or from too low
an opinion of others; from ruling desires; from national,
party, church, or society relations; from preconceived
opinions, association, ignorance, or defective education.
A generous disposition, a love of truth, due caution, and
patient investigation, are guards against the assumptions
arising from prejudice.
3d. Superstition has, especially in the past, been fruitful
in assumptions; consider the mythologies, oracles, omens,
witchcrafis, apparitions, ghosts, fairies, signs, and charms.
Nor has superstition yet lost its influence, as is indi-
cated by such current sayings as these: ''If it rain the
first Sunday of the month, it will rain every Sunday."
^' If you first see the new moon over your right shoulder,
you will have good luck for that month." '' If you have
floating tea-leaves in your cup, you will have visitors."
4th. Hasty generalization leads to assumptions and in-
volves us in error. We thus assume that what is true
of ourselves is true of others; that what is true of a
few individuals of a class is true of the class; that edu-
cation is not desirable, because a few have risen to emi-
nence without it; that fortune favors fools, because a
man confessedly below par has accidentally become rich.
5th. A ivaiit of thorough investigation may lead to the
assunifjtion that a given appearance corresponds to the
reality; that a temporary order of sequence is a law;
that an accidental antecedent is a cause, or that an ac-
cidental consequent is an eflect.
MATEEIAL FALLACIES. 359
2. The fallacy of accident. — This fallacy consists in
extending a rule to a case to which it is rendered in-
applicable by some specific or accidental circumstance.
There are three varieties.
1st. Arguing from the general to the special. Thus,
every man has the right to inculcate his own opinions.
A magistrate is a man. Therefore, a magistrate is justi-
fied in employing his official powers in forwarding his
political or sectarian views. A magistrate has the same
general rights as other men, and he may properly em-
ploy his powers as a man, but not as a magistrate, in
propagating his opinions.
2d. In arguing from the special to the general. Thus,
thieves are dishonest ; but thieves are men ; therefore
all men are dishonest.
3d. In arguing from one special case to another. Thus,
certain beggars do not deserve assistance; therefore,
other beggars do not deserve assistance.
3. Irrelevant conclusion. — This fallacy, technically
called ignoratio elenchij consists in arguing to the wrong
point, or proving one thing when another should be
proved. This fallacy is the great resource of those who
have a weak case, or the wrong side of the question.
A certain English statesman, instead of j)roving the ex-
pediency of taxing the colonies, which was the real ques-
tion to be considered, undertook to prove the right.
A form of this fallacy, called argumentum ad hominem,
consists in arguing the case, not on its merits, but in
relation to the opinion or character of your opponent,
as when it is attempted to refute an opjDonent by prov-
ing that his present position is inconsistent with his
previously expressed views or with his character.
Another form of this fallacv, called araumentiim ad
populum^ consists in appealing to the prejudice or pas-
sions of the people. It is the weapon of demagogues.
360 PSYCHOLOGY.
There is still another form of this fallacy called ar-
gumentiim ad verecundiam. It is an apj)eal to reverence
for resj)ected authority or venerable institutions.
Closely connected with the irrelevant conclusion, which
logically follows from the premises, though it is not the
conclusion in question, is an unwarranted conclusion from
premises which warrant another conclusion. Thus, it is
often inferred that the conclusion is false because the
premises are false or the reasoning is illogical. The true
inference is, that the conclusion is not proved; but it
may be trae, notwithstanding the premises are false.
An able debater once said, "I have undertaken to prove
the conclusion false, by showing the premises on which
it is based to be unsound."
4. The begging of the question, petitio principii, called
also a circle in reasoning, circulus in probando^ consists in
taking for one of the premises something which de-
pends on the conclusion, and then having deduced the
conclusion, employ it in proving the premise. Thus, it
is reasoning in a circle, to assume that a party is right,
and hence conclude that you ought to support it, and
then attempt to justify the assumption that the party is
right because you ought to support it.
The fallacy of reasoning in a circle may be unjustly
charged. Thus, if your opponent sees that your propo-
sition will lead to your conclusion, he may attempt to
evade the force of your argument, by charging you with
begging the question, and then escape in the cloud of
dust which he raises.
5. The fallacy of the consequent. — This is the name
of an argument so loose that no one can discover its
cogency. It has no cogency. It is usually character-
ized by the expression, non sequiter, that is to say, it
does not follow.
6. The fallacy of false cause, or non causa pro causa.
MA TERIAL FALL A CLES. 361
This fallacy consists in calling one thing the cause of
another, because it is an antecedent, or one thing the
effect of another, because it is a consequent. The fallacy
of mistaking a consequent for an effect is described by
the phrase, post hoc^ ercjo propter hoc,
7. The fallacy of many questions. — This fallacy con-
sists in combining two or three questions in one, so that
whether answered in the affirmative or negative, the
answer can be turned to your disadvantage. Thus, if
the question, "Have you left off beating your mother?"
is answered in the affirmative, then the retort is that
you formerly beat her; if in the negative, that you still
beat her.
8. The fallacy of objections. — This fallacy consists in
inferring a conclusion to be false, because objections can
be raised against it. Very few things could be regarded
proved, if only those are proved against which no pos-
sible objection can be raised. It is, perhaps, true that
objections can be raised against any thing whatever. But
this does not prove that nothing is true; for objections
can be raised against either of two contradictor}^ propo-
sitions, one of which must be true. If, however, a
proposition conflicts with a known truth, it can not be
true, and we have a warrant for its rejection.
Miscellaneous examples of fallacies. — Detect the fal-
lacy in each of the following examples :
1. If Christianity were from God, it would be univer-
sal. It is not universal. Therefore, it is not from God.
2. You are not what I am. I am a man. Therefore,
you are not a man.
3. He who calls 3^ou a man, speaks the truth. He
who calls you a knave, calls 3^ou a man. Therefore,
he who calls you a knave, speaks the truth.
4. You do not know what I am going to ask you
about. I am going to ask you about the nature of
Psy.— 31.
362 PSYCHOLOGY,
yourself. Therefore, yoii do not know about the nature
of yourself
5, The following sophism^ called the Achilles^ was pro-
posed by Zeno^ the Eleatic, and is very celebrated: If
Achilles runs ten times as fast as a tortoise one mile
ahead, he will never overtake it; for when Achilles has
run this mile, the tortoise has run -^^ of a mile farther;
when Achilles has run this y^^, the tortoise has advanced
TOT ^^ ^ mile still farther, and so on, ad infinitum.
6, According to Zeno, a finite body is impossible. For
if there be such a body, and if it be divided into any
number of parts, the sum of the parts ought to be equal
to the body. Let the number of parts be infinite. Then
these parts either have magnitude, or they have no
magnitude; if the parts have magnitude, their sum has
infinite magnitude, since there is an infinite number of
parts; if the parts have no magnitude, their sum will
have no magnitude, since the sum of any number of
zeros is zero. In neither case is the sum equal to the
body, as it ought to be, since the sum of all the parts
is equal to the whole. Hence, the supposition that there
is a finite body, which led to this absurdity, is false.
7. The Diodorus Cronus^ so called from its inventor, at-
tempts to prove the impossibility of motion, thus: If
motion is possible, a body moves either in the place
where it is, or in the place where it is not. But it can
not move in the place where it is, since it fills that
place, leaving no room. It can not move in the place
where it is not, for it is not there. Hence, it can not
move at all, or motion is impossible.
8. The Litigiosus^ or Beciprociis, is the notorious di-
lemma concerning a matter of business between Protag-
oras, the prince of Sophists, and Euathlus, his student
in the law. Euathlus had contracted to pay his tuition
fee when he gained his first case. But not being in a
\
m
MATERIAL FALLACIES. 363
hurry to commence the practice of law, Protagoras
sued him for his fee, and thus addressed him in court:
^' Learn, most foolish of young men, that whatever be
the decision of the judges, pay me my demand you
must. For, if the judgment be against you, I shall ob-
tain the fee b}^ decree of the court; but if the judgment
be in your favor, I shall obtain my fee by the terms
of our contract, since you will then have gained your
first case."
To this Euathlus replied, ^' Learn, most sapient of
masters, from your own argument, that, whatever may
be the decision of the court, absolved I must be from
the payment of the fee. For, if the decision be in my
favor, I shall pay nothing according to the decree of the
court; but if the decision be against me, I pay nothing
by virtue of the contract, since I shall not have gained
my first case."
9. The mentiens, or sophism of the liar, was invented
by Eubulides, and runs thus: ''If you say that you lie,
and tell the truth, then you do lie ; but if you tell a lie,
then you speak the truth. Hence, if you tell the truth
you lie, and if you lie, you speak the truth."
10. If an event is to be, it w^ill be, and effort is use-
less. If it is not to be, it will not be, and effort is use-
less. But it is evident that the event either is to be, or
is not to be. Therefore, effort is useless.
11. According to Empedocles, the subject which knows
and the object which is known must be of like nature ;
but the mind knows matter. Therefore, the mind and
matter must be of like nature. Hence, the mind is re-
solvable into matter, or matter into mind.
12. According to M. Comte, the events of the world
are not controlled by supernatural will; for if so, they
would be both variable and beyond human control; but
they are not variable, since they are the objects of hu-
364 PSYCHOLOGY.
man prevision in astronomy; neither are thej^ beyond
human control, since they are subject to human modi-
fication, as in physics.
13. Whatever I know, must be as I know, otherwise
I could not know. I know that you are here. Tliere-
fbre, you must be here, and hence are not a free agent.
14. Wiiatever God foreknows must be as He foreknows,
otherwise he could not foreknow. God foreknows the
actions of men. Therefore, these actions must be as
God foreknows. Hence, these actions are necessitated,
and men are not free agents.
15. If God is both able and willing to prevent sin, it
would not occur; but sin does occur. Therefore, God is
able to prevent it, but not willing; or willing, but not
able ; or neither willing nor able. If He is able, but not
willing, He is not holy; if He is willing, but not able,
He is not omnipotent; if He is neither willing nor able.
He is neither holy nor omnipotent; but any of these
consequences is subversive of the idea of God; hence,
there is no God.
It may be remarked that fallacy, in general, may be
summarily divided into fallacy of apprehension, fallacy
of reasoning, and fallacy of assumption.
Fallacy of apprehension consists in misapprehension
in regard either to the proposition itself or to its
grounds. Its essence is confusion.
Fallacy of reasoning consists in illogical inference, and
is either formal or material.
Fallacy of assumption consists in taking the premises
for granted without evidence. Probable premises, how-
ever, ma}" be employed, if the conclusion also be re-
garded as only probable.
CHAPTEK XIX.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
1. A knowledge of the doctrine of Mood and Figure^
as developed in this and the following chapter, though
not essential in testing a sound argument or in detect-
ing a fallacy, as the preceding discussions prove, is
nevertheless interesting in itself and in its historical as-
sociations.
2. The mood of syllogism is the designation of the
quantity and quality of its propositions, taken in the
order of major premise, minor premise, and conclusion,
each by one of the symbols, ^, ^, /, 0.
Thus, the mood of the following syllogism i^ E A E.
No ikf is P.
All S is M.
,-. No S is P.
3. The number of possible moods is thus determined:
Any one of the four propositions, J., E^ /, O, may be
the major premise, each having either A^ E, 7, 0, for the
minor premise, making sixteen combinations of premises,
each combination having either A, E, I, 0, for the con-
clusion, making sixty-four possible moods. These sixty-
four moods are therefore divided into four groups having
A^ E, 7, O, respectively, for the major j)remise;- each
group is divided into four sub-groups, having A, E, 7, O,
respectively, for the minor premise ; and each sub-group
is divided into four moods, having A, E, 7, 0, respectively,
for the conclusion, as thus exhibited:
( 365 )
366
PSYCHOLOGY,
Group A.
Group E.
Group I.
Group O.
' A
A A
E A A
I
A A
A A
Sub-group
A <
A
A
A E
A I
E A E
E A I
I
I
A E
A I
A E
OAT
u
A
E A
I
A
A
' A
E A
E E A
I
E A
E A
Sub-group
E <
A
A
E I
E E E
E E I
I
I
E E
E I
E E
E I
u
E
E E
I
E
E
•*
' A
I A
E I A
I
I A
I A
-
cy 7
T
A
I E
E I E
I
I E
I E
tSub-group
I <
A
I I
E I I
I
I I
Oil
1
A
I
E I
I
I
10
1
(A
A
E A
I
A
A
I
Sub-group
<
A
A
E
I
E E
EOT
I
I
E
I
E
1
, A
E
I
4. Valid moods are those in which valid arguments
can be constructed. Invalid moods are those in which
valid arguments can not be constructed.
Most of the above moods are invalid, since they vio-
late one or more of the following rules :
(1) If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion is
affirmative.
(2) If one premise is affirmative and the other nega-
tive, the conclusion is negative.
(3) If both premises are negative, there is no conclu-
sion.
(4) If the conclusion is universal, both premises must
be universal.
(5) If one premise is universal and the other partic-
ular, the conclusion is particular.
MOOD OF SYLLOGISMS. 367
(6) If both premises are particular, there is no con-
chision.
(7) The middle term must be distributed in, at least,
one of the premises.
(8) ]^o term must be distributed in the conclusion
which is not distributed in one of the premises.
5. The negative method o^ finding the valid moods is
as follows:
Point out the invalid moods, and tell which of the
above rules are violated. The moods not violating any
of the above rules are valid. Tell which moods are
valid« Eemember that a mood is valid, if a valid argu-
ment can be constructed in it, though other arguments
in the same mood be invalid.
The above method of determining the valid moods
may be characterized as the negative method^ since the
valid moods are not positively determined, but are those
left, after striking out the moods that are invalid.
The following moods are valid : A A A^ A A I^ A E E^
A E 0, A I T, A O 0, E A E, E A 0. E I 0, I A I,
GAG. The mood LEG involves an illicit process of
the major term. Prove this.
6. The positive method of determining the valid moods
is as follows:
1st. If the conclusion is A, both premises must be A.
For since the conclusion is universal, both premises must
be universal, and hence both A, or both E^ or one A
and the other E. Both premises can not be E, for then,
by rule (3), there would be no conclusion. One premise
can not be A and the other E, for then, by rule (2),
the conclusion would be negative. Hence, if the conclu-
sion is warranted at all, both premises must be A^ which
is the only remaining case.
That A A A is Si valid mood, is verified by the follow-
ing valid syllogism :
368 PSYCHOLOGY,
All M is R
All 8 i^M,
.'. All S is P.
2d. 7/" the conclusion is E^ one premise must he A, and
the other E, Prove this and construct valid syllogisms
having the moods, A E E^ E A E, respectively,
3d. If the conclusion is 7, both premises are affirmative,
and one. at least, universal. Prove this and construct
valid syllogisms having the moods, A A I, A I I, I A I,
respectively.
4th. If the conclusion is 0, one premise must be affirma-
tive, the other negative, and one, at least, universal.
Prove this, and construct valid syllogisms whose moods
are, A E 0, E A 0, A 0, A 0, E I 0, respectively.
CHAPTBE XX.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
The figure of a syllogism is the position of its middle
term with respect to the extremes in the premises.
Let M denote the middle term, P the major, and S
the minor, and let the order of the letters denote the
order of the terms. Then we have the following figures:
1st. Fig.
-2d. Fig.
3d. Fig.
4th. Fig.
Major premise,
MP
P M
MP
P M
Minor premise,
S M
S M
M S
MS
Conclusion,
S P
S P
S P
S P
In the first figure, the middle term is the subject of
the major premise and the predicate of the minor.
In the second figure, the middle term is the predicate
of both premises.
In the third figure, the middle term is the subject of
both premises.
In the fourth figure, the middle term is the predicate
of the major premise and the subject of the minor.
Eemember that a universal proposition, A or E^ dis-
tributes its subject; that a negative, E or 0, distributes
its predicate ; that a particular, / or 0, does not distrib-
ute its subject; that an afiirmative, A or 7, does not, in
general, distribute its predicate; also, that the middle
term must be distributed, at least, in one of the premises;
and that a term must not be distributed in the conclu-
sion, if it is not distributed in one of the premises, since
that would be an illicit process.
(369)
370 PSYCHOLOGY,
Figure T.
cM P.
1st. Order of terms. The order of the terms, is ^ >S Jf.
Is P.
2d. Definition. Figure first is that figure in which the
middle term is the subject of the major premise and the
predicate of the minor.
3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. I. are thus
determined :
(1) To have an affirmative conclusion, both premises
must be afiirmative. The major premise must be uni-
versal, otherwise the middle term would not be distrib-
uted, since it is not distributed as the predicate of the
afiirmative minor premise. If the minor premise is uni-
versal, the conclusion may be universal or particular;
but if the minor premise is particular, the conclusion is
particular. Hence, A A A^ A A I^ A 1 1^ are valid af-
firmative moods in Fig. I. The mood A A I i^ usually
discarded, since the premises warrant the conclusion A,
which implies I.
(2) To have a negative conclusion, the major premise
must be negative, in order to distribute the predicate
which is distributed in the conclusion. The minor
premise must be afiirmative, otherwise both premises
would be negative, and there would be no conclusion.
The major premise must be universal, in order to dis-
tribute the middle term, which is not distributed as the
predicate of the affirmative minor premise. If the minor
premise is universal, the conclusion may be universal
or particular; but if the minor premise is particular, the
conclusion must be particular. Hence, E A E^ E A 0,
E I Oj are valid negative moods in Fig. I. The mood
E A is usually discarded, since the premises warrant
the conclusion E, which implies 0.
FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM, 371
4th. Doctrine, The doctrine of Fig. I. is the following:
(1) The middle term is the subject of the major prem-
ise, and the predicate of the minor.
(2) The major premise is universal, and the minor af-
firmative.
(3) The conclusion agrees in quality with the major
premise, and in quantity with the minor.
(4) All forms of conclusion, J., E^ /, 0, are admissible
in Fig. I.
5th, Aristotle's dictum. Whatever is predicated, affirm-
atively or negatively, of any term distributed, may be
predicated, in like manner, of whatever is contained
under that term. This dictum is sometimes separated
into two dicta: — the dictum de omni, Whatever is af-
firmed of any term distributed, may be affirmed of any
thing contained under that term ; and the dictum de nidlo,
Whatever is denied of any term distributed, may be de-
nied of any thing contained under that term.
6th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. I.
are b Arb A r A^ c E I Ar En t, d Ar II, and f ErI 0.
The vowels denote the propositions. Construct these ar-
guments, using the letters, Jf, P, /S, and test their valid-
ity by circles, also by Aristotle's dictum. Illustrate by
concrete arguments. See Schuyler's Logic, pp. 65, 78.
Figure II.
rP M.
1st. Order of terms. The order of terms is I S M.
Ls P.
2d. Definition. Figure second is that figure in which
the middle term is the predicate of both premises.
3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. 11. are thus
determined :
In order to distribute the middle term, since it is the
predicate of both premises, one of the premises must be
372 PSYCHOLOGY,
negative; hence the other premise must be affirmative,
otherwise there would be two negative premises, and
therefore no conclusion. Since one premise is affirmative
and the other negative, the conclusion is negative, aad
therefore its predicate is distributed; hence, the major
premise must be universal in order to distribute its
subject, which is distributed as the predicate of the con-
clusion. If the minor premise is universal, the conclu-
sion may be universal or particular; but, if the minor
premise is particular, the conclusion is particular. Hence,
E AE, A E E, E A 0, AEG, E I 0; AGO, are valid
moods in Fig. II. The moods, E A G, AEG, are usually
discarded, since the premises warrant the conclusion Ej
which implies 0. The striking fact in this figure is that
the conclusion is always negative.
4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. I. is the follow-
ing :
(1) The middle term is the predicate of both prem-
ises.
(2) One premise is affirmative and the other is neg-
ative.
(3) The major premise is universal.
(4) The conclusion is negative, and agrees in quantity
with the minor premise.
5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. II.
are cEsArE, cAmEstrEs, fEstInG, f A k G r G.
Construct the arguments and test them by circles, and
illustrate by concrete examples. Aristotle's dictum does
not directly apply to any of the four figures except the
first. Syllogisms in Figures II., III., or lY. can always
be reduced to those in Fig. I., and then tested by the
dictum, and thus it is shown that all categorical syllo-
gisms conform to one principle, a fact of great scientific
interest. The consonants in the names of the syllogisms
furnish the key to the reduction, as shown hereafter.
FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 373
Figure III.
cM P.
Ist. Order of terms. The order of the terms \h} M S.
Is P.
2d. Definition. Figure third is that figure in which
the middle term is the subject of both premises.
3d. Valid moods. The valid moods of Fig. III. are
thus determined:
In order to distribute the middle term, one of the
premises must be universal. This is also true of any
syllogism, in any figure. The conclusion can not be
universal, either affirmative or negative. For:
(1) The conclusion can not be a universal affirmative;
for then both premises must be universal affirmative,
and there would be an illicit process of the minor term,
since it would be distributed in the conclusion, as sub-
ject of a universal, but undistributed in the minor
premise, as the predicate of an affirmative.
(2) The conclusion can not be a universal negative;
for then both premises must be universal, one affirma-
tive, and the other negative; if the major premise is
affirmative, there would be an illicit process of the major
term, since it would be distributed in the conclusion as
predicate of a negative, but not distributed in the major
premise as predicate of an affirmative; if the minor prem-
ise is affirmative, there would be an illicit process of the
minor term, since it would be distributed in the conclu-
sion, as the subject of a universal, but not in the minor
premise, as predicate of an affirmative.
Since the conclusion can be neither a universal affirm-
ative nor a universal negative, it is particular, which is
the striking fact in this figure.
If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must be
374 PSYCHOLOGY,
*
affirmative. If the conclusion is negative, the major
premise must be negative, in order to distribute its
predicate, the major term, which is distributed as the
predicate of the negative conclusion; and, therefore, the
minor premise must be affirmative. Hence, A A I^ I A I,
All, E AG, OAO, EI 0, are valid moods in Pig. III.
4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. III. is the follow-
ing :
(1) The middle term is the subject of both premises.
(2) One premise is universal, and the miinor is affirm-
ative.
(3) The conclusion is particular and agrees in quality
with the major premise.
5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Pig. III.
are, dArApt I, dis A m Is, dAtlsI, f El AptOn,
d Ok Am 0, fErlsO. Construct the arguments and
test them by circles ; also illustrate by concrete examples.
PiGURE IV.
rPM.
1st. Order of terms. The order of terms is^ M S.
(s P,
2d. Definition. Pigure fourth is that figure in which
the middle term is the predicate of the major premise
and the subject of the minor.
3d. Valid moods. The valid moods in Pig. TV. are
thus determined:
(1) If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must
be affirmative, the minor premise universal, in order to
distribute the middle term which is not distributed as
the predicate of the affirmative major premise, the major
premise may be universal or particular, and the conclu-
sion must be particular, otherwise there would be an
illicit process of the minor term, which is not distrib-
uted as the predicate of the affirmative minor premise.
FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 375
Hence, the valid affirmative moods in Fig. lY. are A A I,
lAL
(2) If the conclusion is negative^ one premise must be
affirmative and tlie other negative, and the major prem-
ise must be universal in order to distribute its subject,
which is distributed as the predicate of the negative
conclusion; and if the major premise is affirmative, the
minor must be negative, since the conclusion is negative,
and universal, in order to distribute the middle term,
which is not distributed as the predicate of the affirm-
ative minor premise, and the conclusion may be univer-
sal or particular; but if the major premise is negative,
the minor must be affirmative, either universal or par-
ticular, and the conclusion must be particular, otherwise
there would be an illicit process of the minor term.
Hence, AEE, AEG, EA 0, EIOj are valid negative
moods in Fig. TV. The mood AE is usually discarded,
since the premises warrant E, which implies 0.
4th. Doctrine. The doctrine of Fig. TV. is the following:
(1) The middle term is the predicate of the major
premise and the subject of the minor.
(2) Either the major premise must be negative or the
minor universal.
(3) If the conclusion is affirmative, both premises must
be affirmative, the minor universal, the major universal
or particular, and the conclusion particular.
(4) If the conclusion is negative, the major premise
must be universal, and if affirmative, the minor premise
must be a universal negative, and the conclusion uni-
versal; but if the major premise is negative, the minor
must be affirmative, either universal or particular, and
the, conclusion must be particular.
(5) All forms of conclusion, except A, are admissible
in Figure TV.
5th. Names. The names of the arguments in Fig. TV.
376 PSYCHOLOGY.
are, hrAmAnt Ip^ c A mEnEs^ d Im A r Is, fEsAp 0,
frEsIs On. Construct these arguments^ test them by
circles, and ilhistrate by concrete examples.
The fourth figure was not recognized by Aristotle,
but is supposed to have been introduced by Galen.
It is an awkward figure, and the propriety of giving
it a place among the figures is questioned by many
logicians. See Mahan, pp. 121-4; Hamilton, pp., 285,
302, 626; Coppee, p. 117; Tappan, p. 347; Thompson,
pp. 201-6; Wilson, p. 110; Whateley, p. 96; Davis, 156-8.
5. Comparative view of the four figures.
1st. In the first figure, the middle term is the subject
of the major j)remise and predicate of the minor; the
major premise is universal, and the minor affirmative;
the conclusion agrees in quality with the major premise,
and in quantity with the minor; every conclusion. A,
E, /, 0, is admissible in this figure, and A in no other;
the dictum is directly applicable only to this figure,
which, from this fact, as well as from its clearness, has
been regarded by Aristotle and by other logicians, as
the most perfect of all the figures.
2d. In the second figure, the middle term is the predi-
cate of both premises; one premise is affirmative, and
the other is negative; the major premise is universal;
the conclusion is negative and agrees in quantity with
the minor premise; this figure is naturally used in dis-
proving a statement.
3d. In the third figure, the middle term is the subject
of both premises; one premise is universal, and the
minor is affirmative; the conclusion is particular, and
agrees in quality with the major premise; this figure is
naturally used when the middle term is singular, and
in establishing objections, by proving exceptions to gen-
eral statements.
4th. In the fourth figure, the middle term is the predi-
FIGURE OF THE SYLLOGISM. 377
cate of the major premise and subject of the minor;
either the major premise must be negative or the minor
universal; if the conclusion is affirmative, both premises
must be affirmative, the minor universal the major uni-
versal or particular, and the conclusion particular; if
the conclusion is negative, the major premise must be
universal, and if affirmative, the minor premise must be
a universal negative, and the conclusion universal; but
if the major premise is negative, the minor must be
affirmative, either universal or jDarticular, and the con-
clusion must be particular; all the conclusions except A
are proved in this figure.
According to Lambert, "The first figure is suited to
the discovery or proof of the properties of a thing; the
second, to the discovery or proof of the distinctions
between things; the third, to the discovery or proof of
instances and exceptions; the fourth, to the discovery or
exclusion of the different species of a genus."
6. The unfigured syllogism. — This demands notice.
1st. Definition, The unfigured syllogism is an argument
in which the terms of the propositions do not sustain to
each other the relation of subject and predicate.
2d. Examples^
A and B always co-exist.
(V) Positive \ ^ ^^^ ^ always co-exist.
.-. A and (7 always co-exist.
A and B alw^ays co-exist.
(2) Negative ] ^ ^i^^ ^ never co- exist.
.'.A and C never co-exist.
3d. Laws. The laws of the unfigured syllogism are
the following:
(1) As far as two terms agree with a third term, so
far they agree with each other.
Psy.— 32.
378 PSYCHOLOGY.
(2) As far as one term agrees and another disagrees
with a third, so far they disagree with each other.
4th. Remark. Some logicians have questioned the ex-
istence of the unfigured syllogism, claiming that such
syllogisms can always be reduced to those in one or the
other of the figures. But the question is not, Can the
unfigured syllogism be made to assume a figure ? but,
Does it, as it stands, have a figure?
The following exercises will be useful:
1st. Eeduce the foregoing examples of the unfigured
syllogism to syllogisms in the first figure.
2d. Deduce the conclusion from the following premises,
and state the figure, mood, and name of the argument:
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
I All mammalia are vertebrates.
1 Some amphibious animals are mammalia.
1 1^0 planets are self-luminous.
1 All planets are heavenly bodies.
I ISTo fish suckles its young.
(The whale suckles its young.
f Ruminants are not predacious.
I The lion is predacious.
3d. Construct an argument having false premises and
a true conclusion.
4th. Supply premises which prove the following con-
clusions, and state the figure, mood, and name of the
syllogism :
(1) ]^o vicious conduct is heroic.
(2) ISTo wicked man is happy.
(3) Some worthy of admiration are not philosophers.
(4) Some who are admired are dreaded.
CHAPTEE XXL
DEDUCTIVE REASONING.
Reduction is the transformation of an argument in
the second, third, or fourth figures into one of the first.
There are two kinds of reduction — the direct and the
indirect.
1. Direct reduction. — The direct reduction of the
so called imperfect figures to the perfect, that is, the
second, third, and fourth to the first, is readily accom-
plished by the subjoined method, than which, as Ham-
ilton has remarked, " There are few human inventions
^hich display a higher ingenuity."
First, thoroughly learn the following lines, which may
be scanned as Latin Hexameters:
B ArbAr A, cElArEnt^ dArll, fEr I Oque prions;
CEsArE, cA7nEstrEs. /Est InO^ fAKOr 0, secundce;
Tertia, dArApt I, d Is Am Is, dAtlsI, f El Apt On,
DOkAmO, fEr I s On, habet ; quartet insuper addit
BrAmAyit Ip, c Am EnEs, d ImAr Is, f E s A p 0,
frEs Is On.
The initial consonants denote reduction to syllogisms
in the first figure, beginning with the same letters.
Thus, initial b denotes reduction to b Arb Ar A; c, to
cElArEnt; d, to dAr II ; f, to f Er 1 0. These conso-
nants do not aid in making the reductions, but are a
check on the result.
The other consonants, so far as expressive, have the
following significations; m denotes that the premises are
(S79)
380 PSYCHOLOGY.
to be transposed; s that the proposition represented by
the preceding vowel is to be converted simply; j9, that
the proposition represented by the preceding vowel is to
be converted by limitation, that is, its quantity is
changed from universal to particular, except in hrAra-
Antlp, in which the quantity is changed from particu-
lar to universal; ^, that the preceding A is to be
changed to j5J, or to J, and the result converted simply.
The following are given as specimen reductions :
r IS^o P is Jf. ^ r 'No Mis P.
cEsArE ) All >S is J£ V^cElArEnUAWSisM.
l.-.l^o >S is Pj * (.-.IN'o >Sis P.
r All P is M. \ r'Eo non-Mis F.
fAkOrOj Some S is not M. I =fErIO ] Some>S^is non-M.
(,.'.Some>SisnotP 3 C.'.SomeASisnotP
The A of the major premise. All P is M, is changed
to E^ No P is non-M^ as denoted by k^ which converted
simply, gives No non-M is P. If the minor premise
remain negative, no conclusion could be drawn, since we
should have two negative premises ; moreover, the middle
term would not be the same in form in the two prem-
ises, giving the ambiguous middle; but if we change (9,
Some S is not M, to /, Some S is non-M^ these difficul-
ties will both be obviated, as seen above.
Reduce all the syllogisms of the second, third, and
fourth figures to those in the first.
2. Indirect reduction. — This is accomplished, not by
the use of the consonants, but by the following nde :
Substitute the contradictory of the conclusion for the
major premise^ except in the second figure and in cAmEnEs
of the fourth, in which substitute for the minor.
One example will serve to illustrate the method :
BED UCTION TO THE FIRST FIG UEE, 381
r No P is ilf. ^ r No P is ilf. \
cEsAvE} All S is M. [gives-] Some 8 is P VfErlO
(.-.NoASisP ; (..-.Some /Sis not ilf J
But Some S is not ilif is the contradictory of All S is
M^ which is true by hypothesis; therefore, Some 8 is
not M is false ; hence, either No P is M or Some 8 is
P is false; but No P is ilf is true by hypothesis; there-
fore, Some aS is P is false ; but Some /S is P is the con-
tradictory of No 8 is P, which is, therefore, true. Ob-
serve that, in the new syllogism, P is the middle term.
The truth of the original conclusion is thus estab-
lished by reasoning in connection with a new argument
in the first figure. In some cases, the new conclusion is
the contrary instead of the contradictory of the rejected
premise; but it is false in either case. The falsity of the
new conclusion involves the falsity of one of the prem-
ises ; but one of these premises is a premise in the orig-
inal syllogism, and is, therefore, true by hypothesis;
hence, the other premise, which is always the contra-
dictory of the original conclusion, is false, and since
false, its contradictor}^, or the original conclusion, is
true.
By indirect reduction^ reduce all the syllogisms of the
second, third, and fourth figures to those of the first,
and vindicate the original conclusions.
Construct concrete arguments, as the following, in the
second, third, or fourth figures, and reduce them by both
methods.
No science is capable of perfection.
All science is worthy of cultivation.
.-. Something worthy of cultivation is not caj)able of
perfection.
CHAPTEE XXII.
INDUCTIVE REASONING.
Induction is the process of inferring general proposi-
tions from particular instances. It includes, therefore,
both the discovery of the particular instances, and the
inference of the general proposition.
Induction may be classified as follows : ,
{Mathematical — demon strative.
r Perfect — demonstrative.
Logical I Imperfect —probable.
Mathematical induction is the process of proving a
general proposition by means of an empirical fact to-
gether with a conditional principle. The empirical fact
is that the proposition holds true for several of the first
of the consecutive cases; and the conditional principle is
that if the proposition holds for any case, it holds for
the next. The nature of mathematical induction will be
made clear by the following illustrations:
1. In the series of odd numbers, 1, 3, 5, 7, . . ., find
any term^ and the sum of the terms.
To find any term, observe that, for the first term,
1=1X2 — 1; for the second term, 3=::=2X2 — ^^1; for
the third term, 5 = 3 X 2 — 1 ; for the fourth term, 7 ^= 4
X2 — 1; that is, so far as examined, any term is twice
the number of the term, minus 1, which is the empir-
ical fact required.
To prove by mathematical induction that the law is
(382)
MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. 383
general, it is necessary to prove the conditional princi-
ple that if the law hold true for any number of terms,
it holds for the next term. Assuming the law true for
n terms, we have 1, 3, 5, 7, ... 2 n — 1.
Since two added to any odd number gives the next
greater odd number, we have, by adding 2, the next
term,
n—lJ^2==2n-^l=2 (n-f 1) — 1 .
But 2(n + l) — 1 i^ twice the number of the term,
minus 1; hence, if the law hold for any number of
terms, it holds for the next term ; but the law does
hold, as shown above, up to the 4th term; hence, by the
above principle, it holds for the 5th term; and since for
the 5th, then for the 6th, and so on up to the nth, that
is, for any number of terms.
To find the suvi of the tervis, observe that for one
term, 1=12; for two terms, 1 -]- 3 ^^ 4: :===: 2^ ] for three
terms, 1 -\- 3 -\- b = 9 =i^^ ] for four terms, 1 + 3 -f- 5 -|- 7
= 16=42; and so on, that is, so far as examined, the
sum of the terms is equal to the square of the number
of the terms, which is the empirical fact required.
To prove the law general, it is necessary to prove the
conditional princif)le, that if it hold for any number of
terms, it holds for one term more. Assuming it true
for n terms, we have
1 _f 3 + 5 + 7 -f , . . + 2 /I — 1 = 7^2.
Adding the next term to both members, we have
1 + 3 + 5+7 + -. ..+2 n — l-f2n4-l = n2-f 2/1+1
==(n + l)2.
Hence, if the law hold for n terms, it holds for n -j-1
terms; that is, since n may be any number, if it hold
384 PSYCHOLOGY.
for any number of terms, it holds for one term more,
which is the conditional principle required; but the law
holds, as shown above, up to the 4th term; hence, by
the above principle, it holds for five terms; and since
for five, then for six, and so on for any number of
terms. Hence, the law is general.
2. The difference of the same powers of two quanti-
ties is divisible by the difference of the quantities.
By actual division, we shall find that
(a — fc) --- (« — &):=: 1; (a2 — 62-)_^ ^a-~h)z=:a -^b;
This gives the required empirical fact.
If we should go on, in this way, to the 100th power,
and find no exceptions, it would not prove the law gen-
eral, though it would render it highly probable. This
is the method of probable induction; and giving only
probable conclusions, it is tolerated only when no better
methods are attainable.
To prove the law general, it is necessary to prove that
if it hold for any power, it holds for the next higher
power.
GBo show this, let us divide a^' + i — 6" + ^ by a — b.
(2^ + ^ — a'^b
a
a *' = quotient
Eemainder :=a''b — 6^ + i=6(a^ — 6**).
Now, it is evident that if a'' — b'\ which is a factor
of the remainder, is divisible by a — 6, the whole re-
mainder, and consequently the dividend, a^' + i — 6'' + ^, is
divisible by a — b ; that is, if the difference of any pow-
ers, of the same degree, of two quantities is divisible by
the difference of the quantities, then the difference of
MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. 385
the powers one degree greater is divisible by the differ-
ence of the quantities, which is the conditional principle.
But it has already been found, by trial, that the. dif-
ference of the powers of the same degree, up to the 3d
power, is divisible by the difference of the quantities;
hence, by the above principle, the difference of the 4th
powers is divisible by the difference of the quantities;
and since the difference of the 4th powers, then the
difference of the 5th powers, and so on to any de-
gree. Hence, the law is general.
3. To find the law of bodies falling in a vacuum, on
the supposition that gravity near the earth is a con-
stant force.
Let g be the velocity generated by gravity in one sec-
ond. Since the body, by its inertia, retains all the
velocity it has acquired, and gravity is a constant force,
it receives each second an increment g of velocity; hence,
the velocity generated varies with the time, and at the
expiration of the successive seconds, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, . . ., is
g, 2^, 3^, ^g, 5^, ...
The body starts from, rest, and is uniformly accelera-
ted, since gravity is constant; hence, the velocity at the
expiration of the first second, which is g^ is twice the
average velocity for the second; therefore, the space
described the first second is ^g. The space described in
any second is equal to the space which it w^ould have
described without gravity, which is equal to the velocity
at the expiration of the preceding second, plus \g^ the
space due to gravity for one second. Hence, the spaces
described in the successive seconds are,
29^ 2"^' 29i 2"^? "2^? • ' •
The whole space described in any number of seconds
Psy.— 33.
386 PSYCHOLOGY.
is evidently obtained by taking the sum of the corre-
sponding number of terms of the last series, and hence is
By examining these series, we observe that the veloc-
ity at the expiration of any second is equal to g multi-
plied by the number of the second; that the space de-
scribed in each of the successive seconds is equal to \g
multiplied by one less than twice the number of the
second; that the whole space is equal to the space de-
scribed in the first second multiplied by the square of
the number of seconds. These are the empirical facts.
To generalize the laws, it will be necessary to show
that if they hold for t seconds, they hold for t-\-l sec-
onds. Assuming them true for t seconds, we have,
(1) g, 2^, 3^, 4.g, ... tg,
2t—l
(2) hg, ig, ig, ig, ••. — tt^ g-
11
\P) '^g-) 2"?? 2"9'j ~2~?7 • • • ~^^*
The velocity for the (t-\-V)^^ second is evidently
(t-\-V)g; the space described in the (t^l)'^ second is
2f + l 2(^H-1) — 1
^g + ^g^ which IS equal to —^ g = g;
the whole space, which is found as before, is
f^ 2t + l __ t'^+2t+ l _ (?^ + 1) 2 ^
~2^ 2^" 2 ^~~ 2^'
Hence, if the laws hold for t seconds, they hold for
^ + 1 seconds; that is, since t may be any number of
MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, 387
seconds, if they hold for any number of seconds, they
hold for one second more, which is the conditional prin-
ciple; but the laws hold, as shown above, up to five
seconds; and since for tive, then for six, and so on, for
any number of seconds up to t. Hence, the laws are
general.
Denoting the velocity by v, the space described in the
V^ second by s\ and the Avhole space by 5, we have
v=gxt; s' = lgxi2t — l)] s = lgXt''.
From the foregoing illustrations of Mathematical in-
duction, it is evident that the empirical fact that the
law holds for several of the first consecutive cases, which
is found by trial, gives, by itself, only a probable con-
clusion, as in probable induction; that the conditional
principle, gives, by itself, only the conclusion that if the
law hold for any case, it holds for the next case; and
that the empirical fact and the conditional principle,
taken together, give an induction of the utmost gener-
ality, whose truth is demonstrably certain.
CHAPTEE XXIII.
INDUCTIVE REASONING.
The subsidiaries of induction are experience, observa-
tion, experiment, hypothesis, analogy, classification, and
denomination.
1. Experience is the accumulated knowledge of the
past, and is either personal, that is, our own experience;
or foreign, that is, the experience of others, obtained
from testimony.
2. Observation is the direction of the attention to the
facts of matter or mind. It takes the form of percep-
tion, when the facts are external, or physical, and the
form of consciousness, when the facts are internal, or
psychical.
3. Experiment is the act of placing the facts in cir-
cumstances favorable for observation, by means of instru-
ments or apparatus by which we vary the conditions of
the phenomena.
In pure observation, we find our instances; but in
experiment, we make them. By experiment we vary
the circumstances or degree of the phenomenon under
consideration, or isolate it, or combine it with other
phenomena, and thus greatly extend our field of obser-
vation. Trial is a simple experiment. It may be made
with little apparatus, or with none at all.
In some cases, experiment is impracticable, as in as-
tronomy, where the facts are acquired by observation,
though the observation may be aided by such instru-
ments as the telescope. In other cases, experiment is
( 388 )
LOGICAL INDUCTION —SUBSIDIARIES. 389
indispensable, as in chemistry, Avliere experiment is the
chief resource. In most sciences, both observation and
experiment are requisite.
To make an observation or to perform an experiment
properly, the mind should be in a vigorous condition,
and free from prepossession, partiality, or prejudice;
and the attention should be withdrawn from all irrele-
vant objects, and concentrated upon the object to be ex-
amined, which should be divided, if necessary, till the
perceptions become clear and distinct.
4. An hypothesis is a supposition made to account for
the co-existence or succession of phenomena.
The tendency of the human mind to frame hypotheses
is very strong. The explanation of this tendency is
found in the intuition of causality — that every event
must have a cause. It should be remembered, however,
that this intuition does not inform us what the cause is,
but only that there must be a cause. Room is thus left
for hypothesis; and since the hypothesis may be true or
false, it should, therefore, be regarded as merely provis-
ional, till verified or refuted by further investigation.
The utility of hypotheses is evident from the follow-
ing considerations:
1st. An hypothesis, though un verifiable, may be use-
ful in affording a probable explanation of phenomena
otherwise inexplicable. The hypothesis of an attenuated
medium called ether pervading space, accounting for the
transmission of light from the stars, is an example of
an hypothesis of this kind.
2d. An hypothesis may be useful in affording an ex-
planation, which, though conjectural, may afterwards be
verified. Kepler discovered the laws of planetary revo-
lution by making various hyj)otheses, some of which he
afterwards verified.
3d. An hypothesis, though it prove false, may be use-
390 PSYCHOLOGY,
ful in leading to another which may be verified. Kep-
ler made no less than nineteen different hypotheses of
planetary motion before he discovered the truth.
4th. An hypothesis may be useful in colligating and
distinguishing the phenomena to be explained, thus di-
recting the course of investigation, and preventing a
waste of time and labor.
The formation of hypotheses is due largely to the im-
agination ; but as the inventions of this fertile faculty
are not all worthy of the highest confidence, it is im-
portant to guard against a hasty acceptance of a plaus-
ible h3q3othesis.
The characteristics of hypotheses worthy of considera-
tion are the following:
1st. An hypothesis should be probably or at least
possibly true.
2d. An hypothesis should, if possible, be of such a
nature as to admit of verification or refutation, or at
least of being rendered, by subsequent investigation,
more or less probable.
3d. An hyjDOthesis should be capable of accounting for
all the phenomena, without exception.
The hypothesis which possesses these characteristics
may be accepted, provisionally, as true, subject, of course,
to subsequent verification or refutation. The hypothesis
which affords, at the same time, an explanation of differ-
ent classes of facts, has a very high probability of truth.
The only possible hypothesis which can account for
the phenomena must be accepted as the true explana-
tion. Such an hypothesis has the force of an intuition.
The following example will serve as an illustration
of an hypothesis considered verified : To account for the
deflection of the path of a planet from a straight line,
Newton assumed a force directed towards the center of
the sun. He then showed that the action of such a force
LOGICAL INDUCTION—SUBSIDIARIES, 391
oa a planet, in connection with its projectile force, is
the only force which could cause the radius vector of the
planet to describe equal areas in equal times — a fact
already known as one of Kepler's laws; hence, the hy-
pothesis of a force directed towards the sun is regarded
as established. It does not follow^, however, that the
sun exerts this force, that is, attracts or draws the
planet towards himself The force may possibly be due
to currents of ether running in towards the sun.
Newton also assumed that the deflecting force varies
inversely as the square of its distance from the sun, and
proved that this is the only supposition wdiich would
account for Kepler's second and third laws— facts al-
ready known; hence this hypothesis is also to be re-
garded as verified. It is remarkable that this would be
the law, if the deflecting force is due to currents of
ether setting in towards the sun,
5. Analogy is the likeness of relations, or the resem-
blance of two things, from which we infer that an addi-
tional fact known of one is probably true of the other.
The conditions to be complied w^ith in reasoning from
analogy are the following:
Ist. The objects compared must agree in certain re-
spects.
2d. The attributes observed should be positive and
essential, and not negative and accidental.
The conclusion is only probable; but this probability
is increased in proportion to the number of congruent
attributes; to the importance of the congruent attributes;
to the number and accuracy of the observations.
The following is an example of analogical reasoning:
A has the attributes p, ^, r, and s.
L has the attributes p^ q, r,
.'. L probably has the attribute s.
392 PSYCHOLOGY.
This argument can be refuted, if it can be shown :
Ist. That s is the effect of some cause found in A but
not in L.
2d. That there are present with ^ and absent from X,
certain circumstances which are indispensable to s.
3d. That L has attributes incompatible with s.
4th. That the circumstances attending L prevent the
existence of s.
As a concrete illustration of an argument from anal-
ogy, and a counter argument, take the following:
The earth is an opaque solid, nearly spherical^ derives
its light and heat from the sun, and is inhabited.
The moon is an opaque solid, nearly spherical, derives
its light and heat from the sun. Therefore, the moon
is probably inhabited.
If the points of agreement are equally likely to be
the conditions of life, the probability that the moon is
inhabited would vary directly as the number of such
points of agreement.
The points of difference, that the moon is only a sec-
ondary, that it is smaller and more rugged, that it re-
volves on its axis but once in twenty-eight daj^s, that it
has no atmosphere and no water, present a counter
probability that it is not inhabited; and this counter
probability is strengthened, when we reflect that some
of the circumstances wanting on the moon, such as air
and water, are indispensable conditions of life on the
earth; we must, therefore, conclude either that the
moon is not inhabited at all or that the conditions on
which life depends on the moon are totally different from
the conditions on which life depends on the earth. The
conditions of life on the moon being, therefore, different
from those on the earth, if they exist at all, the more
points of resemblance established between the moon and
the earth, the indispensable conditions of life which exist
LOGICAL INDUCTION—SUBSIDIARIES. 393
on the earth being wanting in the moonj the less the
probability of the supposed different conditions, and con-
sequently, the less the probability that the moon is in-
habited.
Analogical arguments, if not refuted, may be usefully
employed in showing the reasonableness of the conclusion ;
in removing prejudice; in silencing objections; in pre-
paring the mind for direct argument.
6. Classification and denomination are also subsidiary
to induction; but these have been sufficiently treated in
chapters II-Y. of this division.
The distinction between knowledge and belief may be
profitably considered in this connection.
Knowledge implies that a truth be correctly expressed
by a proposition; that this proposition be clearly ap-
prehended; that the truth of the proposition, if primitive,
be known by intuition, either empirical or rational; that
the truth of the proposition, if derivative, be based on
grounds whose truth is known by intuition or is logically
derived from other grounds ultimately known by intui-
tion.
Belief implies a proposition based on probability ; and
this probability may vary between the limits, known
actuality and known impossibility, without ever reaching
either limit; for if it reach either limit, the belief is
transformed into knowledge, either of the truth or of
the falsity of the proposition.
CHAPTEE XXIV.
INDUCTIVE REASONING.
Logical induction is the process of discovering that
a certain thing is true of parts of a class, and thence
inferring that the same thing is true of the whole class.
Mathematical induction generalizes its common fact,
or proves it to be a law by showing that if it hold for
any instance, it holds for the next; but logical induction
passes from the parts to the w^hole, without the inter
vention of a conditional principle.
Logical induction is divided into two varieties — per-
fect, or demonstrative, when all the instances are ex-
amined; and imperfect, or probable, when only a part
of the instances are examined.
1. Perfect induction is the process of establishing a
general proposition by an examination of all the par-
ticular instances. By discovering that a certain thing is
true of all the parts, we prove that the same thing is
true of the whole. The following are examples:
By examination, we find that A has the property P,
that B lias P, that C has P, and that D has P; but A,
B^ C, and D constitute the class E ; therefore, all of the
class BJ have the property P.
In geometry, sc proposition involving several cases is
proved to be true for each case, and hence to be uni-
versally true. The reasoning in each case may be de-
ductive ; but the method of establishing the general prop-
osition by establishing its truth in each case, is essen-
tially inductive.
(394)
LOGICAL INDUCTION. 395
Some logicians assert that what is called perfect in-
duction is not induction at all, since, after finding that
a certain thing is true of every case, nothing remains
but to sum up and state, in one general proposition,
what is already known. But the process in question
conforms to the definition of induction, since, from the
discovery of what is true of the parts, it establishes w4mt
is true of the whole. Whether we examine all the in-
stances or only a part of them, is not essential to in-
duction itself, though it affords the discriminating char-
acteristic by which we divide induction into perfect and
imperfect. Perfect induction is the limiting case of im-
perfect induction. The same general formula which
expresses the degree of probability of the conclusion in
imperiect induction, expresses, as will be shown here-
after, the certainty of the conclusion in perfect induc-
tion, thus showing, beyond question, that the two are
sj^ecies of the same genus
In perfect induction, the finding that a certain fact
is true in the particular instances, does not warrant the
certainty of the general conclusion, that it is true in
all the instances, unless it is also known that the in-
stances in which the fact is found true are all the in-
stances.
The minor premise does not assert that the fact is true
of all the instances; for then it w^ould be identical with
the conclusion; but that the instances examined are all
the instances. The argument is not stated thus:
A has the property P, so has B, and (7, and D.
All of the individuals of the class E have P.
.-. All of the individuals of the class E have P.
This would be trifling; but the statement is thus
396 PSYCHOLOGY,
A lias the property P, so has B and C and D.
But Aj B^ Cj D are the whole of the class E.
.'. All of the class JS have P.
Perfect induction is applicable to those cases in which
the instances are few in number and accessible.
2. Imperfect induction is the process of inferring tlie
probability of a general proposition from an examina-
tion of some of the particular instances. The following
is an example:
By examination^ we find that A has the property P,
so has By and (7^ and D. . . . . But A, B, C, D, are some
individuals of the class P; therefore, all of the class JE
probably have the property P.
This conclusion is logical so long as it is stated to be
only probable; but it would be illogical if it were stated
as certain.
The following examples will serve to illustrate the
difference between perfect and imperfect induction , the
first being perfect, the second imperfect:
Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., all move round
the sun from west to east; but Mercury, Venus, the
Earth, Mars, etc., are all the known planets; therefore,
all the known planets move round the sun from west to
east.
Mercury, Venus, the Earth, Mars, etc., all move round
the sun from west to east; but Mercury, Venus, the
Earth, Mars, etc., are all the known planets; therefore,
all the planets probably move round the sun from west
to east.
Whether the induction be perfect or imperfect, there
must be no exceptions in the cases examined.
No doubt that in perfect induction, before all the cases
are examined, the mind jumps to the conclusion, or
infers the general proposition by an imperfect induction,
LOGICAL INDUCTION, 397
and then by a perfect induction verifies its conclusion.
In an imperfect induction, the conclusion remains un-
verified.
A comparison of Probable induction and Analogy leads
to the following results:
Ist. By probable induction we infer that if many ob-
jects of a class have a common quality, all the objects
of that class probably have that quality; that is, an at-
tribute known to be present in a part of the extent of
a class is inferred as probably present in the whole ex-
tent of that class.
2d. By analogy we infer that two objects agreeing in
certain respects, probably agree in other respects; that
is, an attribute known to be a part of the content of
one of two objects whose contents agree in many com-
mon qualities, is inferred as probably a part of the con-
tent of the other object.
3d. Probable induction and analogy agree in the fact
that they give only probable conclusions, and that the
degree of the probability may vary between the limits,
impossibility and certainty, without ever reaching either
limit.
4th. There is, however, a most intimate relation be-
tween induction and analogy, which we now proceed to
point out. Eeasoning by induction is essentially the
same as reasoning from analogy, but with this modifica-
tion — that in simple analogy, we reason from one of
the objects of a class to another object of that class,
whereas in induction, we reason from several objects of
a class to the remaining objects of the class, thus in-
creasing the probability of the inference, by increasing
the extent of the evidence, and diminishing the proba-
bility of the inference, by increasing the extent of the
conclusion.
Let A and L be two objects of a class, each known
398 PSYCHOLOGY,
to have the qualities, p^ q; r, and let A also be known
to have the quality 5, then we infer that L probably
has the quality s. This is reasoning from analogy. The
argument is not, that because we have found s combined
with p, q^ r, in many objects of the class, we shall, there-
fore, find s combined with p, q, r, in L; but that because
we have found that A and L agree in possessing so
many qualities, ^, q^ r, in common, we may likewise
find any quality, s, which is in A^ also in L. The ar-
gument is based on the number of qualities common to
the two objects, A and i, and not on the number of
objects having the common qualities.
ISTow, if another object 5, of the same class, has the
same qualities, p^ q^ r, how would the probability that L
has s be affected, if it is also found that B has sf The
probability of the inference that L has s would evidently
be strengthened by finding that B has s. Here we be-
gin to pass from analogy to induction, not on the side
of the conclusion, but on that of the evidence, by in-
creasing its extent.
The probability that L has s is likewise strengthened
every time we find in the class an object, (7, D, j^, . . .
having not only the qualities, p, q^ r, but also s.
So far we have strengthened analogy, increasing the
probability of the inference by increasing the extent of
the evidence, and the process becomes inductive with
respect to the evidence, but not with respect to the con-
clusion.
Let there be, in the same class, another object i¥,
having the qualities, p, q^ r, and differing from L in no
essential circumstance. The probability that M has s is
evidently equal to the probability that L has s; hence,
we can infer with the same probability that any other
object, iV, Oj P, . . . not differing essentially from i, and
having the qualities, p, g, r, and belonging to that class,
LOGICAL INDUCTION. 399
has the quality 5. We still have, so long as we restrict
the conclusion to one of the objects, Jv, Jf, O, P, . . . only
a strengthened analogy, inductive as to the evidence, but
not with respect to the conclusion.
Now, if we infer that all the remaining objects, X, Jf,
Nj 0, P, . . . known to have p, q, r, and belonging to that
class, have the quality s, we reason by induction, both
with respect to the evidence and the conclusion. But
is the ^probability of the inference the same as before,
or is it strengthened or weakened? In other w^ords,
how does the probability that all the remaining objects,
L, M, N, . , , of the class have the quality s, compare
wdth the probability that any one of them, as X, has
this quality? The probability that all have s is evi-
dently less than that any one of them has s; for, since
there is a chance of failure in each instance, there is
greater probability that there will be failure when all
the instances are considered than when only one is con-
sidered.
To estimate this probability, it is necessary to discuss
briefly the doctrine of chances, including simple and com-
pound probability.
Thus, if there be a vase, containing m white "and n
black balls, what will be the probability of drawing a
white ball?
There are m -f ^ chances of which m are favorable ;
. m
hence, the probabilitv of drawing; a white ball is
^ -^ . m + n
Hence the measure of a simple probability is equal to
the number of favorable chances divided by the whole
m
number of chances. Since m<^ ni -[- n.— << 1 ; hence,
m -|- ^^
a simple probability is less than 1.
If in another vase, there are t red and u blue balls.
400 PSYCHOLOGY.
. t
the probability of drawing a red ball is . If 2^ = 0,
Jj — — u
the probabilitj^ of drawing a red ball becomes — =^1,
the symbol of certainty
Now, if a ball be drawn from each vase, what is the
probability that we shall have a white and a red ball?
Combining the balls in the two vases, in sets of two,
any one of the m -\- n balls can be combined with any
one of t -\-u balls, giving (jn -\- n) (t ^ u) ^^mt -\~ m u -^
nt-\-nu possible chances, of which mt are favorable;
hence, by the law of simple probability, the probability of
mt
drawing a white and a red ball is =
mt-\-mu-\-nt-\-nu
m t
X = the product of the simple probabilities.
m -f 71 t^u
Hence, the compound probability of the joint occurrence
of two chances is the product of their simple probabili-
ties. In like manner, it can be shown that the proba-
bility of the joint occurrence of any number of chances is
the product of their simple probabilities.
To return from this digression, let the probability that
X X
L has s be denoted by — ) then — will also express the
probability, that any one of the objects, M.^ JV, 0, , . . has s.
Let n denote the number of the objects, L^M^N^... Then
since the compound probability that all of these objects,
Jj, M, N, . . . have s is the product of the simple proba-
bilities that they severally have s, we have for the com-
pound probability that all have s,
rp rp >y^ I /)•» I'H nr* rv*
\Aj %A~f tX' * tA/ y cA-/ xAj
— X — X ~~ • • • =1 — I 5 which is less than ^, since — < 1.
y y y \ y J y y
Since A^ B^ C, D . . . up to X are known to have s, the
LOGICAL INDUCTION, 401
probability that all the objects of the class have s is
(X y
— I • This probability increases as the number of
y I
objects of the class known to have 5, increases, that is,
as 71 diminishes; it becomes certainty when n=:0; but
then the induction becomes perfect, since the objects
known to have s are all the objects of the class.
The increase of probability as n diminishes, is due to
two causes — the extent of evidence is increased, and
(X Y
— I
y I
exhibits the law, since as more and more of the objects
X
of the class are found to have s, — increases and ap-
y
proaches 1, and n diminishes and approaches 0, and both
these changes conspire to increase I — j . When all the
X
objects are found to have 5,-=^ = !, the symbol of cer-
tainty, and ?z = 0, and we shall have 1^=^1, or the in-
duction is perfect.
/ X Y
Since the expression, I ~~ I , which denotes the proba-
bility of the conclusion in imperfect induction, gives the
certainty of the conclusion in perfect induction, the two
cases are connected by the same law ; hence, perfect in-
duction, so far from not being induction at all, as some
logicians assert, is the limiting case of imperfect induc-
tion; in other words, perfect induction and imperfect
induction are the two species of the genus logical in-
duction.
Pry.— 34.
CHAPTEE XXY.
INDUCTIVE REASONING.
From the fundamental agreement of induction and
analogy, it follows that the ground of induction will be
found, if we find the ground of analogy.
According to the law of association, p^ q^ r, in L would
suggest 5, since s is found in connection with p^ q^ r, in
A; but this is merely the occasion of the suggestion,
and not the ground of the inference.
The ground of the induction is not found by throw-
ing the induction into a syllogism, as Whately does,
as thus exhibited :
Whatever belongs to the individuals examined belongs
to the whole class under which they come.
s belongs to the individuals examined.
.-. s belongs to the whole class.
Observe that in the major premise the predication is
made of every quality found in the individuals exam-
ined, and not simply of the one quality 5. The major
premise having, therefore, a wider subject than the con-
clusion, a subject including that of the conclusion, is less
probable, since it is more probable that any one quality
.s found in connection with jp, ^, r, in A^ will also be
found in connection with ^, ^, r, in i, than that every
quality found in connection with p, ^, r, in A will also
be found in connection with j9, q. r, in L. The wider
induction of the major premise being less probable than
the narrower induction of the conclusion, is more diffi-
( 402 )
[ THE GBOUND OF INDUCTION. 403
cult to establish, and can not, therefore, be taken for
the proof of the conclusion, which is more evident than
the major premise itself. If, however, the major prem-
ise can be rendered probable in an}^ degree hj evidence,
independent of the conclusion, it will follow that the
conclusion will be probable in a still higher degree.
But how is this major premise obtained, resolvable as
it seems to be into the uniformity of the laws of nature?
Whately replies, "Whether the belief in the constancy
of Nature's laws, — a belief of which no one can divest
himself — be intuitive, and a part of the constitution of
the human mind, as some eminent metaphysicians hold,
or acquired, and in what way acquired, is a question
foreign to our purpose.' It is evident that Whately
throws no light on the ground of induction.
Mill says, "'Whatever be the most proper mode of ex-
pressing it, the proposition, that the course of nature is
uniform, is the fundamental principle or general axiom
of induction. It would yet be a great error to offer this
large generalization as any explanation of the inductive
process. On the contrary, I hold it to be itself an in-
stance of induction, and induction by no means of the
most obvious kind. Far from being the first induction
we make, it is one of the last, or at all events, one of
those which are latest in attaining philosophical accuracy.
.... Yet this principle, though so far from being our
earliest induction, must be considered as our warrant
for all the others in this sense, that unless it were true
all other inductions would be fallaciou-s."
If the induction, that the course of nature is uniform,
is the latest induction, and is the warrant of all the
others, then these others are made without warrant, and
this so-called fundamental induction is itself without war-
rant. We have here the fallacv of the vicious circle.
Through the first inductions, made without warrant, we
404 PSYCHOLOGY,
work up to the final induction, that the course of nature
is uniform, and then take this generalization from un-
warranted inductions, as the warrant of those unwar-
ranted inductions of which it is the generalization.
Experience, including observation and experiment, in
furnishing the facts of analogy, has much to do with in-
duction. We have thus often found that, in couples of
objects having common qualities, an additional quality
found in one, is afterwards found in the other. An ex-
pectancy is thus awal^ened in other cases. The finding
of the objects A and i, having the common qualities,
j9, q^ r, is due to experience ; also the knowledge of the
fact that A has s; then by analogy we infer that L
probably has s. The strengthened analogy arising from
finding in the class containing A and i, other objects
B, C, Dj ... each having, not only p, q^ r, but also 5, is
likewise due to experience.
Other reasons than experience, however, seem to en-
ter into the ground of the induction, since, for the same
extent of experience, the induction is much more highly
probable in some cases than in others. In certain cases,
a single instance warrants an induction, with so high a
degree of probability as to approach certaintj^ ; while in
other cases, many instances are scarcely sufficient to
warrant any induction at all, even of a low degree of
probability.
If s is an accident in A^ produced by circumstances
not attending Jj, and not by causes inherent in A, or
if the causes which produce s are inherent in A, but not
in iy, or if L has some attribute inconsistent with s^ or
if the circumstances attending L tend to prevent s, the
probability that Ij has s is greatly diminished^ if not
reduced to zero.
The common ground of analogy and induction is found
in the two following principles:
THE GR O UND OF IND UCTION. 405
(1) Every constant coincidence of phenomena has its
cause and its conditions.
(2) Like conditions and causes are followed by like
consequences.
The reason of the coincidence of the first principle is
that one phenomenon is the cause of the other, or that
they have a common cause or some causal relation.
The reason of the second principle is found in the fact
that the two cases are essentially alike, and whatever
determines the effect in the one case, is present to de-
termine it in the other.
These two principles, which are rational intuitions, fur-
nish the warrant for the induction that nature is uni-
form in her operations, the essential antecedents being,
by supposition, the same in the cases compared.
From the above principles, it follows that in the case
considered, the probability that L has s varies with the
probability that the conditions and causes connected
with L are essentially the same as those connected with
A. If this can be known with certainty, the conclusion
that L has s will also be certain; and if it is also cer-
tain that the same essential conditions and causes hold
for each of the remaining instances, M^ iV, ... of the
class, it will be equally certain that any one of these
instances, M^ N^ ... has s; that is, the expression for the
strength of the conclusion for each instance, which is
X
denoted by — becomes 1, the symbol for certainty;
y
hence, it is certain that all of the instances, L^M^N^ ...
have 5, since the probability in this case is 1 X 1 X 1 X
1 , . . = 1** = 1 = certainty.
To illustrate the above, take the case of the mathe-
matician who in proving the proposition, The square of
the hypotenuse of a right triangle is equivalent to the sum
of the squares of the other sides, draws a particular right
406 PSYCHOLOGY.
triangle and constructs a square on each of the three
sides; and assuming the constructions perfect, proves by
deductive reasoning that the square of the hypotenuse is
equivalent to the sum of the squares of the other sides.
He then concludes that the same is true for every right
triangle of which there is an infinite number, varying
in the relative proportion of their sides, and also in their
magnitude, from those too small to be seen with the
naked eye, to those whose sides are millions of miles in
extent. Here we seem to infer the widest possible in-
duction from a single instance; but the reason which
determines the consequent is the same in everj^ instance.
The proof does not turn on the relative length of the
sides, nor on their magnitude, but solely on the fact
that the triangle is right angled, and hence holds true
for any triangle which conforms to this hypothesis, and,
therefore, for all such triangles. Hence, the strength of
the general conclusion is 1"° = 1 = certainty. The truth
of the proposition, for the figure drawn, is not deter-
mined experimentally, as that would be impossible ex-
actl}^ to do; but it is determined deductively; and since
like reasons hold for every like case, the proposition
is true for every particular case, and hence for all cases,
and is, therefore, universally true.
We are now able to see how mathematical reasoning is
characterized by demonstrative certainty — its facts are
definite, and its processes strictly logical; it keeps the
essential facts clearly in view, and disregards those that
are not essential. Since the essential antecedent condi-
tions are the same in each of the infinity of possible
instances, and the conclusion is demonstrated for one,
it is certain for any other, and hence is true for all. •
Pascal has remarked, that '' Geometry is almost the
only subject as to which we find truths wherein all men
agree; and one cause of this is, that geometers alone
THE GROUND OF INDUCTION. 407
regard the true laws of demonstration." These are the
following :
" 1st. To define nothing which can not be expressed
in clearer terms than those in which it is already ex-
pressed.
"2d. To leave no obscure or equivocal terms undefined.
"3d. To employ in the definition, no terms not already
known.
"4th. To omit nothing in the principles from which we
argue, unless we are sure it is granted.
"5th. To lay down no axiom which is not perfectly
self-evident.
"6th. To demonstrate nothing which is already as clear
as it can be made.
"7th. To prove every thing in the least doubtful by
means of self-evident axioms, or of propositions already
demonstrated.
"8th. To substitute mentally the definition instead of
the thing defined."
These principles are of especial application in deduc-
tion; but they have their bearing upon induction, since
deduction is often employed in establishing the particu-
lar instances which are used in inferring the general
proposition of induction.
In cases not mathematical, the probability of the gen-
eral proposition approaches certainty in proportion as
the antecedents in the cases compared approach essential
identity. This exj)lains why, in certain cases, as in
chemistry, a very few experiments warrant an induction
of very high probability, if not certainty, whereas, in
other cases, as in natural history, many observations
give to the induction but a moderate degree of proba-
bility. Thus, it was thought to be a well established
induction, that all swans are white; but black swans
were afterwards found in Australia.
408 PSYCHOLOGY.
Since, in the inductions of nature, we can never be
absolutely certain from observation that the conditions
and causes are essential!}' alike, the induction can never
be absolutely certain, but at best can possess only a high
degree of probability.
The methods of conducting experimental inquiry have
been elaborately discussed hj Mr. Mill under the desig-
nation of the Method of Agreement, the Method of Dif-
ference, the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference,
the Method of Residues, and the Method of Concomitant
Variations.
The reader is referred to MilVs Logic ^ Chapter VIII.,
and to Fowler's Inductive Logic, Chapter III. See also
Jevon's LogiCj Lessons XXVII. to XXXI.
CHAPTEE XXVI.
MODERN LOGIC.
1. Hamilton, by the quantification of the predicate,
made eight propositions, four of which are ambiguous:
( U) All S is all P.
©
{A) All S is some P.
( r) Some S is all P.
(7) Some S is some P.
©
V
8{ P
(IE) Any /? is not any P. [ .s ] ( T \
Psy.-35 (409)
410
PSYCHOLOGY.
(7j) Any S is not some P.
(0) Some S is not any P. >
( a>) Some >S is not some P.
In Hamilton's scheme, botli (A) and (Y) express the
relation of subordination. In {A)^ the subordinate con-
cept is the subject, but in (F), the subordinate concept
is the predicate; but since we can, if we choose, always
take the subordinate concept for the subject, we shall,
in the following scheme, treat (A) and (Y) as one.
2. Definite deduetion.— In definite deduction the prop-
ositions are all definite, each expressing but one relation
between the subject and the predicate.
There are only four possible relations between two
terms in extensive quantity- — co-extension, exclusion,
subordination, and intersection. Definite propositions
are obtained by expressing these relations.
Let the initial letters, ((7), (-E^), (aS), (/), respectively,
MODERN LOGIC,
411
express the relations of co-extension, exclusion, subordi-
nation, and intersection. Then we have the following
definite propositions:
((7) aS is co-extensive with P.
(E) S is excluded from P.
S
(/S) /S is subordinate to P.
(/) S intersects P.
The laws warranting the conclusions, ((7), (i^), (aS),
(/), may be stated and exemplified thus:
1st. The relation of co-extension is warranted in the con-
clusion^ if each extreme is co-extensive with the middle
term.
!P is co-extensive with M.
S is co-extensive with M.
.\ S is co-extensive with P.
Let the argument be stated in the other figures.
2d. The relation of exclusion is icarranted in the conclu-
sion^ if either extreme is either subordinate to, or co-extensive
with, the middle, and the other extreme is excluded from the
middle.
P is subordinate to Jf.
(1) -l S is excluded from M.
S is excluded from P.
\:
412
PSYCHOLOGY.
P is excluded from M.
(2) -] aS is subordinate to M.
..'. S is excluded from P.
P is co-extensive with M.
(3) ^ /§ is excluded from M,
,-. S is excluded from P.
P is excluded from M.
(4) } S is co-extensive with M,
.'. S is excluded from P.
3d. T/ie relation of subordination is warranted in the
conclusion^ if the middle term is subordinate to the major,
and the minor to the middle; or if the middle is co-exten-
sive with the major, and the minor is subordinate to the
middle; or if the middle is subordinate to the major, and
the minor is co-extensive with the middle.
M is subordinate to P.
(1) ■< aS is subordinate to M.
.'. S is subordinate to P.
M is co-extensive with P.
(2) ^ >S is subordinate to M.
.-. S is subordinate to P.
M is subordinate to P.
(3) -< aS is co-extensive with M.
.'. S is subordinate to P.
4th. The relation of intersection is warranted in the con-
clusion, if the middle term is co-extensive with one extreme
and intersects the other.
I
<*.i
1'
MODERN LOGIC.
413
M is co-extensivo with P.
(1) \ S intersects M.
.-. S intersects P.
M intersects P.
(2) ^ /S is co-extensive with M.
■. 8 intersects P.
Let us now restate the above syllogisms in the brief-
est possible manner, by using (C) for is co-extensive with,
(_JE) for is excluded from, (S) for is subordinate to, and
(7) for intersects. Then we have
P (C) M.
8 (C) M.
.: 8 (C) P.
P (8) M.
8 {E) M.
.: 8 (E) P.
M (8) P.
8 (8) M.
.: 8 (8) P.
M (C) P.
8 (I) M.
.: 8 (I) P.
Illustrate this and the following by circles.
P (E) M.
8 {8) M.
8 (E) P.
M (C) P.
8 (8) M.
8 (8) P.
M (7) P.
8 (C) M.
8 (7) P.
P (C) M.
8 (E) M.
8 (E) P.
M (8) P.
8 (C) M.
8 (8) P.
P (E)'M.
8 (C) M.
.: 8 (E) P.
This method is remarkable for clearness, precision, and
simplicity. The propositions are perfectly definite, each
denoting but one relation.
{A), (7), (0) in Aristotle's sj^stem, and (7), (jj),
(0), (e Morgan, Boole, and Jevons are
worthy of attention. For a knowledge of these systems,
we refer to the works of these authors.
i
PART II.
FEELING AND THE SENSIBILITY,
(415)
CHAPTER I.
PHYSICAL FEELINGS.
Feelings are agitations of the soul. They embrace
all those phenomena of the soul not included in cogni-
tions and volitions. In feeling, the soul is chiefly j^as-
sive in the reception of an incitement, but is involunta-
rily active in its response.
The feelings may be roughly classified as physical,
vital, and psychical.
The physical feelings are those especially related to
the organism, as sensations, instincts, and appetites.
The vital feelings are those which are especially re-
lated to the vitality or health of the organism, as a
sense of rest or fatigue, of vigor or languor, and of
health or sickness.
The psychical feelings are those especially related to
the soul, as emotions, affections, and desires.
The word feeling^ as a generic term, includes all these
phenomena, and is, therefore, the term needed; whereas,
the word emotion^ used by Dr. McCosh, is too specific,
since it includes only a part.
The feelings imply the sensibility or susceptibility of
feeling. Without the sensibility, as a faculty or suscep-
tibility, feeling, as a phenomenon, would be impossible.
The susceptibility of experiencing any specific feeling is
called an appetence.
The feelings also imply causes^ external or internal,
physical or psychical, real or ideal, which excite them
and call them forth as phenomena of consciousness.
(417)
418
PSYCHOLOGY,
Cognitions tend to excite feeling, and the wider the
sweep of the cognitions, the wider the range of the ob-
jects concerning which feeling may arise; but there is
no necessary ratio between the strength of the intellect
and the intensity of feeling.
The feelings are also more or less intimately related
to certain organic affections, either as causes or as effects.
We then have feelings as phenomena of consciousness,
the appetencies implied by these feelings, the exciting
causes, and the organic affections.
The physical feelings have been defined as those es-
pecially related to the organism, and classified as sensa-
tions, instincts, and appetites.
1. Sensations are those feelings which are occasioned
by the excitement of some portion of the organism,
caused, in normal cases, by the action of a stimulus.
Since sensation has already been discussed as the con-
dition of perception^ it will suffice, in this connection,
to give a brief summary^ and assign it to its place
among the feelings.
The conditions of sensation are the sensorium consist-
ing of the nervous system and sense organs, excitants or
objects capable of exciting the sensorium, the action of
excitants on the sensorium, and the sensibility or general
susceptibility of feeling.
Sensations are, in general, localized, definitely or vaguely,
that is, are referred to the part of the sensorium affected.
In certain instances, the location of the sensation is
quite definite, but in other instances it is only vaguely
apprehended.
The object of consciousness in sensation is neither the
sensorium excited, nor the external excitant, but the
sensation itself as a state of the sensibility.
The quality of sensation involves existence as opposed
to non-existence, and identity, or the fact that the sen-
PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 419
sation is itself and nothing else, involving peculiarity,
or the positive characteristics of the sensation, and par-
ticularity, or the negation of the positive characteristics
of any other thing.
The quantity of a sensation involves its degree of in-
tensity ^ varying between the limits zero and a degree so
great as to be insupportable, its temporal relations of
date and duration, and its spatial relations of locality,
and, in some instances at least, but more vaguely, of
extent and form.
Complex sensations only are capable of analysis, which
may be effected, in some cases, by reflection alone, but
in other cases, only by the aid of experiment.
Sensations are identified or discriminated as similar or
dissimilar in kind, according as they are acquired through
the same sense or through different senses.
Sensations are identified or discriminated as similar or
dissimilar in variety, according as they involve similar
or dissimilar qualities.
Sensations similar in kind may be similar or dissimi-
lar in variety, but sensations dissimilar in kind are also
dissimilar in variety.
Sensations similar in kind and variety may agree or
differ in degree of intensity or in temporal or s^Datial
relations, and, as such, may accordingly be" identified or
discriminated.
Sensations are classified as to kind, w^hen referred to
the organs or senses through w^hich they are acquired.
They are subdivided both as to quality and quantity.
Agreeable or pleasurable sensations are those w^hich
arise from normal excitement of the sensorium ; and dis-
agreeable or painful sensations are those which arise
from abnormal exciteme»nt of the sensorium.
The general sensations comprise all those connected
with the various portions of the organism, except the
420 PSYCHOLOGY.
five senses. They raay be divided into the muscular,
the nervous, the nutritive, the circulatory, and the re-
spiratory.
The special sensations are those connected with the
organs of the five senses, — smell, taste, touch, hearing,
and sight.
2. Instincts are blind tendencies to actions, having for
their ends the physical well-being of the individual or
of the species.
The actions prompted by instinct are automatic in
their impulses, though, in form, apparently intelligent
and voluntary. They occupy the border territory be-
tween the purely automatic movements below, as the
beating of the heart, and the rational activities above, as
in reasoning.
The instincts have their basis and spring in the spon-
taneous movements of the living organism. By the ev-
olutionist, they are regarded as habits — not as acquired
habits, induced by the actions of the individual, but as
hereditary habits, organized and embodied in the phys-
ical constitution, and manifested as reflex actions of a
more or less complicated character. The truth probably
is that they have their origin in the constitution of the
species as formed by the Creator, modified by inherited
habits formed through successive generations and organ-
ized in the physical constitution.
Though instincts are directed towards ends, there is
no reason for supposing that these ends are clearly con-
ceived or deliberately aimed at by the individual. The
brute is, no doubt, blind to the end, though his actions
are directed towards the end with as much precision as
if it were clearly apprehended and deliberately pur-
sued.
The end of instinctive actions is the j^hysical well-
being of the individual or of the race, designed and se-
PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 421
cured by the Author of Nature, through the automatic
action of the organism.
The instincts may be classed as follows :
1st. Those relating to subsistence, as in procuring,
storing, and eating food.
2d. Those relating to the propagation of the species,
as pairing, building nests, and the care of the young.
3d. Those of a more general nature, as hybernation
and migration, excited by causes internal and external.
Instincts have the following characteristics:
1st. Through organic states, they blindly prompt to
actions w^hose end is the physical well-being of the in-
dividual or of the species. That the actions prompted
by instinct are blindly directed and not the result of
reflective intelligence is illustrated by the fact that a
hen will sit as readily on stones as on eggs; that she
shows the same solicitude for the ducklings which she
has hatched as for the chickens from her own eggs; and
that when her ducklings take to the water, she manifests
great alarm, yet her eyes are not opened to the fact
that she is rearing the children of strangers. That in-
stinctive actions are prompted by organic conditions is
illustrated by the fact that a hen determined to sit may
be cured of this propensity by dipping her breast sev-
eral times in cold water.
2d. The instinctive actions are always performed by
individuals of the same species in essentially the same
way without the guide of experience or education.
Thus, young mammalia are impelled to suck their
mother's breasts; the young chick to pick up a grain of
wheat at first sight; the young robin to open its mouth
to receive the food which its mother brings.
3d. The instincts, in certain cases, at least, act j)eri-
odically, corresponding to the wants of the individuals
or their offspring. Thus, the old birds care for their
422 PSYCHOLOGY.
young till they ure fully fledged, and then leave them
to care for themselves.
4th. The instincts are not rigidly fixed but are, within
certain limits, plastic, varying with the physical struct-
ure of the individuals, and accommodating themselves,
to a certain extent, to the modifications of external cir-
cumstances, thus enabling the individual to adapt itself
to its environment. Thus, a hen will sit more than
three weeks to hatch the eggs of turkeys or geese, or
less than three weeks to hatch those of quails. Under
domestication, instincts are modified — in some cases in-
tensified, in other cases weakened, so that it might ap-
pear that certain instincts are acquired, and others lost.
Thus, animals can be taught many things they do not
know by nature, and which they will continue to do as
if from instinct.
The conditions for the manifestation of instinct are
stimuli, external or internal, which incite the impulsive
action of the organism. Thus, a young dog of sufficient
age will bark at a stranger, though he has never barked
before or heard any other dog bark. Birds of passage,
incited by the increasing cold of autumn, take flight for
warmer climes.
Examples of instinctive actions may be found in the
construction of the spider's web, birds nests, and honey
comb, and in hibernation and migration.
As we rise in the scale of being, instinct diminishes
and intelligence increases till we reach man, who, though
exhibiting traces of instinct, is especially characterized,
not by instinct, but by reason.
The difierence between man and the lower animals is
strikingly apparent:
Ist. Animals, in caring for their oflfepring, are con-
cerned alone with their physical wants, and with these,
only till they are able to care for themselves; whereas.
PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 423
the solicitude of human parents for their children ex-
tends also to their intellectual, social, moral, and spirit-
ual welfare, and continues unabated till the end of life.
2d. The thinking of animals, if thinking it may be
called, is from particulars to particulars; whereas, man
generalizes his ideas into concepts, and proves general
propositions.
3d. Animals have no language but the instinctive one
prompted by nature; while man has developed an arti-
ficial language, both spoken and written, admirably adap-
ted to meet his present requirements, and to provide
for unlimited advancement.
4th. As to knowledge, animals are stationary, except
within narrow limits in the training they receive in
domestication, while man is progressive without appar-
ent limit.
5th. Animals are destitute of moral and religious
faculties, which are the crow^ning glory cf man.
6th. The training of animals has been accomplished
by man, but this training is only within a very narrow
range; and w^hen withdrawn, the animal relapses into
its original condition. This renders the view that man
is the development of an order of animals, very im-
probable. There was no higher race to train him. He
is indeed a high order of animal — a rational animal, a
moral animal, a noble animal, but he was created so, as
we must conclude, if we regard the facts of the case, to
say nothing of the teachings of revelation.
3. Appetites are the cravings prompted by the recur-
ring wants of organic life.
Appetites are distinguished from sensations by their
periodicity and by the fact that they are cravings di-
rected to the end of satisfying wants, natural or artifi-
cial, while sensations may occur at any time and are
not characterized as craving's.
424 PSYCHOLOGY.
Appetites are distinguished from instincts by the fact
that they are feelings consciously impelling to their
gratification as an immediate end, though undoubtedly
they have an ulterior end in the good of the individual
or of the species, while instincts unconsciously prompt to
actions which secure results that are only means to ul-
terior ends. Thus, the spider is incited by instinct to
weave his web, but by appetite to eat his prey.
The appetites are illustrated by the following crav-
ings — for sleep, for exercise, for rest, for food or drink.
The periodicity of the appetite for sleep is notorious.
After a certain period of wakefulness, there is a craving
for sleep, which becomes more resistless the longer it
is frustrated, unless determined effort or a new excite-
ment causes a reaction, which may, for a time, dispel
drowsiness.
The craving for the alternations of exercise and rest
have the character of appetite, though in a less marked
degree. After toil, physical or mental, there is a craving
for rest ; and, after sufficient rest, there is a prompting to
activity. It should, however, be kept in mind that the
function of rest is to recruit exhausted energy, and to
prepare it for further action. Though there is satisfac-
tion in rest, when it is needed, yet the pleasure it affords
is by no means so exhilarating as that which springs
from the normal activity of vigorous powers.
Hunger and thirst afford the best examples of appe-
tites. These are familiar on account of their frequent
occurrence and decided character. Mr. Bain well says,
" In the case of hunger, there is a double spur to the
taking of food; first, the stimulus of uneasiness, and
next, the impulse arising out of the pleasure of eating.
It is well understood that these two things are quite
different, and on their difference hangs the whole art
of refined cookery. Yery plain food would satisfy the
PHYSICAL FEELINGS. 425
craving for nutrition, but there is a superadded pleas-
ure that we have to cater for." Senses and Intellect,
page 243.
The appetites have the following characteristics:
1st. They are physical as to their origin, conditions,
and immediate ends.
2d. They are not continuous but periodical in their
manifestations.
3d. As craving, or sense of want, they involve uneas-
iness or discomfort, and their gratification is attended
with satisfaction or pleasure.
4th. The end of appetite is both immediate satisfac-
tion and ulterior good, either to the individual or to
the species.
Appetites may also be considered as natural or ac-
quired. The natural appetites are the gifts of God, and
may be innocently gratified, in due moderation, if in
their gratification no moral law is violated.
The excessive gratification of appetite leads to slug-
gishness, gluttony, debauchery, and degradation.
Acquired appetites are modifications of natural ap-
petites, directed towards specific objects. In certain
cases, they are harmless, as when the appetite is culti-
vated for a certain kind of food, as tomatoes, not at
first relished. More frequently the acquired appetites
are harmful, as those disgusting and degrading appetites
for tobacco, opium, and intoxicating drinks. These ap-
petites become morbid and well nigh uncontrollable.
Even the natural appetites for food and drink may be
indulged to excess, leading to gluttony, a vice more re-
spectable than drunkenness, more common, and hence,
perhaps, more generally disastrous.
Acquired appetite may be transmitted, and thus be-
come hereditary — a fact which, in the case of vicious
appetites, ought to lead to reflection and reformation.
Psy.— 36.
426 PSYCHOL OGY,
Simple habits are powerful in their influence; but how
much more irresistible do they become when urged on
by the cravings of an insatiable appetite!
The cravings of appetite are guides to proper action
only in case the appetite is natural or unperverted.
Diseased or perverted appetites should never be gratified,
or rather they never should be acquired; but whether
acquired by the individual, or inherited from his pro-
genitors, they should be corrected as soon as possible;
for the end thereof is death. It is discreditable to hu-
manity that perverted appetites are common among men,
but are rare, if not entirely unknown, among brutes.
As appetite may intensify and strengthen habit, so
may habit, acquired by forethought and persistent effort,
restrain, modify, or even overcome perverted appetite,
inherited or acquired. This fact affords a ground of
hope to those who are enslaved by degrading appetite.
It is possible to be free.
CHAPTBE 11.
VITAL FEELINGS.
The vital feelings are those feelings which are espe-
cially related to the vigor of the organism. They are
the feelings induced by the states of rest or fatigue,
vigor or languor, health or sickness, and by those
more permanent states called temperaments.
1. Rest and fatigue. — The feeling of rest comes as a
consequence of ceasing, for a time, from labor, and in-
dulging in repose. It is both agreeable and stimulating.
After due rest, there is felt an incentive to renewed
activity. This activity, if not excessive, is itself a source
of enjoyment, till the vitality accumulated in rest is so
far exhausted that demands are made on the reserve
forces of the system. Activity prolonged beyond this
point brings on a feeling of fatigue, which may be pro-
tracted till exhausted nature refuses longer to work,
when rest again becomes imperative. In practice, labor
is seldom carried to the point of exhaustion, but it is
frequently carried beyond the point where rest would
be beneficial.
2. Vigor and languor. — These states are analogous to
the preceding, but are, in general, of longer duration.
A man's general condition, for a protracted period, may
justly be described as vigorous; and yet, in this period,
he may experience many alternations of rest and fatigue.
Vigor is that general condition in which vitality pre-
dominates over decay. The feeling of vigor is exhilara-
ting, and impels to activity and achievement. Languor
(427) .
428 PSYCHOL OGY.
»
is a consequence of low vitality. The tone of the sys-
tem is relaxed, and there is a tendency to decay. The
feeling of languor is depressing, causing an aversion to
activity, and a desire for repose. It is the consequence
of more general conditions than those of a feeling of
fatigue, which may be induced by a few hours of labor,
and dispelled by a few hours of rest. It can be over-
come only by restoring tone to the system.
3. Health and sickness. — These are opposites. Health
is the state characterized by the felicitous performance
of the vital functions. It is the normal condition of a
human being. Sickness may be regarded as an ab-
normal condition of the living organism attending dis-
ease or injury. The feelings attending health are agree-
able and exhilarating, and, when invigorated by rest,
prompt to active exertion. The feelings attending sick-
ness are depressing, disagreeable, and often painful, even
to the limit of endurance. They are more marked than
those of health, since it is a law of human nature, that
the unusual and the abnormal are more noticeable than
the usual and the normal.
The feelings of sickness have also a far greater vari-
ety than those of health. Each of the innumerable mul-
titude of diseases has its special sj^mptoms, and is
attended by its peculiar feelings, which, to be realized,
must be experienced.
For a classification of diseases, and a description of
their symptoms and accompanying feelings, the reader
is referred to works on pathology.
4. Temperaments. — Temperament denotes an original
quality of the constitution supposed to be due to the
predominance of one or more of the vital systems — the
respiratory, the circulatory, the nutritive, the nervous,
and the muscular, modified also by the conditions and
relative proportion of the solids and fluids of the system.
VITAL FEELINGS,' 429
It is more fundamental and permanent in its influ-
ence than the preceding conditions, and its effects are
more difficult to trace.
1st. There are four simple temperaments — the sanguine,
the bilious, the lymphatic, and the nervous. Of these,
two have been regarded as primary, — the sanguine and
the bilious; and two as secondary, — the lymphatic and
the nervous, called also the encephalic. Even the bili-
ous has been by some regarded as a modification of the
sanguine, produced by external influences.
(1) The sanguine temperament is characterized by the
predominance of the respiratory and the circulatory
systems, whose centers are the lungs and heart. It is
indicated by a strong and rapid pulse, plump figure,
fair skin, light eyes, soft and light hair, approaching
red, a cheerful disposition, and a love for pleasure.
This is the prevailing temperament of the English peo-
ple. Combined with a well-developed muscular system,
it constitutes, in the absence of mental culture, the ath-
lete, a well developed animal with little mind.
(2) The bilious temperament, due to the predominance
of the nutritive system, is characterized by strong pulse ;
skin, hair, and eyes dark; flesh muscular rather than
fat, strong passions, inflexible wdll, and boldness of
character. This is the temperament of those born to
command.
(3) The lymphatic temperament results from the great
relative proportion of the fluids to the solids, in conse-
quence of the activity of the secreting system and the
inactivity of the absorbents. It is characterized by well-
rounded figure, shapeless person, adij)ose tissue, full
cheeks, flabby muscles, and soft skin. It is aggravated
by wealth, and begets a desire for an easy life, but is
not incompatible with many good qualities. It is the
temperament of a mandarin.
430 -PSYCHOLOGY,
(4) The nervous temperament is characterized by a
prominence of the nervous system. It is indicated by a
slender person, narrow chest, light hair, and mental
vigor. This is the usual temperament of the artist and
the scholar.
2d. The compound temperaments result from a union
of the simple temperaments, giving rise to binary, ter-
tiary, and quaternary combinations. They exhibit the
characteristics of their components mutually modified.
Of the compound temperaments, it will suffice to no-
tice the following:
(1) In the sanguine bilious temperament, the hair, the
eyes, and the complexion are light or dark, according to
the preponderance of one or the other of the compo-
nents. The head is compact, and the muscles are firm.
It is a good combination, and is found in many great
men, giviag them a natural superiority.
(2) In the sanguine lymphatic temperament, the per-
son is plump, the head round, the chest full, and the
complexion fair. Though it is frequently attended with
beauty of person, it is an unfavorable combination, tend-
ing rather to criminal pleasure than to noble achieve-
ment. It is favorably modified by an earnest life.
(3) In the sanguine nervous temperament, the person
is slight, head narrow, forehead high, the skin light, the
muscles feeble, the disposition amiable, and the charac-
ter too gentle for successful contests with the stern re-
alities of life. Persons of this temperament are better
fitted for the counting room than for the open field. '
(4) In the bilious lymphatic temperament, the person
is full, head rounded, hair and eyes dark, and the mus-
cles, though well developed^ rounded over with adipose
matter. Persons of this temperament are usually sound
in judgment, conservative in opinion, and prudent in
conduct.
VITAL FEELINGS. 431
(5) In the bilious nervous temperament, the person is
slender, the head high, the hair and eyes dark, and the
muscles firm though slender. Persons of this tempera-
ment are inclined to moral enterprises and to achieve-
ments which tend to advance the welfare of mankind.
(6) In the sanguine bilious lymphatic temperament, the
forehead is low and retreating, the lips thick, and the
form and disposition that of the prize-fighter.
(7) In the sanguine bilious nervous temperament, the
person is well formed, the head large, the forehead high
and expanded, indicating great physical and mental
power and fertility in resources.
(8) In the sanguine nervous lymphatic temperament, the
head is large, forehead high and broad, indicating great
capacity for literary pursuits, but less adaptation to the
external contests of life.
Marriage alliances contracted between persons of simi-
lar temperaments are supposed to be unfavorable to the
well-being of the offspring.
The disposition of a person is largely determined by
health and temperament. It may be cheerful or morose,
generous or miserly, sedate or volatile, good-natured or
quarrelsome, pleasant or peevish, etc. It may, however,
be modified or controlled by the will, or even perma-
nently changed by persevering effort which has become
habitual.
CHAPTER TIL
PSYCHICAL FEELINGS.
An emotion is the agitation of the sensibility, purely
psychical, seeking neither, as in desire, to bring some-
thing to the subject, nor, as in affection, to go out to
an object. Though a purely psychical feeling, it is pre-
ceded by physical conditions, and accompanied or fol-
lowed by physical effects, as the blu^h accompanying
shame, or the blanched cheek attending fear.
Pleasure and pain. — In addition to the peculiar char-
acteristics of the several emotions, they are, for the most
part, attended with pleasure or pain, which are contra-
ries, not contradictories, since certain emotions, so far
as pleasure or pain is concerned, may, perhaps, correctly
be regarded as indifferent. Let us, in a brief digression,
consider the theory of pleasure and pain.
Pleasure is the reflex feeling which accompanies nor-
mal activity or passivity. It results whenever an object
induces, in due degree and duration, the energy of one
or more of the active powers, or the excitement of one
or more of the passive susceptibilities. The pleasure is
the most complex and agreeable when the object is of
such a character that it involves the greatest number of
powers or susceptibilities, and induces such energy or
excitement as is neither excessive nor defective, either in
degree or duration. By excess, we are to understand a
greater degree of intensity or a longer period of dura-
tion than the constitution of the power or susceptibil-
ity can endure without injury. By defect, we are to
(432)
EMOTIONS. 433
understand a less degree of intensity, or a shorter 2)eriod
of duration, than the full gratification of the power or
susceptibility requires.
It is to be remarked that, in general, the degree of
intensity varies inversely as the duration of the energy
or excitement, and the number of powers or suscepti-
bilities involved. The most intense pleasures are short
lived. They can not be long endured. The soul returns
with satisfaction to the less intense, but more prolonged,
enjoyments.
Pain is the reflex feeling w^hich accompanies abnormal
activity or passivity. It results whenever an object in-
duces, in undue degree or duration, the energy of one
or more of the active powers, or the excitemeiit of one
or more of the passive susceptibilities. Not only does
excess or defect, in either the degree or duration of the
activity or -passivity, diminish or frustrate the pleasure
attending normal activity, but it induces irregular or
abnormal action, thus causing pain. Injury or lesion of
any portion of the physical system is also a cause of
pain, often intense and prolonged. The soul sympathizes
and suffers with the body.
Pleasure and pain are both positive elements in feel-
ing, and each appears augmented when in antithesis
with the other.
As our -views enlarge and embrace the future, our
conceptions of pleasure and pain naturally lead to those
of haj^piness and misery, which are not mere momentary
pleasures or pains, but are more abiding satisfactions or
discomforts.
There is a tendency to exercise our strongest faculties,
since these afford us our highest pleasure, and to leave
dormant those which most need cultivation, since their
exercise is attended with difficult}^ labor, or even pain.
The emotions may be divided into several classes:
Psy.— 37.
434 PSYCHOLOGY.
1. Emotions arising from general conditions.
1st. Cheerfulness is a state characterized by joj^ous
emotions of moderate intensity and indefinite duratioxi.
It may arise from good health, sanguine temperament^,
amiable disposition/ good fortune; satisfactory social re-
lationSj or good prospects for the future.
Dejection is the opposite of cheerfulness^ and is caxised
by contrary conditions.
Content or discontent, gladness or depression, joy or
sorrow, raj^ture or melancholy, may be regarded as hav-
ing the same general characteristics as cheerfulness and
dejection, each, in general, more intense than the pre-
ceding, though usually less prolonged.
In youth, these states are transient and are affected
by slight causes, though, at this period, cheerfulness and
joy prevail. In mature years, these states are usually
more permanent, and less easily affected, but not infre-
quently sadness and melancholy prevail.
2d. Self-satisfaction is the emotion which a person
feels in view of his excellences, real or imaginary. It
may arise in consideration of physical perfection —
strength, agility, or beauty, — or from intellectual en-
dowments or attainments — -genius, talent, knowledge,
skill, or accomplishments.
Self- dissatisfaction is the emotion which a person feels
in view of his defects. It is the opposite of self-satis-
faction, and arises from contrary causes.
Self -complacency arises when, on the whole, we are
satisfied with our past life; and self-displacency when we
are dissatisfied.'
Self-congratulation or self-reproach arises in view of a
deed nobly or ignobly done. Exultation or chagrin arises
in view of success or failure, irrespective of moral quality.
Self-sufficiency or self- depreciation arises from a confi-
dence or distrust in our abilities.
EMOTIONS. 435
2. -31sthetical emotions. — These have reference to the
sentiment of taste, and to the different forms of the
beautifuL
1st. Novelty awakens and gratifies curiosity. A novel
object is sure to attract attention and to excite wonder;
but if it has no other merit, its notoriety and the curi-
osity which it excites will be short-lived. It is, how-
ever, preferable to dull monotony, which results in
weariness and emiui; but even ennui is useful as a stim-
ulus to action.
The effect of novelty is due to previous ignorance,
and is dispelled by knowledge. Familiarity soon de-
prives novelty of its charms. This is seen in the fickle-
ness of fashion.
JSTovelt}^ affords little pleas are to the philosophic mind,
since such a mind seeks rather for agreement, general
principles, universal law, than for disagreements and
novelties.
The curiosity excited by novelty is frequently a vul-
gar desire for gossip, characteristic of a mind weary of
dull monotony, and ignorant of the rich sources of truth
and beauty found in nature, science, literature, and art.
]^ovelty often marks the decay of art. The lack of
originality and beauty is supplied by the new and the
startling, which, for the lack of merit, soon lose their
hold on the attention, and are dis^Dlaced by something-
still more fantastic.
Association has much to do with the pleasure of taste.
It throws around certain objects the dignity of rank,
wealth, genius, or worth, and around others the deg-
radation of poverty, ignorance, or vice.
Fashion is governed chiefly by novelty and associa-
tion. The leaders seek in novelty that which will distin-
guish them from the vulgar; but the common herd fol-
lows, through the influence of association, till general
436 PSYCHOLOGY.
coiiformity forces the leaders to seek distinction in other
novelties, perhaps less beautiful, or still more devoid of
good taste.
Habit and custom have a powerful influence on the
pleasures of taste. Habit is tendencj^ acquired by repe-
tition, and is applicable to the individual. Custom is
the habit of society.
Fashion and custom are antagonistic. Fashion seeks
the new. Custom clings to the old. The one has greater
influence in youth ; the other in mature years. Fashion
has the greater influence in dress; custom, in architect-
ure, in manners, and in etiquette.
2d. Wit^ humor^ ridicule^ the comic^ the ridiculous^ are
sources of the pleasures of taste, though not of a high
order. They elicit attention, provoke laughter, and, as
aflbrding pleasure, have their place, so long as they do
not degenerate, as they are liable to do, into the trifling,
the low, the malicious, or the immoral.
3d. Variety in unity is a source of aesthetic pleasure.
By unity we are to understand, not the absolute sim-
plicity of the object, but the union of the parts in the
whole — many members in one body, E plurihus unum.
Yariety in unity is always pleasing in the scoj^e which
it gives to the intellect in tracing relations and adap-
tations. The unity in variety may be seen, with in-
creasing admiration, as the scale is enlarged from the
individual to the family and dwelling, the citizens and
the state, the human race and the world, rational beings
and the universe.
Harmony is the concord of diversity, and may relate
to tone, color, form, character, or relation. Multiplicity
w^ithout relation and adjustment of individuals, as a dis-
ordered mass, is unattractive and displeasing.
Grace, the harmony of attitude or movement, both
soothes and delicchts the emotions. It is seen in the free
EMOTIONS. 437
movements of nature — the winding rivulet, the swaying
branches, the curling smoke, the fleecy cloudy tiie gam-
bols of the lamb, the circling flight of the bird, or in
the plays of children. It is seen as art in the attitudes
and gestures of the orator.
Contrast^ in things beautiful, is a source of pleasure
by giving play to thought, and by heightening the effect
of the contrasted objects.
4th. Begularity^ proportion^ or symmetry has each its
peculiar effect. Eegularity affords pleasure in revealing
law", and order, and utility. Proportion, the harmony
of the Avhole and parts, and symmetry, the harmony of
part with corresponding part, attract and j^lease, while
deformity repels and offends.
5th. Beauty is that form of expression of idea, thought,
or design, which affords a universal, disinterested, and
necessary feeling of satisfaction. It is a general quality,
including all the sources of aesthetic pleasure.
Beauty is found in various forms, and in countless
varieties of objects from the crystal to the human face
divine. Thus, we have the beauty of color, light, and
shade, addressed to the eye; the rythm of poetry, and
the harmony of music, addressed to the ear; the smooth,
velvet surface, addressed to the touch; the agreeable
flavor or odor, addressed to taste or smell. Indeed, the
word cjesthetics — the name of the science of the beautiful —
indicates that the senses are the avenues through which
beauty approaches the mind. The agreeable assthetic
feeling has its origin in the alternate excitation and rest
of the nerves of the several senses. The repose after
stimulation restores the susceptibility and reactive power
of the nerves, and prepares them for fresh excitement.
The mind, in sympathy w^ith the sensorium, anticipates
the renewal of the stimulation, enjoys the sensation con-
sequent upon the excitement, and is disaj)pointed at its
438 PSYCHOLOGY.
non-recurrence. Hence arises the pleasure from the
rythmof poetry, of music, and of the dance, and the
displeasure from discord.
The beautiful is not realized by itself. It is always
some object which has an end or purpose, which exhib-
its an idea or thought, design or skill, that awakens in
the beholder the emotions of beauty.
Beauty is subject to limitation or restraint. Infinite
profusion would overwhelm the finite faculties of man.
Both nature and art observe the law of economy — nat-
ure, in seeming accommodation to human limitations;
art, from necessity. .
Beauty seeks the alliance of that which has intrinsic
dignity — natural, intellectual, or moral worth; and on
such objects, both nature and art display their power.
It shuns the ignoble and the degraded.
6th. The grand and the sublime exalt the thoughts and
ennoble the emotions. Objects of surpassing greatness
are sublime — the plunging cataract, the lofty mountain
chain, the broad expanse of ocean, the movement of
armies and shock of battle, the flash of lightning, the
roar of thunder, the concussion of the earthquake, in-
finite space, endless duration, and omnipotent power.
Beauty charms and soothes; sublimity elevates and awes.
The one is gentle and abiding; the other, powerful and
short-lived.
Unpleasant sesthetical emotions are excited by monot-
ony, by deformity, b}^ ugliness, by discord, by degrada-
tion, and by decay.
The elements of poetic imagery are originally derived
through sense perception. Note the contrast of the
poetic and unpoetic words — pink, scarlet, crimson, pur-
ple, violet, blue, green, azure, orange, or golden, — dun,
brown, drab, bay, or black; lustrous, luminous, spark-
ling, twinkling, pearlj^, or silvery, — dull, dingy, or tur-
EMOTIONS. 439
bid; curving, winding, curling, flowing, — straight, stiff,
or angular; clear, soft, musical, mellow, melodious, —
shrill, harsh, hoarse, grating; smooth, soft, velvety, —
rough, harsh, coarse; luscious, sweet, delicious, — sour,
bitter, acrid; fragrant, perfumed, sweet-scented — pun-
gent, stifling, suffocating.
The conditions for the gratification of the pleasures
of taste are found both in nature and in art; — in nat-
ure, through countless diversities of landscape, adorned
with hill and dale, and winding stream, and silvery
lake, and distant mountain range, with azure sky and
floating clouds, with trees and bowers, with fields of
grass and waving grain; with living forms, and hum of
bees,, and song of birds, and merry sports of childhood;
in art, in grounds and dwelling, park and palace, in
matchless form of sculptured marble, in speaking canvass,
in the melody of the human voice or harmony of or-
chestral band, in persuasive words of eloquence, or in
the divine creations of poetic power.
Novelty excites surprise and gratifies curiosity ; beauty
and sublimity awaken admiration.
3. Ethical emotions.- — The intellect discovers the fact
that man is under law, divine and human; that the di-
vine law, whether revealed in nature, in the constitu-
tion of man, or in the written word, has for its end the
welfare of the human race; that human law, though
more or less imperfect, has the same end, and in the
main is conducive to human happiness; that it is, there-
fore, right to obey just law, and wrong to disobe^^, and
that we should endeavor to promote the general good.
Ethical acts are accompanied by three distinct classes
of ethical emotions, or phenomena of conscience.
1st. Preceding the act, there is a sense of obligation
to do the right and to avoid the wrong.
2d. Preceding, accomjDanying, or following the act,
440 PSYCHOLOGY.
there is a sense of responsibility, either to divine or
human authority, for moral actions, whether right or
wrong.
3d. Following the act, there is a sense of recompense
— for a right act, the approval of conscience, of our fel-
low-men, and of God, — for a wrong act, the disapproval
of conscience, in a sense of guilt, of shame, of regret, or
of remorse, also the disapprobation of our fellow-men,
and of God.
I
CHAPTEE lY.
PSYCHICAL FEELINGS.
Affection is, in general, either love or hatred of an
object. Emotion is, as we have seen, an agitation of
the sensibility. It may be comjDared to ripples upon
the surface of water.
An affection is an emotion with a current directed
outward, and terminating on an external object.
A desire is an emotion with a current directed inward
and terminating on self.
Passion is violent and controlling aifection or desire.
Inclination is the tendency of the aifections or de-
sires to affect others or to gratify ourselves.
Disposition is the prevailing spirit or character.
Propensity is the constitutional bent or proneness
which gives direction to the inclinations.
The aifections are divided into two general classes —
the benevolent affections, characterized by love, and the
malevolent, characterized by hate.
1st. The benevolent affections. A benevolent affection
is an interest in an object, an inclination towards it, an
attachment to it, with a disposition to care for it, or do
it good.
The inclination, attachment, and benevolent intention,
naturally, though not necessarily, follow from the inter-
est which the object excites. Though the benevolent
affections may, in general, be characterized as love, yet
they are more definitely designated by specific names:
(1) Sympathy is feeling with others as they feel. It
(441)
442 PSYCHOLOGY.
originates in the social nature of man, and is fostered
by the satisfaction which arises when our feelings har-
monize with the agreeable feelings of others. It is not,
however, limited to feelings of pleasure, but is extended
to those of distress. Through sympathy, we not only
rejoice with those who rejoice, but weep with those
who weep.
Personal experience, or at least some knowledge or
conception of a feeling, is a condition of sympathy in
respect to that feeling. We sympathize more readily
with others in those feelings which have deeply affected
ourselves or those with whom we are acquainted.
Certain signs are associated with certain feelings, and
are their indications. Perceiving these signs, we infer
the feelings, and enter into sympathy with them. A
knowledge of these signs is essential to sympathy.
Persons susceptible to external influences, especially
if they are also characterized by a refined sensibility,
are usually more sympathetic than others, though their
sympathy may be superficial and evanescent, like the
sympathy felt for strangers; but the sj^mpathy between
friends of kindred spirit is deeper and more abiding.
Community of interests, of circumstances or opinions,
of hopes or fears, tends to augment sympathy.
The tendency to sympathy is checked by press of
business, a selfish disj)Osition, irascible temper, avarice,
ambition, or disparity in age, education, temperament,
or social position.
Not only does inordinate self-regard diminish sympa-
thy, but also self-abnegation. The hermit or anchorite is
not in sympathy with mankind.
(2) Fity is the sympathy with others excited by their
sufferings. It regards its object, not only as suffering,
but as weak or helpless, and hence as inferior, at least,
in regard to that which awakens pity. Though a be-
AFFECTIONS. 443
nevolent sentiment, it is, in regarding its object as in-
ferior, allied to contempt. The condescension implied
in pity is humiliating to a high-minded sufferer. He
does not like to be pitied, though he may desire to be
relieved. The sense of humiliation in being pitied is
usually obviated, to some extent at least, either by the
intensity of the suffering, or by habitual admission of
inferiority on the part of the object of pity.
(3) Compassion is sympathy excited by misfortune,
and extends to persons in all conditions — inferiors,
equals, or superiors. It is a feeling akin to pity: but
pity may be a mere sentiment, a sym]3athetic emotion,
resulting in no effort for relief; but compassion prompts
to an effort to relieve the distress. The priest and the
Levite, no doiibt, felt pity for the man who fell among
thieves, yet they passed by on the other side; but the
good Samaritan had compassion on him, and went to
him, and dressed his wounds, and poured in oil and
wine, and put him on his own beast, and took him to
an inn, and paid for his care.
A benevolent heart, in performing acts of compassion,
will guard against wounding, by a display of condescen-
sion, the self-respect of those whom he relieves. If, how-
ever, pride in the sufferer is overborne by his sufferings,
and anxiety for relief, the display of condescension may
be disregarded or overcome by a sense of relief and
gratitude to the benefactor.
(4) Mercy is compassion extended to fallen enemies or
to those exposed to suffering for demerit, by one who
has the means of vengeance or the power to remit or
mitigate the penalty. Pity may be bestowed when jus-
tice forbids mercy ; it is felt, even for one w^ho suffers
for crime, though it is augmented by extenuating cir-
cumstances; but mercy seeks for those extenuating cir-
cumstances as a justification for mitigating the penalty.
444 PSYCHOL OGY.
Though justice forbid mercy, compassion offers consola-
tion and softens the rigors of the penalty.
Pity, compassion, and mercy, though differing in their
manifestations or in their objects, have the common ele-
ment of sympathy with others in their distress. Pity
may be felt for men or even brutes, though affording
no relief. Compassion for any object in distress, seeks
to relieve the distress. Mercy is extended to those in
our power, whether enemies or criminals, in forgiveness
of injury, or in remitting or mitigating the penalty of
violated law.
God pities the miseries of mankind, shows his com-
passion by relieving our distress and by his bountiful
provision for our wants, and exhibits his mercy in the
forgiveness of sins.
(5) Gratitude is the feeling experienced towards a
benefactor for benefits conferred. It involves satisfac-
tion in the benefit received, admiration for the generous
deed, esteem for the benefactor, and a desire to make
suitable returns.
(6) Thankfulness is a sense of kindness received, and
a readiness to acknowledge it in words or other appro-
priate signs.
Genuine thankfuhiess may be regarded in its mani-
festations as the expression of gratitude; but the form
of thankfulness may be employed, when gratitude is not
felt. A profusion of thanks may be offered by one
whose conduct proves him to be ungrateful.
Regarding mere thankfulness as an imperfect return
for benefits received, gratitude seeks to make more ade-
quate returns in appropriate deeds.
The common sentiment of mankind approves of thank-
fulness, but demands gratitude. Unthankfulness is re-
garded as a breach of etiquette; ingratitude is branded
as a moral baseness.
AFFECTIONS. 445
(7) Esteem is the regard which we feel for others in
consideration of their excellences of character. Though
entering as an element in gratitude and friendship, it
is not identical with either, since it may be felt in the
absence of benefits received or of personal attachments.
It can be called out only by good qualities, real or sup-
posed, in the object of esteem.
(8) Friendship is the mutual attachment of two per-
sons who have esteem, regard, or predilections for each
other, exclusive of natural relationship or the tender
passion of love. It presupposes an intimate acquaint-
ance, and finds expression in the reciprocation of kind
offices. It implies community of feeling, congruity of
character, and mutual sympathy; though, in many re-
spects, true friends may be diverse, or even the com-
plements of one another, each supplying the deficiencies
of the other, and admiring in the other what is lacking
in himself.
True friendship is the mark of a generous and noble
character, and can be felt by no other. A person des-
titute of true friends is certainly wanting in generous
qualities, and is an object of pity.
Appreciation of high and noble qualities in another,
though an essential condition of friendship, is not iden-
tical with it, since it may exist when friendship is want-
ing. True friends will stand by one another in ad-
versity, that test which distinguishes false friends from
true. Nothing but an unexpected discovery of unworthi-
ness in the character of one of the parties, showing that
the other was mistaken in him, or that he is not what
he once was, will sever the tie of friendship, and even
then he will always be regarded w^ith a melancholy in-
terest which would manifest itself in deeds of kindness.
The friend of former years can never be regarded as
an alien or a stranger.
446 PSYCHOLOGY.
Friendship seeks the good of the object of its regard,
and is disinterested and self-sacrificing. It is not blind
to faults, but sees them and endeavors to correct them,
and thus to render the object of regard more worthy.
Friendship is progressive. Time strengthens and con-
firms it, and renders it proof against the rude blasts of
adversity. It sympathizes both in joy and in sorrow,
rejoicing in the one, affording consolation in the other.
The question has been raised whether friendshij^ can
be cherished between more than two persons. The num-
ber of i^ersons towards whom a warm friendship can be
cherished is not indeed very great; but there is no rea-
son why the number should be limited to a single in-
dividual. The acquisition of a new friend does not im-
ply the loss of an old one, neither is it a just cause of
jealousy. In this respect, friendshij) differs greatly from
love between persons of opposite sexes, which, in the
very nature of the case, is exclusive.
(9) Self-love is that form of love in which the subject
and the object are identical. It is the regard of the in-
dividual for himself, and leads him to guard against
danger and to seek to promote his own happiness.
Self-love is said to be the first law of nature. It is
either due or undue.
Due self-love, or self-respect, which guards our own
welfare and restrains us from whatever is debasing, is
proper and commendable. The injunction, Love thy
neighbor as th^'self, implies that, within reasonable lim-
its, it is right to love ourselves. We are at liberty to
promote our own interests, when, in doing so, we do
not disregard the interests of others. True greatness is
modest, generous, and self-sacrificing.
Undue self-love is selfishness. It seeks our own grati-
fication, regardless of the rights of others.
It is egotism when it seeks to make one's self conspic-
AFFECTIONS, 447
nous, and obtrudes the great I whenever it finds an
opportunity.
It is haughtiness^ when it looks down with contempt
upon others regarded as inferior.
It is j^riV/e when it exalts self, and glories in its own
importance or achievements, exclaiming, ''Is not this
great Babylon that I have built for the house of the
kingdom, by the might of my power, and for the honor
of my majestj'?"
It is selfish cwibition, wdien, for self-glory, it seeks for
ecclesiastical, political, or military power, regardless of
the misery which it causes.
(10) Conjugal love is the reciprocal attachment of two
persons of opposite sexes, who are united by the mar-
riage engagement or tie. It is, perhaps, the strongest
affection of the human heart.
There is a natural affinity or attachment between the
sexes; and if a marriageable man and woman of suita-
ble ages and social position, entertain mutual friendship,
no other attachment intervening, that friendship is almost
certain to develop into love.
This affection, awakened by mutual attraction, and in-
tensified by restriction to a single object, becomes, by
action and reaction, an all-controlling passion. The
lovers are blind to each other's faults, and each sees in
the other the perfection of every excellence.
Conjugal love ought to be enduring as life, and will
be thus enduring if the parties are well mated, con-
siderate, forbearing, and true. But how often is the
ardent love before marriage transformed into indiffer-
ence or hate ! Its very ardor and intensity is unfavor-
able to its constancy. More selfish than friendship, love
is exclusive, easily excited to jealousy, and brooks no rival.
Friendship demands genuine virtues, and is confirmed
and tested by time; but love, capricious and inconsider-
448 PSYCHOLOGY,
ate, blind to faults, deaf to advice, too often sows to the
wind and reaps the whirlwind.
(11) Parental and filial love is that love which exists
between parents and children — parental, the love of
parents for their children ; and filial, the love of children
for their parents.
It is an instinctive feeling, exhibited by the lower an-
imals as well as by man; but in the lower animals, it
ceases when the young are able to care for themselves,
while, in man, it is not only an instinctive feeling, but a
rational sentiment, as enduring as life itself.
This affection seems to have been implanted by the
Creator for the wise purpose of caring for the young
and preserving the species.
Parental love is stronger than filial, and maternal than
paternal. With what unceasing care the mother watches
over her children through the years of helpless infancy
and dependent childhood!
The feeling of parental and filial love is strengthened
by the relation of the parties as protector and protected,
by association and habit, by worth in the parents and
dutiful conduct in the children; but that these circum-
stances do not constitute the affection, or wholly explain
it, is evident from the difierence between the feeling
towards one's own child or parent and that with which
a step-child or a step-parent is regarded.
(12) Fraternal love is the love existing between broth-
ers and sisters. Though less intense than conjugal, pa-
rental, or filial love, it is a beautiful sentiment, and is
abiding as life.
The family affections — conjugal, parental and filial,
and fraternal love, constitute a group by themselves.
They exhibit divine w^isdom in their origin; and, surviv-
ing the loss of Eden, continue to work for the good of
the race.
AFFECTIONS, 449
The affections, the source of the dearest joys of life, are
also the occasions of the sharpest pangs. Sorrow for the
loss of friends refuses to be comforted, save in the hope
of a reunion in a future life. The fact that love out-
lives the natural life of the person loved, is in harmony
with the doctrine of immortality, but is out of harmony
with the gloomy view that death is an eternal sleep.
(13) Philanthropy is the love of mankind. It is a
broad and generous sentiment, neither bounded by state
lines, nor restricted by language or race. It is the
power Avhich moves a Howard or a Wilberforce to deeds
of love, and gives him a place in the hearts of mankind.
Our j)bilanthropic impulses are often overborne by nar-
rower or more selfish feelings.
(14) Patriotism^ or love of country, is a noble senti-
ment. Though inferior to philanthropy in breadth, it
is superior to it in depth. It has for its object the good
of country, and is gratified with national prosperit}^, and
stirred to self-sacrificing activity in times of national peril.
In times of peace, men are engaged with their own
pursuits, and the sentiment of patriotism slumbers; but
if the country be threatened with invasion, or if its life
be imperiled by rebellion, the slumbering fires of patri-
otism will burst forth into flame, and, through sympa-
thy, patriotism becomes contagious.
(15) The love of home is kindred with that of patri-
otism, but warmer, and, in ordinary cases, more intense.
Nostalgia^ or home sickness, indicates the strength of
the affection for home. It more severely affects the un-
cultivated than it does the cultivated — those who through
knowledge and discipline have resources of hapj)iness
within themselves.
(16) Piety is love for God. It is a complex affection
involving reverence^ or profound respect, for the divine
character; adoration^ or worship of Him as Supreme;
Psy.— 38.
450 PSYCHOL OGY,
gratitude for mercies and blessings received; and trust in
God, or confidence of safety and welfare under his pro-
tection and providence.
True love to God prompts to obedience to the divine
laws, and stimulates every noble sentiment.
2d. The malevolent affections. A malevolent affection
is a feeling of resentment awakened by an object which
disagreeably affects us.
The most favorable view that can be taken of them
is that they serve the purpose of inciting to prompt ac-
tion in case of sudden personal danger, and that they
lead to the detection and punishment of crime, and thus
to the protection of society. In this light they may be
regarded as a natural response to a sense of injury.
More frequently, however, they are suffered to control
action, when they should themselves be restrained, or
directed by reason. Though originally constituted by
the Creator for wise purposes, they have been perverted
by sin, and have become the occasions of evil.
(1) Dislike is the repugnance felt towards an object
which displeases. It is more than the negative indiffer-
ence with which those objects are regarded wd:iich neither
awaken desire nor call forth the benevolent or malev-
olent affections.
Something in an object awakens unpleasant feelings
which find expression in some token of disfavor. The
feeling is not positive hatred, but there is aversion or
a disposition to repel the object.
(2) Antipathy is a strong dislike, indicating not only
a want of sympathy, but positive disagreement or dis-
cord. In certain cases it may be regarded as constitu-
tional, since no other reason can be assigned for it.
Certain persons feel antipathy to others at first-sight, so
do certain animals.
(3) Contempt is the feeling of dislike and disapproba-
AFFECTIONS, 451
tion manifested towards those who are considered base.
These are regarded as justly deserving to be branded for
their meanness. It is not external circumstances, such
as poverty or mental inferiority, that render a person
an object of contempt, but baseness of character, or in-
tentional meanness of conduct.
Contempt is not incompatible with the hope that the
obloquy cast upon the person may cause a reaction of
his moral nature leading to reformation. When a person
is despised as beneath contempt, he is regarded as hope-
lessly lost to all that is good.
(4) Scorn is the feeling w^hich leads to the rejection
of something proffered as unworthy of our acceptance.
Contempt implies that something is not good in itself;
scorn, that it is not good enough for us. Scorn is alto-
gether a perversion when the wicked scorn the right-
eous or that which is good.
(5) Disdain is the feeling entertained by a haughty
person towards others whom he despises as unworthy
of his consideration. Haughtiness is the effect of pride,
and leads to the feeling of disdain for those regarded as
inferior, and to an indifference alike to their j)raise or
censure. Arrogance is a compound of pride and vanity,
and manifests itself in pretensions to superiority and in
demands for deference.
A haughty man treats with disdain those whom he
regards as destitute of marks of distinction. An arro-
gant man makes lofty pretensions, and claims superior-
ity for himself, and exacts deference from those whom
he regards as his inferiors. The pride of an arrogant
man would lead to disdain, if his vanity did not covet
praise. His vanity modifies his pride and excludes dis-
dain ; his pride makes his vanity arrogant.
(6) Envy is the resentment felt at the success or su-
j)eriority of others. The envious person, seeing in the
452 PSYCHOLOGY.
success of another his own failure, or in the superiority
of another his own inferiority, resents it by attempting
to lower him by depreciation, insinuation, or slander.
Envy is always base and degrading. It is without
justification or palliation.
The true remedy for envy is to bring ourself up, and
not to bring a superior down. If any one would de-
velop, to their full extent, all the possibilities of good in
himself, he would find little occasion for envy.
(7) Jealousy is a burning desire to possess or to keep
something regarded as valuable, coupled with a fear that
another will appropriate it to himself
Envy regards, with an evil eye, the possessions, the
success, the reputation, or the superiority of others.
Jealousy fears that another may deprive us of what we
desire or possess. We may be envious at the success or
the superiority of others, when it simply reveals, but does
not cause our own failures or inferiority; but we are
jealous of the success or the superiority of others when it
is believed to sustain to our failures or inferiority the
relation of cause to effect. We are envious of superiors
in position, influence, or fortune. We are jealous of
equals who supplant us or gain at our expense. Thus,
one child is jealous if another is praised in his presence,
imagining that the other withdraws praise from himself
Those of the same profession, whose success depends, to
a great extent, upon their popularity, are most liable to
be jealous of one another, as musicians, actors, physi-
cians, or preachers.
The typical case of jealousy is that exhibited by a
lover who believes that he is supplanted by a rival in
the affections of the one he loves. In this case, the
more ardent the love, the more violent the jealousy.
Eeginning with suspicion, which implies doubt, jealousy
becomes furious when evidence dispels doubt, and turns
AFFECTIONS, 453
uncertainty into dreaded certainty, and ardent love into
murderous hate.
"Thy numbers, Jealousy, to naught were fixed,
Sad proof of thy distressful state !
Of differing themes the veering song was mixed ;
And now it courted love, now raving called on hate."
(8) Malice is ill-will cherished towards others, termin-
ating in evil intent or premeditated injury. Though it
may be called out by prejudice, or dislike, or injury,
•real or imaginary, it springs from a bad disposition, or
a wicked heart, and is without justification or excuse.
It is exactly the opposite of benevolence, which is the
cardinal virtue.
(9) Resentment is the reaction of feeling in response
to a sense of personal affront or injury. It seeks ex-
pression in some form of retaliation. Arising from a
sense of wrong received, it tends to continue till the
wrong is redressed. Wrongs to our friends are resented,
since they are regarded, as in a certain sense, personal.
We consider them as wrongs to ourselves.
Resentment implying malice is to be distinguished
from indignation^ or the feeling awakened by the unjust
or atrocious conduct of others. Indignation springs from
a high sense of honor, and, being exempt from selfish
personality, is devoid of malice, and not irreconcilable
with a benevolent disposition. ,
(10) Hatred is cherished resentment. It broods over
wrong, takes time for consideration, and deliberately
plans retaliation. Less violent than anger, it is more
lasting. Hatred between individuals leads to feuds be-
tween families, and clans, or tribes.
(11) Anger is sudden and strong resentment. It often
produces intense excitement, and manifests itself in deeds
of violence. Anger is usually of short duratiou ; its
454 PSYCHOLOGY.
very intensity forbids its continuance; lience, it has
been defined as a short-lived madness. Anger may, by
sudden provocation, be aroused in hearts devoid of mal-
ice, but it is unsafe to be subject to its control, since it
may lead to deeds which may be the lasting regret of
our lives, and which no repentance can remedy.
(12) Wrath is heightened anger felt by a superior to-
wards an inferior. It may be displeasure or righteous
indignation, devoid of malice, felt towards the guilty, as
the wrath of God; but, when provoked by personal in-
juries, if involving malice, it becomes haughty vindic-
tiveness, dangerous or destructive to its object.
(13) Rage is a violent ebullition of anger^ breaking
out into extravagant expressions and vehement demon-
strations of resentment.
(14) Fury is excessive rage, lashing the soul to such
a pitch of excitement, that it is no longer under the
control of reason.
(15) Revenge is deep-seated hatred, manifesting itself
in retalliation for injuries received. It is a destructive
passion, seeking satisfaction in returning injury for in-
jury, and usually with interest compounded. Not
satisfied with the retribution which civil or Divine jus-
tice will visit upon the offender, it takes upon itself the
work of retribution, forgetting that God has said,
"Avenge not j^ourselves, but rather give place unto
wrath; for vengeance is mine, I will repay, saith the
Lord."
CHAPTEE V.
PSYCHICAL FEELINGS.
Desire is a cleaving for a supposed good not in pos-
session. The object of desire must either be known or
believed to be a good, that is, something whose pos-
session would afford satisfaction, or gratify the feelings.
Desire may be regarded as an emotion with a current
directed towards self
Aversion is the opposite of desire. It may be re-
garded as negative desire — a desire to be rid of a suj)-
posed evil. The object of aversion must be either known
or believed to be an evil, that is, somethiog which
would disagreeably affect the sensibility.
In desire, the order is, a supposed good not in pos-
session, an interest in that good or an affection for it, a
desire or craving to possess it. In aversion, the order
is, a supposed evil, a dislike excited against that evil,
and an aversion to it.
Desire attracts; aversion repels. The object of desire
pleases; the object of aversion dipleases.
1st. General desires and aversions. There are three
general classes of legitimate desires and aversions — de-
sire for happiness, for perfection, for usefulness; and
aversion to misery, to imperfection, and to uselessness.
(1) A desire for happiness^ or an aversion to misery,
is universal. Man desires not only pleasure, the gratifi-
cation of a passing hour, but happiness, rational enjoy-
ment; and desires it to be abiding, eternal, which in-
volves a desire for continued existence.
(455 )
456 PSYCHOLOGY.
Happiness is attainable only by a compliance with its
conditions; but a knowledge of these conditions is in-
dispensable to compliance. What, then, is happiness,
and what are the conditions of its attainment? Happi-
ness is the agreeable emotions which spring from the
enjoyment of good. It is not quiescence — it does not
consist in rest. It springs both from the exertion of our
active powers, and from the excitement of our passive
susceptibilities.
But neither is every action nor every excitement a source
of happiness. Certain actions or certain excitements re-
sult in positive misery. Happiness springs only from
proper actions or from proper excitements, that is, from
such exertion of the active powers or excitement of the
2)assive susceptibilities as are in accordance with the
laws of our being. Obedience to law is a condition of
happiness, and a knowledge of law is a condition of
obedience, and therefore a condition of happiness.
A desire for happiness naturally leads to the desire
for those things which confer happiness. An aversion
to misery leads to an aversion to whatever is a cause
of misery.
(2) A desire for perfection and an aversion to imper-
fection, is natural to man, and is, therefore, legitimate,
when not selfishly pursued at the expense of others.
Perfection is either physical, intellectual, or moral,
each contributing to the others, all being essential to
the perfection of man.
Physical perfection^ embracing health, strength, agility,
and beauty, is rather an ideal towards which some prog-
ress can be made, than an end which can be definitely
attained.
A desire for physical perfection tends to guard life
and to preserve health and beauty. It prompts to the
observance of the physical laws in exercise and rest, in
DESIRE AND A VERSION, 457
food and drink, in pure ,air and proper clothing, and
in cleanliness of person.
Physical well-being is favorable to intellectual and
moral perfection, and contributes to human happiness.
Intellectual perfection^ consisting in the symmetrical
development and complete control of our mental powers,
is a loft}^ ideal which can be approximated, though
never reached. The desire for the attainment of this
ideal is an incentive for assiduous culture.
A knowledge of the conditions and laws of happiness
is the indispensable condition of obedience to these con-
ditions and laws, and obedience results in happiness.
By knowledge, man avoids many evils, otherwise inev-
itable, enlarges his dominion over the forces of nature,
and thus multiplies the sources of enjoyment.
Moral perfection^ or virtue — integrity of purpose, pu-
rity of heart, love to God and to man, uprightness of
life, is not only a noble and inspiring ideal, but is, by
the help of God, an attainable end.
Moral perfection is a never-failing fountain of pure
and unalloyed happiness, and will ensure peace of mind
and rest of soul, in spite of poverty, persecution, sick-
ness, loss of friends, or even death itself
(3) A desire for usefulness grows out of man's social
relations, and is legitimate and praiseworthy. It nat-
urally leads to thoughtful plans and noble deeds. It
stimulates the benevolent affections, which seek the good
of others. Its language is, May others be blest, and
may I bestow the blessing.
2d. Special desires and aversions. The special desires
and aversions can be reduced to three classes — desire for
knowledge, for wealth, and for power, and aversion to
ignorance, to poverty, and to inferiority and obscurity.
(1) The desire for knowledge is more than a vulgar
curiosity, a desire for novelty. It embraces the wide
Psy.— 39.
458 PSYCHOLOGY.
field of science, literatnre, and art^ also the professional,
commercial, mechanical, and agricultural purBuits,
The desire for knowledge is closely related to the do-
sire for intellectual perfection. It arises from the utility
of knowledge, from the constitution of the intellectual
powers, from the scope for activity which the pursuit
of knowledge affords, and from the pleasure which tlie
acquisition confers.
Knowledge is a power and a great utility — a means
of distinction and influence. The activity of the intellect
is itself a means of happiness. The field of knowledge,
vast and greatly diversified, is a never-failing source of
pure enjoyment. The desire for knowdedge arises, there-
fore, naturally from the constitution of man in relation
to the world in which he lives. It usually assumes
specific forms — a desire for a knowledge of a certain
science, art, language, or profession.
In early life, the desire for knowledge partakes more
of the character of curiosity; but in mature years, it
seeks rather for the practical, and, in some cases, for
the speculative and the universal.
Aversion to ignorance is the necessarj^ counterpart of
the desire for knowledge. It is also augmented by a
consideration of the disabilities attending ignorance.
(2) The desire for wealth is natural, and within cer-
tain limitations, useful and commendable. It checks
vice, promotes industry, and fosters the useful arts.
The pursuit of wealth affords pleasure in the activity
which it calls forth. The possession gratifies the desire
for its acquisition, affords the means for the gratification
of other desires, confers the dignity of independence and
social distinction, and supplies the means for promoting
the welfare of others.
Avarice^ or the undue desire for wealth, induces anx-
0U8 care and slavish toil, begets covetousness, or desire
DESIRE AND A VERSION. 459
for the property of others, and culminates in a mammon-
worship or miserly wretchedness.
Aversion to poverty^ the necessary consequence of the
desire for wealth, is strengthened by a knowledge of the
evils of j^overty.
(3) Ambition^ the desire for j^ower or farae^ is a native
and powerful impulse to action. The ambition to be
useful is a laudable virtue; but selfish ambition is a vul-
gar vice, detestable in itself, and dangerous to society.
The selfish possessor of power is a tyrant, and the am-
bitious conqueror has been the scourge of mankind.
The desire for the approval of the wise and the good,
coupled with an effort to merit that approval, leads to
worthy achievement; but vanity^ the undue desire for
the approbation of others, is a weak and silly vice, usu-
ally exhibited by those destitute of merit. Coupled with
untruthfulness, it leads to deceit or hypocrisy.
Pride desires power; vanity fame. Pride elevates us
in our own estimation; vanity seeks elevation in the
estimation of others. Mortification is wounded vanity.
Aversion to inferiority or obscurity is the counterpart
of ambition, or desire for power or fame.
3d. Compound desires. These are hope and fear.
(1) Hope is the desire and expectation of good. It
points to the future. We do not hope for that which
we now possess, nor for that which we either do not
desire, or do not expect.
Desire and expectation, the two elements of hope, are
not always in equilibrium. Expectation is an intellect-
ual element, and varies with the degree of probability.
When the probability is small, the exjDcctation is weak,
and we are said to hope against hope, that is, against
expectation ; but when the probability is great, the ex-
pectation is strong, giving the assurance of hope. If
the desire is weak, and the expectation also, but little in-
460 PSYCHOLOGY.
terest is taken ; if the desire is weak, and the expecta-
tion strong, hope approaches pure expectation; if both
desire and expectation be strong, the hope becomes a
joyful anticipation.
Faith is confidence in a person or thing from which
we hope to realize some object of desire. The object of
hope is a good; but the object of faith is a person or
thing regarded as the source of good. Trust implies the
committal of an interest to the keeping of an object of
faith .
Hope is a powerful spring to action. The loss of
hope usually paralyzes effort; but, when coupled with
resentment, it may lead to the rashness of despair.
(2) Fear is the aversion felt towards expected evil.
Expectation is common to hope and fear, but the objects
of expectation, in the two cases, are opposites. In hope,
the object of expectation is some form of good ; in fear,
the object is some form of evil. The desire of hope,
and the aversion of fear are also opposites.
Anxiety is a form of fear in which the evil is rather
possible and uncertain, than probable and expected. It
is usually more continued than fear.
Apprehension indicates a stronger probability than
anxiety. It anticipates danger.
Alarm is the fear excited by the presence of sudden
danger.
Dread is the fear of some impending calamity.
Terror is paralyzing fear.
Horror is the sympathetic terror induced by the sud-
den calamity of others.
Despair is the absence of all hope of deliverance from
present evil. It may result in complete inactivity or it
may, as sometimes in war, exhibit prodigious effort
known as the courage of despair.
PART III,
VOLITION AND THE WILL.
(461)
CHAPTER I.
GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION.
1. Phenomena and faculties of the soul. — We have
already found that the phenomena of the soul are reduci-
ble to three classes, — cognitions, feelings, and volitions.
These phenomena imply three classes of faculties, — the
Intellect, the Sensibility, and the Will.
Since the soul has cognitions, that is, since it knows,
it has the power to know, or the faculty of knowing,
and this faculty is called the intellect. Since the soul
feels, it has the susceptibility of feeling, and this sus-
ceptibility is called the sensibility. Since the soul puts
forth volitions, that is, since it wills, or chooses between
alternatives, it has the power of decision or of choice,
and this power is called the will.
The faculties of the soul are not divisions of the soul;
they are capabilities, or susceptibilities, or powers of
the soul. W^hen it is said that the soul has intellect,
sensibility, and will, the meaning is, the soul can think,
and feel, and choose; but these processes go on together,
though one may be more prominent than the others.
In cognition, the soul thinks. The intellect, or faculty
of cognition, is the faculty, which the soul sj^ecially ex-
erts; but the other faculties, the sensibility and the will,
are relatively, not absolutely, quiescent. In feeling, the
susceptibilities are agitated, and though thought and vo-
lition may be present, the phenomena of the sensibility
are especially prominent. In volition, the soul exerts
its powers of choosing between alternatives, but the in-
(463)
464 PSYCHOL OGY.
tellect and the sensibility are not only not absent, but
not even quiescent.
The cognitions make known the properties of things,
and thus awaken our appetites, or induce affections and
desires or aversions, which become springs to action.
In saying that the will decides which alternative it
will choose, the meaning is, the soul exerts its power of
choice, called the will, and decides which alternative it
will elect.
2. Definition of terms. — In order to avoid ambiguity,
it is necessary to define the principal terms employed.
Decision sometimes signifies an intellectual act, as when
a judge decides a question of law, or, in general, when
the intellect decides whether a given proposition is true
or false; but when used in connection with the will, de-
cision means that we have made up our minds to act
or not to act in a given manner; and growing out of
this, is a secondary meaning of firmness or adherence
to the alternative chosen. A decision to act is always
an act of the will; and, conversely, an act of the will
always involves decision.
A purpose is a predetermination to enter upon a given
course of action.
Intention is the deliberate purpose to accomplish a
certain result. •
Yolition is the intentional decision to act in a given
manner. It is the typical act ^ of the will.
Choice is the election of one of two or more alterna-
tives in view of motives rationally apprehended.
The relation of choice to volition is that of a species
to its genus. Choice is rational volition, electing its
alternative in view of reasons. It implies preference.
Alternatives are necessary to choice; that is, where
there is no alternative, there can be no choice. Ea-
tional motive is also a condition of choice. The term
GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION. 465
rational motive is here generalized, and signiiies motive
in view of reasons good or bad.
Volitions may be put forth in view of motives rationally
apprehended, or from impulses of the sensibility without
reflection, or without motive or impulse. In the first
case, the volition is elective; in the second, impulsive; in
the third, arbitrary. All volition is conative ; choice is
not only conative, but elective.
Refusal is the expressed decision not to accept a given
proffer, or not to comply with a given request. But to
refuse to accept a proffer, is to choose its alternative,
not to accept; and to refuse to comply with a request is
to choose its alternative, not to comply. Eefusing is
negative choosing, or choosing the negative. Thus, an
apple is offered me, I may either choose or refuse to
accept it; that is, I may choose to accept it, or I may
choose not to accept it. I may be requested to lend
$100, 1 may either choose or refuse to comply with
the request; that is, I may choose to comply with the
request, or choose not to comply. To decline to accept
an invitation is a polite refusal to accept, expressing the
choice not to accept.
More than two alternatives may be presented. Thus,
I may choose to take one of two or more apples, or
I may choose to take more than one, or I may choose
iio4^ to take any.
The alternatives here considered are not congruents,
but conflictives, and are either contradictories or contra-
ries — contradictories, if but two in number; contraries,
if more than two.
Volition is not to be confounded with the external
executive act. Thus, the decision to take an apple pre-
cedes the act of putting forth the hand and taking it,
and is, therefore, distinguishable from the act.
Volition is to be distinguished from desire; for desire
466 PSYCHOL OG Y.
is a craving for an object in view of appropriating it to
the use of self; but the decision to act in reference to
it is a volition. The object of desire is something con-
sidered as a good. The object of volition is the execu-
tive act consequent upon the volition. Desires are pas-
sively determined by something foreign to self, consid-
ered as a good. Volitions are intentionally determined .
by the will itself, usually in view of motives. Desires
are phenomena of the sensibility, and do not necessarily
eventuate in action. Volitions are sovereign acts of the
will, determining executive actions. In like manner,
volition is to be distinguished from aversion.
A purpose is, as we have seen, a general choice or
predetermination to enter upon a given course of action.
It may be regarded as a general volition, determining
many subsequent volitions. Thus, the purpose to lead
a virtuous life, that is, the general choice of virtue, de-
termines many subordinate choices or volitions.
The will is the faculty of volition.
A motive is an inducement soliciting the will to choose
between alternatives, or to decide to act in a given
manner.
The expression to act is to be understood in a general
sense, and may signify not only to act, but to refrain
from acting in a given manner.
To will is to decide or to exert the power of volition.
To will and to choose are nearly synonymous, differing
slightly in their applications. It is correct to say, I
choose virtue, not I will virtue, though it is right to
say, I will to be virtuous; and this is the meaning of
the expression, I choose virtue.
A preference is the favor accorded to one alternative
in deeming it rather to be chosen than another. It
naturally precedes choice.
Indifference is the absence of preference. It signifies
GENERAL VIEW OF VOLITION. 467
that one alternative is neither more nor less to be
chosen than another. The opposing motives are equal,
whatever be their influence. In this case, as there is
really no preference, the alternative may be left to be
determined by another jDcrson. or by chance, or in gen-
eral by circumstances foreign to choice, or the person
may decide for himself; if so, he decides without pref-
erence. It is then virtually volition without motive.
Inclination^ propensity^ and disposition have already
been defined; but it is imj)ortant to remember that in-
clination is the reaching forth of the affections or desires
for an object; that a propensity is a constitutional ten-
dency to a given course of action ; and that disposition
is the general attitude of the soul with regard to other
things, out of which arises the favor or disfavor with
which a given thing is regarded.
3. Order of the phenoraena.— 1st. Pre-volitional. The
intellect discovers the properties of many objects which
affect the sensibility as agreeable or disagreeable, thus
exciting the appetites, and inducing affections and de-
sires or aversions. The appetites crave gratification.
The affections and the desires seek those objects which
are agreeable to the sensibility. The aversions repel
those which are disagreeable.
The appetites, the affections, the desires, and the aver-
sions furnish motives or springs of action which solicit
the will to act in choosing between alternatives.
2d. Volitional. The soul, as rational, reflects upon
these alternatives, and by the power of the will decides
which alternative it will choose. The motives do not all
solicit the will to choose the same alternative. The will
is frequently, perhaps commonly, solicited b}^ conflicting
motives. In view of all the motives, the soul prefers
one alternative, and exerts its power of Avill in choosing
that alternative, and rejects the other alternatives.
468 PSYCHOLOGY,
3d. Post -volitional. The decision of the will being
made in the choice of the alternative, there remains the
post- volitional act by which the volition is executed.
Thus, having decided to consult a certain book lying at
hand, I put forth my hand and take the book, and open
it, and read a certain passage.
The threefold phenomenon can be thus simply illus-
trated. An apple is offered me. My appetite is excited,
and a desire for the apple induced, which acts as a mo-
tive soliciting the will to decide to accept the offer, '^o
counter motives appearing, or none of sufficient weight,
the will decides to accept the apple. It now" remains
to put forth the hand and take it. This is the external
execution of the volition, and is a voluntary action.
CHAPTEE II.
FREEDOM OF THE WILL.
1. Nature and limitations of freedom. — Freedom is
exemption both from restraint and from constraint, that
is, from prevention and from compulsion, whether in-
ternal or external.
Liberty is external freedom to act as we choose, that
is, to execute our volitions. It is freedom from external
restraint or prevention, and from external constraint or
compulsion. It is not necessarily freedom from all re-
straint, or from all constraint; for freedom from restraint
in doing any particular thing is liberty to do that thing,
and freedom from constraint to do any thing is liberty
not to do that thing.
A man is not free to appropriate the property of his
neighbor without his consent, or to injure his reputa-
tion or his person. From such actions he is restrained
by civil law. This restraint is not, however, absolute,
since he may violate the law; but for this violation, he
is subject to penalty. He is not free from contributing
his just proportion in bearing public burdens, in defray-
ing the expenses of government. He is compelled to
pay his taxes.
Man is not free from obligation to obey the laws of
God, but he is free from compulsion. If he violate these
laws, as he has power to do, he is not free from the
consequences of the violation. Though a man may pos-
sibly escape the penalty of violated human law, he can
not escape the just judgments of God.
(469)
470 PSYCHOLOGY,
Within certain limits, however, man is free to act as he
pleases; that is, he has liberty, so long as he violates no
law, to execute his volitions. He can choose his place
of residence, and engage, without hinderance, in any
business or profession. He can act with the party he
prefers, unite with the church of his choice, or refuse to
co-operate with any party or church. In such cases
man is free, that is, he has liberty of action.
Liberty, or external freedom, applies, therefore, not to
all external actions, but to those which violate no law.
In regard to these, man has liberty to execute his voli-
tions. Hence, in respect to external action in general,
man has but a partial, or limited freedom; but this is
not the freedom of the will, but freedom to execute those
volitions of the will which violate no law, either human
or divine.
Liberty of action in the cases in which it is found, is
not only freedom from external restraint, as a stone
thrown into the air is free to fall, but it is also free^
dom from external constraint. A man is not free in
doing what he is compelled to do. Freedom includes
exemption from external compulsion. It is, therefore,
freedom from co-action^ that is, both from external re-
straint and from external constraint.
Though liberty of action implies freedom from both
external restraint and constraint, yet such action is not
free from the control of the man himself. The person,
by the power of his will, puts forth the volition, and
the volition, in the absence of external hinderance, neces-
sitates the action. By liberty of action, we are, there-
fore, to understand the liberty of the person to act.
The action, as such, abstractly considered, is not free
from constraint, for it is caused by the volition; but it
is free from restraint. It has the same kind of freedom
that a stone has when thrown into the air. The stone
FREEDOM OF THE WILL. 471
is free to fall, that is, it is not hindered from falling;
but it is not free from falling; for it is constrained to
fall by the force of gravity. In like manner, though an
action may be free from restraint, it is not free from in-
ternal constraint, since it is determined by the volition;
yet free action, so far as man is concerned, is freedom
both from external restraint and from external constraint.
2. Volitions are free from restraint, but not from
constraint. — To suppose them not free from restraint is
to suppose that volitions actually^ put forth have been
prevented from being put forth, which is absurd, since
whatever is, has not been prevented from being. But
volitions are not free from constraint. As events, they
come under the law of causality, which may be stated.
All events have causes. That volitions have causes, that
is, that they are caused or necessitated, can be jDroved
sj^llogistically, thus:
• All events have causes.
Human volitions are events.
.-. Human volitions have causes.
Every volition is, therefore, caused or necessitated;
but, as we shall presently see, the volition is caused, not
by the motive, but by the will itself.
When it is said that volition is not free from con-
straint, it is not to be understood that the volition pre-
viously existed, and that it is forced, in opposition
to its resistance, to be what it otherwise would not
be, for the volition has no previous existence to be
acted upon ; but it is to be understood, in saying that
the will constrains the volition, that the will brings the
volition into being, that is, causes it to be, and to be as
it is.
In like manner, when it is claimed, though incor-
472 PSYCHOLOGY,
rectly, that motives constrain or compel volition ^ it is
not to be understood that the motives constrain or com-
pel a volition already existing to change, or to be what
it otherwise would not be, but that motives, acting upon
the will, not as a volition, but as a faculty, compel it
to assume a certain state, condition, or attitude, called
volition, thus bringing the volition into being, and
causing it to be what it is. If this be so, the will is
not an active power, but a passive susceptibility, and
choice is a j)assive determination of the will, and not its
free action.
3. Is the will free? — The will is the cause of volitions;
but, because volitions are caused, it does not follow that
the will, which is the cause of volitions, is caused to
cause them. The question is not. Are volitions free?
but. Is the will free? In what sense is the will not
frcQ? In what sense is the will free?
The will is not free in the sense that it is, in general,
exempt from the influence of motives. But what is the
nature of this influence? Are motives causes compelling
the will to choose as it does, or are they reasons for
the choice? The question is not, Is the will free from
the solicitation of motives, but, Is it free from compulsion
and from prevention? But prevention from a certain
decision is compulsion not to make the decision, that
is, compulsion to the contradictory decision or to some
contrary decision.
Motives are indeed causes; but causes of w^hat? What
are their eflects? They are causes in the sense that they
awaken thought, afl'ect the sensibility, and influence the
will. But what is the nature of this influence? Do
motives compel, or do they solicit the will? Do the
motives cause the volitions, or does the will cause the
volitions in view of motives? If the motives cause the
volitions, then the will is passive in volition, and the
FBEEDOM OF THE WILL, 473
volitions are phenomena caused in a passive susce2:)tibil-
ity, called the will, by the action of forces called motives,
thus bringing the phenomena of the will within the
province of Mechanics. Eat is the will a j)assive sus-
ceptibility, and not an active power? Can the phenom-
ena of volition be brought within the province of Me-
chanics?
That the phenomena of volition are not included within
the province of Mechanics is demonstrably certain ; for,
if so, the volition would, in a given case, be the result-
ant of the action, at the time, of all the forces called
motives. Thus, a person standing at one corner of a
square, and solicited by two friends, one at each of the
adjacent corners, the motives for going to the two being
equal, would go in the diagonal of the square, passing
the other diagonal by his momentum, till drawn back
by the motives, and after a few vibrations, Avould finally
come to a stand at the middle point of that diagonal.
But this would not be the case. If it be said that the
motives are never equal, the reply is, that so long as
either is not zero, the volition, if caused by the motives,
woctid be the resultant of the action of the motives.
But the fact is, that in choosing one alternative, the
motive soliciting the choice of the other, though not
without influence in inducing deliberation, is without
volitional effect. Hence, motives are not causes of which
volitions are effects. The will, therefore, though not
in general, free from the solicitation of motives, is free
from necessitated determination by motives.
The will is not passive in volition; for, if so, it
would not itself make the decision, but being quiescent,
save as it is passively affected, the volitions would be
the necessitated movements of the will, analogous to
those of a foot-ball as it is kicked about by contending
parties. The same results would follow, so long as the
Psy.-40.
474 PSYCHOLOGY,
will is regarded as passive, whether the motives are
impulses, attractive forces, allurements, or enticements,
acting through the appetites, affections, desires, or aver-
sions. The motives would be causes determining the
volitions as effects. This would make a volition the re-
sultant of motives, which as we have shown above, is
not the case.
The will is free to suspend choice, that there miay be
opportunity for further reflection.
The will is active in volition ; it makes the decision.
We are conscious of the exertion of the power of the
will in making the choice. The motive does not choose;
but the will chooses. The will is not a passive instru-
ment swayed by motives, as the weights sway the bal-
ance; but it is the power which a reasonable soul has
to decide in view of motives as reasons. The will as
free may refrain from putting forth volitions which it
has full power to put forth; hence, the absence of a vo-
lition does not imply the absence of the power to bring
it into being.
As motives do not constrain or necessitate the decis-
ion of the will, so neither do they restrain or prevent
the decision; for then they would necessitate the con-
tradictory or some contrary decision. The will is equally
free from constraint and from restraint. The freedom
from restraint is freedom to choose a given alternative.
The freedom from constraint is freedom to choose any
other possible alternative. But why does the will choose
one alternative rather than another? The choice of any
alternative is accounted for by the fact that the will has
alternative power. An effect is explained by a cause
capable of producing it.
In the order of time, the choice follows the consider-
ation of the motives, and the execution follows the
choice.
FBEEDOM OF THE WILL, 475
4. Does the will ever act without motive P — In case
of contradictory alternatives, the decision must, in some
way, be made in favor of one or the other, since, in this
case but two alternatives are possible. Let the motives
to choose these alternatives be equal, and let the will itself
make the decision. Then the will decides, virtually, in
the absence of motives; for, since, by hypothesis, the al-
ternatives are contradictories, to choose either is not to
choose the other, and the motive to choose either is an
equal motive not to choose the other, and since the pos-
itive motives for choosing the alternatives are equal,
and these are equal motives for not choosing the other,
the motives for choosing either reduce to zero, or there
is no choice; but, since a decision is made, it is made
virtually without motives.
To make this still clearer, let the contradictory al-
ternatives, the fact of deciding in favor of one or the
other, and the equal motives remain, and let the motives
diminish equally till each becomes zero, then there is
decision absolutely without motive, proving that, in this
case, the will is free.
Let the motives still diminish equally. They will
become negative, but will continue equal. Each motive
becomes a motive for choosing the other alternative, -and
cancels the motive for not choosing that alternative, and
again, we would have decision virtually without motive.
In these cases, there is volition, if not choice, without
motive.
5. Condensed statement of phenomena. — The com-
plex phenomena connected vfith the will are, therefore,
the following: Alternatives, any one of which is a pos-
sible object of^ choice or volition ; in general, motives
soliciting the will to choose one or more of the alterna-
tives; deliberation or consideration of the motives in
favor of the different alternatives; freedom of the will
476 PSYCHOL OOY.
from compulsion and from prevention ; the decision, that
is, the volition or choice of one alternative; the execu-
tion of the volition, that is, the external action which
secures or accomplishes the alternative chosen.
6. The decisions of the will not necessarily unrea-
sonable. — Though the will is free, the soul is rational;
hence, the decisions of the will are not necessarily arbi-
trary or irrational. These decisions ought to be, and
may be, in the highest degree, both intellectually reasona-
ble and morally right. When truth and right are in-
volved, the will is under moral obligation to decide in
accordance with the light of reason and of conscience.
Though the decisions of the will are not necessarily ir-
rational, yet they may be so, and often are so, as a
matter of fact. The will has the fearful power to decide
to act contrary to the dictates of truth and righteous-
ness, and this power it often exerts; but, for the exer-
tion of this power, it is responsible.
7. Meaning of the words obligation and responsibil-
ity. — The words, obligation and responsibility or responsi-
ble^ are of frequent occurrence in discussions pertaining
to the moral aspects of the will, and hence their mean-
ing should be clearly understood and discriminated.
When it is said a person is under obligation to do or
not to do a certain thing, the meaning is, he ought or
ought not to do that thing.
When it is said a person is responsible for his actions,
the meaning is, that he is justly accountable, or deserves
reward or punishment, according as the actions are good
or bad, and that he must meet the consequences.
CHAPTEE III.
MORAL RESPONSIBILITY.
1. Freedom is an essential condition of responsibil-
ity. — If the will is necessitated by motives to choose
a given alternative, that is, if the choice is unavoida-
ble, the person choosing is not morally responsible. He
neither merits praise for a right choice, nor deserves
blame for a wrong choice. Indeed, the choice can, on
this supposition, be properly called right or wrongs only
by a comj)arison of the choice with an external stand-
ard, and not in the sense that the man is commendable
or censurable for his choice, since he chooses as he does,
because he can not do otherwise. How could it be mor-
ally wrong for an individual to choose what he can not
help choosing? How could he be guilty for such a
choice? Since the choice determines the action, how
could he be responsible for the action? If a man suf-
fers his will to be enslaved by passion, he is responsi-
ble for this enslavement and its consequences; but this
enslavement is, in general, not absolute.
If the will is not free, it would always be unjust to
the individual to punish him for crime. It could be
justified only on the ground that such punishment is a
motive deterring others from similar crimes. But even
this motive does not always deter from crime. Notwith-
standing the punishment, crime is still committed. The
offender, must, therefore, be impelled by a stronger mo-
tive, and can not avoid the crime; hence, to him, pun-
ishment would be an act of injustice.
(477)
478 PSYCHOLOGY.
2. There is no exception to the principle that freedom
is an essential condition of responsibility. — If a debtor
should willfully squander his resources^ and thus deprive
himself of the power to discharge his obligations, he is
not, therefore, released from moral responsibility. He
had the power to meet his obligations, and for the
proper use of this power he is responsible. In will-
fully squandering his resources, he has incurred guilt;
and for this guilt, he may justly be branded as dishon-
est by honorable men.
If it be asked, Is he now under obligation to pay his
debts, and can he justly be branded for not doing it?
the answer is: Though the legal obligation is still in
force, unless he has availed himself of the provisions of
a bankrupt law, he is not under moral obligation to do
what he can not do, and he (^ught not to be held re-
sponsible for not doing an impossibility; but. when he
had power to pay his debts, he was under moral obli-
gation to pay them. He is now held responsible for
failing to do what he had the power to do, and what
he was under obligation to do. If the ability to pay
the debt should return, the moral obligation to pay it
would revive. Present obligation implies present power.
A man may indeed now be guilty for a past crime
which he can not now avoid, since it is done and can
not be recalled, though he may repent of it; but the
guilt was incurred when the crime was commited, when
he had power to avoid it.
He is not now guilty for not undoing what he can
not now undo; but he is guilty for having done what,
at the time, he had power to avoid.
3. Freedom of the will is freedom to choose any-
one of the possible alternatives. — The question is some-
times asked, Can the will choose differently from what
it does choose? It is possible to become mystified by
MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. 479
such a question. It is, of course, im^^ossible for the will
to choose a given alternative, and, at the same time, not
to choose it, but to choose a different alternative. The
true question is, Can the will choose a different alterna-
tive from any designated one of the possible alternatives?
The answer is. It can. Let A name any one of sev-
eral possible alternatives, then B can always choose
another.
It is sometimes said that we are conscious of the
power to choose differently from the choice actually made,
but this is not correct, since we are not conscious of
powers, but of phenomena. We know powers by the
rational intuition of their conditional necessity as the log-
ical antecedents, or necessary conditions, of phenomena;
but in case of the power of contrary choice there is no
phenomenon implying such a 2)C)wer, since there is no
choice contrary to actual choice.
If there is in the human mind a consciousness of the
power to choose contrary to the actual choice, this fact of
consciousness would settle the question, and controversy
would be at an end. The fact that the existence of such
power of choice is called in question by a large class of
thinkers, is proof that there is no consciousness of such
a power, for a datum of consciousness always compels
recognition.
There is, however, in every unsoj)histicated mind a
belief or conviction that there is power of contrary
choice, and of this belief or conviction such a mind is
conscious. Before choice, there is a conviction that
there is power to choose any one of the possible alterna-
tives; and, after choice, that any other one of the possi-
ble alternatives might have been chosen instead of the
one actually chosen; but a conviction that there is a
certain power is not a consciousness of that power.
That the will can choose any one of the possible al-
480 PSYCHOLOGY.
ternatives, follows from the fact that the volition is not
a resultant of motives, but is an act of the will.
Since the volition is an act of the will and not a re-
sultant, it is free both from the constraint and the re-
straint of motives. Freedom from constraint is freedom
from the necessity of choosing any given alternative;
and freedom from restraint is freedom to choose any
possible alternative. Freedom, both from constraint and
from restraint, that is, the freedom of the will both
from compulsion and from prevention, is the indispen-
sable condition of responsibility.
4. The voice of conscience is decisive as evidence in
favor of liberty.^ — But what does the conscience of the
criminal say? It declares him guilty and deserving of
punishment. The criminal arraigned before the bar of
his own conscience, confesses his crime, admits his guilt,
and acknowledges the justness of his punishment.
If he believed that his choice was necessitated, his
conscience would acquit him of guilt, not that he did
not do the deed, or that he did not will to do it. but
that he could not help doing it, since he could not help
willing to do it. But his conscience does not acquit him
of blame. In his inmost soul, he believes that he is
guilty. He could not be guilty, iii the sense of being
to blame, unless his will was free in the act of volition.
He could not believe himself to be guilty, unless he be-
lieved himself to be free; but he does believe himself to
be guilty; therefore he believes himself to be free. The
voice of conscience is not the voice of a sophist, but it
is the voice of nature, yea, the voice of God declaring
in tones not to be misunderstood, that the transgressor
is not passive, but active in his crimes.
Conscience, in approving the right and condemning
the wrong, postulates the freedom of the will. If, there-
fore, the will is not W^a^ the action of conscience, tht)
MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, 481
noblest of our moral powers, is based on a false postu-
late, and the very constitution of our nature is self-
contradictory.
It would, of course, be reasoning in a circle, to assume
responsibility, and deduce freedom from this assumption,
and then from freedom deduce responsibility, or the re-
verse. The fact is, either responsibility or freedom can
be established on evidence independent of the other; and,
when established, the other may be inferred as a logi-
cal antecedent or a logical consequent.
The phenomenon of conscience is a proof of responsi-
bility; but responsibility implies freedom as its neces-
sary condition, or logical antecedent.
The fact that a volition is not a resultant of motives
is a proof of the freedom of the will ; but this freedom
involves responsibility as its logical consequent.
6. Ground of responsibility. — The ground of respon-
sibility is moral obligation to do right and to avoid
wrong. Freedom of the will is the condition of moral
obligation, and hence of responsibility. Man is respon-
sible for the use he makes of his freedom of will and
liberty of action.
Though the freedom of the will is the condition of
obligation, it is evidently not the ground. The fact that
a man is free to do a certain thing, is no reason why
he should do it. Not only is there liberty to perform
one action and to avoid another, but there is reason
why the one should be performed and the other avoided.
But why should a person do one thing and avoid another?
What is the ground of obligation?
Every man knows that happiness is an object of de-
sire, and that misery is an object of aversion; that in
all lawful ways, he has the right to seek to gain the
one and to avoid the other; and that, so long as he
does not forfeit his liberty by crime, or encroach on
Psy.-41.
482 PSYCHOL O G Y,
the rights of others, he has the right to enjoy, with-
out hinderance, the fruit of his labor. The rights which
one claims for himself, he is under obligation to concede
to others, since they have the same right to claim for
themselves what he demands for himself
JS^ot transient pleasure, frivolous or unsatisfying, but
happiness, substantial and abiding, is the birthright of
man, and this he may enjoy by obedience to the laws
of his being, which are the laws of God, unless, like
Esau, he sells his birthright for a mess of pottage.
To attain to happiness, man must have the opportu-
nities of education in the development of his powers,
physical, intellectual, and moral. He must have the
right of pro^Derty, or the enjoyment of the fruit of his
own labor. He must be protected in person and prop-
erty. To secure these blessings, they must be mutual
and universal, limited only by the requirements pertain-
ing to the general good.
Since others have no right to encroach upon our
rights, we have no right to encroach upon theirs. Since
our happiness is promoted, not only by our own efforts,
but by the good- will, and, in certain cases, by the aid
of others, and since this good-will and aid we gladly
accept, they, in like manner, are entitled to our good-
will and aid, so far as that aid can be reasonably af-
forded. Mutual benevolence is, therefore, the fundamen-
tal moral obligation between man and man, and is of
universal application. Therefore, ^^All things whatsoever
ye icould that men should do to you, do ye even so to them.''
This is the law of righteousness.
Man has no right to squander the powers which God
has given him, but he is under obligation to develop
these, in order to promote his own happiness and that
of others. To promote his own happiness, it is neces-
sary that he guard his life, liberty, and reputation, pre-
MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, 483
serve his health, protect his property, and promote his
physical, intellectual, and moral perfection. The prepa-
ration which enables him to advance his own interests,
best qualifies him to promote the welfare of others.
The family relations of husband and wife, parents and
children, brothers and sisters, involve peculiar and sacred
obligations.
Special duties are implied in the relations of teacher
and pupil, pastor and people, employer and employee.
Man is also under certain obligations to society, to
his government, and to the world at large.
Our obligations to God are based upon the relations
which we sustain to Him as our Creator and Benefac-
tor. In this case, the inequality of the parties modifies
the statement of the law of benevolence. It would not
do to say. Whatsoever we would that God should do for
us, we should do for him; for we desire His help and
protection, and many other favors which we are una-
ble to render Him. But certain things are due to God
from man. We should show repentance towards God
for past sins by confessing and forsaking them. We
should have faith in His mercy and constant goodness.
We should exhibit reverence for God in view of His
power, wisdom, and holiness. Above all, we should ren-
der obedience to His righteous laws.
The science of Ethics may, however, be well under-
stood by those who refuse to reduce its principles to prac-
tice. Virtue is not identical with knowledge, as Socrates
taught, since man does not always do what seems to him
to be morally right. The will does not always choose the
greatest apparent good. A man may know that virtue
is the highest good, and that it will bring the greatest
reward; and yet, with this knowledge before his mind,
and w4th his eyes open to the consequences of evil,
he may follow the lead of his appetites and passions,
484 PSYCHOLOGY.
and pursue the path of sin and death. Justly may lie
apply to himself the language of the poet,
*^ Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor."
His will, in yielding to the solicitations of appetite
and desire, refuses to obey the voice of reason and con-
science. His moral nature is disordered, and he is
brought into captivity to the law of sin and death ; yet
he is free to seek what he so much needs — the regener-
ating energy of the Spirit of the living God.
4^^'7
^3
Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process.
Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide
Treatment Date: Oct. 2004
PreservationTechnologies
A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION
1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive
Cranberry Township, PA 16066
(724)779-2111