Sean Hadit 7 + ARTES LIBRARY 1817 JOULATED VERITAS UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN ZAUTO UNUM TUEBOR VILL SCIENTIA OF THE VAUAAAJAASIKIA UN DIAGR maiartery "SI-QUÆRIS PENINSULAM AMŒEHAM) CIRCUMSPICE DAVAZOVA VEN : BELISFERENTIAMFUNN RIFTERNA pag aarala **** MONTON, 1 JC 389 下げ​て ​19/4 THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS BY THE SAME AUTHOR From Gerson to Grotius. Studies in Political Thought from 1414 to 1625. Camb. Univ. Press. 38. 6d. English History illustrated from Original Sources, 1660-1714. 2nd edition. A. & C. Black. 28. net. Churches in the Modern State. Longmans, Green & Co. 4s. 6d. net. Christianity and History. Finch, 1905. 2s. net. The Gospel and Human Needs. Sixth Impression. Longmans, Green & Co. 4s. 6d. net. Popular Edition. 6d. Civilisation at the Cross Roads. Third Impression. Longmans, Green & Co. 5s. net. Anti-Christ and other Sermons. Longmans, Green & Co. 58. net. Religion and English Society. Fourth Impression. Longmans, Green & Co. Cloth 28. Paper 18. THE DIVINE RIGHT OF KINGS BY JOHN NEVILLE FIGGIS, OF THE COMMUNITY OF THE RESURRECTION, LITT.D., HON. D.D. GLASGOW, HON. FELLOW OF S. CATHARINE'S COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE SECOND EDITION WITH THREE ADDITIONAL ESSAYS Cambridge: at the University Press. 1914 002 44& 522 CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS London: FETTER LANE, E.C. C. F. CLAY, MANAGER ہے Edinburgh: 100, PRINCES STREET Berlin: A. ASHER AND CO. Leipzig: F. A. BROCKHAUS New York: G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS Bombay and Calcutta: MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD. Toronto: J. M. DENT AND SONS, LTD. Tokyo: THE MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA First Edition 1896 Second Edition 1914 All rights reserved ΤΟ THE MEMORY OF EDWARD HENRY MOULE 371002 די PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION SINCE INCE this book first appeared, much water has flowed under the bridge. Yet I have left the essay very much as it was in 1896; not at all because I am satisfied with what I wrote then. However, to write a new book on this topic is not now possible; and it seemed better to make no changes, beyond what were absolutely essential. Historically the chief defect of the book is the absence of any account of Luther's influence. This I tried to remedy in an essay on 'Luther and Machiavelli' in From Gerson to Grotius¹. The early matter is also very incomplete, and the reader may be referred to the chapters in Mr Carlyle's History of Political Theory in the West, which deal with the doctrines of obedience and non-resistance in the early church. Secondly, I wrote the pages on Pres- byterianism without understanding how deeply its 1 I take this opportunity of repeating that in the passages on the Jesuits, there is in that book a grave error: I 'followed a multitude to do evil'; and interpreted a certain idiom in their constitutions, as though it meant an order to commit sin. It meant nothing of the kind. viii PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION exponents (at least from the days of Cartwright and Andrew Melville) were imbued with the doctrine of the two kingdoms. Light on this may be afforded by the lecture on Jus Divinum in 1646, which was delivered last May in the University of Leeds and is printed as an additional Essay. Mainly, however, the historical account stands as before, and needed little change, although it might easily have been expanded. It is different with the political structure. On the theory of sovereignty and the relation of small groups to the State, and the notion of a 'higher law,' the opinions of the author have undergone much change; nor has he all in vain heard the wisdom of masters like Acton and Maitland or read the great work of Gierke. It was difficult to know what to do with Chapter IX., but I have changed little; and present views can be seen in the lecture above mentioned, and also in the paper, which follows it, on Bartolus. I have developed them still further in a recent work on Churches in the Modern State. The last paragraph of the original essay is also expunged, since on the matter of modern capitalism both views and sym- pathies are changed. The paper on Bartolus was delivered in 1905 to the Royal Historical Society, and it appears in the Transactions of that body, from which it is reprinted by permission. Also, I have to thank the proprietors of the Journal of Theological Studies for allowing me to reprint the article on Erastus and Erastianism, PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION ix which appeared in 1900. It shares with the main body of the book the defect of being written beneath the shadow of the Austinian idol. All this makes a lame defence. But a new edition was called for; and I have done the best I could. I must not conclude this preface, without ex- pressing my warm thanks to my friend, Mr C. N. Sidney-Woolf, Fellow of Trinity College. He has not only read through the proof sheets, but has been good enough to make the Index. It is an added pleasure to me to feel that this office has been performed by the man who took to heart the writer's expressed wish, and has given us a study of Bartolus¹, at once profound and sympathetic which illuminates for all a very obscure region of the history of medieval thought. J. NEVILLE FIGGIS. HOUSE OF THE RESURRECTION, MIRFIELD. December 3, 1913. 1 Bartolus of Sassoferrato, by C. N. Sidney-Woolf, Cambridge University Press, 1914. PREFACE I HAVE to thank the Adjudicators of the Prince Consort Prize for their kindness in permitting me very much to expand, and entirely to rewrite, my dissertation of four years ago. To the late Professor Seeley in particular was due the suggestion, that I should investigate French political theories in the sixteenth century and endeavour to discover their bearing on English thought. Even so, I am sensible of the extreme inadequacy of this sketch. Within any reasonable time it would be impossible to arrive at a complete account of a doctrine, which has relation to every political theory from medieval to modern times. At some future date, it may be within my power to attempt a fuller account of the develop- ments which political theory has undergone since the later Middle Ages. This little essay is at most a preliminary survey of the ground, and can lay claim to neither finality nor completeness. With the view of fixing attention, so far as possible, on the main subject, I have avoided discussing in any detail the origin and development of the rival theories, such as the original compact and popular PREFACE xi sovereignty. On the other hand I have endeavoured in many cases to give the means of verification of statements as to the true nature and purpose of the doctrines discussed, by putting into footnotes a few of the more striking utterances of all parties. Lest however the notes should be unduly heavy, I have collected into an Appendix a small number of passages illustrating the points which Chapters VIII. and IX. are intended to elucidate. To Mr R. A. Nicholson of Trinity College, for his kindness in going through the whole book and drawing up the list of Errata, and to other friends, for help and suggestions, while the sheets were passing the press, I tender my grateful thanks. J. N. F. CHAPTER I. II. III. IV. V. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTORY EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II. KINGSHIP IN ENGLAND FROM HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH VI. HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES VII. VIII. PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE CHURCH OF ENGLAND. IX. NON-RESISTANCE AND THE THEORY OF SOVE- X. CONCLUSION AARON'S ROD BLOSSOMING OR JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM "" REIGNTY BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS APPENDIX A. EXTRACTS FROM STATUTES RELATING TO THE SUCCESSION INDEX. B. EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII. AND IX. . PAGE 1 17 38 66 81 107 137 177 219 256 267 293 343 373 377 402 CHAPTER I (C INTRODUCTORY the Divine as absurd. A MODERN essayist has said with truth, that The never has there been a doctrine better written Theory of against than the Divine Right of Kings." But Right of Kings those, who have exhausted their powers of satire commonly in pouring scorn upon the theory, have commonly condemned been at little pains to understand it. That the doctrine is absurd, when judged from the stand- point of modern political thought, is a statement that requires neither proof nor exposition. But the modern standpoint is not the only one, and the absurdity of the doctrine in our eyes is the least interesting or important fact about it, except as driving us to seek further for its real meaning and value. Nor is "The Divine Right of Kings" But differentiated by reason of its absurdity from other theories of political theories of the seventeenth century. rival doctrine of an original compact was no less ridiculous in theory, and (if we consider its other The the time whit absurd. also 1 Gairdner and Spedding, Studies in English History, 245. Cf. also Mr Gairdner's remarks in the preface to Letters and Papers Illustrative of the Reigns of Richard III. and Henry VII. xI—XIII. F. 1 2 INTRODUCTORY The causes of the pre- valence of the doctrine more im- portant than the influence upon Rousseau) infinitely more explosive in practice than the notions of Indefeasible Right and Passive Obedience. It is noteworthy, that, while Macaulay has nothing but contempt for the sup- porters of Divine Right, he does not find it needful to mention that its opponents would make no better figure among political thinkers of to-day. Instead of stating a fact, which is common to all obsolete doctrines, it were surely better to enquire into the notions of those, to whom the doctrine seemed natural, and to set it in relation to the conditions which produced it. Large numbers of men may embrace a belief without good reason, but assu- validity. redly they will not do so without adequate cause.- And it is commonly of far greater importance towards the right understanding of a doctrine to know the causes, which lead to its prevalence or decay, than it is to be able to criticize the reasoning, by which men think to support it, while it is popular or to demolish it, as it grows obsolete¹. reasons against its Its import probably different it appears. Further, although the theory may seem absurd, when framed into a set of bald propositions, it is not from what wise therefore to infer that it had no other meaning to its supporters, than that which it bears to us. It may prove to have been in the main a counter- theory to some other notion of Divine Right, more ridiculous and less useful. Judged in relation to the circumstances which produced it, and to the rival 1 Mr Balfour takes these two theories as offering the most salient illustration of the fact that the causes of belief are widely different from the reasons for it, Foundations of Belief, 216- 17. INTRODUCTORY 3 doctrines it was formed to extirpate, the theory of the Divine Right of Kings may prove to be neces- sary and even sensible. The import of the battle- cries of "Passive Obedience" and "Ius Divinum" to those, who were fighting the battle, must have been very different from what it seems to those, who can see no meaning in the cries, because they have for- gotten that there was a battle. The method of Whig historians is apparently to isolate the pheno- menon, and to observe it in vacuo. Considered in this way any theory of government must appear ridiculous, so soon as it has ceased to influence practice. It is not so that the true import and value of 'forsaken beliefs' is to be gauged. It has been shewn that the earlier free-traders were at fault in treating the believers in the Mercantile theory as conscious knaves or incurable fools. They erred in supposing, that since a theory has become obsolete, it therefore had never anything to recom- mend it, save the self-interest of the few and the stupidity of the many¹. May not the same thing be true of some of those, who have poured out upon the believers in the Divine Right of Kings ridicule, that certainly has the merit of being obvious? not Nor again can the doctrine be dismissed as the The work of an isolated thinker with a turn for paradox. doctrine It was essentially a popular theory, proclaimed in academic the pulpit, published in the market-place, witnessed popular. on the battle-field. The names, which have come down to us, as especially connected with it stand out but 1 Cunningham, History of English Industry and Commerce, Part II. §§ 307, 357. 1-2 4 INTRODUCTORY The outcome of actual needs. rather by lapse of time, than through any eminence of their own. Filmer is not to be regarded as a prophet or thinker, followed as a master by a crowd of inferior men. He was only slightly more able and far more notorious, than a host of other writers, whose names and works have faded from the general recollection. A belief so widespread was surely the product far more of practical necessity than of intellectual activity. No enthusiasm for a scheme of ideal politics, no quasi-scientific delight in discus- sions upon the nature of government could generate so passionate a faith. The pressure of circumstances could alone produce it. Nor as a matter of fact is the doctrine much regarded by the makers of Ideal Commonwealths in the sixteenth and seven- teenth centuries. It might seem that no scheme of politics could be more purely ideal than one which asserts Divine authority for its basis. Yet there is no trace of propagandism in the works of royalist writers, whether in France or England. Some indeed are at pains to assert that they have no quarrel with other forms of government, when once established, whether elective monarchies or republics¹. There is no desire to establish universal Kingship, akin to the passionate enthusiasm of French Revolution- aries for abolishing it. For the most part, the horizon of the politico-theological writers of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries is bounded by a particular country in a definite stage of deve- lopment. A Frenchman will indeed find in the Davidic kingdom the model of a state governed by 1 E.g. Hickes in Jovian. INTRODUCTORY 5 LO the Salic law. An Englishman will see in. it the Divine justification for the English law of succes- sion. But, except for the purpose of finding God's authority for a given polity, neither really looks beyond his own country. The theory is the out- come of facts far more than it is of thinking. From the consideration of the popular acceptance and practical object of the doctrine, some obvious con- clusions may be drawn. First, it seems clear that The so general and enthusiastic a faith must have been the expression of deep-seated instincts; secondly, satisfied deep in- that a doctrine so fully elaborated and yet so stincts eminently the product of a definite epoch must fulfilled a have been the result of a long chain of historical function. causes, and that it must have been formed to meet real needs. If so, it had a definite function to fulfil in the development of society. It is the purpose of this essay to enquire how far this was the case. doctrine must have and The theory of the Divine Right of Kings in its Statement completest form involves the following propositions: the theory. (1) Monarchy is a divinely ordained institution. (2) Hereditary right is indefeasible. The suc- cession to monarchy is regulated by the law of primogeniture. The right acquired by birth can- not be forfeited through any acts of usurpation, of however long continuance, by any incapacity in the heir, or by any act of deposition. So long as the heir lives, he is king by hereditary right, even though the usurping dynasty has reigned for a thousand years. (3) Kings are accountable to God alone. Mon- archy is pure, the sovereignty being entirely vested 6 INTRODUCTORY Illustra- tive quota- tions. { in the king, whose power is incapable of legal limitation. All law is a mere concession of his will, and all constitutional forms and assemblies exist entirely at his pleasure. He cannot limit or divide or alienate the sovereignty, so as in any way to prejudice the right of his successor to its complete exercise. A mixed or limited monarchy is a contra- diction in terms. (4) Non-resistance and passive obedience are enjoined by God. Under any circumstances resist- ance to a king is a sin, and ensures damnation. Whenever the king issues a command directly contrary to God's law, God is to be obeyed rather than man, but the example of the primitive Chris- tians is to be followed and all penalties attached to the breach of the law are to be patiently) endured. The following passages set the doctrine forth in the language of the time:- "We will still believe and maintain that our Kings derive not their title from the people but from God; that to Him only they are accountable; that it belongs not to subjects, either to create or censure, but to honour and obey their sovereign, who comes to be so by a fundamental hereditary right of succession, which no religion, no law, no fault or forfeiture can alter or diminish." "Obedience we must pay, either Active or Passive; the Active in the case of all lawful commands; that is whenever the Magistrate commands something which is not 1 From an address of the University of Cambridge to King Charles II. in 1681, printed in the History of Passive Obedience, p. 108. INTRODUCTORY 7 - contrary to some command of God, we are then bound to act according to that command of the Magistrate, to do the thing he requires. But when he enjoins anything contrary to what God hath commanded, we are not then to pay him this Active Obedience; we may, nay we must refuse thus to act (yet here we must be very well assured that the thing is so contrary, and not pretend conscience for a cloak of stubbornness), we are in that case to obey God rather than man. But even this is a season for the passive obedience; we must patiently suffer what he inflicts on us for such refusal, and not, to secure ourselves, rise up against him¹.” (< If Adam himself were still living and now ready to die it is certain there is one man, and but one in the world who is next heir, although the know- ledge who should be that one man be quite lost?." theory. The theory is commonly supported by a number Common of Biblical illustrations and texts, of which some of arguments in favour the most important may be mentioned:-Samuel's of the description of a king, on the Jewish nation de- manding one'; David's refusal to touch "the Lord's anointed"; the text "By me kings reign and princes decree justice"; the passage describing the vision of Nebuchadnezzar, asserting that "the 1 Whole Duty of Man, Sunday xiv. § 5. The passage is quoted by Hobbes as giving the best expression of "the doctrine of the King's party." (Behemoth, Part 1. p. 80.) 2 Filmer's Patriarcha. Chap. 1. § 9. 31 Sam. vii. 10-18. There is much controversy as to whether Samuel intended to describe a good king exercising his sovereign rights, or a tyrant. 4 Prov. viii. 15. ¡ Сс INTRODUCTORY ! No im- portance (( Most High ruleth in the kingdom of men, and giveth it to whomsoever he will, and setteth up over it the basest of men¹"; the command to "render unto Cæsar the things that are Cæsar's ""; Christ's words to Pilate "thou couldest have no power at all against me except it were given thee from above"; the behaviour of the primitive Christians; and above all the direct enjoining by both S. Peter and S. Paul of obedience to constituted authority, The powers that be are ordained of God. Whoso- ever therefore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God. And they that resist shall re- ceive to themselves damnation." "Ye must needs. be subject, not only for wrath, but for conscience' sake." "Submit yourselves to every ordinance of man for the Lord's sake-whether it be to the king as supreme, &c."" The Pa- triarchal The Patriarchal theory, the most unqualified form of the form of which Filmer and others profess to find theory not in Genesis, forms the basis of the most symmetrical form of the doctrine of Divine Right, but it is far from universal and there is no reason for regarding it as of the essence of the theory. essential to it. Nor, again, does the sacramental character of unction play much part in the exposition of the 1 Daniel iv. 2 S. Luke xx. 25. 3 S. John xix. 11. 4 Rom. xiii. 1-7. It was held of great importance to maintain that plois meant damnation in the strict sense. There is a lengthy dissertation of Hammond to prove this single point. 1 Pet. ii. 13-17. A favourite argument to prove that kings are accountable to God alone is the text "Against thee only have I sinned" (Ps. li. 4). It is quoted by a French writer as having the authority of Otto of Freising, and is used by Leslie among others. INTRODUCTORY 9 I i to unction. divine authority of kings. Richard II. undoubtedly attached believed that unction conferred an indelible mark, and the motion of the sacredness of royal power, as compared with all other constituted authority, was certainly strengthened by this ancient cere- mony'. But it plays, in the controversies of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, a quite differ- ent part. In France the supporters of the League are found arguing, that unction is necessary to make a king, and that Henry IV., who as a heretic cannot be anointed by the Archbishop of Rheims, can therefore never be truly king. In England, the writers on the popular side are con- tinually pointing to the coronation oath as evidence of the theory of compact, and as limiting the royal authority. Hence both in France and England, the counter-assertion is common that unction is of no importance, and confers no special grace; that the king is king before his coronation as fully as he is after; and that resistance to an 'uncrowned' king is verily damnable. The phrase, "the Lord's Anointed," is merely common form for the sacred person of the Magn 1 Shakespeare expresses the sentiment rather of Richard II. himself than of the believers in the Divine Right of Kings, in the famous lines :- "Not all the water in the rude rough sea Can wash the balm from an anointed king." There can be no doubt that the notion of the sacred character conferred by unction was held by Richard, and that it long remained an element in popular feeling. But the exigencies of their position. drove the supporters of the theory of Indefeasible Right to mini- mize the effect of unction. Any stress laid upon it tended to make the king a mere official, and to support the doctrine of the originally elective character of kingship. 10 INTRODUCTORY / King and is used by writers who are far from attri- buting any sacramental character to the ceremony. Undoubtedly the ordinary view is that of a royalist divine, who declares in set terms that "Royal Unction confers no grace, but declares a just title only." Indeed no other view was really compatible with the notion of indefeasible hereditary right¹. 1 The Royal Charter granted unto Kings, Chap. III. What is meant by the anointing of Kings. "Unxit in regem includes nothing but a due title, excludes nothing but usurpations; gives him the administration to govern, not the gift to govern well; the right of ruling, not of ruling right." Anointing is a sacred signature betokening sovereignty, obedience to the throne, allegiance to the Crown." Usher after quoting David's sentence on the Ama- lekite for slaying the Lord's anointed goes on: "And this indeed must be the main foundation not only of the observance but also of all the other branches of that allegiance, which we do owe unto our Prince; that with the right which he hath obtained by Election or Succession here below we be careful to conjoin that unction which he hath received from above." (Power of the Prince, p. 125.) Clearly unction is regarded as equivalent to God's institution of kings, not as a grace conferred by the sacrament of anointing. Cf. Coke on Calvin's Case. "Coronation is but a royal ornament and solemnization of the royal descent, but no part of the title.' He goes on to quote the case of two seminary priests, who claimed that before his coronation it was not high treason to seize and imprison King James. This doctrine was of course condemned by the judges, who declared him to be as full king before coro- nation as after (7 Reports, 10 b). It is significant, that neither The Maid's Tragedy nor The Royal King and Loyal Subject, although each asserts most emphatically the sacred character of Kingship, contains the slightest hint that this character is acquired through unction. In France again, Servin writing on behalf of Henry IV. distinctly denies that uuction has any significance, or is more than a pious ceremony. Blackwood indeed appears to take a different view: "An non quemadmodum sacerdotes sic et reges cum inaugurantur oleo id est divina quadam virtute inunguntur? Nam oleum, illud quo reges olim sacerdotes (( >> INTRODUCTORY 11 theory belongs to when theology closely Now a theory, such as that described, has plainly The as much relation to theology as to politics, and cannot be judged from the standpoint of an age, when the an age, two are sharply divided. Although something is heard politics at times of the importance of religious considerations and in regulating international politics or state-inter- were ference, yet no one now claims that politics is a connected. branch of theology. Men may appeal with more or less of sincerity to Christian sentiment as a factor in political controversy, but they have ceased to regard political theory as a part of Christian doctrine. The theory of the Divine Right of Kings belongs to an age in which not only religion but theology and politics were inextricably mingled, when even for utilitarian sentiments a religious basis must be found if they were to obtain acceptance. All men demanded The same some form of Divine authority for any theory of government. There is hardly a hint that those ployed by who disbelieved in the Divine Right of Kings had of the any quarrel with the methods of their opponents. Until towards the close of the seventeenth century, the atmosphere of the supporters of popular rights is as theological as that of the upholders of the Divine Right of Kings. methods are em- opponents theory. John Hall¹ indeed brushes aside the Biblical illustrations and authorities of the royalists; but most are content to argue on just the same lines as their et prophetae perfundebantur, divinitatis symbolum erat ac veluti sacramentum" (Apologia pro Regibus, p. 15, cf. also De Vinculo Religionis et Imperii, pp. 232, 314). But this view is far less common than that given in the text. 1 The Grounds and Reasons of Monarchy prefixed to Harring- ton's Works, p. 8. 12 INTRODUCTORY opponents. They point out that Scripture has been misunderstood, that texts have been ignored which inculcate the right and duty of resistance, that the early Christians exhibited the virtue of Passive obe- dience merely because they could not help themselves. Even the original compact finds its biblical model in the 'law of the kingdom' laid down by Samuel. Towards the end of the seventeenth century, with Locke and Sidney and even the more able of the royalists, politics began to pass into a more modern stage. But most writers, of whom Johnson the author of Julian the Apostate is a fair specimen, have hardly a notion, that political theory can be framed except on a theological basis, or proved save by the authority of the Bible. Writers on behalf either of unlimited obedience or popular rights, though they are undoubtedly impelled by a pressing sense of the utility of resistance or vice versa, yet seek by appealing to Scripture to establish their theory upon an immutable basis, and to base it upon trans- cendental grounds, of which no fresh view of what was merely expedient should ever destroy the force. To judge aright the political theories of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, we must not consider them from the standpoint of an age in which all political theory is confessedly utilitarian'; their true relations are to a time when theology and politics. were closely united both in theory and practice. It is useless to demonstrate, what nobody doubts, that the theory of the Divine Right of Kings has ¹ Professor Sidgwick (Elements of Politics 34) bears witness to the exclusively utilitarian character of modern politics. INTRODUCTORY 13 no affinity with the creed of any modern political party. Rather we must seek to find what political theories of ecclesiastical power met their coun- tervailing influence in this theological theory of politics. (( of sove- Again, the theory assumes the fact of Sove- The theory reignty." When it is borne in mind, that the idea of involves sovereignty in the Austinian sense was unknown in the notion any single nation in the middle ages, it will at once reignty. become a matter for enquiry how far the uncom- promising absolutism of the royalist writers may have been merely the expression of a thought, which came to them with all the force of a discovery. While the fact that the notion appears in the claims to universal supremacy of both Popes and Em- perors, may point to the possibility of similar causes operating in the struggles on the part of the national states for independence of Papal control, it was not, perhaps, easy for a writer like Austin to see, how a theory of the state can ever be formed without the recognition, that there must be in it some ultimate authority, which because it can make laws is above law. Yet it is certain that this notion is modern, and that the idea of the complete supremacy of one body or person in the state did not enter the heads of those who wrote of the English polity in the middle ages. Bracton knows of no sovereign in the Austinian sense, and distinctly denies to the royal authority the attribute of being 'incapable of legal limitation'.' How indeed could it have been 1 Cf. Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law, I. 160. "That the king is below the law is a doctrine which even a royal 14 INTRODUCTORY Origin of the theory to be sought in the conflicts of the Papacy and Empire. otherwise under the conditions of feudalism, however modified, and in the face of the admitted claims of the Papacy and the canon law¹? In addition, then, to setting the theory of the Divine Right of Kings in relation to contemporary conflicts of politics and theology, it will be needful to enquire how far the doctrine is the expression of a dawning idea of sovereignty, whether or no this idea was realised by the opponents of Divine Right, and what are the true relations of the latter doctrine to the more systematic theory of sovereignty, expounded by Hobbes. The fact, that Imperialist writers in the middle ages, endeavouring to refute the claims of the Pa- pacy, develope for themselves the essential notion of sovereignty, points, as was said, to the conflict with Rome as the true source of the theory of Divine Right. Again, the necessarily theological character of politics, so long as the Pope's claims to supreme political authority were a main factor in the situa- tion, makes it yet more plain, that the history of the theory must be largely concerned with the political side of the Reformation struggle. But in order to learn how the weapons were forged, which were to be used in the seventeenth century, it will be needful to study the earlier conflicts of Pope and Emperor. KOT justice may fearlessly proclaim. The theory that in every state there must be some man or definite body of men above the law, some 'sovereign' without duties and without rights would have been rejected." See also p. 208, and Bk. 11. Ch. 11. § 13, The King and the Crown. 1 Cf. Maine, Early History of Institutions, Lectures XII. and XIII. in which is shewn the practical inapplicability of Austin's theory to primitive societies and half developed states. INTRODUCTORY 15 In these the Papalist writers first will be found developing a theory of sovereignty for their Lord the Pope, while this is met by the counter-contention of the Imperialists that not the Pope but the SBR. IN 200 Sicon wyc With STEUNSUPRIMIY .25. Emperor is truly sovereign, and that he is so by God's direct appointment. Here clearly are the main elements of the later doctrine. DENTAL doctrine was need- That to the Reformation was in some sort due If the the prevalence of the notion of the Divine Right of Kings is generally admitted¹. If then it should ful to effect the prove that the doctrine was an essential element of Reforma- success in the struggle against the political claims tion, it did good of the Papacy, it will be vain to condemn its service. supporters for trying to set back the clock of time. If the theory was needful, it did good work, and the fact that the work is done is no reason for pouring ridicule on those who took part in it. The value of a doctrine is to be gauged, not from its having given place to a better, but from its having superseded one which was either pernicious or had become obsolete. The interest of the subject is great. It marks History of the transition from mediæval to modern modes the theory of interest, of thought. In studying it we see the links of as mark- connection between thinkers like Dante and Ockham ing the change on the one hand, and Locke and Rousseau on the from other, while, despite the notion of natural rights, to modern Locke and Sidney with their strong vein of utili- thought, as proving tarian sentiment are plainly the forerunners of the de- Bentham and Mill. But not only does the history of theory pendence mediæval 1 See especially Mr Gairdner's valuable essay on the subject. Gairdner and Spedding, Studies in English History, 245 sqq. 16 INTRODUCTORY upon practice. 1. of the doctrine serve to bridge the gulf between mediæval and modern thought. It also illustrates the inevitable dependence of theory upon circum- stances. That facts are the parents of theories far more than theories of facts, that political thought is inevitably relative to political development, men are all too prone to forget. But no one who studies the origin and history of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings is likely to do so. On the other hand it is unquestionably true, that a doctrine produced by the pressure of circumstances may have a great practical work to perform. It gives expression to real needs, and strengthens men in their determination to make a stand, for what they instinctively feel to be of vital importance. No belief could be more the child of circumstance than that in the Divine Right of Kings; while it played no despicable part in giving the nation some sort of intellectual and doctrinal basis for its claim to independence of ecclesiastical control. These points it will be the aim of the following essay to elucidate. LAGER AT CHAPTER II EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP sentiment as to THE developed doctrine of kingship of the seven- Early teenth century has been described by Sir Frederick Pollock as "not rational, not ingenious, not even sanctity of Kings. ancient¹." Yet the instinct, which it satisfied, is as old as history. In some form the sanctity of kingship has been held from very early times. Although the theory of the seventeenth century was mainly the expression of immediate needs, it is not possible to deny some part in it to a sentiment of loyalty, which is as old as human society. Most primitive tribes seem to have thrown some sort of halo round the person of the chief. Either the mysterious supernatural power of the medicine- man was the basis of his dominion among races, who perhaps had not risen to any definite notions of a divinity; or else he was believed to have been The King an actual incarnation of the deity. Dr Frazer nation.. in The Golden Bough has brought together a large number of instances of the prevalence of this notion. He shews also the intimate connection between kingship and priesthood. The maxim, Rex est 1 History of the Science of Politics, 65. an Incar- F. 2 18 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP The King of Divine descent. Influence of Chris- tianity. mixta persona cum sacerdote is the expression of what was once an actual fact; and to this is proba- bly due much common sentiment as to the sanctity of royalty. With the lapse of time, the belief that a king was a god gave way to the notion, that he was of divine descent. As the Incas claimed to be the children of the Sun, so the notion of divine parentage is the first germ of the theory, which meets us upon the threshold of English History. When the institution of royalty was developed by the circumstances of the Conquest among the communities that migrated to Britain, all the petty monarchs of the early English tribes found it well to strengthen their title by a direct claim to descent from Wodin, thus investing the new authority with something of a supernatural sanction. With the introduction of Christianity a fresh. and more enduring source of strength was given to the notion that obedience was a divine command. Suffering for conscience' sake became a duty. The divine institution of the Davidic kingdom, the mysterious character of Melchisedec the priest king, and the very definite commands of S. Peter and S. Paul could not be, and, as a matter of fact, were not overlooked. The sufferings of the early Chris- tians were an example, which later apologists of resistance might explain away, but they could not well be forgotten. Without crystallizing into a definite theory of the nature of government or of the limits of obedience in extreme cases, there subsisted throughout the middle ages a feeling that EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 19 ages. kings and all in authority were the vicars of God, Obedience to Kings and that resistance to their commands was, in general, › as vicars a damnable sin. An aspiring Pope like Hildebrand of God regarded might indeed declare later, that all secular govern- as a reli- ments were of diabolic origin. But there remained gious duty throughout in the common consciousness some sense that the the middle king's power was of God, that obedience to him was a religious duty, taught and practised by Christ himself and the Apostles. It was not a theory, but it afforded material out of which a theory might be formed, if at any time circumstances should drive men to seek for one. As an instance may be taken the report of the legates George and Theophylact of their proceedings in England A.D. 787'. They appeal, as a non-juror might have done, to the fourth of Daniel, to the thirteenth of Romans, to the words of S. Peter. They quote the prohibition against cursing the king even in thought, and speak of all who are accessory to regicide, as on a level with Judas. is evident that the legates are using the common form of enjoining obedience to civil government. Clearly they put forward no abstract theory of indefeasible right or of absolute sovereignty or even of invariable non-resistance. It It must be remembered, that later royalist writers were only following in the wake of centuries, when they quoted It 1 Stubbs and Haddan, Councils 111. 453, Cap. XII., De ordina- tione et honore regum. "Omnes generaliter admonuimus, ut consona voce et corde Dominum rogent, ut Qui eligit eum in regnum, Ipse ei tribuat regimen disciplinae sanctae Suae ad regendam plebem Suam.......In necem regis nemo communicare audeat, quia christus Domini est. Omnis quisquis tali sacrilegio consensat... aeterno anathematis vinculo interibit, et Judae traditori sociatus." 2-2 20 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP Early English Kingship. Scripture to prove the duty of obedience, or called the king the vicar of God, and employed far-fetched Biblical analogies and forced interpretations to support their contention¹. All this was old enough². What was new, was the attempt to draw from it a con- sistent logical theory of the nature of government and of the mutual relations of sovereign and subject. With regard to early English kingship, that it was not strictly hereditary by the law of primogeniture, is well known. But it must be borne in mind, that, although the right of election and deposition rested with the Witan, they could only exercise their right within the limits of the royal family. The case of 3 1 The non-juror Leslie is very angry with Burnet for declaring that the theory of Divine Right was the product of the Reforma- tion. “None knows better than his Lordship, that the notion of Kings having their power from God, was long in the world before either the Reformation or Popery. All the ancient Fathers are full of it. And they took it from the Holy Scripture, where it is abundantly testified" (The Good Old Cause, § 2). As to the developed doctrine there is no doubt that Burnet was right and Leslie wrong; but Leslie is quite right as to the notions out of which it grew, as is shewn by the passage cited on page 19. That the Fathers would have been astounded could they have seen their phrases about obedience to the Emperor, taken as proof that they held the theory of the non-jurors, is true enough; that the non-jurors had the least notion that their theory was in any way different from the sentiment of antiquity, there is no reason to suppose. 2 Cf. for the development of these doctrines in the Fathers and Early Middle Ages, Carlyle, History of Political. Theory in the West. Mr Carlyle shews by many instances, that the attribu- tion of the origin of kingship to the fall is in no way incompatible with the belief that obedience is a religious duty. 3 Hotman in the Franco-Gallia tries to prove a similar rule of election, but election within one family, as the ancient custom of the Franks. ! EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 21 Earl Harold is quite exceptional, and it is at least not proved that his election was legal¹. Although the power of the Crown was circumscribed within somewhat narrow bounds, yet in various ways the sanctity of the king was asserted; his peace was of a high nature, above that of other men. In the rise of the law of treason under Alfred we see how import- ant the protection of the king's person is becoming, although as yet it is only as part of the general law, differing merely in degree from treason to a lord, that we discern the germs of the later code of high treason³. With the Norman Conquest the royal power Effect of the received a vast accession of strength. But the Norman doctrine of elective kingship gained additional force Conquest. from the circumstances of William and his sons. The struggles of the reign of Stephen shew, on the one hand, that considerations of hereditary right are not yet regarded as decisive. On the other, the mere fact of the Empress obtaining a large measure of support indicates, that men are beginning to attach importance to succession by primogeniture. If the theory of sovereignty had been recognised at this time, there could be no doubt that all theo- retical limits upon the royal authority must have been done away with; for the king was immeasurably the strongest power in the state; but no such theory was held, and forms of constitutional checks remained in theory, for a later age to use them in practice. 1 Mr Round is at issue with Mr Freeman on the point. Geoffrey de Mandeville, 8, 437, Norman Conquest, III. App. C. 2 See Stubbs, Constitutional Hist. 1. § 72; Pollock, Oxford Lec- tures, 65; and Pollock and Maitland, Hist. of Engl. Law, 1. 22. 3 H. E. L. p. 28, and Stubbs, Select Charters, p. 62. 1 4. 22 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 1086.' Again, the action of the Conqueror in compelling all landowners to take the oath of fealty to him against everyone¹, including their immediate lords, tended to widen the generality of the duty of obedience to the central authority, and to form a basis for a complete theory of allegiance. Its sig- nificance as guarding against the dangers of an infinitely subdivided sovereignty, the worst evil of feudalism, has often been pointed out. Primo- geniture. assimi- lated to inherit- ance of fiefs. It was perhaps in another way that the Conquest Succession led most directly to the development of principles, to Crown that made up an important element in the theory of the Divine Right of Kings. While withstanding the danger of introducing feudal principles of govern- ment, the Conqueror introduced, or, at least, crystal- lized into system all the influences that made for a complete recognition of feudal principles of land- tenure. The king is now not only the national representative, but also supreme landowner; all land is held of him mediately or immediately. This, " the great generalization that governs the whole of Domes- day" led not only ultimately to the conception of territorial sovereignty, but assimilated the succession of the Crown to the developing law of the inherit- ance to fiefs. The Norman kings were far more than 1 Stubbs, Select Charters, pp. 81, 2. 2 Stubbs, Constitutional History, 1. § 94. 3 Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law, vol. 1. p. 46. Cf. also p. 210: "Every acre of English soil and every proprietary right therein have been brought within the compass of a single formula, which may be expressed thus:-Z tenet terram illam de... domino rege." 4 Maine, Ancient Law, 106. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 23 1 national monarchs. They were lords of a great estate. And the rules which were beginning to govern the succession to fiefs, were held to apply to the Crown. The elective character of kingship began to fall into the background, and the influences, leading to a rigid rule of primogeniture in the case of land, tended to the same result in regard to the succession. Hitherto the Crown had been partially elective, and so far as it tended to become hereditary, there are reasons for supposing that it might have descended, as was so often the case in the earlier mediæval monarchies, by being partitioned among all the surviving sons of the deceased monarch'. But the rise of the rule of primogeniture, after the kingdom had become the greatest of estates, ensured that succession should be impartible. It is only because the notions of public law and sovereignty were as yet undeveloped, that this was possible. Because men cannot think of the king as other than a natural person, or of the rules governing the succession except as a part of the ordinary law of inheritance, they were driven to assimilate the succession to the Crown to the succession to a fief. The king was the landowner par excellence; his lands must descend by the same rules as those of other men². ¹ Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law, 11. 260 sqq. 2 Ibid. 1. 497, 8. "The king is conceived to hold his lands by a strictly hereditary right. Between his lands and the kingship it would be hard to distinguish....The descent of the Crown was not so unique a phenomenon then as it is now." Cf. also I. 209. “The king, it is true, is a highly privileged as well as a very wealthy person; still his rights are but private rights amplified and inten- sified." 24 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP Causes of primo- geniture. King John. It has been recently shewn, that it was probably the interest of the overlord, the desire to have one. person responsible for the discharge of all the feudal incidents, that led to the developement of primo- geniture. For not primogeniture, but equal division is the most natural mode of hereditary succession. But though the holder might well desire that his lands should be partitioned among his children, this would not suit the purpose of the Crown, which stepped in and decreed the rule of impartible succession. And it was owing to the fact, that the notion of hereditary kingship only superseded that of election, when this rule was becoming universal in regard to private lands, that the succession to the Crown, when it became hereditary, went by promogeniture and not by partition'. There are grounds for supposing that the Conqueror divided his dominions among his sons, on the same principle that actuated so many Frankish monarchs. And Richard Cœur de Lion refused homage to his brother Henry, because brothers were equal. However, primogeniture triumphed and was applied to the Crown, as to other estates. The 'case of the king' so often cited by Bracton is a proof both of the incomplete acceptance, as yet, of the rule of primogeniture, and of the entire assimilation of the succession to the Crown with that to a fief. On the one hand, John's succession to the throne in defiance of the strict rule of primogeniture, and the exclusion of Arthur his elder 1 Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law, 11. 260 sqq. 2 Ibid. 1. 505. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 25 brother's son, are evidence that the theory of re- presentative primogeniture was not yet accepted. On the other hand, this case, until the death of Arthur's sister in 1241 determined it, was held to leave the question of right undecided, and to protect seisin in cases of private lands, as between an uncle and the son of an elder brother, who had not himself held the land¹. John's case is also noteworthy as containing in the reported speeches of Archbishop Hubert, the strongest possible assertion of the right of election, and (afterwards at the coronation) of the binding character of the oath. On the other hand, the territorial character of kingship was coming into prominence. John is Rex Angliae, no longer Rex Anglorum; while the recent assumption of the style royal affords an indication of a dawning notion of the mystical and official personality of the king. John's reign is further important on account of the submission to the Pope. So long as the position accepted by John was, with whatever reluc- tance, recognised at all, and the suzerainty of the Pope admitted by the payment of tribute, the state- ment that the king was under no one save God was the expression of patriotic aspiration rather than of actual fact. But the final rejection of the Pope's demands in 1366, and the protest against Papal claims. with which it was accompanied³, formed the basis of the later assertion that this realm of England is an ¹ Bracton, De Legibus Angliae, ff. 267 b, 282, 327 b. 2 Matth. Paris, Chronica Majora, 11. 454, 5. 3 Rot. Parl. II. 290. 26 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP Empire' and contained the germ of that appeal to the grace of God against the will of the Pope, which was the raison d'être of the theory of Divine Right. Further it is to be noted, that in this case as in others the Papacy, though willing to loosen the bonds of allegiance in order to compass its own ends, shewed no preference for constitutional government as such. The tyranny of both John and his son leant largely upon Papal support. Magna Charta needs no mention, save for the well-known fact, that the sixty-first clause approaches more nearly than any other statute of English History to giving legal sanction to the right of resistance, and making government and obedience truly a matter of compact. Edward I.'s reign election, not coro- nation. The accession of Edward I. marks a further step dates from in the developement of hereditary kingship and in the removal of the significance and necessity of the coronation ceremony. The story is well known. Edward was absent upon the crusade at the time of his father's death; the barons, dreading the evils of a lengthy interregnum, elected him king four days after. He reigned from the date of his election, and was not crowned for nearly two years. The crown was claimed by hereditary right, and the will of the barons'. Thus coronation, as a neces- sary element in kingship, sank into abeyance, and the notion, that though kings may die, the authority of the Crown remains undisturbed, began to arise. Not yet will men assert that 'the king never dies'; 1 Rymer, Foedera, 1. 497. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 27 but the germ of the notion is here, and those who in later ages argued that coronation was merely a ceremony, and that the heir to the throne was every inch a king' without it were right in claiming, that they were merely following the precedent of Edward's reign¹. ' pears. With the accession of Edward II. election itself Election disap- fell into disuse, and he succeeded his father with no interregnum. Thus the pressure of circumstances and the influence of feudal land law brought about the triumph of the notion, that the right of inherit- ance is the only essential element in making a king. The right to the Crown was no longer that of election or of coronation, but that of the next heir, whom God alone can make. If we have not yet come to the days when hereditary right was regarded as indefeasible, and no breach was admitted, however short, in the continuity of the succession, yet there were by the beginning of the fourteenth century all the elements of the theory. The Crown had become a birthright. *** ', • cance. But the reign of Edward II. had a deeper signifi- Growth of It has been pointed out, that the very royal pre- theory of developement of a constitutional system led to a rogative. counter-attempt to exalt and liberate from control 1 Majestas Intemerata, p. 45. 2 Stubbs, Const. Hist. 11. §§ 247, 273. "On the one side every advantage gained by the parliament is regarded as one of a very limited number of privileges; on the other every concession made by the crown is made out of an unlimited and unimpaired poten- tiality of sovereignty....... The theory of sovereignty held by Henry III. is far more definite than that of Henry II., and that of Richard II. than that of Edward I." 28 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP << the royal prerogative. For every assertion of national right there is a counter assertion of royal autocracy." The growth of Parliament, as the source of legislative activity, emphasized the dis- tinction between the power of the Crown in Parlia- ment and the personal power of the king. Kings now will insist upon their personal privileges, upon their right to issue ordinances, to misinterpret at their pleasure the petitions of Parliament, in trans- forming them into statutes. Thus the whole con- stitutional struggle of the fourteenth century raged round the vexed question of the royal prerogative. On the one hand popular rights had been crystallized into a definite system; on the other the kings exalted their personal position, and tended to regard it as a thing apart, above the constitutional machinery. Before Parliament became an essential element in the state, there was no reason for the king to claim extra-legal authority, save in taxation, for with trifling limitations he was the source of law. He was in his own person not only supreme landowner, but the fountain of justice, the executive authority, and the amender, if not the maker of law. But when Parliament gained the right to petition for new laws, and when in 1322 this right was made exclusive¹, it was natural for the king to distinguish between his rights in his own person and his authority in Parliament. The growth of Parliament, then, is 1 'Revocatio Novarum Ordinationum.' It is remarkable, that the Act was passed in defence of the king, not of the people. The object is to secure the king's freedom from any lords ordainers of the future. Statutes of the Realm, 1. 189. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 29 the origin not only of the immediate struggle around royal prerogative and privilege, but also of the dis- tinction between the personal and political capacity of the king, of which a later age was to hear so much. tion the and Nor was the matter a trifling one at the time. Distinc- Even in the days of Edward II. it became a matter appears of controversy. The distinction was apparently one between of the arguments for the banishment of Gaveston. personal The ordinances of 1311 accuse him of "encroaching political to himself royal power and royal dignity and lording capacity it over the state of the King and the People," terms King. which the Long Parliament might have applied to Strafford. Later on, however, in the trial of the De Spensers, the doctrine that there is any distinction between the king and the Crown was condemned¹, of the 1 The following is the passage condemned:-Statutes of the Realm, 1. 182. Homage and the Oath of Allegiance is more by reason of the Crown than by reason of the Person of the King, and it bindeth itself more unto the Crown than unto the Person; and this appears in that before the Estate of the Crown hath descended, no allegiance is belonging to the Person; wherefore if the King by chance be not guided by Reason, in right of the Crown, his liege Subjects are bound by the Oath made to the Crown to guide the King and the Estate of the Crown back again by reason, or otherwise the Oath would not be kept. Now were it to be asked, how they ought to guide the King? Whether by Course of Law, or by Violence? By Course of Law a man will not be able to get Redress, for he will have no judges but such as are the King's, in which case, if the Will of the King be not according to Reason he certainly will have only Error maintained and confirmed; Wherefore it behoveth, in order to save the Oath, that when the King will not redress the matter and remove that which is hurtful to the People at large, and prejudicial to the Crown, it is to be determined, that the thing be removed by Violence, for he is bound by his oath to govern the people and his Liege Subjects, and his (6 30 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP and writers of the seventeenth century were able to point to the statute exiling them, as proving the iniquity of the notion, that it was lawful to levy war against the king's person in defence of his Crown. No theory of sove- during ages. It was the glory of England, that it was subject reignty in not to the written law,' but to the ancient customary England law of the race, although many modern ordinances, middle such as the assizes of Henry II., had become a part of it. This fact, perhaps, as much as the prevalence of the theory of feudalism, prevented during the middle ages the growth of any theory of sovereignty, save in the Empire. The doctrine would indeed have seemed ludicrous to an English lawyer of the twelfth or thirteenth century. The feudal idea, despite all the efforts of the central power, was still strong, and Its forma- there is perhaps no more essential element in feudal tion pre- vented by theory, than the belief in the infinite divisibility of feudalism. sovereign power. Doubtless, by the fiction of dele- gacy, it is possible to stretch even the feudal system on the Procrustean bed of Austinian sovereignty. Yet at least it will be admitted, that no country, in which feudalism was at all a force, whether as forming theory or influencing practice, could possibly have suggested to the acutest mind the conception of an omnipotent sovereign with neither rights nor Liege Subjects are bound to govern in aid of him and in his default." It will be seen that these ideas were exactly those of the Long Parliament. The author of Majestas Intemerata makes much use of the fact that the distinction between the political and personal capacity of the king is a part of "the Spensers' treason." Coke, Calvin's Case (7 Reports, 11 a) calls it a "damnable and damned opinion." EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 31 duties. The relations of the Duke of Normandy, or later of Gascony to the King of France, the Scottish overlordship, the question of the franchises (which it required all the dexterity of the Crown lawyer to get recognised as merely delegations of royal power¹) must have been fatal to any attempt towards the formation of a theory of sovereignty. Indeed the nature of the feudal tie operated to suggest the notion that government is based upon contract. trine un- necessary. Nor again was such a theory needed. So long The doc- as custom is regarded as the main source of law and the province of legislation is restricted, the abstract truth of Austin's doctrine may remain, but its practical applicability is gone. For the idea of sovereignty to arise, there must be a developed state and a considerable measure of legislative activity. Both these conditions were unfulfilled at the time of Bracton. The only sources, from which such a theory might have been drawn, were the civil and the canon law. But, if any writer with a turn for the Roman jurisprudence should have directed his attention thereto, facts would have been too strong for him. The claims of the Pope, recognised and unrecognised, the existence of the canon law, the wide sphere of spiritual jurisdiction, and benefit of clergy would have been a sufficient bar to the formation of any such doctrine2. The theory of sovereignty is only of value, when applied to states which are organised; at this time 1 See Maitland, Introduction to Select Pleas in Manorial Courts; also History of English Law, 1. 559. 2 Ibid. 1. 160, 1. 32 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP the organization of national states was only in the making¹. Lawyers ascribe If, then, it be borne in mind that no theory of sovereignty was or could be held by Bracton, it will sovereign not be surprising to find him ascribing to the king rights almost to the rights, which apparently amount to little less than complete sovereignty, while in set terms the king is declared to be under the law. Many passages there are which to modern ears sound inconsistent, such as the statement, that the king is under no one but God, and yet is not above the law. Where then is the source of law? Whence is its sanction derived, if neither the King nor any other person or body of persons are above it? This inconsistency is apparent only to us, because we are unfamiliar with the notion that custom can be truly sovereign. The blunder which a modern reader might be tempted to make on first opening Bracton is that of either charging the author with contradicting himself or of understanding the law, under which the king is said to be, in some fanciful sense as equivalent to no more than moral or natural law. This mistake was actu- ally committed by the uncritical pamphleteers of the seventeenth century. Circumstances had generated in them the idea that in every state there must be some sovereign. Observing that Bracton and Britton ascribed to the king rights which seemed of the essence of sovereignty, they jumped to the conclusion that in the thirteenth century the power of the Crown was believed to be free from all legal limitations. Unless they were setting forth the moral and religious 1 See Maine, Early History of Institutions, Lectures XII, XIII. King, yet treat him do not as sove- reign. Writers in seven- teenth century misunder- stood Bracton. G EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 33 duties of the king, they ignored all that was said about his being subject to the law; and this without conscious dishonesty. They were wedded to the idea of sovereignty, and seeing that in Bracton's view the sovereignty, if not vested in the king, was nowhere to be found, they adopted what seemed to them the only possible alternative, and inferred that the power of the Crown in the thirteenth century was legally unlimited. Once the fact is grasped, that the royalist writers of the seventeenth century were almost as deeply imbued with the idea of sovereignty as was Austin, the course which they took is seen to be natural. It has been said that "had it [the theory of sovereignty] been accepted in the thirteenth century, the English kingship must have become a tyranny, for nowhere else than in the person of the king could the requisite sovereignty have been found¹." If this be so, it follows that those, who had no suspicion that the theory was not accepted in the thirteenth century, must have imagined that English kingship at that time was an absolute monarchy. thought Hence it is not surprising, that royalist writers of They the seventeenth century quote Bracton only less that frequently than the Bible, and, although they must Bracton regarded have read his distinct assertion to the contrary, regard the King him with evident bona fides as irrefragable testimony as to the truth of their doctrine, that England in the Middle Ages was an absolute monarchy, tempered only by (always iniquitous) revolutions2. absolute. 1 Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law, 1. 160. 2 Majestus Intemerata, a pamphlet of 50 pages, is crowded with appeals to the authority of Bracton, Britton, &c. Cf. also Jenkins F. 3 34 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP They had grounds for their view in many phrases of Bracton and Britton. They found it declared repeatedly that the king plausible is God's vicar¹; that all persons in the realm are under him; that he is under none but God; that he has no peer that if he break the law, it is enough that he await the vengeance of God, for none of his subjects may punish him²; that no judgment to make void an act or charter of the king is valid³; that our Lord the King has ordinary jurisdiction over all in the land; that all (save spiritual) rights are in his hand¹; that he was created king to the end that he should do justice to all; that the Lord should sit in him; that a jury may be fined for deciding against the king"; that none may impose on him without his consent the necessity to amend an injury of his own doing, for necessity may not be imposed on him". They found that Britton regards the whole common law as an emanation from the royal authority, that he declares his regality to be inalienable, and the king to be the sole interpreter of his will10. Redivivus. Cowell quotes Bracton's authority for his assertion that the king is above the law by his absolute power" (Prothero, Statutes and Constitutional Documents, 409, and note). 1 Bracton, f. 1 b. 2 Ibid. ff. 5b, 6, 369. 3 Ibid. f. 34. 4 Ibid. ff. 55 b, 412. 5 Ibid. f. 107. 6 Ibid. f. 290 b. 7 Ibid. ff. 368 b and 389 b. 8 Britton, 1. 1. 9 Ibid. 1. 221. "Rois aussi e porrount rien aliener les dreitz de lour coroune ne de lour reauté, qe ne soit repellable par lour successours. This is on the same lines as the arguments of seventeenth century writers, to prove that all the rights of Parliament and people are but concessions, which may at any moment be recalled. 10 Britton, 1. 414. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP 35 contrary It is not wonderful that writers of an uncritical The pas- age, imbued with the idea that there must be in sages in a the State some power above the law, should have sense explained supposed that the lawyers of the thirteenth century away. regarded the king in that light. It was easy to ignore what was said about the king being subject to law, to treat it as a fine phrase, or to suppose that nothing more was intended than their own distinc- tion between a king, who rules according to the law of nature, i.e. morality, and the tyrant who governs by caprice. The seventeenth century royalists were willing enough to admit the desirability of the sovereign governing by fixed rules; only they denied that he was legally incapable of altering them. They no more desired a king to govern without, law, than a modern writer, asserting the omnipotence of Parliament and its power to abro- gate all existing laws, would desire that each suc- cessive Parliament should repeal all the acts of its predecessors. They too wished the king, in obedi- ence to Divine Law, to govern according to the law of the land; in this sense they understood 1 Bracton, ff. 5 b, 34. The lengthy passage, in which a king who rules without law is treated as the vicar not of God, but of the devil, would serve to strengthen the view of the royalists, that Bracton regarded moral law alone as superior to the Crown. They must have explained these passages as suggested; for it was impossible for any writer, however dishonest, to ignore the strong phrases about the supremacy of the law used in the very passages, which they quote as asserting the power of the Crown. Bracton was a book constantly in the hands of their opponents, and, without some such justification in their minds, they could not have faced them. See next note. $ 3-2 36 EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP Bracton's assertion, that the king was under God and the law ¹. Only God an heir,' Another notion to be found in Bracton must have can make contributed much towards generating the belief in the sacredness of primogeniture. The view of the lawyers of the thirteenth century, that only God can make an heir², although expressed with reference to private inheritance, must have tended greatly to strengthen the sentiment in favour of strict hereditary succession. It led men to regard this mode of the devolution of the Crown, as in some mysterious way superior to the merely human method of election. The birth of an heir is the judgment of God, and has the same sanctity attached to it, as the ordeal or the lot. Men, if they elect, may well make a bad choice; God, though we may not fathom His reasons, will not make an heir without good grounds. Summary. To sum up, it appears that Kingship has ever been regarded as in some especial way protected by a Divine authority; that the influence of Christianity has in all ages been held to support this view; that • 1 The strongest evidence that this was the common view is the remarkable passage in which Filmer boldly grapples with the most awkward of all Bracton's statements. He declares that the words asserting that the king has a superior in his court of Earls and Barons are to be explained of the king's own consent to this check, which has thus no real authority, for the king's consent may be withdrawn. After boldly sweeping aside this difficulty, he naturally enough declares, that, in saying the king was under the law, Bracton merely meant that he ought to govern by means of it; he is thus under the directive, but not the coactive power of the laws. (Free- holders' Grand Inquest, p. 12.) This method of escaping the dilemma is precisely that attributed above to the royalist writers. 2 Bracton, f. 62 b. 37 English Kingship from being elective in a single family had become purely hereditary by the fourteenth century; that coronation had ceased to be regarded as necessary to the making of a king; and that in the systematic presentment of English law in the thirteenth century there were ample materials for men in a later age, devoid of the historical sense and imbued with the theory of sovereignty, to suppose that the English Kingship towards the close of the Middle Ages was strictly hereditary and uncon- ditioned by constitutional restraints. EARLY IDEAS OF KINGSHIP Gly 曾 ​CHAPTER III The Holy Roman Empire embodies mediæval ideal of a state. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY THE medieval notion of an ideal state is em- bodied in the theory of the Holy Roman Empire. The failure of events to give practical effect to the theory generated controversies, out of which was developed the root idea of the later doctrine of the Divine Right of Kings. The dream was a noble one, of a perfect state with two elected heads, one temporal and one spiritual, working in harmony for the maintenance of peace and for the ordered conduct of life among Christians, in a polity that should com- bine all that was of lasting value in the system of the The theory Roman Empire with all that was essential to the unwork- able. realization of the City of God. But for the most part it remained but a dream, save for a few fitful intervals of brilliancy under Charles the Great or Otto III. or even Henry III. Yet the contro- versies of the seventeenth century took the shape they did owing to the earlier struggles between Popes and Emperors. If there had been no Holy Roman Empire, or if there had been no failure to realize the ideal embodied in it, there would have THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 39 versies claims planation been no theory of the Divine Right of Kings¹. The whole standpoint of political thought during Contro- the period of the Reformation is explicable only about by being referred to its counterpart in the ideas Imperial and the methods methods of the men, of the men, who wrote who wrote on form ex- behalf of the Papal or Imperial pretensions to of theory sovereignty. One, who has not entered into the of Divine Right. feelings of the earlier age, can scarcely fail be hard put to it to comprehend those of the later. A study of the controversies that raged around the claims of Pope and Emperor, will reveal the genesis of most of the notions embodied in later theories; and will bring us into contact with the mental atmosphere, in which alone such theories could take shape. to politics. The Holy Roman Empire, however shadowy Connec- tion of its power, was, so long as men made it an aim theology to work for, a testimony to the most important and characteristic of political thought till the close of the seventeenth century-the belief in the intimate connection of politics and religion. The ideal of the Empire, with Christ as its King and His two vice- gerents upon earth, was that of a theocracy. This is the explanation of the otherwise strange fact, that men should ever have believed in so unworkable a theory, as that of two equal heads of the State. Christ is the real head of the Empire, and Pope and Emperor are both conceived rather as executors armed from above with administrative powers than 66 1 The claim to Divine Right......was first put forward by Imperialist and Royalist opponents of the Papacy." (Gardiner, History of England, vIII. 182.) 40 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY as themselves ultimate authorities¹. There is no difficulty in having two superior officials indepen- dent of one another, if they are both regarded as essentially subordinate to a single supreme governor. It was the vividness with which men realized the position of Christ as Lord of the Christian common- wealth, that could alone render possible, as an ideal, a state in which temporal and ecclesiastical juris- diction existed side by side, and each claimed 'coactive' power. That the ideal State is the kingdom of God upon earth, and that no other can be an object of veneration to a Christian, is the notion that lies. at the root of the Holy Roman Empire. It is only as the immediate character of Christ's Kingship is lost sight of, and the two subordinate authorities. begin to claim, each for itself, perfect independence and supremacy, that there is revealed the insoluble character of the problem involved in the recognised positions of the Pope and the Emperor. As this process continues, first the Pope, as most plainly the depositary of Divine Authority, afterwards the Emperor, as called to his office by God's election and appointment, claims to be the true and supreme head of the Christian commonwealth, by Divine Right Lord of the world. But the notion of an earthly polity has for neither party disengaged itself as yet Opposition between two servants of the same king is incon- ceivable, each being bound to aid and foster the other: the cooperation of both being needed in all that concerns the welfare of Christendom at large." (Bryce, Holy Roman Empire, p. 102; and the whole of Chap. vII.) 1 66 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 41 from that of the heavenly kingdom. Both Emperor and Pope are forced to claim Divine Right for their pretensions, for each believes himself to be head of something more than a temporal state founded from motives of human convenience. They are not merely the directors of an artificial contrivance for satisfying ephemeral needs; they conceive them- selves the chosen captains of the divine organization revealed by Christ, as part of the eternal order of the universe. And thus, whatever claims of supremacy are made for either Pope or Emperor, it remains that the theory upon which they are based is essentially religious. Neither side dreams for a moment of asserting, that the sphere of theology can be separated from that of politics, or that the source of political theory is to be found save in revelation. Neither side imagines that the views of its opponents can be discredited, unless their opinions as to religious duty and the drift of Christ's teaching can be shewn to be false. Those who deny the political supremacy of the Pope are heretics, says Boniface VIII. Those who affirm it are heretics, says Marsiglio of Padua. Theology can in some way teach men the true theory of government, the relations between various powers in the State, and the mutual duties of sovereign and subjects. No one doubts this, and it remains, with whatever admixture of philosophical and historical argument, the fundamental basis of political controversy, not only throughout the Middle Ages, but until the theory of Divine Right has passed away, and men have abandoned the attempt 4 • 42 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY to defend or controvert a doctrine, which has dis- appeared. Position of Em- peror bars Further, the position of the Emperor as in theory, lord of the world, must have had an influence, the way to however slight, in retarding the development of any theories of clear notions of sovereignty in the national states. ty in national States. In England, with its belief in the Imperial position of English kings', this influence may have been small or virtually non-existent. Yet the fact that an ignorant writer in the fourteenth century can declare that a statute which he dislikes is invalid, because it has received no confirmation from the Emperor', is evidence not indeed of the truth of his statement, but of the existence in men's minds of some lingering belief, a relic from earlier times, in the Imperial claims to universal sovereignty. In regard to France the writings of William of Ockham are evidence of a belief equally untrue to actual fact, that the Emperor in the fourteenth century was still possessed of inalienable rights of sovereignty over the French kings³. 1 Cf. Freeman, Norman Conquest, 1. 132, 3, and Appendix B, 552-556. 2 Mirror of Justices, Lib. v. c. 5, p. 195: cf. also the passage : Jurediccion est poer a dire droit. Cele poer dona deux a Moysen, e cel poer unt ceaux qi tenent oreson lu en terre, si com lapostoill e lempereur e de souz euz tient ore le Roi cele poer en son royaume." (L. IV. c. 3, p. 123.) 3 "Licet Imperator possit multas libertates concedere regi Franciae et aliis; tamen nullo modo potest regnum Franciae. vel aliud totaliter ab Imperio separare, ut nullo modo subsit Imperio. Quia hoc esset destruere Imperium, quod non potest Imperator." (Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. II. c. 7; Goldast, II. 908.) In the ninth chapter Ockham declares all kings to be subject to THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 43 of such a Moreover, in the notion that the Holy Roman Possibility Empire was but the continuation of the Empire of theory for the Caesars, the Flavii, and of Justinian, there was Emperor. the material for a theory of sovereignty, which the nations did not as yet possess. But, if the action of any power should operate to lower the prestige of the Emperor and to place kings upon a level with him, so that an English, or French king can speak of himself as Emperor¹, it would be only natural for the pretensions asserted by the civilians on behalf of the Emperor to pass over to them, and to be regarded as of the essence of all kingship that is real, i.e. Imperial. The mere use in later times of the phrase Imperial rights as equivalent to sovereignty is evidence of the source, from which the theory was derived³, the Emperor, even though he has not commanded it, and they are unaware of the fact. ¹ Richard II. in legitimating the Beauforts speaks of himself as "Entier Emperour de son Roialme." (Rot. Parl. 111. 343.) Raoul of Praelles declares, "Un chacun Roy est chief de son royaume, et Empereur de son Empire." (Goldast, 1. 51.) 2 Bishop Jewel asserts that what was the Emperor's right "is now a common right to all princes, for so much as kings are now possessed in the several parts of the whole Empire." Apology. Works, III. 98. 3 The Statute of Appeals in the well-known words of its preamble "this realm of England is an Empire" is an instance of this. Here it is plain that rights of empire are equivalent to rights of sovereignty. Phrases of this sort can only be explained by the fact that there was a belief, that true sovereignty, i.e. independence and unquestioned authority, had been derived from an appropri- ation by each kingdom of rights originally confined to the Empire. 44 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY Papacy reduced to an equality Kings. This work was performed by that power in Emperors the Empire, which overshadowed and eventually destroyed for all practical purposes that of its with other temporal head. It may indeed be doubted, whether the claims of the Emperor as lord of the world, to be universal sovereign and international arbiter¹, could ever have been brought into effect, as the new peoples awoke to the consciousness of national life. As a fact, however, it is certain that this was prevented by the action of the Papacy. In order to establish their own claims to supremacy, the Popes were driven to minimize the prerogatives of the Emperor, and to recognise in him less instead of more authority, than they did in the case of other kings. Thus all monarchies were free to appropriate such rags and trappings of his ancient majesty, as still belonged to the 'ever august increaser of the Empire' in the shape of theories of power that was never exercised and claims of sovereignty that was never effective. In the contest of the Popes with the Emperors was evolved a theory that was destined to play an important part in future anti- papal conflicts, and to perform during the period of the Reformation, the work that was too hard for it, when Pope John XXII. crushed Lewis of Bavaria. This theory was the divine right of secular govern- ments to be free from Papai control. It took shape Origin of theory of Divine Right of Kings. 3 The Empire as 2 Wyclif distinctly declares the division of the Empire to be due to the claim of the clergy to secular power. De Officio Regis, 1 See Bryce, Holy Roman Empire, Chap. xv. an International Power. 252. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 45 in the fourteenth century as the Divine Right of the Emperors. With various additions, of less importance than is commonly supposed, it was to re-form itself in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as the Divine Right of Kings. It is in the gradual rise of Papal claims to Theory of Papal su- universal supremacy, that are first put forth those premacy. conflict notions which form the basis of all theories of Divine Right; the conception of sovereignty, of the absolute freedom from positive laws of some power in an organized human society; the claim that this sovereignty is vested in a single person by God, and that resistance to the sovereign is the worst of sins. With two powers within the State in the relative positions of Pope and Emperor, it was inevitable that sooner or later there should arise between them a struggle for supremacy. The condition of coordinate Need of authority in two diverse but ill-defined spheres the state a unity in could not be one of lasting duration. Sooner or source of later the desire of power, coupled with a sense between of the need of unity in the society, must bring Popes and either temporal or spiritual head to claim for itself absolute supremacy. There could not fail to be awakened the sense, that the unity of the Christian commonwealth, whether as an earthly state or as a reflection of the Divine order, could be secured only by the recognition of the ultimate authority as vested in one or other of the two powers. Nor was it doubtful which of them had, as a fact, the best claim to superiority. At the best of times, the Emperor was hard put to it to maintain his position, even as king of Germany, against the disintegrating Emperors. 46 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY t of uni- versal Emperor tendencies of feudalism; while his authority over weak, Pope other nations as lord of the world, was, save strong and possessed perhaps under Charles the Great, of the most shadowy kind. The Pope on the other hand could authority. allege that with some limitations his jurisdiction was admitted by all western nations; and was effectively exercised. In every nation there was a large class of men subject to his tribunals, and exempt from the ordinary law, while in a number of matters only constructively ecclesiastical, such as testamentary and matrimonial cases, the Canon law regulated the lives of the laity, and drove numbers of them to the curia to buy justice. It is not surprising that there was developed against the Imperial claims a com- plete theory of Papal sovereignty. Later ages might dispute as to whether this sovereignty was direct or indirect, immediate or constructive. But, from the days of Hildebrand to those of Boniface VIII. and John XXII., the theory goes on developing and it is of course a theory of sovereignty by Divine Right. The doctrine of the plenitudo potestatis' is an assertion of the Pope's claim to sovereign power, as a direct grant from God to S. Peter and his successors¹. 1 The views of S. Thomas Aquinas on the subject are com- paratively moderate. Yet he declares all kings to be subject to the Pope, and alleges the great authority of the Druids in secular politics as a proof of the natural "superiority of sacerdotal power to royal. (De Regimine Principum, 1. 14.) The author, Ptolemy of Lucca, of the latter part of the treatise goes farther; he proclaims with emphasis the doctrine of the 'plenitudo potestatis' as one of absolute monarchy, vested in the Pope, and quotes the stock instances of Papal jurisdiction over the Empire. S. Thomas, it is noticeable, carefully avoids all debateable ground in his A { THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 47 ( The canonist could allege the donation of Constantine Arguments as evidence of temporal dominion, and with good claims. for Papal show of justice point to the translation of the Empire' from east to west, as proof that from the time of Charles the Great, the Emperor's authority was derived from the Pope. In support of the Pope's claim to judge of the fitness of the Electors' choice, he could urge the fact that no Emperor was more than Emperor-elect, until he had received coronation at the hands of the Pope. He could find in Scripture many passages asserting the superior dignity of priestly power to royal; and could explain away, as he pleased, any which bear at first sight an opposite sense. The image was ready to hand of the greater and the lesser lights signifying (it was plain) the spiritual and the temporal power; the two swords which Christ declared to be "enough, not too much" in the hands of His disciples, would form an apt illustration of the Papal authority in temporal as well as spiritual matters. And so it is proclaimed that the Pope cannot be bound by the Emperor¹, that Imperial laws are void, if they conflict with the Canon law, although the Church may commentary on Romans xiii.; but the position there taken up appears to differ widely from that afterwards assumed by Boniface VIII. (For a fuller account of the political theory of S. Thomas see Poole, Illustrations of the History of Medieval Thought, Chap. VIII. The Hierarchical Doctrine of the State.) A saeculari Potestate Pontifex prorsus nec solvi nec ligari valet." (Decret. Dist. xcvI. c. 7.) 2 Decret. Dist. x. c. 4. The usual method of argument is that of the next chapter, "Suscipitisne libertatem verbi? Libenter accipitis quod lex Christi sacerdotali vos subjicit 48 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY employ the laws of the Emperor to assist her', that the Emperor as the son, not the sovereign, of the Church is subject to the Pope, for did not Con- stantine give the Crown and all kingly dignity to Pope Sylvester³? Further, the translation of the Empire is a final proof of the Pope's supremacy over the Emperor whom he had set up of his own mere and proper motion. Against the Latin Emperor of Constantinople urging the command of S. Peter to obey the secular prince, Innocent III. can answer, that it applies only to those who hold their temporalities from him, or else that obedience is enjoined only for the Lord's sake and may there- fore presumably be neglected, if the Lord speaking through His vicar should order otherwise, or, thirdly, that the command to obey him is not without qualification. He can point to the commission of Jeremiah, "I have set thee over the nations and over the kingdoms to root out and to pull down, and to destroy," and, after drawing edifying conclusions from the lights in the firmament, finally crush his Imperial disputant with the commission to S. Peter. S potestati atque istis tribunalibus subdit? Dedit nam et nobis potestatem, dedit et principatum multo perfectiorem princi- patibus vestris. Aut numquid justum vobis videtur, si cedat spiritus carni, si terrenis caelestia superentur, si divinis prae- ferantur humana?" 1 Decret. Dist. x. c. 7. 2 Ibid. Dist. XCVI. c. 11, "Si Imperator Catholicus est, filius non praesul ecclesiae." 3 Ibid. c. 13. 4 Decret. Greg. Lib. I. Tit. vI. c. 34. 5 Ibid. Tit. XXXIII. c. 6. There is a delightful explanation of obedience being ordered not to 'the king,' but merely 'the king as THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 49 It is no new doctrine, that the theory of Papal A theory of sove- supremacy, with the power of releasing subjects reignty by from their allegiance and deposing kings, involves a Divine Right. claim to universal monarchy¹. It is clear, that the doctrine of the plenitudo potestatis embodies the most important elements of the theory of sovereignty, the notion, that is, that unity in a state is only to be obtained by the unquestioned supremacy of some one authority, whose acts are subject to no legal criticism. Further, it asserts the Divine institution. of monarchy, as a form of government. This was the position claimed by the Papacy; men were driven thus to formulate its pretensions by the sense of the need of unity in the commonwealth. They do so by asserting the unity of the Church and of the universe, the claims of the Pope to derive his power immediately from God alone, and to be subject to none other. This is expressed most clearly in the The Bull Bull Unam Sanctam. There Boniface VIII. after supreme,' "Nec pure sit subscriptum regi praecellenti, sed inter- positum forsitan non sine causâ, tanquam." Unam Sanctam. 1 An instance of the habit of alleging the Papal sovereignty in proof of the superiority of monarchy to other forms of govern- ment is the following passage of Barclay :-"Deus enim in suo peculiari populo hunc gubernandi modum expressit, unum illis ducem judicemque praeficiens. Ejusdem sic et Christus typum nobis edidit, sacratissimam illam monarchiam in persona Petri instituens......Neue in tam augusto perfectóque imperio imper- fectam regiminis formam post se sineret inolescere; unum omnium hierarcham esse voluit, quem tota ubique Ecclesia principem agnoscat pastorem. Quae res satis declarat, quanto caeteris gubernandi speciebus gratior sit unius principatus, ad quem omnes fere nationes, quantumuis barbarae et feroces, occulta quadam naturae vi, et primorum parentum exemplis incitantur." (De Regno, 82.) F. 4 50 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY Same method as that of seven- teenth century. f * asserting emphatically the unity of the Church and of all government and speaking of the unrent coat of Christ, declares that a body politic with two heads is a monstrosity. He employs the illustration of the two swords, declaring that the material sword is to be used for, not by the Church; and goes on to proclaim that the temporal power must be subject to the spiri- tual, that derelictions on the part of the temporal power may be judged by the spiritual, but that the supreme spiritual power is accountable to God alone. He quotes the commission to Jeremiah as proof that he is invested immediately by God with sovereign authority; and closes by applying to himself the command, "Whoso resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God¹." Now, here, it is to be noted, are the methods and arguments, which subsist until the close of the seventeenth century. The Pope proclaims for him- self a theory of complete sovereignty; he is king, the one true king, accountable to God alone; he asserts that unity is the soul of government, and that every government must have some supreme head as the centre of its unity; that the Christian commonwealth is a monarchy with this supreme authority vested in himself; he denies that there can be two ultimate authorities in the common- wealth, one temporal, one ecclesiastical; one must be subject to the other. He claims that his power comes from God alone, and is derived from no earthly intermediary. He declares that, on no pretence whatsoever, is resistance allowable to this 1 Extrav. Commun. Lib. 1. Tit. VIII. c. 7. g THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 51 divinely ordained sovereign; while, in order to prove his doctrine of non-resistance to Papal commands, he employs the very text, which a later age makes the bulwark of its defence against the Pope in the claim that resistance to the king as God's vicar is worthy of damnation. Here then is a theory of government by Divine Right, the exact converse of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings. It will be strange if the latter doc- trine is not found to have its raison d'être as a contradic- tion and a counter-theory to that of Papal supremacy. of obedi- Once more, it is to be remarked that the theory A theory described above is essentially one of obedience, and ence, not of obedience from motives based upon religion. It of liberty. is needful to bear this fact in mind. In the pursuit of their own aims the Popes were frequently driven to dissolve the bonds of allegiance in communities. Their supporters will speak slightingly of the duties of subjects to their sovereign. In their zeal for Papal authority, they will be found developing that theory of an original compact, which lies at the root of all theories of popular rights in the seventeenth century. Yet this was but an accident of the Papal position. Of its essence was the claim to the implicit obedience of all men, based upon even stronger sanctions of eter- nal punishment, than was the Divine Right of Kings. Hildebrand indeed may argue that all secular government is of diabolic origin¹. John of Salisbury may quaintly decide the question as to whether it be lawful to flatter a tyrant, by the suggestion that it is lawful to flatter a man whom it is lawful to kill². 2 Policraticus, 111. 15. 1 Migne, Patrologia, 148, 595. 4-2 52 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 4 as wel With evident leaning to the more lenient view, S. Thomas Aquinas may debate the point as to whether a nation acting in common may restrain the excesses of a tyrant, and declare in an obiter dictum that regal as distinct from political power is a con- sequence of the Fall'. Lastly, John XXII., who in the Bull Si fratrum takes up a position of complete sovereignty and claims that, the Imperial authority being merely a delegation from the Pope, it reverts to him during an interregnum2, may seem to ascribe to the Emperor the same merely official position as delegate of another earthly power, as was attributed to kings by Whig theorists. Yet all this is not because these men believe government and obe- dience to be things of small importance with 'the trail of the serpent over them all.' It is because government is in their eyes a sacred thing, and obedience an integral part of the Divine Law, that they cannot conceive of secular government, as possessing any beyond subordinate authority. All power is of God; therefore the temporal power is only secondary, and must be subject to the spiritual. Obedience to governors is a Divine in- junction; therefore in the last resort all men must obey the Pope, the depositary of Divine authority as against King or Emperor, whose position is either, as some say, of merely human origin, or, as in another view, a grant from God through the mediation of the Pope. Men must obey a king, although obedience Garda ¹ De Regimine Principum, 1. 6. He is quite clear that private individuals are forbidden to resist the sovereign. 2 Extrav. Joh. Tit. v. c. 1. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 53 involves disloyalty to an immediate lord, the king's vassal; but the Emperor is God's vassal, therefore he may be deposed at the bidding of the Pope, whose word is the voice of God. So far indeed were the Popes from claiming on behalf of subjects any general rights against their sovereign, that, as in the case of John or Henry III. in England or of the Spanish monarchy, they ever shewed themselves stern supporters of royal rights, where they felt sure of the king. The very claim to release subjects from their oath of allegiance implies that the oath is binding without such release on the part of the Pope. In essence the theory of Papal sovereignty is a doctrine of obedience, of the Divine institution of all government, simply and strictly so called,' and of perfect sovereignty vested in a single head. It is merely an accident that the theory was accompanied by views of the rights of resistance against governors of the secondary order, whose authority is merely delegated. Absolute monarchy deriving its title from God alone, and obedience as a Divine command, are the root ideas of Papal theories of dominion. Empire. Now against these claims it was needful for the 4 counter theory Imperialists to manufacture some weapon. The needed materials were ready to hand. The Pope had for the claimed entire sovereignty because the common- wealth was one, and two authorities in it are a monstrosity; the Imperialists must do the same. The Pope had claimed rights of jurisdiction over the Emperor as shewn by the donation of Con- stantine and the translation of the Empire; the 54 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY Imperialists must argue that the donation of Constantine if a fact, was invalid, and that the translation of the Empire had been misinterpreted. They could maintain that, since the Empire was inalienable, Constantine could not have given lasting authority to the Papacy, and that the Pope, far from creating Charles the Great Emperor, had merely assented to a fait accompli; that so far was the Pope from possessing a right to review the choice of the electors of the Holy Roman Empire, that the Emperor possessed the right of reviewing the choice of the conclave, and of examining into the fitness of a proposed occupant of the Papal chair; and that, as a fact, this right had been exercised. Lastly, the Pope had claimed Divine Right for his sovereignty, the Emperor must claim it for his. He must demonstrate that the Empire is held of God immediately and not of the Pope; that, since the Emperor is God's vicar, he cannot be the Pope's vassal; that the passages of Scripture alleged in support of the duty of unlimited obedience to the Pope are, if rightly interpreted, evidences of the un- conditioned authority of the Emperor; that the words "my kingdom is not of this world" shew the falsity of the pretended Papal supremacy; that the true heretic is not he who denies, but he who asserts that supremacy; that the command to "Render unto Cæsar the things that are Cæsar's," and the words of Christ to Pilate, "Thou couldest have no power at all against me, unless it were given thee from above," prove at once that the Pope has no universal sovereignty and that secular government • THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 55 is of Divine appointment. In a word, to the Divine Divine Right of the Pope must be opposed the Divine Right of Right of the Emperor. opposed to Divine Imperialist writers claim in the first place that Right of unity, the soul of government" is entirely lost, if Pope. Unity there be two distinct powers with competing systems needed of law and jurisdiction claiming authority at the in a same time; for "every kingdom divided against wealth. itself cannot stand." This is the burden of a great part of the Defensor Pacis of Marsiglio¹ of Padua, of the great Dialogus of William of Ockham², and of common- (( ¹ Defensor Pacis, 1. 17; the whole of the second part is taken up with a demolition of the Papal pretensions, the great cause of disturbance and discord in the Empire. Cf. Hobbes's Leviathan, Bk. III., "The Kingdom of Darkness," where the Church of Rome is regarded in the same way as above all things the enemy of peace in a State. 2 E.g. the following passage: "Non solum illa societas est propinqua desolationi et ruinae, quae est contra se divisa; sed etiam illa quae ex modo regendi est disposita ad divisionem et divisioni propinqua. Sed si communitas fidelium habeat duas partes quarum una habeat judicem summum, et alia alium; communitas illa est disposita ad divisionem et divisioni pro- pinqua." Ockham is feeling his way to the notion of territorial sovereignty, though it was entirely alien from the early theory of the Empire. "Potestas non solum est impatiens consortis super eosdem subjectos; sed etiam impatiens est consortis in eodem loco; sicut enim judex aliquis nollet, quod subditi sui essent alterius subditi; ita nollet quod aliquis alius haberet potestatem in loco, ubi subditi sui morantur. Ergo non solum est periculosa societas fidelium, si sint plures judices super eosdem populos vel subditos; sed etiam periculosa est societas fidelium, si in eodem loco etiam super diversos subditos fideles fuerint plures summi judices con- stituti, et ita non expedit quod clerici habeant unum summum judicem ecclesiasticum, scilicet papam; et laici unum summum judicem scilicet imperatorem; cum clerici et laici in eisdem locis simul commaneant......Nulla communitas simul viventium vita 56 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY the De Monarchia of Dante'. A large section of the work of William of Ockham could have no more appropriate title than "the anarchy of a mixed monarchy." Need of unity in the State an argu- ment for This passionate sense of the importance of unity in the State is the ground of much of the sentiment not only against the Pope, but also monarchy against those who propose any but a single person as head of the State. It cannot be denied that "unity, the soul of government," is theoretically more completely realised in a monarchy than in any other form of government. At least there is no danger of the sovereign power dividing from within and splitting into two hostile factions, as may be the case with government under a repre- sentative system. There could be no fear of a schism in Prince or Pope as there might be in Parliament or Council. If this be taken into account, and the reaction against Papal claims be admitted as a ground of the feeling that unity in the State must be secured at all costs, there will be less inclination to blame the men in the seventeenth politica est optime ordinata, nisi sit civiliter una. Unde fideles sicut sunt unum corpus in Christo (ad Rom. 1. 2), ita etiam debent esse corpus seu collegium in vita civili: sed communitas illa quae habet diversos summos judices seu diversa capita sive rectores, non est civiliter una; sicut illi, qui non habent unum regem, non sunt unum regnum." (Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. III. c. 19.) 1 Dante argues that God cannot will what is contrary to nature; apparently he means by this that God cannot approve of any competing jurisdiction within the Empire, or of any earthly authority claiming to restrain the acts of "the lord of the world.” (De Monarchia, III.) THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 57 that Similarity of argu- same ments in and seven- or the fourteenth century', who argued that not only must there be one sovereign and not two, but that the sovereign must be one person, or else unity cannot be secured. The noteworthy fact is the arguments employed are precisely the in the fourteenth as in the seventeenth century. fourteenth Ockham's long argument to shew that the Emperor teenth cen- is "over all persons and all causes supreme 2" is turies. on exactly the same lines as those of later times on behalf of royal authority against Papal inter- ference; save that Ockham treats the Pope as an authority within the State, while English writers regard him as a foreign sovereign. elements There appear other elements of the theory of Other sovereignty. It is a maxim with anti-papal contro- of theory versialists that sovereignty is inalienable. Thus of sove- reignty. Dante and Ockham are found arguing that the 4 1 Dante indeed carries the argument further and makes it the basis of his proof of the need of a universal monarchy. Monarchia, Lib. 1. De 2 Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. III. cc. 16-23. What could express more completely the claim to be 'supreme over all causes' than the following passage? "Concluditur ergo, quod communitas fidelium non erit optime gubernata civiliter, etiam quantum ad vitam politicam, nisi tota et omnis pars ejus habeat unum judicem et rectorem supremum, de cujus jurisdictione immediata vel mediata in omni casu ab eo vel à judicibus inferioribus eo omnis alius pro quocunque delicto debeat judicari." (Ibid. c. 20.) The words I have italicised shew that secular politics are not the primary consideration of the author. Supra, pp. 39-41. 8 De Monarchia, III. 10. 4 Ockham's argument is that the Empire, not having been founded by the Pope, could not afterwards have become subject to him; any action of the Emperor with that object is invalid, for it destroys the Empire. Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. I. c. 18. 58 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY donation of Constantine must be invalid, for the Emperor may not destroy the Empire. Ockham declares that sovereignty can neither be divided, nor diminished, nor alienated'; although his notions. of obedience are not those of later times. In the seventeenth century all these notions reappear. The king grants privileges to Parliament, but sovereignty is inalienable, therefore they may be revoked. He governs by the law, because he is virtuous, not be- cause he is obliged by it. He cannot by diminishing his sovereignty prejudice the rights of his successors. corona- tion and in later times. } Even the special points, around which later controversy rages, are discussed. The importance of coronation is insisted upon by Papalists, as a unction, as means of proving that the Emperor holds his office from the Pope, exactly as in the later times it is held to be evidence of a compact between king and people. The author of the latter part of the De Regimine Principum regards the ceremony of unction, as evidence of the authority over kings vested in the Pope, the interpreter of the Divine Law; the king is the Lord's anointed; and therefore the Lord by means of His vicar may exercise authority over him². Controversialists assert, on the other side, precisely as those of later times, that coronation has no necessary place in conferring royal or imperial power, which exists equally before it. There are *** Contro- versy about 1 "Romanum imperium non potest minui nec dividi, saltem absque consensu tacito vel expresso communitatis mortalium." (Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. 1. c. 31.) 2 De Regimine Principum, III. 16. 3 "Omnem gladii potestatem et administrationem temporalem THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 59 arguments, quite in the manner of Hickes, to prove that an infidel may be the lawful recipient of obedi- ence; special stress is laid on the case of Julian the Apostate, just as French writers on behalf of Henry IV. and English opponents of the Exclusion Bill were to argue, that since the primitive Christians were loyal to Julian, the fact of the heir being a heretic could not bar his claim to the succession. S than this But this was not enough. It was vain to demon- More strate the necessity of unity in a stable common- needed. wealth. The Papalist was as ardent an enthusiast for unity as the Imperialist. Indeed, had the dream of Papal sovereignty ever been entirely realised in practice, it would not have been of the lack of unity in the governing authority that men would have complained. It was useless to prove the incon- venience of the Papal claims or the utility of the Imperial power. What could avail considerations of expediency and theories of utility against an opponent, who claimed to exercise power derived by a direct grant from God? The only effective method Divine Right of controverting the Papal pretensions was to ela- borate a counter theory that the Emperor's rights claimed for the came direct from God. Emperor. must be Dante perceived the necessity of this more clearly Dante than some other Imperialist writers. This it is, this. The perceived which gives to the De Monarchia a value, as a con- De Mon- troversial treatise, far above that of other works in many ways more interesting. Dante meets the archia. habent ante coronationem quam habent post.' (Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. I. Lib. I. c. 22.) Cp. also the Octo Quaestiones of the same writer. 60 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY Papal claim to a universal sovereignty by Divine Right with a direct counter-claim on behalf of the Empire. He shews that a universal monarchy is ordained by God, that the Roman Empire won its position through God's grant, and that the Emperor derives his authority not from the Church, but immediately from God. Since all power is of God, if the Emperor's power be lawful at all, the only question is whether it comes from God directly, or through the medium of the Church. Dante occupies himself with a careful demolition of the Papalist arguments, thus proving indirectly that the Emperor holds his crown immediately from God alone; he finally proves this directly. Even had Dante written no other work than the De Monarchia, it would be hard to refrain from admiration of the mind, which struck out with such force and lucidity the line of argument, which was to remain for centuries the one effectual answer to all claims of the right of Papal or clerical interference with the freedom of secular governments. By its intellectual grasp and breadth of treatment, the De Monarchia, despite its scholastic character, is raised far above the great majority of controversial treatises on the same subject. It is easy for us to admire the political philosophy Defensor of Marsiglio¹, to hail him as the earliest upholder of Marsiglio of Padua, Pacis. ¹ Defensor Pacis, 1. 12, 13. For a further exposition of Marsiglio's philosophy and its relation to modern thought see Poole, Illustrations of the History of Medieval Thought, chap. 9, The opposition to the temporal claims of the Papacy: also Wycliffe and Movements of Reform, 28-42. On his teaching of religious toleration, see Creighton, Persecution and Tolerance, 94-97. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 61 religious toleration and to recognise his acuteness in striking out the notion of representative democracy. Yet it is impossible not to feel that this very fact, the modern character of the Defensor Pacis, which renders its interest so great, must have detracted from its controversial value. As a counterblast to the Papal claims, it is far less effective than Dante's short work, and lacks the ring of enthusiasm which vibrates through every page of the De Monarchia. and Moreover, both Marsiglio of Padua and William Utili- of Ockham are largely, though not exclusively, con- tarian ar- guments of cerned with utilitarian arguments, and utilitarian Marsiglio arguments must ever appear beside the point to an Ockham. opponent arguing on behalf of an authority which he believes to be Divine. Again, both these authors allow to subjects some right of resisting the sove- reign¹. Such an admission made immensely in favour of the Papacy. For if resistance or coercion. of the prince be justified at all, clearly it must be so in defence of the Divine Law, and who is to inter- pret the Divine Law save the vicar of Christ? Further, the notion of Marsiglio that the true legislative authority is the people may have the merit of anticipating modern ideas²; but it weakened his position as a controversialist. from the dignity and authority of the Emperor, the For it detracted 1 Defensor Pacis, 1. c. 18. Ockham argues that monarchy is the best form of government, because it is easier to restrain a single head of the State. "Facilius sit populo emendare unum rectorem (si taliter exorbitaverit), ut sit puniendus vel etiam amovendus, quam plures." (Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. Lib. 1. c. 13.) Defensor Pacis, 1. 12, 13. Take anyth 62 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY William of Ockham. only power whom it was possible to regard as upon a level with the Pope. If, as Marsiglio claimed, the Emperor was to have coercive authority over the Pope, he needed every possible accession of dignity and prerogative. It was absurd to lay claim to this position, for one who is not conceived as truly sove- reign, but is merely an official executing the will of the true sovereign, the people. So exalted a privilege as that of judging the vicar of God, asserted on behalf of a merely representative Emperor, must have ap- peared supremely ridiculous in the eyes of men, for whom Canossa was the terminus a quo of Papal assumption, while their theory of ecclesiastical dominion exceeded the wildest dreams of Gregory VII. or Innocent III. Both William of Ockham and Marsiglio of Padua assert, that the Emperor's power is from God. But both of them regard the constitution of the Empire and even its existence as of human institution¹; if in the future it should transgress the principle of utility, it may be abolished. For both of them it arises by human, not Divine ordinance. Yet Marsiglio regards the Emperor as God's vicar in a far fuller and truer sense than is the Pope. With the rights of the Electors still effectively exercised, it was plainly impossible to assert any such claim of im- mediate investiture by God, as might be claimed for hereditary monarchs. Although, however, Mar- Kateg 1 Defensor Pacis, 1. 18. Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. 11. L. 1. cc. 8, 29-31. Marsiglio expressly disclaims any inquiry into the Mosaic polity, which was ordained directly by God; he is concerned only with principalities set up by human law. (1. 9.) THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 63 siglio¹ and William of Ockham are aware that some Divine authority must be asserted on behalf of the Imperial power, they are far too much governed by the notion of utility to make this the kernel of their work. Ockham indeed, in a passage that sounds to modern ears like an echo of Hobbes, places the origination of the Empire in the people². The account, as may be supposed, is far less historically accurate, than is that of Dante. The latter is so deeply wedded to the notion that the Empire is held immediately from God alone, that he regards the electors, not as themselves choosing the Emperor, but as merely announcing God's choice³. In asserting his claim to supremacy the Pope Conflict of came into collision not merely with the decaying with the Papacy forces of the Empire, but with the rising nationalities France. of Europe, which were growing stronger every year, as feudalism gave way before the central power. Perhaps the most dramatic achievement of the middle ages, if the journey of Henry IV. to Canossa be excepted, was the repudiation by Philip the Fair of the claim of Boniface VIII. to a position of com- plete supremacy over all earthly potentates. In the Bull Unam Sanctam Boniface VIII. had carried Papal assumption to its highest point; and the ruin, that in consequence befell him, forms the 4 1 Defensor Pacis, II. 30. Marsiglio is at pains to expound the true meaning of Rom. xiii., and to declare in strong terms the sin of resisting the ordinance of God. (Ibid. 11. 25.) 2 Dialogus, Pars III. Tr. II. L. 1. c. 8. 3 De Monarchia, III. 16. 4 Supra, p. 49. 64 THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY starting-point of all later French argument against the political claims of the Papacy. Praelles, 1370. From this time forth the freedom of France from Papal interference is the despairing admiration of Imperialist authors'. It is not then a matter for surprise, that writers in France begin to develope the same notions of the Divine Right of secular govern- Raoul of ments, as are to be found in the Empire. One author in the fourteenth century asserts with emphasis, that the French king holds his kingdom immediately from God alone. Another argues, that, all priesthood before Christ being merely typical, kingship is the older and therefore the superior of the two. He declares, that the Papal authority cannot come im- mediately from God, for in that case the prince would be the servant of the Pope, as he is of Christ, and this would be to contradict the xiiith of Romans, where the king is spoken of as the vicar of God, not the Pope¹; he goes on to argue in the usual manner from the words, "Touch not mine anointed" and other texts". M Theory of Divine Right in France. John of Paris, 1305. Summary. Thus it appears that from the beginning of the middle ages politics were conceived as essentially a branch of theology; that the Popes were gradually driven by the exigencies of their position to claim for themselves a position of perfect sovereignty, 1 Ockham repeatedly alleges the case of the King of France, who is admittedly free from Papal interference, as an argument on behalf of the Emperor. 2 "Il tient et possede son Royaume de Dieu tant seulemen sans aucun moyen en tele maniere, que il ne se tient de quelque homme, ne qu'il ne le tient du Vicaire de Jhesu Christ, ne en tant come homme, ne en tant com son Vicaire." (Goldast, I. 49.) 3 De Potestate Regia et Papalia, cc. 4, 5. 4 Ibid. c. 11. 5 Ibid. c. 14. THE HOLY ROMAN EMPIRE AND THE PAPACY 65 sovereignty by Divine Right, disobedience to which is a mortal sin; that, as against this doctrine, the supporters of the Emperor formulated a theory of sovereignty based upon the ground of the necessity of unity in the state; that they met the Pope's pretensions to supremacy as God's vicar by asserting, all of them in some measure, Dante most clearly and completely, that the Emperor's authority exists by Divine Right and comes by grace of God, not of the Pope; that they applied to him the scriptural injunctions to obedience, which Boniface VIII. made bold to wrest into a command of unlimited obedience to the Papacy; and, lastly, that this or a similar position was taken up by writers on behalf of the French king. The necessity of unity as the foundation of sovereignty, and the Divine Right of secular governments to be free from Papal inter- ference are the root ideas of Imperialist writers. The Divine Right of the Emperor is asserted not for its own sake, but against a similar claim to Divine Right put forward by the Pope. Both sides recognise that power is of God, both are aware that there must be in the state some supreme authority above the law. But in one view the Divine source of all authority is held to carry with it the supre- macy of the spiritual power. These pretensions could only be met by the assertion, that secular government was not merely allowed but was actually ordained by God, and that the secular prince held immediately of Him with no intervening authority; or in the words of John of Jandun, Potestas im- perialis est immediate a Deo, non a Papa. F. 5 English claims of freedom from Papal control. CHAPTER IV WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II. IN the middle ages thought and learning were international, and it would be strange, if the con- troversies which were seething on the Continent during the earlier part of the fourteenth century found no counterpart in England. Moreover William of Ockham was an Englishman and an Oxonian. England had claimed for long to be an Empire; freedom from Papal interference was more or less an aspiration of English statesmen from the times of the Conqueror and Henry II. Even at the period of completest subjection to the Papacy, the Barons could meet the attempt to assimilate the English law of inheritance to the rules of the Canon law with the emphatic negative "nolumus leges Angliae mutari¹” From the time of Edward I., who outlawed the clergy rather than submit to the bull Clericis laicos, there had been passed a series of statutes in restraint of Papal claims. All this might well induce a writer with an anticlerical bias or a monarch with high ideas of his own dignity, to claim complete 'freedom,' 1 Statute of Merton, c. 9. - WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 67 i.e. sovereignty for the English Crown, and to claim it as coming by Divine Right. This view finds expression in the writings of Wycliffe, and is also, so far as we can gather, the basis of the definite theory of kingship held by King Richard II. I. The De Officio Regis was written by Wycliffe Wycliffe's 'De Officio rather with the object of asserting the duty of the Regis.' sovereign to assist' the Church by disendowing the clergy of their temporalities¹ than with any direct purpose of exalting regal as against Papal authority. Yet the writer bases his practical exhortations upon a doctrine very similar to that proclaimed in the Empire and France. The king is God's vicar in things Royal temporal, as is the priest in things spiritual. But superior to the dignity of the king is superior to that of the sacerdotal. priest, for the king reflects the godhead of Christ, the priest only His manhood. Thus the spiritual power 1 De Officio Regis, 216. The references are to the pages in the Wycliffe Society's Edition. 2 Ibid. 73. "Non enim est jus humanum nisi de quanto fundatum fuerit in lege Dei divina." This is the fundamental basis on which all anti-papal writers ground their theory of Divine Right. There is no humau right except by God's law. But there are real human rights. Therefore divine authority must be asserted for them. Starting from the same major premiss the Pope drew the conclusion that all human rights centred in him; and thereby would have ultimately dissolved them. Those who felt the importance of justifying secular governments, were forced to argue that they have true rights by Divine law independent of the Papal grant. 3 Ibid. 12-14. "Ex quibus videtur, quod oportet vicarium Cristi sub racione qua Christus per vicarium Cristi sub racione qua deus capitaliter regulari.” X 5-2 68 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II : power is inferior to the temporal in earthly dignity and authority, although in true dignity the priest excels the king. The famous decretal of Innocent III. is explained away, and a theory extracted from it of the complete sovereignty of the temporal power¹. The author admits that of the two jurisdictions, the secular and the ecclesiastical, one must control the other. But he argues that the more perfect state has not always the higher authority; Christ's clean- sing of the temple is an imperial, His submitting to death a sacerdotal act; hence royal authority is the higher. There must be one supreme head in a state, else there will be confusion; the temporal power is this head, and it is not enough to have the king supreme in temporals, he must be supreme in all causes. Wycliffe is not certain, which of the two Malay ¹ Supra, p. 48. De Officio Regis, 34-36. The argument is less sophistical than might appear. For Innocent's letter was merely about a question of precedence, and might be held to imply no more, than would a claim to give the toast "Church and State." Compare Cardinal Vaughan's explanation of his giving the toast "The Pope and the Queen" at the Mansion House in 1893. 2 Ibid. 137. "Unde Cristus quedam fecit ut Imperator, ut ementes et vendentes in templo flagellando ejecit. i q. iii Ex Multis, quedam ut sacerdos cum se ipsum in cruce obtulit. Cum igitur prior potestas habet racionem agentis eciam in sacerdotes, secunda vero potestas habet racionem pacientis eciam ab eisdem sacerdotibus, videtur quod ex hoc naturali principio ‘agens est pre- stancius passo,' potestas regali. sit prestancior potestate sacer- dotali." 3 Ibid. 138, 9. "Item vel oportet illas potestates ex equo haberi vel unam subordinari alteri. Si enim neutra subordinaretur alteri secundum leges humanas vergeret ad confusionem ecclesie." We note here as elsewhere in Wycliffe that the term ecclesia is used indifferently of commonwealth or church; there is no thought of two societies. WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 69 powers is truly greater, yet the Pope cannot be above the Emperor in the sight either of God or man; for he is his minister¹. Besides (according to S. Augustine) Adam was the first king, and Cain the first priest2. Priests should not refuse to be called the king's priests". The common arguments and illustrations are employed. The Pope was the liegeman of the Emperor before the donation of Constantine, and he can never have ceased to be so since. Emperors have deposed Popes". To understand Romans iii. or 1 Peter ii. of any but the secular power is sophistry". above the Wycliffe will not allow that the king is subject The King to positive law. He should obey his own laws but Law. his obedience is voluntary, not by compulsion. For the king is solutus legibus; and when law is spoken of as governing him it is moral or Divine and, not positive law that is intended". For him as for Ockham the necessity of unity in the state is the main proof of the excellence of monarchy. 1 De Officio Regis, 143. "Unum audenter assero, quod nec clamor cleri nostri nec scriptura faciunt quod papa iste sit majus cesare, vel quo ad seculum vel quo ad deum. Nam ministrare sacramenta non est opus auctoritatis sed vicarie servitutis, sed conducere et precipere taliter ministrare. Quod autem papa sit sic magnus reputative quo ad mundum hoc habet a cesare.' 2 Ibid. 144. 3 Ibid. 197. 4 Ibid. 202. 5 Ibid. 128. 6 Ibid. 67. 7 Ibid. 93 sqq. After defining the law of reason or nature, he goes on: "Lex contracta per civilitatem connotat supra talem veritatem ordinacionem et promulgacionem humanam ad civile dominium regulandum, et sic est rex principalis conditor legis sue." 8 Ibid. 246. "" 70 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD JI Incon- sistency of notions upon obedience. Similar theory to Here is a theory of sovereignty, vested in the that of Im- king by Divine Right and in no way subject to the perialists. Pope. It can hardly be supposed, that so great a scholar as Wycliffe wrote his treatise in ignorance of the works of Ockham. Although its method is not quite the same, and the whole book is inferior in grasp and insight to that of the earlier author, yet the conclusions are the same, and it cannot be assuming too much to suppose, that the Im- perialist theory influenced English thought in this way. It need scarcely be mentioned, that with Wy- cliffe's theory of dominion founded in grace, a bad king has no real dominion¹. Yet in Wycliffe's system this would be no bar to a doctrine of un- limited obedience. Throughout the greater portion of his work he appears to uphold a theory of this sort, arguing in favour of passive obedience and quoting with approval the examples of the Saviour and the primitive Christians. Yet in other places he con- tradicts this, first declaring that it is possible to obey by resisting (by which he might mean no more than passive obedience), but going on to in- culcate the duty of rebellion and even tyrannicide as possible modes of obedience. It is impossible to 1 De Officio Regis, 17. Tyrants have power but not dominion. "Realiter habent potestatem et dignitatem consequentem secun- dum quam regunt... Sed illa potestas non est dominium." 2 For expositions of Wycliffe's theory of Lordship, sec Poole, Illustrations of the History of Medieval Thought, Ch. x.; Wycliffe, Movements of Reform, Chap. VI. 3 De Officio Regis, 6 sqq. 4 Ibid. 82. • Ibid. 201. WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 71 acquit him of inconsistency in this respect. Indeed, this same inconsistency is found in Marsiglio and Ockham. Both of them emphatically proclaim the authority of the Scriptural prohibitions of resistance, yet in certain cases they seem to approve it. this. It is only natural that this should be the case. Causes of The writers of the fourteenth century were en- gaged in elaborating an anti-papal theory. In a doctrine, which is only in the making, it is vain to look for the same harmony and consistency in all its parts, as is to be found, for instance, in the developed theory of the Divine Right of Kings. Yet there is no doubt, that this admission of a right of resistance, however qualified, gives away the whole case against the Papacy. Once resistance under any circum- stances be admitted, heresy is seen to be a plain case for it, and the Pope on any view is the judge of that. Wycliffe condemns all who resist a tyrant, save on behalf of God's law; he will have nothing to do with utilitarian obedience¹. Now this is to pro- claim a doctrine of complete subjection, so far as civil matters are concerned, while by implication it 1 De Officio Regis, 8. "Vel illata est iniuria quo ad causam propriam vel pure quo ad causam dei. In primo casu post exhorta- cionem evangelicam paciencia est optima medicina. Si pure in causa dei cristianus debet, post correpcionem evangelicam, preposito suo usque ad mortem, si oportet, confidenter et obedienter resistere. Et sic utrobique innitendum est paciencie, comittendo humiliter deo judicium iniuriam vindicandi.' Et qui excedit hanc regulam resistit dampnabiliter potestati et dei ordinacioni, ut faciunt hii qui rebellant precipue, id est affeccione comodi temporalis potestatis." Mutatis mutandis, Wycliffe's view is that of Bel- larmine. 72 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II grants to the Pope, as the interpreter of the Divine Law, the right of interference in all states. Wycliffe takes away the independence of the prince without establishing the liberty of the subject; and his theory, if practically carried out, would have been used to support both the tyranny of an orthodox¹ king, and the interference of a meddlesome Pope. It would have had all the disadvantages of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings combined with those of clerical supremacy, and would have been without the advantages of either doctrine. But this was not foreseen by Wycliffe, and the main drift of his work is to inculcate the universal authority of the Crown and the religious duty of submission to it on the part of all classes. Until religious toleration should become an accepted maxim, or the claim of Pope or clergy to authority in spiritual things be disallowed, there was no completely effective method of meeting the Papal claim to political supremacy save by a theory of absolute non-resistance and Divine Right. It should, however, be said that both Wycliffe and Marsiglio are anti-clericalist and Erastian even as regards religion, and would not have admitted the final authority of the Pope in questions of faith and morals. 1 'Orthodox' here must be taken to mean orthodox in the view of the recognized spiritual authority, whether Pope or "poor priest." The theory really subjects the temporal power to the spiritual, and would justify all ecclesiastical theories of politics. WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 73 II. influences II. Whether the speculations of Wycliffe exercised Possible any influence over Richard II. may be doubted. upon Nor is there evidence that his theory of kingship Richard was in any way derived from the writings of the Imperialist advocates. Yet at least it is certain that men could not remain unaffected by the great controversy between John XXII. and Lewis of Bavaria, and that the ideas expressed by writers on behalf of the Emperor would be peculiarly welcome to Englishmen. Nor can it be denied that the assertion about this time of the independence of England from Papal interference might easily move a man of Richard's narrowly logical type of mind to claim for himself the position of an absolute monarch by Divine Right. He was the last person to ignore the significance of the preamble to the great Statute of Praemunire, which asserts, that "this crown of England hath been so free at all times that it hath been in no earthly subjection in all things touching the regality of the said crown¹." If this were really His so, he would take care to maintain intact the "right position and liberty of the crown," and would see to it, that papal. no Parliamentary or baronial combination should drive him to abate it one jot or tittle. Although we find him attacked for lowering his dignity before the Pope, this is undoubtedly a case of collusion, in which anti- 1 16 Ric. II. c. 5, Statutes of the Realm. 2 Articles of Deposition, c. 10. Cf. also Walsingham, 11. 203; the king and John of Gaunt are regarded as more inclined than Parliament to yield to the Pope in regard to the repeal of the Statute of Provisors. 74 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II he sought to obtain the Pope's authority for the great constitutional changes of the Parliament of Shrews- bury. When it is his interest, he is willing enough that Archbishop Arundel should be translated to S. Andrew's, by Papal authority; yet he complains to the clergy of the abominable custom of Papal trans- lations, which in the case of Archbishop Nevill had been employed as a political weapon against himself; and he offers his support, if they will make a stand in the matter against the see of Rome¹. He cannot understand why the Pope should demand the repeal of the "statutes" of Praemunire and Quare Impedit, although he is glad to learn that his Holiness has no desire to diminish the right and liberty of the Crown of England. When he is on the side of the Pope, it is for reasons of immediate convenience; at heart he is as anti-papal as Henry VIII. Indeed, he was accused of interfering with the ecclesiastical courts". But whether or no Richard was influenced by theory of the writings of Wycliffe and the Imperialist theory, monarchy. he certainly believed in the sacredness of his office and in the 'liberty' of his Crown more strongly than any of his predecessors, and devoted all his energies 3 Richard's 1 Walsingham, 11. 228. 2 John Malverne in Appendix to Higden, Ix. 256. " Walsingham, II. 108; Higden, ix. 26. 4 Articles of Deposition, c. 29. In regard to a dispute as to an election of the Abbot of S. Edmondsbury we are told, that "the seide kynge sende embassiatours to the Pope commawndyng them to saye to the pope, that his wylle schoeld not be flexible in this matter." Appendix Iv. to Higden's Polychronicon, VIII. 452; Walsingham, II. 68. Richard afterwards yielded, much to the disgust of Wal- singham. "Sicut Ecclesiae Anglicanae detrimentum, ita Papae et curialibus magnam peperit materiam insolescendi." (Ibid. 97.) WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 75 to the establishment of a despotism. He is ever nervously 'guarding' and 'saving' his Crown and dignity. In the shrill tones of the doctrinaire poli- tician, he repeatedly declares that nothing he does shall prejudice his prerogative. On the nobles threatening him with deposition he gives way 'saving the rights of the Crown'. The commission of 1386 he sincerely regards as void, as being against the liberty of the Crown². He is the sole source of law, not bound by customs; king by God's grace and right of birth, he will not endure that his liberty be touched. Nor did Richard confine himself to words. He His tampered with the Rolls of Parliament'; he altered practice. and nullified statutes agreed upon by both Houses of Parliament. He exercised a dispensing power that was liberal beyond the custom of such a king 1 John Malverne, Appendix to Higden's Polychronicon, ix. 115. 2 Richard appears to have felt that in assenting to the demands of this commission he was virtually resigning the crown. Walsing- ham, II. 152. Cf. also Rot. Parl. III. 224, "Le roi en plein Parle- ment, devant le fyn d'icell, fist overte Protestation par sa bouche demesne, Qe puriens qu'estoit fait en le dit Parlement il ne vorroit que prejudice avendroit a lui ne a sa corone; einz que sa Prerogatif et les Libertees de sa dite Corone feussent sauvez et gardez." 3 "Rex...dixit expresse vultu austero et protervo, quod leges suae erant in ore suo, et aliquotiens in pectore suo, et quod ipse solus possit mutare et condere leges regni sui." Articles of Deposi- tion, c. 16. 4 Rot. Parl. III. 339. "Walsingham, 11. 227; Articles of Deposition, c. 8. • Walsingham, II. 48. "Sed quid juvant Statuta Parliamen- torum, cum penitus expost nullum sortiantur effectum? Rex nempe cum Privato Consilio cuncta vel mutare vel delere solebat, quae in Parliamentis ante habitis tota regni non solum communi- tas, sed et ipsa nobilitas, statuebat." Articles of Deposition, c. 17. 76 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II < Parlia- ment of 1397-8. as Edward III.; in various ways he shewed that he regarded neither law nor custom as binding his action. But it is in the last years of his reign, that his views found their fullest expression and came near to being embodied in the constitution. In the famous Parliament of 1397-8, he obtained the repeal of the pardon of the Lords Appellant; he pro- cured the ratification of the opinions of the judges at Nottingham, which condemned the Commission of Reform of 1386, declared the proposers of it guilty of high treason, and gave the king power to arrange the order of business in Parliament, a rule that would have entirely prevented the growth of the maxim Redress of grievances before supply; finally he per- suaded the Parliament to delegate its authority to a perpetual committee of eighteen'. His object There can be no question, that by these measures to create a Richard was attempting to create a written consti- despotism. tution, a lex regia, which should save the rights of permanent the English Crown for ever. It is made high treason to attempt the repeal of the statutes; all solemnly swear to keep them. For the future, tenants of fiefs, whether barons or bishops, are to swear to maintain the acts, before obtaining livery of seisin. The king writes to the Pope in order to obtain his con- firmation of the measures, an unheard-of thing, made one of the grounds of his déposition. Finally, in his ¹ 21 Ric. II. cc. 1--20. 1 Statutes of Realm, 11. 94—110. 2 Rot. Parl. III. 352 sqq. Even this oath is taken "sauvant au Roi sa Regalie et Liberté et le droit de sa corone." 3 The articles of deposition are given in Knyghton (Twysden, Decem Scriptores, 2746-2756); Rot. Parl. III. 417–427. WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 77 will Richard bequeathed his private treasure to his successor, with the proviso that he should ratify and observe the statutes of the Parliament of Shrews- bury. Failing his compliance with the condition, the treasure is left to others, who are to labour even unto death to effect the ratification of the statutes¹. The import of this is plain. Richard desired to found an absolute monarchy, and to relieve the Crown of all the limitations, with which custom had fenced it about. The principle which animates the king is clear and definite. He acts not from caprice or momentary lust of dominion; but with a settled purpose he asserts the rights of kingship and attempts to render them secure for future ages. The clearest insight into Richard's theory is given by the sermon preached by the Bishop of Exeter at the opening of this Parliament'. The text is Rex unus est omnibus³, and the Sermon of Bishop of preacher argues that there must be one king, and Exeter. one governor; otherwise no realm can be governed; in a word, "mixed monarchy" is anarchy. To this end of unity in the state three things are necessary; the king must be powerful, the laws must be kept, and subjects must be obedient. The Crown is possessed of certain privileges, which may not be alienated; any act attempting to do so is void. Parliament is there- fore summoned to enquire, whether any such rights have been alienated in the past, that remedy may 1 Rymer, viii. 75, Articles of Deposition, c. 31. 2 Rot. Parl. III. 347. 3 Ezek. xxxvii. 22. 78 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II be taken, non obstante any ordinance to the contrary. For the king is the source of law and the judges are bound to maintain the rights of his Crown. The same idea comes out in the speech of the Chan- cellor at the re-assembling of Parliament at Shrews- bury; the object of meeting, he says, is to see that there be not several sovereigns in the kingdom, but one only¹. All this is on exactly the same lines as the anti-papal arguments of Ockham and others, to prove the omnipotence of the sovereign authority from the necessity of unity in the state. It may be noticed, that in making Parliament the instrument of the destruction of its own liberties, Richard set the precedent, afterwards followed with better success by Henry VIII. The general pardon which he granted to his subjects, is an exact parallel to the famous pardon of the whole realm. by Henry VIII. for its breach of the Statute of Praemunire. Richard appears also to have been the first king, who saw the advantage of manipulating Parliament; he is accused of packing the House with his own nominees and of bribing members³. Walsingham tells us that after this act the sacredness sheriffs throughout the kingdom were compelled to Richard's views of of king- ship and take new and unaccustomed oaths, that they would of unction. obey the king's commands whether signified under the Great Seal, the Privy Seal, or even the Signet¹. - 1 Rot. Parl. III. 357. 2 21 Ric. II. c. 20: the Bishop of Exeter declares the granting of this pardon to be one of the chief grounds of the summoning of Parliament. 3 Articles of Deposition, c. 19. 4 Walsingham, 11. 231; Articles of Deposition, c. 20. WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II 79 That Richard was standing up for what he believed to be a principle seems proved by his repeatedly declaring during his troubles, that his wretched condition was an outrage on all kings, and would bring royalty into dishonour¹. We know, that until the day of his death he regarded himself as king by virtue of unction, despite his deposition, that he regarded this ceremony as conferring a sacra- mental grace², and that he directed in his will, that he should receive a royal funeral. It seems clear, then, that ideas, originally framed into a system of defence against the Papacy, found expression in a doctrine of absolute monarchy held by a self-willed English king, and of the divine origin of kingship, as evidenced by the custom of hereditary succession and by the indelible character of unction. For the position of Richard as king was itself a His accession 1 "Ce sera pour lui [le roi de France] grant vitupere, Voire et pour tous les royz qui nez de mere Sont au jourduy; Veu loultrage et le tresgrant ennuy, La povrete et le point ou je suy." (Histoire du Roy d'Angleterre Richard: Archaeol. Britann., xx. 339.) There is much more in the same strain. In speaking of Boling- broke Richard is made to say: "Tous ceulx seront ses ennemis Qui aymerout honneur, loyaute, pris Et vasselaige." 2 Walsingham, II. 240. The king had wished to be a second time anointed, with oil from the Holy Land. It was used for Henry IV.; Richard speaks of himself as unworthy tam nobile sacramentum. That he desired the ceremony of unction to be re- peated is nothing against his regarding it as a sacrament, conferring a grace. 80 WYCLIFFE AND KING RICHARD II Appear- ance of doctrine of legiti- mism. S a proof of strong proof of the progress of the idea that in- advance of ideas of herent birthright is the chief title to the regal primo- dignity. Like Arthur of Brittany, Richard was a geniture. boy when the throne became vacant; as in the case of Arthur, his father had not himself worn the Crown; while, in both cases, there was living an uncle ambitious and unscrupulous, and one of the most powerful men in the country. Yet while in the twelfth century, the uncle succeeded and the prin- ciple of an elective monarchy was affirmed; in the fourteenth, there was no question about the nephew's succession; the principle of representative primo- geniture had triumphed. Lastly, the speech of the Bishop of Carlisle, which is familiar to us from Shakespeare's version¹, is evidence that the doctrines of unlimited obedience and of legitimism were becoming popular, and that the new dynasty which based itself on the rights of the nation and the choice of Parliament would have to encounter an opposition grounded upon the claims of hereditary right and upon the iniquity of rebellion². 1 King Richard II. Act Iv. Sc. 1, ll. 114-149. Shakespeare, who changes the circumstances, took the speech from Holinshed, who got it from Hall. The latter apparently found it in Lystoire de la traison et mort du roy Richart dengleterre. (English Histori- cal Society's Edition, pp. 70, 1.) Cf. also the speech of the Earl of Warwick in 1386. (Higden, Ix. 110.) 2 The proclamation of the French king against the usurper is further evidence of this. Lystoire de la traison, Appendix H. CHAPTER V KINGSHIP IN ENGLAND FROM HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH volution THE claims of Richard II. to found a despotism Constitu- were repudiated by the nation. The Revolution of tional Re- 1399 is an assertion of the right of Englishmen to of 1399. constitutional government. The articles of deposi- tion in which the charges against Richard are set forth, contain or imply a theory of constitutionalism as uncompromising as the absolutist doctrine of the king. Nor was this all. In elevating Henry of Bolingbroke to the throne the English nobles passed over the nearest heir, and asserted the right of Parliament to elect the fittest person from within the royal family. Yet the position is not quite clear. Henry paid homage to the principle of legitimism by his claim to be the nearest heir to Henry III. The fiction was transparent enough; no one believed Henry's Henry's ancestor Edmund Crouchback to have been hereditary older than his brother Edward I. Yet the more right evidence ridiculous the fable appears, the stronger is the of popular evidence it affords of the hold upon the minds of sentiment. Englishmen of the principle of strict hereditary succession. Men will not bolster up a claim by a claim to F. 6 82 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM transparent falsehood, save to satisfy some really existing sentiment. However, constitutionalism triumphed for a time, and the theory of government propounded by an English lawyer¹ at the close of the period is as emphatic in its repudiation of des- potism and preference for 'mixed monarchy,' as were the doctrines of Wycliffe and Richard II. upon the other side. Yet the new dynasty was a failure; strong government was needed, and the country "perishing for lack of it" called the legitimate line to its assistance2. It is as a reformer, not as a pre- tender, that Richard Duke of York first comes into prominence. Yet it was only owing to his position hereditary as the legitimate heir of Edward III. that he gained right a the leadership of the reforming, party. From the doctrine. position of popular leader clamouring for good go- vernment he quickly passed to that of the dispos- sessed heir demanding his rights. It is now that the notion of indefeasible hereditary right first appears in English history. On no theory of the Inde- feasible Yorkist 1 Fortescue, De Laudibus Legum Angliae (1468–70); The Governance of England (1471–6). Accounts of Fortescue's theory are given by Mr Plummer in his introduction to the latter and by Dr Stubbs, Constitutional History, § 365. 2 Ibid. § 372. Parliament thus sums up the grievances of the nation under the Lancastrian dynasty, "In whose [Henry's] time not plenty, peace, justice, good governance, policy, and virtuous conversation, but unrest, inward war and trouble, unrighteousness, shedding and effusion of innocent blood, abusion of the laws, par- tiality, riot, extortion, murder, rape and vicious living have been the guides and leaders of this noble realm of England." Rot. Parl. v. 464. 8 It is an extension to the succession of the doctrine Nullum tempus occurrit regi. Some of the arguments employed are noticeable: The Duke of York answers the objection raised HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 83 State can a rightful heir be greatly blamed for heading a revolt against a usurper. But after the original usurper is dead, and his dynasty to all appear- ance established, the dispossessed line will not obtain any general support, unless there be prevalent a strong sentiment of legitimism, a widespread belief that, so long as the rightful heir is to be found, nothing can bar his claim. Thus the nominal occasion of the Wars of the Roses, however little it may have been their real cause, is a proof of the influence, which the principle of legitimism had gained by the middle of the fifteenth century. Men will not profess to take The up arms in support of a doctrine, that is not popular trium- principle and widespread. And the principle triumphed. Not phant. against his claim, that allegiance had been sworn to Henry VI. with the assertion that no oaths are binding if they conflict with the law of God, i.e. hereditary right. He claims to be "right inheritor of the said crowns as it accordeth with God's law and all natural laws." (Rot. Parl. v. 377.) In the first year of the reign of Edward IV. Parliament condemns the treatment of Richard II. "king anointed, crowned, and consecrate," as "against God's law, man's legiance, and oath of fidelity." There is no act upon the Statute book granting the crown to Edward, as in the case of Henry VII. and even James I. Parliament merely declares that he took to him the right on the death of his father. It speaks of the Duke of York claiming the crown as "using the benefice of the law of nature, not having any Lord then above him but God." (Ibid. 464, 5.) It would be impossible to express more strongly the notion of inherent right, as the one title to the crown; questions with regard to the succession are already acquiring a mystical character, and lawyers refuse to meddle with the arcana imperii. The judges on being asked to discuss the validity of the Yorkist claim, declared that the "matter was so high and touched the king's high estate and regalie, which is above the law, and passed their learning, wherefore they durst not enter into any communica- tion thereof." (Ibid. 376.) 6-2 84 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM only was Edward IV. able to oust those who were Kings in deed and not in right¹"; but his opponents themselves put forward pretensions to hereditary right. Abandoning the claim that Henry IV. was the nearest heir to Henry III., they advanced the plausi- ble contention that the Yorkist line was barred by its descent from a woman. Thus in one way or another the validity of the hereditary test was admitted. Nor are the breaches of the principle before the reign of Henry VIII. as important as might appear. Richard III. may have been a usurper, but at least he claimed to succeed by the best right. He alleged that Edward V. was illegitimate, and that the young Earl of Warwick's claim was barred by the attainder of the Duke of Clarence. If this were so, he was the undoubted heir of Edward IV. Anyhow, the titulus regius said he was, and gave him the Crown for that reason². (( Heredi- tary Bosworth field put an end for a time to the succession claims of strict right, and the Crown was won by an adventurer, who probably had a better title to be regarded as heir of Welsh princes than of English. Yet even for the hereditary claim of Henry under the Tudors. 1 Statutes of the Realm, 11. 380. 2 English Historical Review, vI. 260 sqq., 453, and Gairdner, Life and Reign of Richard III. Chapter III.; Speed's History, 717-25. The author of Majestas Intemerata is well aware that "the first of Richard III. bastardizes Edward the Fourth's posterity to flatter a tyrant; but what historian since ever fixed a truth upon this act?" The Act professes merely to resolve the doubts by declaring the succession not granting the crown, to which the title of Richard III. is "just and lawful as grounded upon the laws of God and nature and also upon the ancient laws and customs of this said realm." HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 85 Tudor something might be said. The legitimation of the Beauforts might be held to extend to the suc- cession. It could be pretended that the titles of all other claimants were barred; that of Elizabeth of York as a woman, that of Richard III. as a usurper, and that of Warwick as scion of an attainted house¹. At least, by marrying Elizabeth Henry endeavoured to secure for his dynasty the hereditary title, which he must have felt flimsy in his own case². Henry VIII. reigned as the unquestioned heir of Edward III. These facts shew that, if the principle of hereditary right was not allowed to prevent title by conquest or choice, it was at least felt desirable to pay to it the decent respect of ingenious falsehood. On the other hand, a curious contrast to the sentiment is the statute, which gives protection to all supporters of a de facto king³, and even attempts to prohibit future Parliaments from attempting its repeal. The next reign exhibits the most startling breach of the principle of hereditary succession. The pecu- liar matrimonial relations of Henry VIII. necessi- tated continual changes in the succession, which could no longer be regarded as a sacred thing. When Henry was empowered to choose his own successor, absolutism had triumphed at the expense of legi- timism. Certainly a king, in whose hands are 1 On the claim of Henry VII., see Stubbs, Lectures on Medi- aval and Modern History, 392—4. 2 For the pains, which Henry VII. took to destroy all evidences of the early marriage of Edward IV. see English Historical Review, VI. 265. 3 11 Henry VII. c. 1. 4 28 Hen. VIII. c. 7, and 35 Henry VIII. c. 1. 86 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM Claims of Mary Stuart. placed the control of the succession, is more com- pletely sovereign in theory, than even Louis XIV. whose will might indeed be law, but he would never have been recognized as competent to alter the succession. Henry named his own children in the order which appeared to follow most closely the rule of primogenitary succession: in that order they suc- ceeded. Doubtless it is true that Mary and Eliza- beth could not both of them be lawful heirs; one of them must be illegitimate; yet at least the suc- cession of Edward VI. and his sisters followed the natural order; if the dissolution of the marriage with Catharine of Aragon be regarded as merely a divorce, it is even possible to maintain, that the sentiment of hereditary right had not been violated. Position of Yet Elizabeth's case, which was the most doubt- It Elizabeth. ful of the three, certainly aroused controversy. does not appear, that she was regarded upon the Continent as a legitimate sovereign. From the outset, Mary Queen of Scots claimed the Crown by here- ditary right. This right she undoubtedly possessed, if the divorce of Catharine were invalid. Elizabeth's irritation at Mary's quartering of the arms of England, her vain attempts to obtain from Mary the ratifica- tion of the treaty of Edinburgh, in which her present and future claims to the throne were renounced, were the inevitable result of her own doubtful title. They shew how deeply Elizabeth was penetrated with a sense of the insecurity of her position, and testify to the strength of Mary's claim and of the sentiment in its favour. Doubtless other and more potent causes led to the insistence upon Mary's rights; yet S HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 87 these alone would not have been sufficient to render Mary a dangerous competitor, had not a defective hereditary title been felt to be a good handle against a sovereign, who was for other reasons objectionable. Upon no other grounds were Mary's claims formid- able; for not only had Henry VIII. been at pains to exclude the Scotch line from the succession, but this disposition had been ratified by Parliament in the first year of Elizabeth's reign'. It appears, then, that, as in later times, there was some popular sentiment that hereditary right was indefeasible, a 'fundamental law,' which no Act of Parliament could override. statute c. 1. Additional evidence of this is the statute 13 Eliz. Import- cap. 12, which makes it high treason to question ance of the the right of Parliament to alter the succession. This 13 Eliz. Act is evidence both ways. In the first place it proves, what indeed is clear on other grounds, that neither Elizabeth nor her ministers regarded them- selves as bound by the rules of primogenitary suc- cession, and that they claimed for Parliament absolute freedom of choice; clearly, hereditary succession is no 'fundamental law' to them. On the other hand, the Popular doctrine of indefeasible hereditary right would not have been condemned, had it not been prevalent hereditary among a considerable section of the nation. Thus, then, in the theory of the Tudor period assertions of indefeasible hereditary right are not to be expected; actual facts are against it. Probably, however, the sentiment as to right. 1 1 Eliz. c. 3, § 2. 2 Statutes of Realm, iv. 52: also printed in Prothero's Statutes and Constitutional Documents, 89. 88 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM notion was widespread, but its utterance was unsafe. The sentiment must have been general, or the unanimity which welcomed James I. to the throne would have been impossible; for James had no title save that of inherent birth-right, and succeeded in spite of the two Acts of Parliament excluding his house. On the other hand the existence of these statutes and that discussed above is alone proof that the Crown is far the most important power in the State, and that theories are prevalent which exempt it from all restraints in regard to the succession. theories of Nature of The causes and character of the Tudor despotism Tudor despotism need not be here discussed. Yet one point must be implies noted. The exaltation of the royal authority was universal due to the need of a strong government. The crime obedience. of the Lancastrian dynasty had been, not that it was capricious or self-seeking or oppressive, but that it was weak, that law and order were not maintained and private war was once again becoming prevalent. It is as 'saviours of society' that the Yorkists and afterwards the Tudors win their position. In the statutes of liveries and in the Star Chamber is to be found the raison d'être of Tudor despotism. Government must be effective, private oppression must be punished, great offenders must be forced to submit to the authority of the Crown. That is the general sentiment: In a word, obedience must be enforced. The very causes, which drove men to support the Tudors at all, drove them also to insist on the paramount importance of obedience, and to proclaim the iniquity of rebellion. But, if the Tudor dynasty was essentially a HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 89 the Re- VIII. has yet to be dynasty of rulers, the Reformation gave to them a Result of vast accession of power. One aspect alone is impor- formation. tant here. In the series of statutes enacted in the years 1529-1534, culminating in that of the royal supremacy, another stage was reached in the long struggle, for centuries waged by the English kings against clerical immunities and the political claims of the Papacy. What had been little more than an aspiration under Henry II. or Edward III. or Richard II. was at last an accomplished fact. England was free from Papal interference, if only she could maintain her position. The battle was The inde- pendence not won yet, and in this fact lies the justification claimed by of men's passionate faith in the Divine Right of Henry Kings. We are too apt to think that, from the time of Henry VIII. or at least of Elizabeth, the success made of the English Reformation was assured. The per- sistent efforts of foreign powers to convert England, the dreams of so able a man as Gondomar¹, and the overtures to Charles I. and Laud², are alone sufficient proof to the contrary. If all danger of England's submitting to the Papal yoke were over, certainly the fact was unknown at the time either to English statesmen or to Papal diplomatists. England in the time of Henry VIII. asserted her claims to inde- pendence. A century of statesmanship and conflict was required before they were finally made good. Thus a theory was needful which should express the national aspirations. It was impossible to assert the sovereignty of the English Crown and its 1 Gardiner, History of England, 11. 218, 19, 252—4. 2 Ibid. VIII. ch. LXXIX. good. . 90 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM needed to position taken up against the Pope. A theory independence of Papal control without some grounds justify the being given. It was necessary to meet the Pope's claim to allegiance and his pretended right of de- posing kings, with some counter claim. There is no need to investigate afresh the causes, which determined the nature of this counter claim. They were at work in the earlier struggles between the Empire and the Papacy. Clearly, the Pope's claim to a universal monarchy by Divine Right, and to implicit obedience on pain of damnation, must be met in similar fashion, whether in the sixteenth or the fourteenth century. The English State must assert a claim to Divine appointment. Obedience must be demanded as due by God's ordinance, and all resistance must be treated as sin. 1 Need of a single central Now it is to the conception of a single supreme authority in the State, that men are inevitably authority. driven in seeking to formulate an anti-papal theory. Wearied of quasi-feudal anarchy and disgusted with ecclesiastical interference, Englishmen felt the need of relying upon one central power and of asserting its universal jurisdiction. Nor could it seem doubtful at that time, who was vested with the sovereignty. The king The king was immeasurably the most important naturally element in the State; in the case of Henry VIII., regarded assove- especially after the Act of 1539, the idea of sove- reign.' reignty was almost completely realised in his person'. It is far easier to arrive at the notion of sovereignty, 1 31 Henry VIII. c. 8. It is thus described by the Bishop of Oxford. "Here was a 'lex regia' indeed; a dictatorship, which with all conceivable limitations, left the 'king master and only master in his own house." Lectures on Medieval and Modern History, 303. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 91 if it be seen to be vested in a single person, than if it belong to an assembly or to a body such as Par- liament, made up of more than one assembly. Only under the form of monarchy does the notion of sovereignty readily lend itself to popular exposition. Further, the Reformation had left upon the statute Act of Supre- book an emphatic assertion of unfettered sovereignty macy. vested in the king. And the supremacy of the Crown constituted a new prerogative, which, since Parliament could allege no precedent for controlling it, might be claimed as the personal right of the head of the State. Lastly, the king had the name of sovereign. That complete sovereignty is to be found in some person or body of persons in the State is a necessity of effective anti-papal argument. If during the Tudor period it was not to be found in the Crown, where was it? Sir Thomas Smith might indeed write of the power of Parliament', but if the directing will is the supreme power in the State, Elizabeth was sovereign far beyond any despotic Premier or 'uncrowned king' of our own day. If we take into account the powers of arbitrary juris- diction exercised by the Privy Council, the infre- quency with which Parliament sat, and its lack of independence when sitting, there can be no doubt that Elizabeth was the person 'habitually obeyed' by the majority of Englishmen throughout her reign. Cf. Maitland's Introduction Therein it is shewn how 1 De Republica Anglorum, II. 1. to Mr Alston's edition of this work. Sir Thomas was halting between two opinions in the matter of sovereignty. 92 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM teenth century. Whether based upon authority or influence, the supreme power could be more truly conceived as belonging to the queen alone than as shared with anyone else. Some theory of uncontrolled secular authority is needed to meet the Papal claims; some power must be called into play to overthrow them. The most natural theory of sovereignty is that of monarchy. The only authority which could for an instant match itself with the Pope was that of the Crown. For the purposes of theoretical consis- tency and practical efficiency alike, a doctrine of sovereignty vested by Divine Right in the king was the indispensable handmaid of a national Reformation. to law the the six- S Obedience For a time, the thought will suffice of the uni- governing versality of law and of its absolute claim on the con- thought in science. Men must assert the power of the Crown and the duty of obedience to it, not so much because they have framed any general notions of its majesty and dignity, as because it is the one effective au- thority. Royal power must be exalted as against that of the Pope. If phrases slip in which grant to kings an unconditioned omnipotence, which few of them ever dreamed of exercising, that is rather because no one as yet is concerned to deny them, than because they are construed strictly or regarded as of much importance. Against the Papal supre- macy the unlimited jurisdiction and authority of kings is asserted. That these positions were de- structive of popular rights, which nobody claimed and nobody exercised, is not as yet seen. Monarchy will only come to be defended for its own sake when G HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 93 authority Bellarmine and Suarez have elaborated a theory of popular sovereignty as a weapon against recal- citrant monarchs, and when Knox and Goodman have proclaimed the lawfulness of resistance (when the Presbyterian clergy command it) and the duty of deposing 'idolatrous' kings. Meanwhile it is of Divine kings and their appointment by God as necessitating of kings. obedience that men will talk. This is the position most easily proved from Scripture and forms the natural antithesis to the Papal monarchy. Un- limited authority must be claimed for the law or the king; as yet there seems no difference. The king is the source and interpreter of law; men have no fear that he will seek to change existing arrangements or to overstep the boundaries set by custom. The only authorities which claim unlimited allegiance are the king and the Pope; there is no question as yet between Crown and Parliament. Obedience is essential. To give it to the Pope dissolves the political union.' It must therefore be due to the king. In the Thus it is obedience, rather than a theory of A theory of obedi- government, that writers in the sixteenth century once not of insist upon. Nor did they repeat the error of the State. Wycliffe and Ockham, and leave a loophole for sixteenth Papal interference by admitting the possibility of century no resistance in extreme cases. While claiming, as the sistance is writers of the fourteenth century, Divine sanction admitted. for secular governments, they dwell further upon the absolute duty of non-resistance in all cases. re- In Tyndall's work, The Obedience of a Christian 1528. Man, passive obedience is inculcated without any 94 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM qualification. No terms could be stronger than those i which the writer enforces the duty of non-resist- ance. Written to demonstrate the groundlessness of the charge of anarchism levelled at the Reformers, the book asserts that the Pope is the true anarchist, and declares that under Papal dominion "kings are but shadows, vain names and things idle, having nothing to do in the world, but when as the holy father needeth their help¹." Robert Barnes in his 1534. Supplication to the most gracious prince Henry VIII. and Men's Constitutions bind not the Conscience, declares most emphatically in favour of Passive Obe- dience. Another work of 1534 carefully expounds regal authority as against Papal, and claims God's ordinance on behalf of kings. Bishop Gardiner in 1535. his Oration On True Obedience developes completely the notions of absolute subjection to the sovereign, of the King's power being God's ordinance, and of the sinfulness of resistance; and infers from this the weakness of the Papal claims. More clearly than other contemporary writers, he sees that the real question is not as to the religious duty of obedience in general, but of the limits of obedience in ex- treme cases. For only then does the Pope enjoin G 1 The Obedience of a Christian Man, 114. 2 Opus eximium de vera Differentia Regiae Potestatis et Ec- clesiasticae. Goldast, III. 22. 8 The argument is as follows: "If he [the king] be the head of the people, and that by the ordinance of God, as no man sayeth nay," the Pope's claims to supremacy must fall to the ground (58). I quote from the reprint of Heywood's translation of 1553. 4 "It is certain that obedience is due, but how far the limits HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 95 disobedience; but he denies that any limits to obedi- ence are to be found in Scripture'. Like Wycliffe, he repudiates the notion, that the thirteenth of Romans can refer to the Pope. The distinction between the greater and lesser lights is declared to be a "blind distinction and full of darkness." He is at pains to assert that the royal supremacy is no new doctrine, but runs through English history and implies no more than that "the Prince is the whole prince of all the people and not of parts." The central idea of the book is the same as that of all effective anti- papal treatises; that obedience is due to the king, as a divinely appointed governor. Papal precedents of royal subjection are brushed away by a development of the doctrine nullum tempus occurrit regi. "Time may not prescribe against God's truth," and kings cannot alienate a God-given right. His contention, that examples are needless, for God's law is constant, and man's precepts variable, implies the whole force of the sentiment, that led men to frame a theory of the Divine Right of Kings. A stable bulwark was needed against the Papal attack. Obedience must be absolute and immutable, or the Pope will find it possible to make good some part of his claim. This can only be if the power of the Crown be regarded G of requiring obedience extend, that is the whole question that can be demanded." Ibid. 59. } "What manner of limits are those that you tell me of, seeing that the Scripture hath none such?" Ibid. 2 Ibid. 63. 8 Ibid. 72. "It appeareth that the thing itself which was expressed by the name was not only true but ancient." • Ibid. 80, 81. 96 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM 1543. as God's appointment and non-resistance as a Divine ordinance¹. The Necessary Erudition of a Christian Man is another early work, which authoritatively asserts the Divine authority of Kings and the iniquity of all resistance2. In more than one of Latimer's Sermons³ and in the two famous Homilies, that of the reign of Edward VI. entitled An Exhortation concerning Order and Obedience, and that of Elizabeth's collec- tion directed Against Wilful Rebellion, the religious. basis of non-resistance is asserted. Doubtless it is true, as the popular party afterwards claimed, that it is non-resistance to law which is here set forth in general terms; and that no guidance is given by the Homilies for the case of a monarch, like James II., arbitrarily violating the laws. In the reign of Elizabeth there are the strong assertions of Jewel that "obedience is due to princes and magistrates though they be very wicked," that 1 Gardiner declares that his purpose in writing is "to move all men to obedience, which only in the commandments of God and for God's sake maketh us happy and blessed." (Ibid. 101.) 2 The Necessary Erudition of a Christian Man, the Fifth Com- mandment. "Scripture taketh princes to be as it were fathers or nurses to their subjects." "By this commandment also subjects be bound not to withdraw their said fealty, truth, love and obedience towards their princes, for any cause whatsoever it be, ne for any cause they may conspire against his person, ne do anything towards the hindrance or hurt thereof." The terms of the following passage are significant. "And furthermore by this commandment they be bound to obey also, all the laws, proclama- tions, precepts and commandments made by their princes and governors except they be against the commandment of God." 3 Latimer's Sermons, 148, 496. 4 Apology for the Church of England. Jewel's Works, III. 74. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 97 the "Pope ought to acknowledge and call the Em- peror Lord and Master," and that "we ought so to obey princes as men sent of God¹." versial im- The arguments of Jewel's Apology are evidence Contro- of the direct connection between the theory of the portance sixteenth and seventeenth centuries and the earlier of early Imperial Imperialist doctrine. Further evidence is the transla- history. tion of Marsiglio's great work which was published in 1535, the chapter on the modes of restraining a bad prince being significantly omitted as not "pertaining to this realm of England." Bilson's work, The True 1585. Difference between Christian Subjection and un- Christian Rebellion is important, as not merely containing a theory of non-resistance, but also as covering almost the whole ground of the historical argument against the Papal claims. The relations of Popes and Emperors form the subject of many a page of anti-papal argument, which must seem to modern readers pedantic and unimportant. But the independ- ence of the Emperors was the necessary ground on which to rest the later claim to the independence of all states. Without this, it was impossible to prefer for national independence any claim founded on right as distinct from force. If the King was or had been supreme and free from Papal control, nothing of course could alter the fact. But it was no more than a fact. The Pope claimed a Divine Right for his position, and this could only be met by a counter claim not of fact, but of right. The historical ques- tion depended entirely upon the relations of Popes and Emperors, Eastern as well as Western. If it 1 Apology for the Church of England. Jewel's Works, 111. 76. F. 7 98 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM could be clearly proved, that in early times the Pope had submitted without a murmur to the authority of the Emperor, the fact would go far to justify the assertion that the political claims of the Papacy were of modern growth, and rooted in nothing better than the false decretals and acts of power. In the view of the defenders of the Act of Supremacy the position of the Pope was that of a usurper. The Protestant writers were maintaining the claims of the genuine heir. It is true that their contention could not be demonstrated by shewing that Papal interference was of recent growth; yet such a proof would raise a strong presumption in their favour. Thus the position of Constantine, the rights of Julian, the acts of Theodosius, the powers of Jus- tinian, the claims of the medieval Emperors were of vital importance in the controversy. Unless the Imperialist position were tenable, the Pope's claims were unassailable historically, and there would be small ground for the oft-repeated assertion of the freedom of the English monarchy. If the Pope had always claimed and exercised the powers he now pretended to, there was good reason for sup- posing them given of God. If on the other hand they were originally vested in the Emperor, his power must be of God, and the cause of secular governments in general was justified. Thus that Paul of Samosata or the Donatists appealed not to the Pope, but to the Emperor, is no mere academic point, but a necessary step in an argument of incalculable practi- cal importance. This fact may account also for the leaning some shew in the direction of Erastianism. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 99 j Bilson, for instance, appears thoroughly to approve the conduct of the Eastern Emperors in regard both to Popes and Patriarchs. His desire to demonstrate the political supremacy of the secular power carries him to extremes. (( Heredi- Bilson's book is further noteworthy, in that it Bilson on contains not merely the customary announcement tary Mon- that the King's power is from God and subject archy. to him alone, but also a demonstration that God especially prefers hereditary monarchy. From the example of the Davidic kingdom the author infers that succession in kingdoms hath not only the consent of all ages and nations; but the manifest subscrip- tion of God himself; that it is His special favour and blessing to continue the successions of godly princes¹.' The last instance of anti-papal argument that 1571. need be considered here is Bullinger's reply to the Bull of Pope Pius V. excommunicating Elizabeth. In this the anti-papal character of Tudor theories of obedience is fully exemplified. The author declares that the Pope usurps the rights granted to Kings by God, but regards (naturally enough) these rights as equally attributable to the supreme power in a republic², and equally granted by God in that case. With Mary Stuart still alive he is at pains to declare that the succession to the Crown goes by election. One phrase of this book expresses the whole senti- ment at the root of the theory of the Divine Right 1 True Difference, 515. 2 Bullae Papisticae Refutatio, 44. 3 Ibid. 69. K 7-2 100 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM of Kings: The bonds of political society are not dissolved, but strengthened by the word of God¹. Need of a theory of the Divine Kings. It is the occasion of this treatise which marks most completely the necessity of a theory of the Divine Right of Right of Kings. So long as the Popes were content with a general claim, or dreamed of converting Elizabeth, an uncompromising royalist doctrine was scarcely needed. But, when it was attempted to put the theory into practice, and all good Catholics were bidden to become traitors on religious grounds, it was necessary that a theory should appear of the religious duty of obedience to the established government. Loyal and patriotic feeling under the circumstances must inevitably lead to the exaltation of the dignity and authority of the Crown. Its complete independence of the Pope, its institution by God, and the duty of non-resistance must now be emphasized with wearisome reiteration, if the State was to retain the allegiance of those large numbers who were gazing with longing and regret at the old order. From the year 1570 of the Bull of excommunication there is a king across the water' claiming allegiance, threatening and sometimes organizing descents upon the coast. Every patriotic Englishman must henceforth affirm, that his own princess is the lawful recipient of obedience, with as good or better title than that of the Pope; in a word that she is Queen by Divine Right. If the Pope had excommunicated Council or Parliament, men might have urged the divine authority of 1 "At politica vel civilis gubernatio confirmatur, non dissolvitur verbo Domini." Bullae Papisticae Refutatio, 71. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 101 the Sanhedrim or God's favours to the chosen people. But since it was the Queen who was deposed, the Queen must be defended, and the rights of the Crown shewn to exist by a Divine decree. the death Lastly, it may be observed that the position of Effect of affairs in respect of the succession had undergone of Mary a change towards the close of the reign. It was no Stuart. longer necessary to speak of hereditary right with bated breath. So long as Mary Stuart lived, to enforce the claims of strict right might be to countenance immediate rebellion; certainly it would pave the way for a Papal reaction that was likely to prove more lasting than that under Mary Tudor. But now that the young King of Scotland was heir according to strict rule, there was nothing to prevent the national sentiment in favour of legi- timism exerting its full force. Besides, it is the Papalists Roman writers who now begin to attack the doc- trine. Doleman's Conference about the Next Succession hereditary to the Crown of England (written by the Jesuit Parsons) proclaims in strident tones the new alliance between Papal sovereignty and popular rights. The author repeatedly declares that "Propinquity of birth or blood alone, without other circumstances, is not sufficient to be preferred to a Crown¹"; that forms of government are variable and may be established now oppose doctrine of succession. 1593. 66 ¹ A Conference about the Next Succession, 1; cf. also 11, It [that any prince hath his particular government or interest to succeed by institution of nature] is ridiculous, for that nature giveth it not, but the particular constitution of every common- wealth within itself." 102 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM and changed according to the will of the community¹; that “the succession to government by nearness of blood is not by Law of Nature and Divine, but by human and positive laws only of every particular government, and consequently may upon just causes be altered by the same?" The basis of the author's political theory is frankly utilitarian; Doleman asserts that "the Commonwealth hath authority to dispossess them that have been lawfully put in possession, if they fulfil not the Laws and Conditions by which, and for which their dignity was given them³." He upholds the right of resistance, although, with a shrewd eye to the Papal supremacy, he forbids it to be exercised by "private men," who are inferior to the Prince; whereas the Commonwealth is superior to him. The importance of the Coronation oath as implying the conditions of allegiance is insisted upon. In this book there is found the complete expression by an Englishman of the doctrines of the right of resistance, of popular sovereignty, and the merely official character of kingship. These are proclaimed purely in the interests of the Papal monarchy, without the smallest enthusiasm for liberty. The book appears to have been widely circulated, as the ability with which it was written deserved. Doleman is the most frequent subject of attack by supporters of James, and his work is ¹ A Conference about the Next Succession, 10. "The Common- wealth hath power to choose their own fashion of government, as also to change the same upon reasonable causes. 2 Ibid. cap. 1. title. 8 Ibid. 26. 4 Ibid. 58. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 103 evidently regarded as the most salient exposition of the treasonable character of the Papal aims. Speed, 1611. in describing the peaceful accession of James, goes out of his way to make a thrust at this treatise in particular. "Let Doleman therefore dote upon his own dreams, and other like traitors fashion their bars upon the People's forge; yet hath God and his right set him on the throne of his most lawful inheritance¹." of the book By the irony of fate the work was not only Use made hashed up in the interests of the Puritan party in in later 1647; but had the fortune to be reprinted by the times. supporters of the Exclusion Bill as the best com- pendium of arguments against the doctrine of inherent right. It was strange that a work written to exclude a Protestant prince from the throne of England should have exercised its most effectual influence in all but causing the exclusion of a Papist³. 1 Speed's History, 911. 2 Halifax charges the author of the History of the Succession with plagiarism from Doleman, from whom he asserts all his arguments to have been drawn. 3 Cardinal Allen's Defence of the English Catholics is based upon a similar theory of popular rights to that of Parsons. The purpose of the book, however, is to justify the deposing power, and the succession is not discussed. Yet Allen's insistence on the importance of the coronation ceremony as conferring rights upon the Pope is interesting. Once more it is in the necessities of Papalist controversy that originates the theory that the corona- tion oath proves the existence of a compact between king and people. "Upon these conditions [the oath to preserve the Catholic faith] therefore, and no other, kings be received of the Bishop that in God's behalf anointeth them; which oath and promise not being 104 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM cir. 1600. Anti- Roman writers strong From this time forth anti-papal writers will feel bound to attack the notions of popular sovereignty henceforth put forward by the great Jesuit controversialists supporters in order to serve the occasion. Doleman, Bellar- of absolute mine and Suarez are the bêtes noires of Anglican monarchy. divines. Against them, as the preachers of resist- ance and inventors of the theory of original compact, the heavy artillery of the royalist pamphleteers is always directed. The attempt of the Jesuits to manufacture anti-monarchical sentiment in the interests of the Papal claims could not but have as its main result the effect of causing orthodox English churchmen to attach an increased value to kingship and to emphasize the peculiar importance of hereditary succession. Heywood's Royal King and Loyal Subject¹ reaches perhaps the high-water mark of sixteenth century loyalism. The plot and general development of this play have no other object than that of illustrating the virtue of absolute obedience under oppressive and tyrannical treatment. To the King of England is attributed arbitrary and unlimited authority. Loyalty could hardly go further than the unbroken submission of the Earl Marshal, nor could caprice ever make more unreasonable demands, than the King in this play. The author evidently observed, they break with God and their people; and their people may, and by order of Christ's supreme minister their chief Pastor in earth, must needs break with them; heresy and infidelity in the Prince tending directly to the perdition of the Commonwealth" (113). 1 For the probable date of the play see J. Payne Collier in Introduction (p. vi) to the reprint by the Shakespeare Society. HENRY IV. TO ELIZABETH 105 wrote his work with the one aim of inculcating this lesson of royal omnipotence and perfect obedience. Nor is the play evidence of Heywood's sentiments only; its success testifies to those of his audience. Assuredly no other motive but that of loyalty could have led to such a play being 'acted with applause,' as we are told that it was. Despite the recent panegyric on the author by a republican critic¹, it may be questioned whether this production is not too deficient in dramatic power and poetic interest to have afforded pleasure to an audience that was not steeped in royalist sentiment. Of The Maid's Tragedy, which was a little later, the same cannot be said. Yet that also proves how strong was the popular belief in the mystical nature of king- ship and in its claims to unquestioning obedience. Thus, then, it appears that by the close of the sixteenth century events had done much to strengthen the monarchy, and to generate notions of its Divine institution; and that there had been elaborated a theory of the unlimited jurisdiction of the Crown and of non-resistance upon any pretence, which was not to be brought to the test of popular criticism until the next century. These notions had all arisen out of the necessities of the struggle with the Papacy, although the Civil Wars of the previous age had doubtless produced by way of reaction a sense of the necessity of securing strong government 1 Mr Swinburne in Nineteenth Century, Oct. 1895 (400), The Romantic and Contemporary Plays of Thomas Heywood. It is fair to say that The Royal King is not placed on a level with most of the author's works. 106 ENGLISH KINGSHIP FROM HENRY IV. and universal obedience to the law. English contro- versialists, in answering the theory of the Papal supremacy, were driven to propound a doctrine of the Divine Right of secular governments, which is in its essential meaning no other than the Imperialist theory of two centuries and a half before. To the Empire ancient and mediæval they go for the historical justification of their position, and for the rest build up their argument with texts and illustrations from Scripture. Theories of inherent rights of birth as governing the succession are latent rather than expressed. But the sentiment in favour of indefeasible hereditary right has been steadily growing, and will appear triumphant, so soon as England's Empress" shall have left the way free for a successor, reigning by right of birth alone. (C : I CHAPTER VI HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW contro- England THE political and religious questions which occu- Similarity pied the minds of Englishmen in the seventeenth of political century find their counterpart in controversies evoked versy in during the French Wars of Religion¹. In the theories and of Huguenots, Lorrainers and Politiques appear most France. of the ideas, of which we hear so much in England a little later. France indeed was a soil peculiarly suited to the development both of Regal and Papal theories. From the position of the King, as eldest son of the Church, men might demonstrate his subjection to the Pope. The deposition of Childeric by Pope 752. Zacharias was the earliest exercise of the deposing power, and was alleged by the supporters of the league against both Henry III. and Henry IV. as conclusive proof, that this power had been recog- nized in the past. In no other country is the connection of politics and theology more intimate and vital. Of pure politics there is even less than there is in England in the next century. Political theory is rarely developed, save with the object of strengthening some theological position. } 1 On this point and the position of Henry IV. see the remarks in Seeley's Growth of British Policy, 1. 68. 108 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW The pretensions of the Huguenots to be taking up arms against their prince by the authority of God exemplify the fact, more patent later in Scotland and England, that the Presbyterian and the Papal theories of politics have common elements. The essence of both is the claim put forward by an ecclesiastical organization to control and direct the action of the State, although in the case of Presbyterianism the acceptance of the doctrine of the 'two kingdoms ' makes for liberty (cf. Appendix III-Jus Divinum in 1646). Huguenot Preachers and Presbyterian Dis- ciplinarians are like their Papalist enemies in this, that they would place the secular power under the heel of the spiritual, or else would claim the exercise of sovereign rights for a portion of the community. It was as a danger to the State, claiming for themselves an imperium in imperio, that the Hugue- nots as a political power were finally crushed by Richelieu, while religious liberty was preserved to them. Again, in the position assumed by the League with regard to Henry III., there is much that is parallel to the relation between Charles I. and the Long Parliament. Henry is lawful king; no one doubts it. Yet he must be restrained and coerced by force of arms in the interests of the Crown which he wears. The distinction between the per- sonal and political authority of the Crown first arose, as has been shewn, in England under Edward II., and will reappear during the Great Rebellion. But the conception of their office entertained by the ultra- royalist rebels of the League is precisely similar. HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 109 They too claim to be taking up arms against the person of their king in support of his authority. Lastly, the reign of Henry IV. is the supreme triumph of legitimism, and far outdoes in import- ance the accession of James I. to the English Crown. James I. had the sentiment of the whole English nation at his back; and the very few disloyal Catholics were a negligible quantity compared with the League. Henry of Navarre, with almost every- thing against him save his right as legitimate heir by the Salic law and the grant of God, yet made good his claim to the Crown. His success finally disposed of any claims of the right of election or of the Papal sanction, and testified to the depth of the sentiment in favour of hereditary succession by rule of law. Yet the issue was in one respect different from any possible question of English politics. The strength of Henry's position was not as that of James I. or Charles II., the indefeasible right of the heir ac- cording to the rule of primogenitary succession. It was the Salic law, as commonly understood, that gave him his claim, and its inviolability is of the essence of all arguments in his support. He was not the heir by primogeniture, and had the Crown descended, as in England, the Duchess of Savoy¹ must have worn it. Hence there will be an important difference 1 Catharine, who married Charles Emmanuel the Great, was Philip's elder daughter by Elizabeth of Valois. The claim to the throne of France was however put forward on behalf of Isabella, the second daughter. The reason apparently was that she was as yet unmarried. 110 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW between French and English theories of Kingship. The inviolability of the succession "as by law esta- blished" will play a much greater part in French controversy. Supporters of Henry IV. can hardly develop such a theory as that of Filmer, for the Salic law is an artificial institution; and it can scarcely be claimed, that it has the author of Nature on its side. At least, the Divine Right of the law of succession is less plausible a doctrine in France than in England. We must expect then to find French. theory more legal than English. The Salic law is "the peculiar institution" and especial glory of France; but universality cannot well be claimed for it. In Filmer and Leslie we have what purports to be a universal system of politics. This will be less possible in France. French theory is in many respects iden- tical with English, but in this matter it must differ from it. French thought will be less theological, less transcendental, more legal and local than English. But against the claims of the Pope, Gallican doctrine will be as uncompromising as Anglican. the Pope. Its historical justification is indeed stronger. French Position of France in regard to 2 authors can look back to a long series of triumphs over Papal aggression, they can point to conflicts no less acute and more successful than any which England had witnessed in pre-Reformation days. The triumph of Philip the Fair over Boniface VIII. is the most impressive event in the relations between France and the Papacy¹; whereas in power to strike 1 King James remarks, "Most notable is the example of Philip the Fair, and hits the bird in the right eye" (Works, 412). HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 111 : ! the imagination the submission of John to Innocent III. far outdoes any of the successful efforts of the English kings. A Frenchman can detail with pride the relations of Charles VI. to Benedict XIII., or of Louis XII. to Julius II., and can even point to the recent refusal of Henry II. to admit the validity of the Tridentine decrees?. Whereas in England the Popes had constantly protested against all legislation directed against their autocracy, their partial re- cognition and reluctant endurance of the Gallican liberties³ may be adduced to prove, that in the case 1 See especially Toussaint Berchet, Pium Consilium super Papae Monitorialibus, Pars I. 2 Apologia Catholica, 186, 7. "Interea vero dum legitimum illud concilium expectatur neque Rex Francorum neque supremae ipsius Curiae Concilii illius Tridentini decreta unquam in hoc regno mandari voluerunt, nec nisi ab Ecclesiasticis, qui Pontificiae Monarchiae subsunt, fuerunt recepta. Contra Rex Henricus II. piae memoriae certam legationem misit, qua huic Concilio (prout Concilium esse volunt) obsisteret et renuntiaret se nullo pacto id probaturum esse. Etenim revera illud accipi non potest, quin eadem opera corrumpantur et jura authoritasque Francorum Regis, et vetera decreta in summis Regni Ordinibus constituta pragmaticae sanctionis nomine et sanctissimae libertates Ecclesiae Gallicanae, quibus florentissime hujus regni dignitas conservatur." 3 On the Pragmatic Sanction, see Creighton, History of the Papacy, II. 198, 9 and 423 sqq. "It was a memorial of national opposition to the theory of the Universal Church. It expressed the claim of a temporal ruler to arrange at his pleasure the affairs of the Church within his realms." Louis XI. first abolished the Pragmatic Sanction and afterwards restored its provisions by royal ordinance. "The Pragmatic Sanction rested on the basis of the power of General Councils, of an inherent right of self- government in the Universal Church, which was independent of and superior to the Papal monarchy" (Ibid. Iv. 231). Although the Pragmatic Sanction was superseded by the Concordat of 112 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW of France all claims to political supremacy have been expressly renounced by the Pope. Yet there were difficulties in the position of French Catholics, to which neither Imperialists nor Anglicans were exposed. For they admitted the spiritual claims of the Papacy, and it is far from easy to do this, while denying in toto its pretensions to political supremacy. It was impossible for the sup- porters of the King to take the line of the Imperialists and boldly to claim that the Pope was amenable to the jurisdiction of their master. To admit, as did French Catholics, that the Pope is a sovereign prince, and that he further has spiritual authority over the orthodox in every nation, is to grant him a power of interference, out of which very little ingenuity is required to con- struct a theory of universal supremacy. Nor on the other hand can the politiques boldly cut the knot in the Anglican method, by denying that the Pope is head of the Church. The inconsistency of their position necessarily affected their theory. Since it was hard for French writers to reconcile the liberty claimed for the French king, with the authority allowed to the Pope, they may be expected to be less clear than either Englishmen or Imperialists in their statement of the necessary unity of the sovereign power. Save in the Maria Francis I. with the Pope, yet the sentiment it enshrined was preserved: the new arrangement gave no further rights to the Pope, but relieved the Crown from the fear of being thwarted by the leaders of the Gallican Church. So to say, the Pragmatic Sanc- tion had affirmed the independence of the nation, the Concordat secured the supremacy of the Crown. On this aspect of the Concordat see Kitchin, History of France, II. 182, and Armstrong, French Wars of Religion, 122. کے: Į I } ; I 1 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 113 case of writers with a Huguenot bias, this notion is far less prominent in French than in English or mediæval opponents of the Papal claims. A little want of harmony and consistency in this matter was to be expected from the circumstances of the case. With this brief account of the causes which led to the growth in France of a theory similar in its main scope, though different in certain details from the English doctrine, the study of the chief controver- sialists may be approached. rights. In the Vindiciae contra Tyrannos and the Theories Franco-Gallia are to be found the ideas at the of popular bottom of all theories of popular rights until the eighteenth century. The doctrine of an original compact appears full-blown in the Vindiciae, although it is worthy of remark that the compact between King and people is here regarded as not the first, but the second contract involved in the institution of civil society. The first compact is that between God on the one hand and King and people on the other, as contracting parties; this was discarded by later writers. The second compact is the ordinary con- tract of government, and is identical with that of Hooker or Locke. From it are drawn the usual proofs that the right of resistance is vested in the people and may be exercised upon a breach of the contract by the sovereign. This compact may be express or tacit, but it is inviolable and unchangeable in its terms; no oath or consent of either party or of both can abrogate it'. The basis of the argument 1 "Inter regem et populum mutua obligatio est, quae sive Civilis sive Naturalis tantum sit, sive tacita, sive verbis concepta, F. 8 114 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW throughout the book is the principle of utility¹. It is contended, just as in the manner of Locke, that the King can have no power over either the life or the property of his subjects, for it is contrary to the principle of utility for men to give power over their life or property into the hands of another. For such a purpose men, who are naturally free, would never have set up a King. There are the very same erroneous beliefs in the artificial nature of government, and in the possibility of limiting the 'sovereign,' which Locke was afterwards to render famous. The author shares with the great Whig philosopher the inability to see that in any developed state there must exist some ultimate supreme authority, to whose action no legal limits can be affixed. Both Locke and Languet think they can "put a hook into the nose" of the Leviathan³. The law is for them endowed with Divine Right, eternal and immutable, the breath of nullo pacto tolli, nullo jure violari, nullo vi rescindi potest." Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 147. 1 "Hic considerandum est imprimis certissimum totius huiusce disputationis fundamentum, quo reges utilitatis publicae causa constitutos fuisse statuimus. Eo enim posito tota lis finita est." Ibid. 112. The author repeatedly has recourse to the principle of utility as the final proof of his position. 2 Ibid. 112 sqq. 3 It is hard to overestimate the resemblance between the ideas of Locke and the author of the Vindiciae, e.g. "Primum sane palam est, homines natura liberos, servitutis impatientes et ad imperandum magis, quam ad parendum natos, non nisi magnae cuiusdam utilitatis caussa imperium alienum ultro elegisse, et suae quasi naturae legi, ut alienam ferrent, renunciasse." Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 98. The question as to whether the Vindiciae should be attributed to Languet or Du Plessis Mornay need not be here discussed. ! ་ HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 115 God rather than man, controlling sovereign and subject alike. This of course is to miss the conception of sovereignty, for the argument will apply to any form of government. Locke saw and boldly admitted, that his theory was as fatal to Parliamentary om- nipotence, as it was to royal prerogative, but the author of the Vindiciae appears to confine his views to kings. In another respect the author of the Vindiciae is as curiously at one with Whig Englishmen of the seventeenth century, as he is at variance with modern feeling. He is emphatic in his rejection of 1 Rexne, inquam, a lege an Lex a rege pendebit? Itaque est quod reges legi ipsi pareant, eamque tamquam reginam agnoscant. …………… 66 *** Quis vero ambigat, quin legi, quam regi parere, id est, homini utilius et honestius sit? Lex est boni regis anima; per hanc movet sentit vivit Rex Legis organum, et quasi corpus, per quod illa suas vires exerit, sua munera obit, sua sensa eloquitur. Animae vero, quam corpori, parere, justius est. Lex est multorum prudentum in unum collecta ratio et sapientia. Plures autem oculatiores et perspicaciores sunt, quam unus. Tutius itaque est Legem, quam hominem, quantumuis perspicacem, ducem sequi. Lex est ratio sive mens, ab omni perturbatione vacua, non ira, non cupi- ditate, non odio, non studio mouetur, non precibus, non minis flectitur. Homo contra, quantumuis rationis particeps sit, ira, vindicta, aliove subinde appetitu vincitur rapiturque, et ita variis affectibus perturbatur, ut sui ipse compos non sit: nempe, quia ex appetitu et ratione constat, quin hic interdum vincat, fieri nequit. * * * Denique lex est mens, vel potius mentium congruata multitudo: mens vero diuinae aurae particula, ut qui legi paret, Deo parere, Deumque arbitrum quodammodo facere videatur. Contra vero, quia homo ex mente divina, et anima illa belluina constans, sibi saepe non constat, saepe dementat, et insanit: cum vero ita afficitur non jam homo sed bellua est; qui Regi parere mavult, quam legi, belluae quam Dei imperium malle videatur.” Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 103. ! 8--2 116 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW the right of private individuals to resist the prince on any pretence whatsoever¹. Passive obedience is their duty, prayers and tears their one resource. Only to corporate bodies, integral parts of the king- dom, does the Vindiciae grant the right of resistance. To private individuals Christ's patience is held up as an example; and the precedents of tyrannicide in the Old Testament are explained away, as the result of direct Divine inspiration. Anyhow, the view is closely parallel to the English doctrine, that resist- ance is unjustifiable on the part of private persons, but lawful, when commanded by the "inferior magis- trate." Probably the doctrine is a relic of feudal theory. Its appearance in Huguenot theory, with its strange exaltation of municipal and provincial authority, seems to carry us back to the days of provincial sovereignty and semi-sovereign communes. Certainly under any form of government great dangers would arise, if the rights ascribed by 'Brutus' to the municipal organizations were admitted. His theory would reduce the State to a confederation of semi- independent bodies and would give rise to scenes like those so vividly depicted in Mr Chesterton's Napoleon of Notting Hill. It would be quite in accordance with the doctrine, if the London County Council were to direct an insurrection in favour of G 1 Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 65 sqq., 178 sqq. No supporter of Passive Obedience could be more emphatic in his denunciation of any general right of insurrection than is this upholder of popular liberty. If the aristocracy lend their support to a tyrant, it is by God's command, and the only lawful weapon is prayer. This notion is of course exactly similar to the royalist contention, that kings are frequently "given in wrath.” . HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 117 the principle of betterment, or the Leicester Board of Guardians to organize rebellion against the Vac- cination Statutes. There would be less unity, but greater freedom. There are some points of similarity to Papal theory in this book. God is the true king, and therefore must be supported against the earthly king, who is merely God's vassal. Just as a single city of the empire would be within its rights in supporting a duly elected Emperor against a usurper, so a city of France may support God against a king¹. Moreover, kings hold their dignity by Divine right, therefore they are amenable to God's authority, and in support of God's truth they may be resisted². The author argues that if the maxim Nullum tempus occurrit regi be true, it is a fortiori evident that no prescription can touch the inalienable sovereignty of the people. Indeed the notion that sovereignty is 2 Ibid. Qu. 1. 1 Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 57 sqq. 3 Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 96. The following passage, sum- ming up the whole argument, may be quoted: "In summa, ut hunc tandem tractatum concludamus, principes eliguntur a Deo, constitu- untur a populo. Ut singuli principes inferiores sunt: ita universi, et qui universos repraesentant, regni officiarii, principe superiores sunt. In constituendo principe intervenit foedus inter ipsum et populum, tacitum, expressum, naturale, vel etiam civile, ut bene imperanti bene pareatur, ut reipublicae inservienti omnes in- serviant.......Huius vero foederis seu pacti regni officiarii vindices et custodes sunt. Qui hoc pactum perfide et pervicaciter violat, is vere exercitio tyrannus est. Itaque regni officiarii ipsum et secundum leges judicare, et renitentem vi coercere, si alias non possunt, ex officio tenentur. Hi duorum generum sunt. Qui regni universi tutelam susceperunt, quales Comes stabuli, Mareschalli, Patricii, Palatini et caeteri singuli per se caeteris 118 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW Hotman's 'Franco- Gallia.' inalienable finds expression on all sides, whether the doctrine advocated be the ultimate authority of Pope, of King, or of people. Nor is this surprising. Practical necessity rendered it essential for each side to insist much upon the doctrine. For neither party could shew such an unbroken series of pre- cedents, that they could make their position secure without asserting that, while examples might support their own view, precedents against them will avail nothing. The Franco-Gallia of Hotman is a work of a different order. It is a purely historical argument to prove that the Frankish kingdom was, in the earliest stages of its development, a limited monarchy. The inference is that the present autocratic power of the Crown is an usurpation and may justly be abolished in favour of a return to the old state of things. The notion that governs the whole course of the argument, is the same as that held by English writers of all schools in the next century. Constitutional arrangements, whether they consist in the sovereign rights of the Crown or in the power of the people, are believed to be unchangeable, a 'fundamental law' which no lapse of time or developement of circum- stances can abrogate. Thus the primitive system of government, whatever it be, is the only rightful ، K conniventibus aut colludentibus, tyrannum coercere debent; qui alicujus partis, regionisve, quales duces, marchiones, comites, consules, maiores tyrannidem tyrannumque ab ea regione urbeve arcere jure suo possunt. Porro singuli sive privati adversus tyrannos exercitio, gladium non stringent; quia non a singulis, sed ab universis constituti sunt" (Ibid. 182, 3). F HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 119 one. Whatever powers originally belonged to the people, they still possess, however long be the period since they were recognized as effective. Whatever rights were vested in the Crown at the beginning, it still has, and no amount of constitutional develope- ment can check them. Hotman's conclusions are similar to those of the Vindiciae and of Whig writers. To him the King is a mere official created by the people for their own behoof¹. Like Locke and Rousseau, he will allow omnipotence to no adminis- tration, and would apparently, like Rousseau, regard all forms of constitution as liable to change at the will of the sovereign people. The basis of the argument, where it is not historical, is utilitarian, and Hotman has frequent recourse to the maxim Salus populi suprema lex². son with Here, then, are the same ideas, as were at the Compari- bottom of English theories of popular rights in the English seventeenth century. Proclaimed first of all by theories of Huguenots, they passed over to the ultramontane supporters of the League, when the death of the Duke of Alençon left Henry of Navarre the heir resistance. 1 "Deinde cum illi populi Regem sibi crearent, (sicuti et jam prius dictum est et postea dicetur) perabsurdum est existimare populum a Rege potius, quam Regem a populo denominatum" (58). 2 It is noticeable that Hotman adduces in proof the limited character of the French monarchy, the admitted fact that the Salic law was unalterable, and that the treaty of Troyes was invalid for that reason. It is curious how completely this weak point in their position escaped the notice of most supporters of the Divine Right of Kings. In one and the same breath they assert that the succession is fixed by a fundamental law, and that the king is absolutely sovereign. 120 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW to the French Crown. Henceforward they become identified with Papal pretensions. The great treatise of Barclay, De Regno, is directed against Buchanan, Brutus, and Boucher, the Scotch, the Huguenot, and the Papalist opponents of the rights of the Crown and of the inviolability of the Salic law¹. It is now, in the later years of Henry III. and the earlier of his successors, that there appears a well- defined theory of the French monarchy. Against the Papal claims to interfere with the internal politics of France and to alter the succession as by law established, the Divine Right of Kings and the fundamental character of the Salic law are emphatically asserted. Similarity to English RAIS Matą gde j Veer T The main arguments are similar to those em- doctrine." ployed by English controversialists. Kings are of Divine appointment, all resistance to them is there- fore sin?. The Pope has not and never had authority to depose princess. Since the King's rights come directly from God, the Pope can have no power to take away what he never granted. The deposition of Childeric was merely the formal ratification of a change, that had long ago taken place and affected the name, not the reality of kingship. It was effected with the consent, not by the authority of the Pope. Perhaps the deposition was not quite Theory of Divine Right of Kings. 1 For a complete account of Huguenot and League politics see Armstrong, The Political Theory of the Huguenots (Eng. Hist. Rev. Iv. 13) and The French Wars of Religion. 2 Barclay, De Regno, 113. 3 E.g. Toussaint Berchet, Pium Consilium, Pars 1. 4 Berchet (Goldast, III. 163). HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 121 justifiable and were better forgotten; it was a case of doing a little wrong, that a great right might result¹. The instances of royal repudiation of Papal inter- ference are duly recorded; and the usual Scriptural passages and illustrations are brought into play2. The position of the Emperor in regard to the Pope is affirmed to be one of superiority. This is an important element in the controversy; for the Carolingian monarchs are regarded as kings of France. The translation of the Empire is thus in- vested with significance, from the French, as from the Imperialist standpoint, and the treatment of Julian by his subjects receives, as usual, its meed of attention. It is not easy to single out any one. name as pre-eminent, in the case of a doctrine so widespread. Yet the fact that the theory of the Divine Right of Kings was in its origin a weapon of anti-papal controversy, is made plain by the treatise of Berchet in favour of Henry IV. and comes out in the collection of Gallican writings made by Pithou. between Special points, for comparison with English theory, Points of may be indicated. In the first place comes the difference difficulty (before alluded to) inherent in the circum- English stances of French Catholic writers. Barclay and French others are clearly hampered by the necessity of doctrines. and 1 Masson, Responsio in Franco-Galliam, 126. 2 The following is a specimen of the mode of argument: "Nec enim solum propter iram, id est metu poenae, illis [regibus] obedien- dum est, sed propter conscientiam, quia nimirum omnes scire oportet, id est divina voluntate et constitutione fieri debet." Servin (Goldast, III. 200). 3 Barclay, De Potestate Papae (Goldast, III. 635). 4 Les Libertez de l'Eglise Gallicane. 122 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW admitting the spiritual claims of the Pope and his title to the obedience of the clergy. Barclay is unable to take the same line as Imperialist or English writers and to affirm the absolute necessity of unity in the sovereign authority. He is content to admit that the Papal and Regal power are equal, and must respect one another¹. At bottom he holds the notion, also held by Presbyterians, that Church and State are two separate kingdoms, each a 'societas perfecta." He will allow no exemptions to the clergy from the operation of the ordinary law, and even hints a wish. that excommunication should be unaccompanied by civil disabilities2. Other writers, such as Du Moulin and Servin', are found arguing like Ockham or Marsiglio, that Christ's kingdom is not of this world, and that the whole doctrine of Papal sovereignty is based upon a fallacy. But all alike are clear, that the prince is to be obeyed, although he be excommunicate or a heretic. All affirm that kings are accountable to God alone, and above the restraints of civil law; only natural law can lay commands upon a king, says Servin'. All are agreed that subjects must obey for conscience' sake, and not merely for wrath. 1592. Servin also has a lengthy argument to prove that coronation and unction are mere ceremonies and no essential part of the regality, and that the coronation oath gives the people no rights 3 1 Barclay, De Potestate Papae (Goldast, 111. 645). 2 Ibid. c. XXXIV. 3 Goldast, III. 63. 4 Ibid. 241. 5 His argument is strange; the Pope is solutus legibus, therefore a fortiori the king is also. Servin, Vindiciae (Goldast, III. 197). HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 123 against him. It is a pious custom only; it will not affect Henry's authority, though the Archbishop of Rheims refuse to crown him, as a heretic¹. Law. In regard to the Salic law more than one line The Salic is taken. Du Moulin finds in it evidence of the 1561. perfection of the French monarchy, as founded on the model of the Davidic kingdom'. Bodin seeks a philosophical justification for it as the ideal mode of succession. Most writers content themselves with the declaration that the custom is a fundamental law and may not be violated by the King. They do not, as a rule, lay claim to any special Divine sanction for it, but declare that the law of succession in all kingdoms is of merely human origin; obedience to the lawful successor is a Divine ordinance¹. The Apologia Catholica is clearest in its exposition of the point. There can be little doubt, that the stress necessarily laid on so plainly artificial a rule as that of the Salic law, gives to the French theory a far more legal aspect than had the English. Past 1 Goldast, III. 209 sqq. Cf. also Apologia Catholica, 100 sqq. Bodin takes a similar view, supporting it by the maxim The king never dies. This aphorism, as a proof of inherent right, is a favourite argument of French, as of English writers; it is the most effectual way of disposing of any claims, that kingship is elective or founded on compact. 2 Du Moulin, De Monarchia Francorum (Goldast, III. 51). 3 Bodin, De la Republique, vi. 5. 4 "De jure divino est servare veram fidem et religionem; de jure autem humano est, quod hunc aut illum habemus regem." Barclay quotes these words from Bellarmine, and says that he ought to have added, "Ubi hunc vel illum regem semel habeamus, de jure divino est, ut ei in civilibus causis cum omni honore et reverentia pare- amus." De Potestate Papae (Goldast, 111. 659). 124 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW struggles and present necessities alike rendered necessary this emphatic assertion of the binding character of the Salic law. Not only was it the ground of Henry's claim, but it was the source of the independence of the French monarchy. For Edward III. was undoubted heir to the French Crown, had there been no such rule. Thus the sentiment in its favour had to strengthen it every feeling of patriotic pride at the successful issue of the Hundred Years' War. It is a commonplace with French writers that the treaty of Troyes was invalid, for it gave to Henry V. and his heirs the reversion of the Crown, and a treaty to violate the Salic law is void. The vividness with which men realized the distinctive character of the rule of succession, as giving to the French monarchy a perfection lacking to other kingdoms, made it the more impossible for them to claim universality for so peculiar a system. There is no such attempt as that made by Filmer, to seek for hereditary monarchy 1 Du Moulin thus describes the close of the Hundred Years' War: "Tandem vero Angli spe sua frustrati, a lege antiquissima Salica dejecti sunt." Goldast, III. 51. 2 Servin, whose main source of inspiration is hatred of Spain, declares that even if the League could make good its point, there would be no advantage gained by Spain, for England's claims would have been valid, if the Salic law were not binding. "Sed ista dicentes non animadverterunt se non tam Hispaniam et Guisianam causam, quam Anglicam defendere" (Goldast, III. 206). It was no wonder that the Salic law awakened such passionate enthusiasm; for if the Hundred Years' War be taken into account, it seems true to say that it was the salvation of France. The claim of Edward III. was far better than that put forward by Philip II. for himself or for his daughter. : 125 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW a foundation in the natural constitution of society. It is of Nimrod, rather than Adam that we hear as the founder of kingship. Certainly we come across comparisons of a kingdom to a family, and of kings to fathers. But they are never the basis of the theory, as in the Patriarcha or The Rehearsal. If agnatic kinship had been regarded as primitive or universal, there would have been stronger grounds for a French patriarchal theory of kingship, than there were for the English. But it does not appear that the possibility of such a theory ever suggested luself. Besides, it would not have been easy to derive the doctrine of the French succession from the common rules of inheritance. Henry IV. was not heir of Henry III. at private law; and much pains is taken by the author of the Apologia Catho- lica to demonstrate that, although the Bourbon prince was too distantly connected with the Valois to inherit their private property, he was yet the lawful heir to the throne¹. The Crown is regarded as something different in its nature from mere property; and a peculiar custom is needful to regulate the succession to the mystical position of a king. Bodin is at pains to declare that the King succeeds not by right of inheritance or by gift of God, but solely through the rule of law. It is easy to see how different is this view from the English conception of succession, which is always regarded as mysteriously 1 Apologia Catholica, 20. "Hoc quidem jus regni, inquiunt Doctores nostri, revera non est ereditarium, sed ad familiam pertinet, etiamsi nemo in ea existeret, qui succederet in defuncti bona." 126 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW Bodin, De la Re- publique, 1577. above positive law, founded by God and Nature, and followed in all rightly regulated families. To other French writers Bodin stands in some- what the same relation as does Hobbes to the English supporters of Divine Right. Nominally scientific, his treatise has really the same practical aim as those of Servin and Berchet. All his acute- ness and philosophical grasp of the nature of govern- ment are directed to one end, that of securing the Crown to the next heir, Henry of Navarre. More clearly perhaps than any previous writer French or English does he realize the nature of sovereignty¹. Of the conception of a 'mixed' or limited monarchy he is as contemptuous as Hobbes or Filmer or Austin. Quite in the manner of the last, he de- scribes the notes of sovereignty, and defines law as a command of the sovereign generally binding. Sovereignty he declares to be indivisible and in- alienable, and upon the question of customary law comes to conclusions similar to those of Austin³. 1 De la Republique, 1. 8, 10. 2 Ibid. 11. 1. Speaking on a 'mixed form of government' he says:-"Je respons qu'il ne s'en est jamais trouué, et qu'il ne se peut faire ny mesmes imaginer, attendu que les marques de souveraineté sont indivisibles." p. 263. 3 'La coustume prend sa force peu à peu, et par longues années d'un commun consentement de tous ou de la plus part; mais la loy sort en un moment et prend sa vigueur de celuy qui a puissance de commander à tous; la coustume se coule doucement et sans force; la loy est commandee et publiee par puissance et bien souvent contre le gré des subjects; et pour cette cause Dion Chry- sostome compare la coustume au Roy, et la loy au tyran: dauan- tage la loy peut casser les coustumes et la coustume ne peut deroger ù la loy * * * la coustume ne porte loyer ny peine; la loy emporte HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 127 ! In depth and accuracy of thought his treatise far surpasses the Leviathan, and Bodin escapes the pit- fall, into which Hobbes fell, of seeking the origin of sovereignty in a contract. Even a lex regia is according to him an impossibility in France, for the people never having possessed sovereign authority cannot have transferred it to the Crown. The practical part of the treatise is much the same as that of other writers. The authority of the Pope is repudiated, although little is said on the subject'. The power of the prince is asserted to come from God, and the usual texts are employed to inculcate the duty of absolute non-resistance². Monarchy is shewn to be the best form of govern- ment, in an argument of similar character to that of Ockham³. But Bodin is more emphatic in his contention, that since the members of a sove- reign number" may disagree, sovereignty should be vested in a single person. Finally, a philosophical << tousiours loyer ou peine, si ce n'est une loy permissiue qui leue les defenses d'vne autre loy: et, pour le faire court, la coustume n'a force que par souffrance, et tant qu'il plaist au Prince souuerain, qui peut faire une loy y adjoustant son homologation. Et par ainsi toute la force des lois civiles et coustumes gist, au pouvoir du Prince Souverain" (De la Republique, 222). 1 Ibid. 190 sqq. 2.46 Qui mesprises son Prince souuerain, il mesprise Dieu duquel il est l'image en terre." Ibid. p. 212. 3 Ibid. VI. 4. 4 De la Republique, p. 968. "Il n'est pas besoin d'insister beaucoup pour monstrer que la monarchie est la plus seure [forme de gouvernement], veu que la famille qui est la vraye image d'vne Republique ne peut avoir qu'vn chef, comme nous avons monstré, et que toutes les loix de Nature nous guident à la monarchie, soit que 128 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW Summary. justification is sought for the rule of the French suc- cession, and the Salic law is alleged to be in harmony with the teachings of nature¹. Thus it appears that in the writings of French controversialists there was developed a theory, which with slight modifications is identical with the English theory of the Divine Right of Kings. The essential notion is that the King owes his position directly to Divine appointment and is therefore accountable to God alone, and not to the Pope. From this naturally arises the sense of the absolute duty of non-resistance upon religious grounds. The King is regarded as above the restraints of positive law, save in the matter of the succession. This, like the English custom of hereditary succession, is regarded as a constitutional or fundamental' law, which may not be violated by King or people or both together. In English theory the notion appears as indefeasible hereditary right, in the French as the inviolability of the Salic law. The legendary antiquity of the latter further strengthens the sentiment in its favour, although when Hotman pointed out the true meaning of the passage supposed to prescribe the rule, Servin is content to say, that whatever the origin of the rule, it is a custom of long continuance nous regardons ce petit monde qui n'a qu'un corps, et pour tous les membres un seul chef, duquel depend la volonté, le mouuement, et sentiment, soit que nous prenons ce grand monde qui n'a qu'un Dieu souuerain; soit que nous dressons nos yeux au ciel nous ne verrons qu'un soleil: et jusques aux animaux sociables, nous voyons qu'ils ne peuuent souffrir plusieurs Roys, plusieurs seigneurs, pour bons qu'il soyent." 1 De la Republique, vi. 5. HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 129 and may not be broken¹. Bodin completely de- veloped the theory of sovereignty, but the position of French writers, as loyal subjects at once of Pope and King, renders many of their utterances on this subject less clear than those of Englishmen far inferior in ability. upon theory. How far, then, was English political thought Influence actually influenced by these writings? It is im- of French possible to say. It is however plain that the English English theory of Divine Right was a plant of indigenous growth. However much French writers may have done to influence English thought, or to render general a sentiment in favour of Divine Right, yet assuredly English theory did not arise out of French. On the other hand the position of England as an ally of Henry III. and Henry IV., the unpopu- larity of the Guises including Mary Stuart, and the hatred of the Spanish monarchy and of all schemes for advancing its power would tend in various ways to attract English sympathy to the side of those who were defending the French monarchy from Papal aggression and Spanish intrigue. Further, there is some evidence of direct influence. The treatise of Bodin in particular largely formed men's notions of government in the next century. It was translated into English and made a text-book at Cambridge. There is no question of the great effect of Bodin's writings upon those of Hobbes and Filmer and Leslie; and he is quoted by various other writers. There can hardly be any doubt, that the compara- tively thorough understanding of the doctrine of 1 Goldast, III. 207. 4 K F. 9 130 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW sovereignty evinced by some of the least able among English writers was due to Bodin rather than to Hobbes, who was hated as an atheist' and despised as a believer in the original compact¹. A further source of influence is to be found Scotland. in the relations of France to Scotland. The close pro connection between the two countries led to the migration to France of some Scotch Catholics, who would look with unfriendly eyes at the attempts of the Presbyterian leaders to dominate the politics of their country, whether by deposing Mary Stuart or menacing her son. The theory of popular govern- Apologia ment propounded by Buchanan was met by a Regibus. reply from Blackwood, a Scotsman settled in France. Buchanan was again one of the chief objects of attack De Regno. in the De Regno of Barclay, another Gallicised Scot. That Barclay should have announced upon the title- page that his book was a reply to a Scotch Pres- byterian, a Huguenot, and a French Papalist writer is evidence of the connection between the political ideas of France and Scotland. This book was dedi- cated to Henry IV. But Barclay never forgot that France and 1 It is worthy of note that Bodin in more than one place expresses himself in the strongest terms on the subject of the sovereignty being vested in the English king. In the coexistence of the privileges of the English Parliament and of the unlimited authority of the Crown, he finds evidence of his contention, that conciliar assemblies, whatever their power and antiquity, are no legal check upon the sovereign.' From Elizabeth's treatment of the House of Commons in respect to the succession he infers that Parliament has no real power to control the action of the Crown. La Republique, 1. 8, pp. 139 sqq. 'La souueraineté appertient pour le tout sans diuision aus Roys d'Angleterre, et les estats n'y ont que voir." 1 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 131 F X he was a Scotsman and that James I. needed to be defended in the exercise of his Divinely granted authority. Had it not been for the latter making it a condition that Barclay should renounce Catho- licism, he would probably have returned to Scotland, there to find a new field for controversy in the sacred cause of monarchy'. But the influence of both Barclay and Blackwood upon the mind of James is unquestionable, and through this channel, if no other, they must have influenced English thought. Filmer, indeed, singles them out along with Heywood as his chief forerunners, and regards their utterances as a complete expression of the rights of kings. Barclay's treatise De Potestate Papae was translated into English in 1611, a proof that his influence was not confined to France. Thus there is a chain of connection between the English and French theories of Divine Right. French theory and practice must certainly have influenced these Scotch writers. They could hardly enter into the controversy against 'Brutus' or Boucher, without taking account of French writings in support of monarchy. Nor could Scotsmen, living in France, remain unaffected by what was going on around them and by the circum- stances which led to a large body of French Catholics supporting the Divine Right of Henry IV. There can be no doubt that the earlier struggles of Huguenots, Leaguers, and Politiques all contributed to the developement of English political thought in the seventeenth century, whether in the direction of Divine Right or of the original compact. 1 Dict. of Nat. Biog., III. 173. 9-2 132 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW Black- wood. Blackwood's two works, De Vinculo Religionis et Imperii and the Apologia pro Regibus, are instances of the double aspect of the theory. The former treatise was written in order to emphasize the con- nection between the true faith and the doctrine of non-resistance. Its first two parts published in 1575 are written to shew that Calvinism involves a theory of resistance and is therefore false. The book is a protest from a strong Roman Catholic against the clericalism of the Presbyterian system. Exactly as Anglican divines affirm the Papal claims to be heretical, because they tend to dissolve the bond between sovereign and subjects, so Blackwood contends that Calvinism is proved to be false by its teaching of resistance¹. He complains that the new system takes away all freedom from states: whereas true religion is ever the support of government, and forbids resistance even to tyrants. The inference is that religion is the only security of states,—that there will be an end of law and order if false sects are permitted to exist. It is a sense of the political danger involved in toleration that prompts the author to write. The aim of most writers is to 1 "Religio quae semper hucusque regnorum conservatrix fuit, nunc temporum in reges armatur. Ex quo apparet veram non esse religionem, sed larvatam hypocrisim et perfidiam personâ religionis indutam, eo detestabiliorem, quo meliore se auctore jactitat." (De Vinculo, 261.) 2 "Quae, vestram fidem, conscientiae libertas quae in effraenam progressa licentiam, nihil imperio, nihil reipublicae, nihil mori- bus, nihil legibus liberum reliquit?" (De Vinculo, 262.) "Jamne religione perfidiam velabant suam? At religio servat ac tuetur, non labefactat, non evertit imperia." (Ibid. 289.) HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 133 inculcate the religious duty of obedience, that of Blackwood is to assert the political necessity of persecution. The third part of the book was not published until after the assassination of Henry IV. and is notable as containing a very strong condemnation of the League. The author is nearly heartbroken to think that any Catholic should have borrowed the maxims of Protestants. The interest of this treatise is great, for it affords complete justification for the manner in which Anglican divines identified Papist and Dissenting principles of governments. Blackwood makes the same identification from the opposite point of view. His argument is that no true Catholic can approve resistance, therefore all who profess to approve it in defence of the Catholic cause are in reality on the side of the Protestants. The Anglican view is that no true Protestant can approve resistance, and therefore that those Dissen- ters who allow it in the cause of Protestantism are Papists in disguise. G The Apologia pro Regibus is interesting in a different way. Whether or no it be out of compli- ment to the reputation of Buchanan, as a classical scholar, the inspiration of the book is largely clas- sical¹. Although Scripture is sometimes cited, the 1 Blackwood's position as at once a strong royalist and a devoted Papalist is remarkable. In the last part of the De Vinculo he extols the Pope's power, but avoids all reference to the deposition of Childeric or any disputed case; he is careful to confine himself to the perfectly harmless instances of royal reverence for the person of the holy Father. But in the 134 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW bulk of the illustrations and arguments are from classical history or philosophy. Appeals to Roman law are frequent and the secular tone of the whole. is remarkable. Perhaps Blackwood thought that his former work said enough upon the religious side. Or it may be, that the cause lay in the position of the writer as a Roman Catholic defending against Presbyterian subjects a King who was known to be a heretic. The book is further interesting for its. references to England, which to Blackwood as to Bodin, is a clear instance of undiluted absolutism. Certainly if the derided principle of a mixed monarchy were proved to have no force in England, it would hardly be thought to exist in France or Scotland. Blackwood, who is a strong Anglophobist, declares that neither in England nor certain other countries can the people be admitted to share the sovereignty, even with the consent of the King¹. He denies the validity of Henry the Eighth's testa- mentary devolution of the Crown; for the succession descends by an immutable law to the next of kin, Apologia pro Regibus his views come out more clearly. He cannot understand why Buchanan should object to the Pope doing what he approves in his own ministers (121). The depo- sition of Childeric was done not at the bidding, but with the consent of the Pope, and therefore implied no popular rights against the prince (197). He ascribes sovereignty to the Pope and declares him to be as far superior to other monarchs as they are to their subjects. Yet he admits an ultimate power in the council to depose for heresy. But since this power is never exercised, save in cases of Papal heresy, no inference of popular sovereignty can be drawn from it. The people are no judge of truth (201—4). ¹ Apologia, 6. HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW 135 not as his father's heir, but as the legitimate ruler of the kingdom¹. Blackwood's theory of sovereignty is complete with this exception. Monarchy may not be divided or shared in any way. Yet he regards force as the origin of kingship, a view curiously un- like that of other writers, while Nimrod is clearly the first king². He is so anxious to assert that the king is above the law, that unlike Justice Berkeley he denies that he is lex loquens. He declares that all laws only retain their force through the tacit assent of the sovereign at his accession³, while in regard to local laws and customs he approaches the Austinian maxim, "Whatever the sovereign permits, he commands4." 1 ¹ Apologia, 73 sqq. "Reges non regum sed regni sunt heredes" (112). 2 Ibid. ch. VII. 4 44 3 Ibid. ch. XI. Neque tamen eam vim ac firmitatem habent, ut a principe mutari non queant, cuius tum in leges, tum in homines potestas nulla ratione definiri potest" (Ibid. 110). Buchanan desired a mixed form of government, in which the King should have the supreme executive, the judges interpretative, the people legislative power. Blackwood ridicules this, and pertinently asks, "Non attendis legis interpretationem legis vim obtinere?" (ch. XIII.). He shews that there could be no supreme power in Buchanan's ideal state with its three ultimate authorities independent of one another. Regem populo subesse iubes, quem populo vis inuito legem im- ponere. Populo summam rerum attribuis, quem reluctantem et inuitum regis imperio subiicis. Sed qui fieri potest ut idem patiatur et agat? idem dominatur et serviat?" (295). The whole of Chapter XXXIII. is an argument in favour of monarchy as the expression of the principle of unity in all states. It is noteworthy that he regards this as the supreme effort of art, not nature; he apparently regards the family as an artificial organization. He finds it necessary to point out to his opponent that all states 136 HENRY OF NAVARRE AND THE SALIC LAW Previous enquiry necessary derstand- ing of This long preliminary investigation has shewn the causes at work in medieval England, in the to the un- conflicts within the Holy Roman Empire, in the French Wars of Religion, and in the circumstances of the English Reformation, which contributed in various ways to the development of a theory of kingship more uncompromising, narrow, and abso- lutist than had yet been prevalent in England. seven- teenth century contro- versy: It is now possible to approach the political controversies of the seventeenth century with some prospect of understanding why they took the shape they did. The ideas have arisen of Divine Right, of a fundamental law' of succession, of sovereignty, and on the other hand of the original compact, and of the duty of resistance at the bidding of the Church. It remains to view these notions welded into harmonious theories, to trace the process by which they were superseded, and to estimate the practical effect upon later ages of their once having been prevalent. contain some supreme authority, that the Roman or Athenian democracy or the Venetian oligarchy ruled with exactly that 'regal,' i.e. sovereign power which Buchanan thinks it possible to eliminate from the commonwealth (193). CHAPTER VII FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES THERE were many reasons why James I. should James I. hold the doctrine of the Divine Right of Kings in and the Theory of its strictest form. His claim to the throne of Divine Right. England rested upon descent alone; barred by two Acts of Parliament, it could only be suc- cessfully maintained by means of the legitimist principle. Further, it was disputed by the Roman controversialists, who had not sufficient hope of converting James to make them love his title. Doleman's attack on the hereditary principle is written from the Papalist standpoint. But it was not only from the Roman side that the position of James was threatened. Presbyterianism in Scotland, as expounded by Knox or Buchanan, and inwoven with politics by Murray and Morton, was a system of clericalism as much more irritating and meddlesome, as it was stronger and more popular in its basis than that of the Papal sovereignty. Even had there been no question of the English throne, there was enough in the position of a king, thwarted and insulted on all hands by the ministers of an upstart and narrow communion, to bring him into approval of a theory, 1598. 138 S which asserted against Papist and Presbyterian alike that every soul without benefit of clergy is subject to the royal authority, for the secular power is or- dained by God alone and may not be controlled by Pope or minister. Nor could the influences at work also in England and France, which led to the theo- retical exaltation of monarchy, have been devoid of effect upon the mind of James. Thus it is no matter for surprise, that at a time, when the sons of Zeruiah were too strong for him, and he felt his authority a mockery before the insolent representatives of eccle- siastical bigotry, James should promulgate with logical completeness and grasp with the tenacity of a narrow, but clear-sighted intellect the theory of the Divine Right of Kings. In the True Law of Free Monarchies, which saw the light five years before the death of Elizabeth, is to be found the doctrine of Divine Right complete in every detail¹. On his accession Parliament passed a statute which purported not to give James a title, but merely to declare his inherent right. This would seem evi- dence that the theory of Divine Right was by this time generally prevalent. Yet though, as was shewn above, approaches had been made to it in more ways than one, it does not appear as yet to have taken ** FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES ¹ There is an error on this point in the article in the Dictionary of National Biography. There it is stated by Gardiner that 1603 was the date of its appearance. But it was published anonymously in 1598. 2 1 Jas. I., c. 1. See Appendix A. Cf. also Coke's Reports, VII. 10 b: "The king holdeth the kingdom of England by birth- right inherent, by descent from the blood royal, whereupon succession doth attend." 1 ! [ FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 139 F 1 much hold of the popular imagination or even to Incon- have been fully grasped by those who professed to sistency of believe it. opinion. Evidence of this is to be found in Overall's Con- vocation Book. This was avowedly intended to be an authoritative exposition of the doctrine, but it exhibits a curious inability to understand what it actually involved, and is very different from the per- fectly harmonious system of the royalists of the Restoration or of James himself. The Canons are emphatic on the Divine authority of de facto governments¹. The language of the book on this point so greatly alarmed the King that he wrote irritably to Archbishop Abbot, bidding him not to meddle in matters too high for him. James was justified in declaring that, should Philip of Spain succeed in conquering the country, his right to the throne would be Divine on the principles of the Convocation Book, and Englishmen would be pre- cluded from ousting the usurper in favour of the lawful king. The compilers were so deeply imbued with the root idea of the theory of Divine Right, that secular government is lawful without Papal or clerical confirmation, that they were unable to attach due importance to the 'organic details' of the 1 Canons XXVIII-XXXIII. 2 The letter is printed in the edition of the Convocation Book in the Library of Anglo-Catholic theology. The book was, on account of this, not published until 1690. There is a strange inconsistency in the letter of James; for he complains of the Canons as not affording a justification of England in assisting the United Provinces. 140 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES doctrine, or to distinguish between claims founded on force and the right of conquest. James on the other hand met with a rebuff, The theory not yet generally when he attempted to expound his views of the accepted. inalienable character of sovereignty. The irritation of Parliament at his assertion, that, since all its privileges were originally granted by the Crown, they were liable to be revoked by the same autho- rity, may be taken as fairly representing the general sentiment at this time. Further, the answer of Coke to the King's request that he might sit as judge in the courts of law, is a precursor of the coming breach between the supporters of the sovereign rights of the Crown and the upholders of the Common Law. However, in Calvin's case the personal character of allegiance was asserted to the full¹, and the decision of Bates's case2 affirm- ed the doctrine that no King may materially 1 The unanimous opinion of the judges decided that allegiance is due by the law of nature and God and may not be altered, and is due to the person of the King, not to his politic capacity. It was greatly to exalt the position of the King to declare that the mere fact of his being King of England and Scotland so united the countries that henceforward no one born in one of them was an alien in the other. And the language in which this is declared still further exalts the Crown: "Whatsoever is due by the law or constitution of man may be altered: but natural legiance or obedience of the subject to the sovereign cannot be altered; ergo natural legiance or obedience to the sovereign is not due by the law or constitution of man. Again, whatsoever is due by the law of nature, cannot be altered, but legiance and obedience of the subject to the sovereign is due by the law of nature; ergo it cannot be altered." Coke's Reports, vII. 25 a. 2 Prothero's Statutes, 340-353. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 141 : diminish the rights of sovereignty, therefore that the statutes of Edward I. and Edward III. pro- hibiting unlimited customs did not bind their successors. Mainwaring's Sermons published in 1628 are evidence at once of the prevalence of the doctrine. and of its slow progress. The preacher asserts the Divine basis of royal authority and the right of the King to satisfy his necessities as seems good to him. Laud, however, thought the publication of these sermons inexpedient and endeavoured to prevent it¹. When the character of Laud's own opinions as to royal authority are taken into account, this fact is significant of the popular attitude on this subject. As yet the country would not swallow the doctrine that was so palatable to it during the latter half of the century. Not that there was much disloyalty. Up to a much later date the nation as a whole was profoundly loyal to the monarchy. But it was not until extreme theories of popular rights aroused the antagonism of the large class who held to the old order, that counter theories of a royal sovereignty uncontrolled by custom became at all widely prevalent. grows into From the time however that the conflict between The doctrine King and Parliament entered upon its acute stage there grew up a passionate sentiment of loyalty to popularity the Crown, which would be satisfied with nothing less Civil during the than the doctrine of Divine Right in its extremest War. form. As a popular force in politics the theory 1 See Gardiner, History of England, VI. 208, 9. 142 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES . hardly exerted much influence until the time of the Long Parliament. Henceforward Divine Right be- comes the watchword of all supporters of the rights of the Crown, at least until the Revolution. The most servile Parliament of Henry VIII., or that which recognized with such fulsome redundance the flawless title of James I., would scarcely have suffered the employment of such terms, as those which in 1640 gave expression to the sentiment of the great majority of the clergy :— "The most high and sacred order of kings is of Divine Right, being the ordinance of God Himself, founded in the prime laws of nature, and clearly established by express texts both of the Old and New Testaments. A supreme power is given to this most excellent order by God Himself in the Scripture, which is, that kings should rule and command in their several dominions all persons of what rank or estate soever, whether ecclesiastical or civil. * * * For any person or persons to set up, maintain or avow in any their said realms or terri- tories respectively, under any pretence whatsoever, any independent coactive power, either papal or popular, (whether directly or indirectly,) is to under- mine their great royal office, and cunningly to over- throw that most sacred ordinance which God Himself hath established; and so is treasonable against God as well as against the king. For subjects to bear arms against their kings, offensive or defensive, upon any pretence whatsoever, is at least to resist the powers which are ordained of God; and though they do not invade, but only resist, yet S. Paul tells FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 143 them plainly they shall receive to themselves damnation¹." It will be observed that there is no mention here of indefeasible hereditary right. None was needed. So long as Charles I. was King and his right to reign undisputed, there was no cause to linger over any question of hereditary right. Only, when the notion is expressly rejected by an influential section of the community, will it become necessary to reaffirm it. It is a truism that dogma never takes definite shape, save as a result of its denial by some thinker or leader. Thus the enthusiastic attachment to the notion of Passive Obedience was due to the Civil War and to the anarchy and tyranny that followed it. Before that time men might well have misgivings about the duty in extreme cases. But henceforward all who had suffered through the war entertained no doubt but that obedience to the most oppressive of regular authorities would lead to less misery than would resistance. So with hereditary right. It was the execution of Charles and the exclusion of his heir that led men to dwell upon the distinction between a de facto and a de jure authority. The logical mind of James I. would have found nothing to shock it in royalist pronouncements of this period. The confusion apparent in Overall's Convocation Book had now disappeared from the popular mind. No one now, whichever party he favours, but has a clear enough sense that it is possible to assert Divine Right for the lawful heir without predicating it of an usurper. 1 Cardwell's Synodalia, 1. 389. 144 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES There was now present every condition necessary for awakening men to the sharp distinctions between de jure and de facto authority and between passive obedience and active resistance however slight. On the one hand there were the recollection of the arbi- trary rule of Charles I. and the general hatred of the methods of Strafford and the Star Chamber. These would serve to keep men in mind that a lawful government might be intolerably oppressive, and that therefore complete or active obedience would not always be a duty. On the other hand there was the existence of an upstart military autocracy, claiming to be the inheritor of the secular traditions of the English constitution and demanding universal allegiance, as though there were no question about the legality of its acts. This would sufficiently ensure that every royalist and every opponent of Cromwell and the Major-generals should realize, that an usurper can have no moral claim to obedience, and that it may be a sacred duty to restore the dispos- sessed heir. Passive Obedience and Indefeasible Hereditary Right were no new conceptions; they had long been in the air, and the necessity of com- bating Papal claims had brought about a doctrine of which they were merely the logical expansion. But as a force in English politics they owe their im- portance largely to the Civil War and the successful usurpation of Cromwell. The horror which was awakened by the execution of Charles, and the melancholy reverence which Eikon Basiliké won for the Martyr, would tend to deepen in men's minds their sentiment in favour of royal power, as clothed *** FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 145 with mysterious sanctity, and separated by a gulf from all other forms of government. Thus, while the origin of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings is earlier and due to other causes -for no real additions are made to the doctrine expounded by James, its widespread prevalence was certainly due rather to the Civil War than to any more remote causes. It is the sentiment that brought back Charles II. to his father's throne, and finds- expression in the Act of Uniformity¹. stages of the gious in In the Tudor period the doctrine is seen in the Three making. It is forged as a weapon in the great con- flict with ecclesiastical aggression. The character doctrine. given to it by that controversy remained ever its 1. Reli- most essential quality. But the theory of govern- sixteenth ment was developing at the same time and partly century. through the same causes. In the seventeenth century 2. Poli- the real value of the theory in the development of tical in political thought appears. Retaining still its anti- teenth papal character, it yet exhibits itself more completely, as the form in which was expressed the discovery of sovereignty. The controversies which rage round the origin of law become now prominent. And the supporters of the doctrine of Divine Right are constantly found fighting for their contention, that law cannot exist independently of some lawgiver, and seven- century. Pag 1 Declaration to be made by schoolmasters &c.: "I A.B. do declare that it is not lawful upon any pretence whatsoever to take arms against the king, and that I do abhor that traitorous position of taking arms by his authority against his person or against those that are commissionated by him," 14 Car. II. c. 4. 13 Car. II. c. 1, makes it an offence to declare that either or both Houses of Parliament have any legislative power without the king. F. 10 146 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES that the ultimate legislative authority in any state is -necessarily above all positive law. The value of the theory as a political force is due not to this purely scientific element, but to the testimony it bears to the need of continuity in national life and to the para- mount importance to a state of a law-abiding habit. It is easy to deny the doctrine. But those, who do this, should bear in mind that the singularly orderly character of English constitutional development, its freedom from violent changes, would not have been obtained but for the influence of this doctrine. In contemplating the earlier stages of the Re- formation, we are driven to regard with gratitude the men, who alone made possible a justification of the position of independence assumed by the English monarchy against the Pope. But the Divine Right of Kings is more than the effective expression of Gallicanism. It has a purely political side, which comes out most strongly in the middle of the seven- teenth century. From the writings of that period we learn how it has stamped upon the English mind. the conception of sovereignty, and thereby rendered a service which can hardly be overestimated by all who value the writings of John Austin. Further, in contemplating the Restoration and the period of the Exclusion Bill and the Revolution, we are driven to express the debt of modern times to the faith, through which alone men weathered the storm of political change and achieved the ends of freedom and good government with less of bloodshed and anarchy than has been the lot of any other nation. This passionate sense of the need of continuity in national institutions FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 147 1 is perhaps the dominant note of the pamphlets and sermons which poured forth in a deluge, when men were debating the question of a Popish successor to Charles II., and weighing in a balance the risks of persecution and the advantages of an unbroken succession. Exclusion A further impulse to enthusiasm was afforded by The the Exclusion Bill. The controversy, which raged Bill. round that ill-fated measure, was the source on the one hand of the most emphatic expressions of belief in indefeasible hereditary right and passive obedience, and on the other of the clearest exposition of the theory of popular rights. Doleman's pamphlet was reprinted. The theory of original compact and of the purely official character of the kingly dignity was elaborated; while the discussion on the position of Julian the Apostate reveals the similarity of the arguments employed to those of French and Im- perialist thinkers, and is evidence that the popular party had no fault to find with the dialectic method of their opponents. opponents. In Julian the Apostate Johnson argues that Johnson the inference commonly drawn from the obedience and his of the Christians to an unbelieving Emperor is false, for as a matter of fact they did not recognize his authority, and S. Gregory Nazianzen had fears that his father the Bishop would have kicked the Emperor¹. To this it is replied in Constantius the Apostate, that the assertions are unfounded and are a libel upon Christians; further, that if 1 Johnson's Works, p. 21. 10-2 148 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 1681. Filmer's 'Patri- archa.' they were true, it would not affect the argument, for Christians recognized Constantius and obeyed him, although he was an Arian. Thus the duty of obedience to a heretic sovereign was demonstrated. The acknowledged dangers to be apprehended from James lead men to emphasize the duty of passive obedience. Tears and prayers are repeatedly de- clared to be the only lawful weapons against a tyrant. It was felt that there might ere long be need of them. The Doctrine of the Cross, as it is called, is written up with much enthusiasm in a host of pamphlets and sermons. It was shortly after this time that Filmer's Patriarcha was first published. The work won great and deserved popularity as the ablest justification of the extreme royalist doctrine. Filmer had the acuteness to see that of the two modes of argu- • ment, that of relying upon a medley of Scripture texts, forbidding resistance and asserting Divine sanction for kingship, and that of claiming that monarchy is in accordance with the teachings of nature, the latter rested upon a far more solid basis. It is always possible to explain away single texts of Scripture. Indeed no one nowadays but knows that, when S. Paul and S. Peter enjoined obedience to established government as a religious duty, they were far from considering the question of men's duty in extreme cases, and had no notion of discussing the right of insurrection. Whether or no Filmer was aware of this may be doubted. Probably he was not, as in another place he founds an elaborate argument on the thirteenth · FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 149 mode of of Romans¹. But he was instinctively conscious that this was not the best method of establishing his position. In his treatise the textual method of argument falls quite into the background be- fore the prominence given to the conception that Changed monarchy is founded in nature. The idea is not argument. new. It was introduced with more or less of com- pleteness by most of the supporters of Divine Right. Indeed Harrington alludes to it as a recognized argument. But with them it is rather an illustration or a figure of rhetoric than the basis of an argument. Filmer rests his whole system upon it. He attempts to find the origin of kingship in the natural consti- tution of society, and bases it neither on force nor on popular sanction, but on human nature, as formed by the Creator. Most writers regard the fact that kingship is founded by Divine ordinance, as proved by the institution of the kingdom of Israel or by isolated phrases in Daniel or Proverbs; to this proof they are content to add that kingship is indeed natural, as may be seen in a family or the animal kingdom among geese or sheep. Filmer on the other hand contends that kingship is natural, and that therefore it must be ordained by God, the author of nature. His whole argument depends on the identification of the kingdom with the family, and of royal with paternal power. That the King is the father of his people was a metaphor frequently employed by writers in favour of monarchy. Filmer expands the metaphor into an argument, and founds. upon it the only rational system of absolutist 1 Preface to Observations on Aristotle, 150 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Many politics. The patriarchal conception of society is far writers do from being of the essence of the theory of the not make archal theory the basis of the the patri- Divine Right of Kings; it is merely the best argu- ment by which it is supported. Some supporters of the theory scarcely refer to the idea, most however doctrine. do so, but employ it very loosely, and clearly without the notion that it was a far better justification for their opinions than the phrase, “By me kings reign, and princes decree judgment." King James uses the analogy avowedly as a metaphor. Sir Dudley Digges declares that the King is "without a metaphor the father of his people," evidence that the comparison is commonly regarded as a mere figure of speech. Like other authors he regards the marriage tie, as equally typical of the bond between King and people, and is ready with the argument against resistance, "What God hath joined, let no man cut asunder." Sanderson, like Bodin, declares that kings have more powers than parents, and that a monarch is a brother and something more." Mainwaring regards the bond between King and people as fourfold, con- sisting of the ties that bind (1) The Creator and the Creature, (2) Husband and Wife, (3) Parents and Children, (4) Masters and Servants¹. << These are only a few instances of the general view, which is merely that allegiance is the strongest of all bonds and includes all other human ties. Of any general patriarchal theory of kingship there is little evidence before Filmer2. It is his merit to have 1 Religion and Allegiance, 3. 2 S. Thomas Aquinas, who regards the family as something similar to the kingdom, is the type of most thought. Sanderson FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 151 discovered that the common metaphor contained within it the germ of a system far more substantial in its basis than the ordinary hotch-potch of quota- tions from Scripture. The popularity of the book is further evidence that the idea came to most men with the force of a discovery. For its sole contribu- tion to the theory is the careful elaboration of the patriarchal conception of kingship. If the notion had previously been regarded as a necessary element of the doctrine, it would be hard to account for Filmer's reputation. Men clutched at the chance, given them by the Patriarcha, of grappling with their opponents on better terms than were afforded by the weapons with which they were familiar. At the same time Filmer can hardly be said to have been the discoverer of the conception. His book was ܘ ܓ ܪ ܐ ܕ ܓ ܓܝܕ says "the master or paterfamilias is a kind of petty monarch there" (Judgment in One View, p. 106), and argues that "what power the master hath over his servants for the ordering of his family no doubt the same at the least, if not much more, hath the supreme magistrate over his subjects for the peace of the Common- wealth, the magistrate being Pater Patrie as the master is Pater familias” (p. 108). And again, "A governor is a brother too and something more; and duty is charity too and something more. .. If then I may not offend my brother, then certainly not my governor" (p. 112). Vox Populi, a pamphlet against Spain of 1624, is an instance of the loose way in which the patriarchal power is regarded, even by a writer who seems to approach Filmer. "C Amongst all nations the rule of a family or country was conferred upon the eldest. Until there were kings they were instead of such, and when there were kings, either they were chosen out of these, or these were their substitutes in such families and places where they resided" (7). The Royal Charter granted unto Kings regards the Divine origin of kingship as proved by the case of Melchisedec, who was "without father, without mother" (6). 152. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 1644. certainly the occasion of its prevalence, but so wide- spread a metaphor as that of the King being pater patriae is sure to be pressed to its full extent by some writers. The arguments of Bodin in favour of monarchy and the phrases employed by Williams, Bishop of Ossory, in a little pamphlet, Jura Magis- tratus, are an indication that men were feeling their way to a system akin to that of Filmer¹. The importance of Filmer in the history of the doctrine is indeed great. But he deserves to be remembered, less as the most perfect exponent of the theory, than as the herald of its deca- dence. It is an easy transition from the con- ception of government as directly established by Divine command to the notion that, since God is the author of nature, whatever is natural has His sanction. Yet the change is great. For direct Divine Right has been substituted a constructive theory of Divine approval. The theological conception of politics is giving way before what may be termed Transition the naturalistic. In this disguised form the theory to natural The con- structive theory of Divine Right. rights. of Divine Right, as the only possible justification for any political system, lingers on until with the present century the notion of natural rights has fallen into discredit. In a sense it may be said, that Filmer paved the way not only for Locke, but for Rousseau. It is plain that the theory of natural rights, whether vested in King or people, is the next stage of 1 Jura Magistratus, 15: "Every master of a family that ruleth his own household is a petite king"; and again, "A kingdom is nothing else but a great family where the king hath paternal power," 22. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 153 believe in natural developement to the conception that all political systems must find their sanction in the Bible, as the complete Revelation of the Divine Will. Whether the theory be one of Divine Right in the older sense, or of natural rights as a proof of Divine sanction, the motives which lead men to adopt it are the same. It is the desire to find some immutable basis for Motive to politics and to lift them above considerations of mere a theory of expediency, that prompts men to elaborate systems Divine or of Divine or natural rights. They are haunted rights. with the hope of finding a universal system, superior to time and circumstance, untrammelled by con- siderations of historical development or national idiosyncrasy. And to both schools, that of the believers in Divine right, whether of Pope or Presbytery or King, and that of the upholders of natural and inalienable, i.e. Divine rights of nations or individuals, the same objections apply. No system Fallacies of politics can be immutable. It is impossible in of theories framing a doctrine of government to lay down rights. eternal principles, which may never be transgressed. A universal theory of the state is a chimæra, for historical development and national character are the most important of all considerations in investigating the laws of political development. The arguments, with which Burke encountered the system of the Revolutionary idealists, are equally applicable to the theories of Bellarmine on behalf of the Pope, or of James I. or Filmer in favour of monarchy. The theory of natural rights is the old theory of Divine Right disguised. natural Yet it was disguised. There is no denying the ? > 154 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Filmer's change of front really gives up the ground. great transformation thought has undergone, when controversialists have abandoned the habit of un- critically compiling a cento of Scripture phrases for arguments. No longer is the Bible regarded as the sole source of political theory. Instead of this, an attempt, however imperfect, is made to seek in the nature of man and the necessity of human society the changeless principles of civil government and inviola- ble laws of political duty. Once the project of finding an immutable system of politics be granted as worthy of undertaking, it is certainly more reasonable to seek it in the teachings of nature, than in the doubtful import of a fortuitous concourse of Scripture texts. At least it is one step further towards a utilitarian or a historical system of politics, for nature certainly would seem to approve the principle of utility, and it distinctly indicates the importance of developement according to the law of an organism. The first fact, that utility is in accordance with the law of nature, was recognized by Locke and Sidney, while Filmer has certainly more of the historical spirit than any of his opponents, or than some of his predecessors, such as Blackwood. In any case it is the merit of Filmer to have seen, that a natural system of politics was more likely to prove well-founded than a purely theological scheme; or rather to have regarded theology as point- ing to nature as the teacher of political philosophy. Yet the credit due to him as a political thinker, is not clearly his as a supporter of his own theory. His method paved the way for its overthrow. The older mode of arguing from Scripture texts as direct Divine injunctions, had this advantage, that it was FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 155 impregnable to the assaults of criticism, and that neither natural law nor the principle of utility could avail aught against it. In partially deserting the old method of argument Filmer has in reality surrendered the case for Divine Right. In ap- pearance his position is far stronger than that of his predecessors. The reason of this is that his argument approaches more closely to those with which we are familiar. Filmer's theory of Divine Right was expressed in a syllogism:- What is natural to man exists by Divine Right. Kingship is natural to man. Therefore Kingship exists by Divine Right. This is a sounder mode of procedure than that of collecting a few texts and illustrations from the Bible and ignoring or emptying of their meaning any that make for the contrary view. Yet Filmer's position is far more open to attack than that of the - older controversialists. The verse "they that resist shall receive to themselves damnation" is apparently of unmistakeable import, which can only be evaded by sophistry. No arguments from expediency, no fresh reading of history could affect the elaborate accumulation of texts made by Mainwaring in support of his doctrine. The only possible way to meet him was to deny the interpretation or the applicability of the passages quoted. In fact, considerations of utility or historical circumstances could not affect the ordinary argument for Divine Right. But with Filmer's arguments this is not the case. For the whole question of what constitutes the law of nature is involved, and it is easy to argue as did 1 156 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Locke for the principle of utility, the instinct of self- preservation, as of natural and therefore Divine origin. Both Locke and Sidney, indeed, elevate their own principle of natural rights above any considera- tions of temporary expediency, and would not allow that the legislature in a state is sovereign, even though it were manifestly expedient that it should be so. But the principle of utility governs much of their thought, and they are justified in regarding its dictates as being every whit as much a law of nature, as the necessity of obedience to government. The theory of natural rights and original compact propounded by the Whig opponents of Filmer is less well-founded and more artificial than the Divine Right of Kings. But the speculations of Locke and Sidney have this of value, that they recognize to some extent the importance of considerations of utility in framing a practicable theory of politics. It is the failure to see this, not the elaboration of an abso- lutist system, that is the real ground of the puerilities of the royalist school. But in appealing to natural law Filmer was paving the way for the use of this principle of utility to overthrow his idealist system. With those of the old school it was useless talking of utility. They regard the Bible as containing in set terms an emphatic prohibition of resistance, and they put this in the forefront of their argument. Against such a contention no argument from the inexpediency of absolute non- resistance can have any hope of success. The arguments drawn from isolated texts seem to modern readers the most absurd part of the theory of Divine FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 157 * * Right. They are in reality the strength of the position. If the arguments were absurd, it was not easy to prove it. But for Filmer the Bible is no mere storehouse of texts, though he will be ready so to employ it on occasion. It is the one historical document which gives authentic information as to the nature of primitive society. In the early chapters of Genesis he finds evidence, that society is as old as humanity, that kingship is an expansion of family life, and that monarchy is the inalienable natural power of the father. The value of the conception is great; it is far less unhistorical or artificial than the Whig idea of the state, and contains by implication the pregnant truth that the state is an organism, not a machine. Yet the Divinity claimed for kingship is, as has been pointed out, purely constructive. The protection afforded by Filmer's direct Divine injunction is abandoned; the inspira- position tion of the Bible is of service, only so far as was attack. needed to authenticate the account of society given. in Genesis. The truth or falsehood of Mr McLen- nan's theory of primitive society would have been a vital matter for Filmer. Had the theory of the former been accepted, the system of the latter would have fallen like a house of cards. But the mutterrecht would have had no bearing on the common argu- ments. Nothing was easier than to meet Filmer on his own ground, and Locke did so. He asserts that Filmer has misconceived Genesis, that, as a fact of history, no such kingly power as was claimed for him, was ever held by Adam, that, if it had been, it could have no possible reference to the open to J 158 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES : power of modern kings. Locke then interrogates his own consciousness, as to what are the natural instincts of men, and infers, on the same ground of natural law as Filmer, a totally opposed conclusion. Filmer's political theory is in brief this. Natural rights are Divine rights. There is one natural right only, the authority of the father. This is preserved in the sovereign power in all states. All men are born slaves. Locke on the other hand asserts, that all men are born free and equal, with inalienable rights granted them by God; that states are founded upon compact from motives of utility, and are not given unlimited authority, for that would be to contradict the law of self-preservation. The point of view of both Locke and Filmer is in reality identical. Both believe that there existed a state of nature, and that true principles of politics may in some way some way be discovered by investiga- tion into it. Both believe that whatever rights belong to man living in a state of nature are inalienable and may not be taken from him by any form of organized society. Filmer believes that the W Comet one inalienable right is the power of the father. He saw what Hobbes and Locke and all believers in the original compact failed to see, that political society is natural and necessary to men, and is no artificial creation of their choice. But his method of proving this is by finding the state of nature in the patriarchal society described in the Bible. He, indeed, believed that there was irrefragable evidence to prove that his state of nature was a historical fact; while Locke and Hobbes were content to FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 159 urge on à priori grounds that theirs must have existed, although there was no evidence to shew it. between actual the state In both cases there was the same impassable Gulf gulf between the present condition of society and what was believed to be the primitive state. The society and theory of compact is Locke's method of bridging the of nature. gulf. Filmer in this point is less successful. He admits that the heir of Adam is not now to be found, and only escapes the difficulty by means of the principle that possession gives the best right, where none else is to be found. But, as with Locke the rights of man in the state of nature still subsist to be the foundation of political liberty, save in so far as they have been partially surrendered to the civil government, so with Filmer the rights of the father are the foundation of all political society and of the title of every government to the obedience of its subjects. Locke of course had no difficulty in pointing out, that it is a strange proceeding to argue Divine appointment for a number of monarchs, who are admittedly the descendants of usurpers, merely on the ground that their ancestors were less scrupulous than those of other men. Locke's destructive criticism is completely effective, owing to the slender bond of connection between the primitive family and modern political society. Thus Filmer's work forms the transition stage between the older views and those of Locke in more ways than one. Not only does it afford the necessary link of developement between theories of Divine and of natural right; but it approaches the schemes of Locke and Rousseau 160 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES h in its singular idealism. It is almost grotesque to treat political theory as though all its problems could be solved by an appeal to the primitive family. The attempt to find in patriarchal authority the sole source of all political rights, and to derive the modern state directly from the Adamic society gives to Filmer's work an air of unreality, which is not shared by that of earlier writers. While Filmer's method was sounder, his system was more artificial than that of his predecessors. The same might be said of Locke with reference to Filmer. His system is as much more unhistorical in its basis, as it is more reasonable in its conclusions, than that of Filmer. Stages in the develop- ment of the theory The change which had thus come over the royalist method of conducting the controversy is significant. The theory of the Divine Right of and sub- Kings took its rise as a doctrine of the right of Agadirat Ja secular governments to be free from clerical inter- ference. In its essential idea the doctrine had been at work in English politics from the days of Henry VIII. So long as there was much to be apprehended from the side of those who claimed a Divine right to control the state in the interests of an ecclesiastical organization, it was necessary to lay stress on the religious side of the argument for kingship. But as this danger tended to disappear, and the doctrine had begun to do its work, secular politics were free to develope on their own lines. Theological systems of politics and purely theological arguments were no longer needed to meet the claims of Pope or Presbytery, and politics entered sequent ideas. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 161 upon the modern stage. The theory of natural rights is inevitably the next stage of developement. It abandons the attempt to discover in Scripture the sanctions of civil society, and its direct institu- tion by God. Yet it retains the conception of an immutable system of politics, rooted in the nature of man, and not to be changed through motives of mere expediency. Like the theory of Divine Right, the doctrine of natural rights is an attempt to determine à priori the nature of govern- ment, the limits of obedience, and the principles which should govern state action. Less even than the theory of Divine Right does it take account of circumstances or historical causes. It proclaims a system of politics, clear, universal, and unalterable, based not on the uncritical study of Scripture, but on what are believed to be the teachings of nature and the dictates of pure reason. Many supporters of Divine Right confined their view to special states, and peculiar circumstances, whatever their system might claim of abstract truth and universality. The supporters of natural rights in most cases paid no regard to racial characteristics or external con- ditions, but proclaimed a doctrine that should last for all time and be valid for all stages of civilization Yet if they erred greatly, in seeking an eternal system of rights and duties to govern the fleeting arrangements of political constitutions, at least their plan of seeking political theory in nature had this merit: that they could not altogether ignore the principle of utility. Thus they were one step nearer to modern political theory. G F. 11 162 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES At this point considerations of utility will begin once more to be of importance, while a further stage will be the abandonment of the attempt to find an immutable political theory; and politics will become, as they are at the present day, purely utilitarian or historical. It was the work of the supporters of the Divine Right of Kings to make this possible. It was impossible for the state to develope its principles, so long as its very existence, as an independent power, was constantly threatened by clericalism. To set it free from ecclesiastical control it was needful to claim Divine institution for its head. But when this purpose was realized, and indepen- dence attained, the state, secure in its new-found freedom, may develope principles of politics without reference to theology. Before, it would have been at once dangerous and useless so to do. The main work of the theory of Divine Right was drawing to a close, although a little remained to be accom- plished. It was natural that its supporters should alter the basis upon which their theory rested. Men do not desert a belief, until some time after its main purpose is fulfilled. As has been seen, there were still potent causes to attach men to the doctrine. So long as the recollection was vivid of the martyrdom of Charles and of the tyranny of Oliver, men would continue to assert the theory. Besides, all danger from Rome or Scotland was scarcely over as yet. But the latter had sufficiently diminished in magnitude, to admit of the transition from the purely Scrip- tural to the sociological argument on behalf of bang FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 163 Divine Right¹. It is also a note of the more general change from the theological age to the rationalist, which marked the latter half of the seventeenth century, and may be discerned in Baxter. The changed method of conducting the con- Nalson. troversy appears in a work written later, though published earlier than The Patriarcha, Nalson's Common Interest of King and People. The title 1678. of this book sufficiently indicates the main line of argument employed. The author begins with an elaborate account of the principle of self-preservation and of the desire of happiness, as the ruling motives of human nature. No terms could be stronger than those in which the writer sets forth the universality of this law of nature, and, were it not for the excel- lence of the style, the first few pages might have been written by Bentham. The basis of the theory, unlike that of Filmer, is utilitarian, although other proofs are not discarded. There is a short exposition of the patriarchal theory, but this is not made the foundation of the system. Monarchy is proved to be the most perfect form of government by reason of its antiquity, its universality, its conformity with human nature, and of the fact that it satisfies the 1 A proof that this was the case is afforded by the writings of Bellarmine. The Cardinal repeatedly allows to kingship the con- structively Divine character of being rooted in natural necessity. But he declares that the Pope has an immediate commission from God, which kings have not. Their right is indeed Divine, for it is natural, but it is not, as the Pope's power is, founded on direct Divine injunction. Against Bellarmine the older writers assert that the king does hold his power by a direct Divine grant. But Filmer partially abandons this argument. 11-2 164 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES great ends of all action, the instinct of self-preserva- tion and the desire of happiness. So far the tone is strangely modern. Then in a short passage the writer reverts to the older mode of argument, and adduces the fourth of Daniel as clear evidence of the Divinity of Kingship. The book is remarkable for its lucidity and grasp of principles. It is further to be observed, that it contains an elaborate demon- stration of the incompatibility, not merely of the Papal sovereignty, but of the Presbyterian system with the independence of the secular authority and with the liberty of the subject. Nalson is convinced that Presbyterianism, if allowed a free hand, is de- structive of the freedom of Crown, Parliament, and individual alike. Here again with all his ability, which invests the work with an interest lacking to the usual hash of texts in royalist pamphlets and sermons, the author has yet surrendered his whole case by his adoption of the utilitarian standpoint. In a case like that of James II. will it be possible seriously to maintain that his continued reign would be agreeable to the principle of utility? Doubtless it might be the case, for, as Hobbes thought, the evils attendant on the most peaceful Revolution may outweigh every benefit attained thereby. Luther also had taken the view, that no price was too high for the peace secured by the power of the prince. But such a view could never become popular. Unless the doctrine of non-resistance has something higher than considerations of utility to recommend it, it cannot hope to hold its ground. The mass of man- kind will never be convinced, that it is useful to pag FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 165 maintain in power a government, which is oppressive beyond limit. But they may be persuaded that it is their duty to do so. If acuter minds have come to the conclusion that a revolution is always inex- pedient, the only method of making their opinion practically effective will be by inducing the vulgar to believe that it is always iniquitous. This was the great source of strength to the upholders of Passive Obedience, as the plain teaching of the Gospel. If Christianity be indeed a doctrine of the Cross in their sense, and every kind of tyranny is to be endured by true Christians, there will be no use demonstrating the inexpediency of non-resistance. The more foolish it is from a common-sense point of view, the more clearly is it the duty of those who look beyond this world. What has convenience to do with God's direct command? But with Nalson's system these considerations lose their force, and in his book, even more than in that of Filmer, we see the beginning of the end. But Filmer's patriarchal theory was the necessary transition to the next stage of developement, that represented by Locke and Sidney, while Nalson's thought rather looked forward to a yet further day, when natural rights themselves should be scouted as ridiculous, and po- litical theories be constructed on utilitarian principles alone. J - is still Both Filmer and Nalson were a little in advance Yet the old method of most contemporary writers. They do no more than foreshadow the decadence in store for the old modes popular. of thought and argument. Meanwhile, these remain. with little diminution in popularity for some time 166 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Third stage of the theory: to come. The majority of the supporters of Divine. Right, even after the Revolution, use arguments that differ but slightly from those of the time of the Commonwealth. Indeed, one effect of the Revolution was to turn the eyes of all who did not love it on the past and to deepen for a time the sentiment in favour of the purely Biblical method of political theory. The non-jurors had been beaten by accom- romantic. plished facts. Like all supporters of "lost causes and forsaken beliefs," they draw their main inspiration from the past. The very fact that men are beginning to discredit their modes of reasoning as obsolete, will cause them to cling to them with greater tenacity, as the loved relics of the order which has passed away. The raison d'être of their party is the sentiment of romantic attachment to old modes of thought and feeling, to outworn theories, and to ideals which practical men have forgotten. The Jacobite will be more, not less inclined to lay stress upon the re- ligious duty of Passive Obedience and upon the direct appointment of kings by God, than was the contro- versialist of the Restoration, who had, as he hoped, not merely to justify the past, but to carve out the future. To the one Divine Right was a force of practical value, and its employment part of the business of life. To the other it was a memory and a vain regret. The Revolution and the Act of Settlement disposed for ever of the doctrine of indefeasible hereditary right, and made it all but impossible to maintain the theory of non-resistance. Yet these results were by no means immediate, so far Prevalence of the belief even after the Revolu- tion. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 167 as the bulk of Englishmen were convinced. The doctrine indeed could not die out all at once. And the existence of a widespread feeling in favour of the Stuarts is evidence that it did not do so. The Revolution threw on to the side of the Stuarts the whole latent sentiment in favour of all institutions or beliefs of which the life is decaying. The great practical reason for supporting the theory of Divine Right no longer existed. At last all danger to the state from clerical interference was at an end. It became moreover increasingly clear that the doctrine as a pillar of government had done its work, and that the leaders of thought and action, with whom rested the future, had far other aims in view than the conduct of politics in accordance with theological theories of kingship and obedience. But all this tended to beget a sentiment, that was to invest the Stuart line with a dignity, which it never had when in possession, and to bestow upon it a charm, to which no reigning dynasty can lay claim. From 1688 the Stuart cause is the expression of the 'passion of the past'; and the theory that supports it suffers a like change. All men's hatred of what is new because it is new, their dislike of conquering ideas because they are winning, their love of the antique for no reason than that it is not modern, will draw them to the side of the 'king over the water.' The Divine Right of Kings has reached its last stage. At first a method of meeting in argument a foe, whom it was impossible to conquer by force, it grew in weight and efficiency, until it became one of the chief means whereby men justified to themselves the rejection of 168 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES that Papal supremacy that threatened to retard the free developement of the national states. The deep sentiment of anti-clericalism which it enshrined saved men from the danger of submitting to another and a yet more blighting tyranny of ecclesiasticism, that threatened to suck the life out of state and people with a network of inquisitorial jurisdiction and with a narrow code of life and morality. In the political conflicts of the seventeenth century, in which religion played so large a part, the Divine Right of Kings had been the form in which expression had been found for men's reverence for tradition and for their instinctive sense that progress can never come by trampling on old institutions. Thus the theory was the bulwark of the restored monarchy, by rallying sentiment round the King, as the ancient centre and symbol of national life. It had preserved the continuity of the constitutional system, and was probably a main cause of the tranquillity, which marked the English alone among the Revolutions Effect of of history. By a fiction, as expedient as it was the theory transparent, the sentiment in favour of obedience taining the to law was prevented from receiving any shock, and continuity those who smile at the falsity of the assertion that English James II. 'abdicated the throne' would do well to bear in mind that it is far easier to shake the law- abiding sentiment by an admitted break with the legal system of the past, than it is to repair it by any improvement in the constitution. But, if with a certain amount of ingenuity the doctrine of non- resistance might still be maintained to be a principle of English constitutional life, it was not so with in of the state. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 169 Jacobite indefeasible hereditary right, which, after suffering a shock at the Revolution, received an irretrievable blow in the Act of Settlement. Nor was it possible any longer to contend that the King was absolutely sovereign, and accountable to God alone. Hence- forward the Divine Right of Kings is the expression of regretful aspirations, and in no sense of actual fact. From a practical force it has become a romantic sentiment. Pity for the unfortunate and loyalty to a forlorn hope were now the main elements in the faith. Its true character is to be found in that burst The of lyrical lament, that echoed with pathetic melan- Songs. choly of tone the longings of men, who were ever "looking backwards." It is in this rather than in sermons or treatises that we must seek the source of such lingering vitality, as still remained to the doctrine. No fresh developement in argumentative method was possible, and the writings of Leslie are in many respects little more than an expansion of Filmer. But perhaps in the very brilliancy of the non-juring controversialist, in his pungent satire and acute criticism we may have an indication, that the defence of the doctrine is becoming rather a jeu d'esprit than a serious labour. Once an intellectual weapon against the assaults of Rome, the by no means contemptible expression of a very practical determination to ensure for the state a free hand, the doctrine in losing its value as a force has ac- quired a certain æsthetic interest. The feeling which keeps it alive is partly artistic, partly sentimental, and becomes vivid to us in the song for the blackbird, and the legendary halo surrounding Bonnie Prince 170 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Charlie. This phase of the belief is enshrined for ever in the novels of Sir Walter Scott. The use, which more recent writers of romance have made of the Jacobite sentiment, is a further proof that the main interest of the belief after 1688 is æsthetic. This aspect of the doctrine is indeed so familiar to us, that it is hard to realize that it ever possessed any other. We find it easy enough to regard with a certain tolerance a faith, which is to us a mere romantic pose. But it is not so easy to recognize, that this was only the latest phase in the history of a theory, which had been a force of great practical importance, the expression (in obsolete forms) of deep truths of political philosophy and of a necessary stage of political developement. That all this was the case there is ample evidence to prove. But the practical work of the doctrine was done before the Revolution, and it is well to realize that the tendency to hold it was the inevitable feeling, that touches all dying causes with a sunset charm. It is those, who find artistic gratification in contemplating with half- simulated regret an order which is no more, who will more and more make up the diminishing band of Jacobite enthusiasts. It is worthy of remark that Swift and Boling- broke, the two most brilliant practical politicians on the Tory side, have neither of them anything but contempt for a doctrine which they regard as absurd and as emptied of all effectual influence. Swift's pamphlet, The sentiments of a Church of England man, save in the assertion that the supreme legis- lative power may never be resisted, is utterly unlike FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 171 the work of earlier royalist writers. Nor does Boling- broke like the theory any better. Indeed his criticism is far more modern in its tone, than that of any other writer with views resembling his own. His assertion that "a divine right to govern ill is an absurdity; to assert it blasphemy1" might have been written a hundred years later, and exhibits the same sort of ignorance to be deplored in most criticisms of the doctrine. The real point of it is entirely missed, and a faith, which had at least in the past exercised great influence, is exhibited as though it had never been more than antiquarian pedantry. Just in so far as for practical men the theory is ceasing in the reign of Anne to have any interest, it begins to have a value for all who with whatever motive are in love with what is antiquated, and is passing into tradition. There is always a sense of attachment to a dispossessed house, and some men still cling to Divine Right as investing with a certain glamour of mystic import the ancient line and its God-given title. The Divine Right of the Stuarts becomes the symbol and the sacrament of the con- trast between right and might, between the favour of men and the justice of God, between the romance of the past and the sordid turmoil of the present, between the ideal of a state and the reality of politics. Perhaps it is not too much to say, that the doctrine yet survives as an influence through the peculiar melancholy interest, that is still felt to surround the ill-fated race, whatever be the light in which their rule is regarded. ¹ The idea of a patriot king. Bolingbroke, Works, 11. 379. 172 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES Yet the theory had still some vitality. Yet even as a practical force the doctrine was by no means dead for some time yet. In this connection, the non-jurors may perhaps be disregarded as a small body of idealists. But the insecurity of the new order, the constant intrigues with the court of S. Germains, the perpetual fears of Jacobite risings are a proof that the feeling in favour of the dispossessed dynasty, as alone possessing a lawful title, has by no means spent its force. The incidents of the Sacheverell case are alone evidence that the nation had not as yet made up its mind on the question. Mr Lecky¹ is of opinion that the Revolution was brought about by a small minority of men far in advance of the general body of their countrymen. Had Boling- broke been the victim of an idea, and proclaimed the Pretender, as Atterbury wished, there would in all probability have been a peaceful restoration of the Stuarts. On the other hand, the failure of the rebellions of 1715 and 1745 shews how little of practical vitality there was about the Jacobite creed. Yet it may well be, that if a great leader had arisen, he might have brought about a successful reaction. Men may follow a statesman in carrying to a successful issue a cause, for which they will not move a finger in doubtful circumstances. Yet it is something that the belief in hereditary right should have been strong enough to cause the only High Church schism in the history of the English Church. At the Sacheverell trial Divine Right is clearly a popular sentiment. Even as late as 1747 1 History of England, 1. 19. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 173 a pamphleteer is found lamenting its continued prevalence. It must not be forgotten, that the English clergy claimed the phraseology of the Bill of Rights in support of their contention that the Revolution did not transgress the principle of non-resistance. The strength of popular belief in the principle is attested by the very insertion of the word "abdicated” in that document. Again, the fiction of the supposititious birth of the Pretender is a proof of the influence the Whigs felt it necessary to counteract. Further, it was possible by skilful omission for the clergy to continue to preach the duty of passive obedience to the established government. Sacheverell was able to allege in his defence that the Revolution was not a case of resistance¹, and that those who brought it about have grossly lied, if they claim that it was. Many, then, even of the loyal clergy are still found maintaining the doctrine of non-resistance. Of the non-juring controversialists Leslie and Hickes are the most interesting. 1709. Berkeley's Discourse of Passive Obedience is Berkeley, worthy of note as a specimen of the later method of argument. Nothing is said therein of hereditary right, which cannot well be defended by a sup- porter of the Act of Settlement. The argument is that government is natural and necessary to the 1 Speech of Dr Sacheverell, 4: "My Lords, the Resistance in that passage by me condemned is nowhere by me applied to the Revolution, nor is it applicable to the case of the Revolution, the Supreme Power not being then resisted": cf. also Leslie, The Best Answer and The Rehearsal, passim. 174 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES wellbeing of mankind, that obedience is a natural law, that to natural laws there is never any exception. If once hard cases be admitted as a ground for disregarding the rule, it will be as easy to prove the convenience of murder in certain circumstances, as it is to justify resistance to a tyrant. Thus the transformation of method, which Filmer was found beginning and Nalson carrying a little further, was completed by Berkeley¹. He deliberately drops the old mode of argument, because, as he plaintively remarks, men will no longer suffer it. He hopes, however, to prove his case by employing the law of nature to endow with immutable and inviolable authority the principle of passive obedience. At the close of this enquiry may be quoted Bishop Butler, whose speculations on government and subjection shew what was the residuum left by the doctrine of Divine Right. Human society and government are in his view part of the con- stitution and course of nature, and therefore Divine. Obedience is also a part of the law of nature and has therefore Divine sanction. He contends that government, as distinct from mere force, necessarily implies reverence in subjects, and that reverence will be liable to disappear, if it be not founded on the sentiment that authority is the ordinance of God. The duty to obey the prince rests however on the same footing as all other general obligations, which are none of them absolute or without ¹ Berkeley's theory applies to the supreme power in all govern- ments. 2 Butler, Sermons on Special Occasions, III. and v. FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES 175 exception. Butler is clear that the possibility of exceptional cases arising ought to be as little brought to mind as may be. Rather there should be inculcated the duty of Christian subjects to obey not only for wrath, but for conscience' sake. This view, similar to that held by Hooker¹, is a fair specimen of the point of view of the eighteenth- century divine. It is evident that by this time all sense of the original purport of the theory has been lost, and, since its work is done and facts render it impossible of support by any loyal subject, its edge has been taken off. Yet, whittled down to a few harmless truisms, it still remains to stimulate the sense that obedience to law has some sanction higher than mere personal convenience. To sum up out of the sentiment common to all Summary. Christians that subjection to lawful authority is in general a religious duty, since authority is part of the natural and Divine order, the Papacy developed a claim to complete supremacy, as the only Divinely ordained government. This claim was met by a counter-claim to Divine Right on behalf of the Im- perial dignity. In the sixteenth century the doctrine was elaborated with greater rigidity,-the principle of absolute non-resistance seemed necessary to pro- tect secular government from clerical interference. In combination with other causes, this doctrine gave birth to a theory of indefeasible hereditary right, the 1 Hooker, Supposed fragment of a sermon on civil obedience and Ecclesiastical Polity, Book VIII. passim, e.g. “God doth ratify the works of that sovereign authority which kings have received by men." Ch. II. § 7. 176 FROM JAMES I. TO THE JACOBITES prevalence of which was largely due to the fact that both Henry IV. of France and James I. of England obtained their thrones by right of birth alone and without Papal sanction. In the seventeenth century the political side of the doctrine came out most strongly, and it is seen to be the form in which alone could become popular the theory of sovereignty. It further accomplished a work in softening or pre- venting political changes. Its work done, it began to become obsolete at the Revolution, and tended to pass into a mere sentiment. Meanwhile the older method of argument by means of a medley of Scrip- ture texts had given place to the contention, that monarchy and obedience are a part of the natural order and therefore Divine. The basis of the theory was no longer Biblical and theological, but historical and utilitarian. Yet on this basis the ground could not be maintained; and the theory gave way before the doctrine of natural rights of the people pro- pounded by Locke, which is only the Divine Right of Kings in a disguised form. There is however far more weight allowed by Locke, than by Filmer to the principle of utility. This conception may be expected to overshadow and then to supersede the artificial fiction of the original compact and the dream of natural inalienable rights. The doctrine of Divine Right not only was transformed by imperceptible degrees into the theory of natural rights, but it left behind it a legacy, in the sense that government in general is Divine, because it is natural, and that obedience to law is a religious duty. CHAPTER VIII PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE CHURCH OF ENGLAND be con- relation to theories. THE doctrine of the Divine Right of Kings has now been considered in respect of the process of its developement and decay. It remains to regard it Divine statically, so to say, to view it in relation to rival Right to theories of government. It must be remembered sidered in first of all that the import of the phrase "Divine rival Right of Kings" is mainly negative. It implies that there is no foundation for the pretensions advanced by certain other authorities to supremacy by God's especial grant. The notion of Divine Right is in the air; all theories of government are theories of Divine Right, and most of them admit so much¹. The Pope claims by Divine Right, so do the Presby- terians. Even the author of the Vindiciae contends, that since kings hold their crowns by God's grace, they may be judged by the people, as interpreters of the original Divine compact2. Again, most of the English writers on behalf of resistance assert for law and custom a claim to absolute authority by 1 On this point see Leslie's able paper, The Rehearsal, no. 53, Divine Right in Government acknowledged by all. 2 Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, Quaestio 1. passim. F. 12 178 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE All theories of seven- teenth century P are theories of Divine Right. Divine Right. The theory of natural rights is but the theory of Divine Right under a changed guise, a fact of which the writings of Rousseau form the clearest evidence. Algernon Sidney contends that an unjust law ought not to be obeyed, since it cannot bind the conscience and lacks Divine authority¹. This view is one which admits law to be law "simply and strictly so-called," only when it is believed to be in accordance with the Divine will. Sidney's notion, that the sovereignty of the people is inalienable, as being a grant from God, which neither human ordinance nor the people's own consent may alienate, is every whit as much a theory of Divine Right as the views of Mainwaring or Sacheverell. The doctrine under investigation does not differ from contemporary theories of politics in alone claiming Divine Right for the supreme authority, but in claiming that the King is the supreme authority. All the theories alike are at variance with modern political philo- sophy, for they all assert or imply a claim to Divine Right. In this respect, they differ from the thought of to-day, but agree among themselves. If the Divine Right of Kings be, as is so often asserted, the stupidest of all theories of politics, it cannot be because it seeks to find a Divine authority for government. We have no right to condemn it beyond other theories for a notion, which they all hold in common. The point to consider is, how far it was a specially stupid theory of politics, as com- pared with other views prevalent in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. 1 Discourses on Government, III. § 11. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 179 discussed. It will be convenient first of all to examine the Religious side of the theory in relation to those doctrines which most theory will directly controvert it and assert a Divine Right for be here some ecclesiastical authority. In this chapter the religious aspect of the theory will be the main element considered. Afterwards it will be examined on its political side, and its relations to other views of politics investigated. origin. From the foregoing investigation it must have Its anti- appeared sufficiently that the theory arose out of the papal reaction against the Papal pretensions. It was the need of a controversial method to meet the claims of the spiritual power, which produced the doctrine of the Divine Right of Kings. This has been shewn to be the case in the Empire, in France, and in England. If further evidence be required, it is only necessary to take up at random any tract or pamphlet on behalf of royal rights written during the seventeenth century. In all probability the name of either the Pope or Bellarmine will be prominent on the first page. The royalist authors have the Pope on the brain. Whoever be their immediate antagonist, the Pope is always in the background, and it is against him that the long struggle is waged. Preachers on Jan. 30th assert that the martyrdom of Charles was really the work of the Jesuits, or they open their sermons with an elaborate proof not that resistance is a sin, but that Papal interference is against the laws and liberties of this realm of England'. Filmer was perhaps less 1 In a sermon preached before the King on January 30, 168, Dr Turner's first thought is of the Pope and of the advantage to 12-2 180 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE Dissenters with Jesuits. anti-papal in sentiment than most of the supporters of the theory. Yet his Patriarcha opens with an attack on Bellarmine. Hobbes was the one great writer of the time, whose thought was not domi- nated by the notion of Divine Right. Yet Hobbes devotes a whole book of The Leviathan to the consideration of The Kingdom of Darkness, or the Roman Church. Besides, the commonest term for a Identifica- Dissenter is Jesuit. This is used with a definite tion of intention and is not merely vague vituperation. The Jesuits are regarded as par excellence the teachers of the doctrine of resistance. All the special tenets of the Society go for nothing beside this one striking fact, that its members deliberately weaken the bonds of allegiance and argue that under certain conditions a nation may resist and even depose its sovereign. Now the Dissenters teach the same doctrine, and therefore they may without injustice be dubbed Jesuits in disguise. It is not possible to read the numerous pamphlets and sermons, in which this view is set forth, without seeing that the royalist writers were sincere and believed themselves to have made an important discovery, as to the true nature of Dissent. Rome would for its own ends permit subjects to resist. Dissenters would for the good of the Commonwealth permit the same. Therefore Dissenters are in reality Romanists, and only play at Protestantism. The dominant feeling is that the supreme heresy of the Roman Church was the claim Rome of the execution of Charles. "Is the greatest misgovern- ment sufficient pretence for any Pope or consistory on earth to depose a Sovereign Power?" (23.) CHURCH OF ENGLAND 181 put forth on behalf of the Papacy to a political supremacy over all kings and princes. The sense of this dwarfs everything else, and all the other de- fects of the Roman system are viewed as nothing in comparison with the cardinal iniquity of the Papal sovereignty. Every sect, which in any way approaches to the claim of Rome to limit the "true law of free monarchies," is thus regarded as consciously or un- consciously Roman in its tenets. It is impossible to deny that intense hatred of the Pope and the Jesuits, as his chief supporters, was the animating motive of the upholders of the Divine Right of Kings. Yet the hatred, be it observed, is rather political than religious. Comparatively little is said Jesuits are of the erroneous doctrines or corrupt practices of the attacked Roman communion. Here is not the place for such cal rather discussion. What is attacked is the Papacy as a religious political authority, claiming universal Empire, and grounds. dissolving the bonds of national allegiance. A burning and fanatic hatred of the Society of Jesus is another note of all these writings. Yet here again it is not as the servants of a system destructive of morality or inimical to truth, that the Jesuits have won for themselves their monumental meed of execration. This is not the ground of their evil name. That comes of their ardent support of the Papal claims. It is not as believers in Roman Catholic doctrine¹, on politi- than 1 For Bellarmine's theory of the indirect political supremacy of the Pope see De Romano Pontifice, L. v. especially cc. 4, 6; also his contemptuous brushing aside as irrelevant of Barclay's refutation of the theory of the canonists in De Excusatione Bar- claii, cc. 1, 2. 182 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE but as Papalists, that they are attacked. The Jesuits, above all others, have devoted their energies to an elaborate defence of the Pope's position. Whether, as the canonists claim, his political power be direct, or, as Bellarmine argues, it be merely indirect, certain it is that far the weightiest argu- ments in his favour are those of Jesuit writers¹. Others, who think themselves loyal enough to the Pope, may reason and refine away his political power, and argue in favour of the oath of allegiance. But of all this the Jesuits will have nothing. They assert on behalf of the Pope pretensions, which would have shamed neither Boniface VIII. nor John XXII., and they met their reward. This is the head and front of their offending; and it is for this cause that they have won for themselves a name among Englishmen, which those who hate them most nowa- days would least of all be able to interpret. It may well be that the shouts of applause, with which a present day audience at Exeter Hall would greet an attack on the iniquities of Ignatius Loyola, are a tribute unconsciously, but none the less really paid to the Divine Right of Kings. And, when the members of the Protestant Alliance or the Church Association devote a field-day to the exposition of the evils and dishonesty of Jesuitry, they are, Ging ¹ Besides Bellarmine, there stand out more particularly Mariana, who approves of tyrannicide in general and of the murder of Henry III. of France (De Rege et Regis Institutione, 1. 6) and decides against the power of the prince to legislate in matters of religion (Ibid. 10); and Suarez, De Legibus, L. III., De Lege Positiva, cc. 7, 34, and L. IV. De Lege Canonica, especially cc. 9, 19. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 183 though they think it not, uniting with Andrews and Bramhall, with Taylor and Jackson in repel- ling an assault, which is dangerous to the State rather than to the Church, and are exhibiting a relic of that patriotic indignation, which, in days when the political claims of Rome were real and formidable, had a meaning and a value. Anyhow, in the seven- teenth century there is little evidence that the Jesuits in England are attacked, because their system is disliked or their teaching believed to be immoral. The polemic against the conquering Society is not the lofty indignation of a Pascal, denouncing a casuistry which is debasing the moral standard and destroying all principles of right action. The spirit of the English royalists is as far inferior to that which breathes through every page of the Provinciales, as is the form in which it is embodied. But if the irony of the believer in Divine Right be lacking in the polish of the "letters," his declamation at least surpasses them in the blind force of passion. The English hatred of the Jesuits is the narrow, but fervent enthusiasm of patriots disgusted at claims which fetter the free action of the nation, and enraged with those who presume to justify such claims with the pen or to put them into practice with the sword. The Jesuits are villains-that the royal- ists believe. But the cause is not that they believe or teach false dogmas in theology, not that they are paving the way for moral scepticism, nor that they (in general) urge and permit immoral actions, but merely that they are traitors guilty of high treason against the sovereignty of nations, seeking to wrest 184 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE Teaching of resist- ance regarded as main element in Popery and Dissent. the diadem from the imperial crown of England, that they may place it on the brows of a priest: Le clericalisme c'est l'ennemi is the governing thought of those who cry for Jus Divinum and Non-resistance. As was said, it is this sense, that the essence of Popery is a claim to political supremacy, that is the cause of the numerous accusations for holding Jesuit or Papist views, that are levelled against the Dis- senters. Filmer tells us that "the main and indeed the only point of Popery is the alienating and with- drawing of subjects from their obedience to their Prince¹." It is not, then, surprising that Hickes is of opinion that "Popery having apparently corrupted the Gospel in the doctrines of obedience, and submission, and the divine authority of the supreme power, especially of Kings; they cannot be sound and ortho- dox Protestants, who hold the very same destructive principles to regal government, by which the Papists have corrupted the Gospel in these points. No they are not sound, and orthodox Protestants, but Pro- testants popularly affected, Papists under a Protes- tant dress, wolves in sheeps' clothing, rebellious and Satanical spirits transformed into angels of light"." To this well-known passage quotations similar in spirit might be multiplied a thousand-fold³. The 1 Preface to The Anarchy of a Mixed Monarchy. 2 Hickes, Sermon on Jan. 30, 168. Another sermon describes Jesuits as Rome's Fifth Monarchy Men; Mr Gardiner's account of the Fifth Monarchy is a proof of the appositeness of this descrip- tion (History of the Commonwealth and Protectorate, 1. 32). 3 We have one pamphlet directed against The Six Popish Pillars, Anabaptists, Quakers, Presbyterians, etc. (1690). Jewell writes, "Why hath he [the Pope] and his complices (like Anabaptists CHURCH OF ENGLAND 185 reiterated charge that Dissenters are all Jesuits at heart is only to be explained upon this view of what was really the mind of the Anglican divines. The term is not employed merely as an opprobrious epithet. It is the expression of a deep sense, that since the real object of Jesuitism is to loose the bonds of civil allegiance, all who hold doctrines of resistance are believers in the only essential and The distinctive doctrines of Loyola and Rome¹. purely theological points on which Dissenters differ even more widely than Anglicans from the Roman Church may be ignored as mere details, which do not concern the main position. Noncon- Rome resistance. But here a distinction must be made. The theory Some of most English Nonconformists and of the average formists Whig politician, is open to the taunts of the royalist agree with on the score of its likeness to the Jesuit doctrine only in of resistance. If resistance in any form for any cause allowing be damnable, and if it be Popery to teach it, then Whigs like Locke and Sidney, and Parliamentarians like Prynne may be accused of Popery. It is true that religion is one of the main grounds for re- sistance in practice, but at least neither Whigs nor Independents believe that the state is to be and Libertines, to the end they might run on the more licentiously and carelessly), shaken off the yokes, and exempted themselves from being under all civil power?" (Apology, 75). In The Apostate Parliament occurs the query, "Setting aside the Romish faith and the vow of blind obedience, tell me wherein these men differ from the disciples of Ignatius Loyola? Why only these are Popish and they Protestant Jesuits?" See Appendix C. 1 On the political theory of the Jesuits cf. From Gerson to Grotius, Chap. v. 186 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE Presby- terianism advances claims similar to those of Rome. controlled in the interests of a religious body. They would not fetter its action, as the Papalist would do. Indeed, as the notion of toleration begins to develope, any general theory of clerical supremacy becomes an impossibility. That men view the mere teach- ing of resistance as evidence of Popery is indicative of a state of feeling, difficult for us to bring into imagination, when non-resistance is regarded as the most essential element of religion. S But in regard to one ecclesiastical system other than the Roman, the taunt of Jesuitism is more truly justified. Presbyterianism, as exhibited in Geneva or Scotland, veritably claims, as did the Papacy, to control the state in the interests of an ecclesiastical corporation. The cardinal error of the royalist writers, when viewed from the modern standpoint, is that in formulating the theory of the Divine Right of Kings against that of the Pope, they were driven into the position of supporters of despotism and oppression. However much this is to be condemned, it was probably inevitable. Cer- tainly it may seem to us a strange thing that in defending the secular power against the spiritual, men should ignore or minimize the dangers of the secular power itself becoming a tyranny. But it is not strange, that those who were inspired by a pas- sionate indignation at the preposterous assumptions of the Papacy, should have been no less hostile to the political side of the Presbyterian system. "New presbyter is but old priest writ large" is a maxim of deeper import than is sometimes imagined. It is the felicitous expression of men's sense of CHURCH OF ENGLAND 187 the danger still to be apprehended from clericalism. A theory of cleri- The same mischievous claims to place secular calism in governments under the heel of an ecclesiastical politics. organization, as had led to so much conflict in the Middle Ages and were only finally overthrown by the Reformation, had reappeared in a yet more irritating form in the Presbyterian system. The con- dition of Geneva under Calvin was an object-lesson, which neither statesmen nor patriotic churchmen were likely to ignore. Affairs in Scotland would form a sufficient warning, if any should be tempted to fall out of the frying-pan into the fire, and after throwing off one ecclesiastical tyranny to rivet upon their necks another, which would differ from it mainly in being narrower, more searching, more inquisitorial, more ubiquitous, and less careful of the larger needs and hopes of humanity, less likely to force upon states and their rulers the sense that sectional and local interests are not the only rule of right. The Papacy, whatever might be said against it, was at least a standing witness to the need of international morality, and might be sup- posed to have the advantage of viewing political problems from a universal standpoint. Despite the evils and mischief attendant on the political claims of the Popes, it might be contended with some plausibility that these claims were the only se- curity the medieval world possessed for something like justice and fair-dealing between kings and princes. The fear of Papal excommunication un- doubtedly tended to confine aggression within limits and to make rulers temper expediency with right 188 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE reason. No such defence could be made for the Presbyterian system. It would have controlled the action of the state more completely than did the Papacy, while it would have strengthened, instead of diminishing all the tendencies that made for a narrow patriotism, and that would lead men to regard local and provincial feeling as all-important. The posi- tion of the Papacy could not fail to lift it in a great degree above the limitations, that must surround and sometimes fetter the thought and action of the national statesman. But there was no such cause at work in the Presbyterian system, and its rulers would, so far as politics were concerned, have exhibited most of the defects, without any of the merits of clericalism. Unless it be contended that their possession of a purer system of theology would ensure the wisdom of their political action, it can hardly be doubted that the Presbyterian system, if allowed to run its course, would have made greater havoc of politics, than did the Papacy. It would have subordinated all state action to consider- ations at once narrowly local and rigidly ecclesiastical. Thus it is not surprising that the ablest defenders of the doctrine of Divine Right are at pains to shew not merely that the Papal claims would dissolve the bonds of civil society, but that they go on, as does Nalson, to prove that the 'Presbyterian Discipline' is equally destructive not merely of royal power, but of Parliamentary authority and the liberty of the subject'. The two systems of Papal S 1 "There may be many particular interests which may be disadvantageous to the safety, security and happiness of the CHURCH OF ENGLAND 189 supremacy and Presbyterian 'discipline' are both clerical in essence. They both assert a claim by Divine Right for God's minister, whether he be the Pope or the office-bearers in the Presbyterian body; this claim is to be superior to all civil government whatever. Bishop Bramhall's tract A warning to the Church of England is an able exposition of this view. In this is shewn the political danger of Presbyterianism, as an ecclesiastical system claiming dominion by Divine Right over the secular power. The latter part of Nalson's Common Interest of King and People is a singularly lucid and well-balanced statement of the same position. theory. Nor do these writers attribute to the Presby- Illustra- terians any pretensions which they do not make for tions of Presby- themselves. Cartwright's works are almost as full terian as those of Bellarmine of the claim to control the Cart- State in the interests of the Church; in many wright. respects they form an exact parallel to Papalist pretensions. The magistrate is the Lord's officer, and must wield the sword as the Church directs, persecute all'idolatry' at its bidding, and grant no Imperial Crown of this Realm of Great Britain, and its other dominions, as well as to the liberty and property of the People; but there are two which are directly and fundamentally opposite and contrary to them, both in their principles and practices, and these are the pretensions of a universal supremacy and spirituo- temporal monarchy of the Church of Rome or Papacy on the one hand, and the Democratic Presbyterian on the other. That both these are utterly inconsistent with the safety and very essence of monarchy and particularly with that of these nations, as also with the peace, happiness, liberty and property of the subjects is that which I hope to prove" (Nalson, The Common Interest of King and People, 173). 190 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE ļ pardon upon the recantation of a heretic. He is to be guided by the example of Constantine the Great, who persecuted in favour of orthodoxy¹. The 'discipline' is universal and immutable2 and is to be maintained by the magistrate; the civil magistrate is to provide some sharp punishment for all who contemn the censure of the Church. In fact the State is to wield the temporal sword, and the Church to dictate how it shall be wielded. The civil magis- trates as they are the nurses, so they are the servants of the Church and must throw down their crowns before it. Since the Church is prior to the State, the constitution of the latter must be fashioned and made suitable unto the Church. Church government is to be the model of the civil State. Cartwright knows that the 'discipline' is regarded in the light of a new popedom and tyranny in the Church; but so to term it is blasphemy". The author's views are as definitely theocratic, as those of the mediaval Papacy. He is not merely using phrases to emphasize the spiritual subjection of the prince, as a layman, to the officers of the Church; but he teaches that the prince is merely the minister and executant of the Church's decrees. Finally, his object being to move the people to obedience, he shews no sort of in- clination to popular government or liberty as such. The only liberty he desires is the liberty of the JAG 1 Cartwright, Second Reply, cxv. sqq. 2 Declaration of Discipline, 13. 4 Second Admonition to Parliament, 49. • Reply to Whitgift, 144. 7 Demonstration of Discipline, 75. 3 Ibid. 187. 6 Ibid. i CHURCH OF ENGLAND 191 office-bearers of the Church to control the action of the State and to use its forces at their will. The duty of private individuals is merely that of obedience¹. Still stronger are the views of Christopher Goodman. Goodman. His book How to obey or disobey was written in 1558 against the tyranny of the 'idol- atress' Mary, and the monstrous regiment of women, although there is flattery of Elizabeth, "that godly lady and meek lamb void of all Spanish pride and stranger blood." Goodman will have nothing of pas- sive obedience²; idolatry must be resisted by force³. Like the Papalists, Goodman conceives of God as the true recipient of civil obedience, and of all earthly governments as subordinate to His rule, and liable to be overturned at any moment, if they transgress it¹. Of the nature of God's ordinances and of the question as to whether or no they have been transgressed, he would apparently make the rulers of the Church the sole and irresponsible arbiters. For princes are not to suffer their subjects to be ignorant of God's law, but to enforce theological doctrine universally". On this condition obedience is to be paid to the magis- trate and no tyranny will absolve from the dutyº. As in the view of Cartwright or Bellarmine, the subject's duty is mere obedience, but obedience to an ecclesiastical corporation; only secondarily and under qualifications, will obedience to the civil * 1 Declaration of Discipline, 185. The passage is quoted below, p. 222. 3 Ibid. 77. 2 How to obey, 30, 64. 4 Ibid. 44 sqq., 60, 110, 118, 139. 5 Ibid. 105. • Ibid. 110. 192 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE magistrate become a duty. The State exists solely on sufferance; and the officers of the Church may meddle with its policy and upset its organization at their pleasure. For no heretic is truly a king; not the clearest legal right, neither election nor succes- sion, can give any title to a claimant unless in the opinion of this self-constituted authority, he "be a promoter and setter forth of God's glory." The contention that neither prince nor people are free, but both are subject to God's law might indeed be used to-day in an innocent sense; but, as in the case of all teachers of the political supremacy of ecclesiasticism, in Goodman's mouth the words imply a claim on the part of an irresponsible person or body of persons, not experts in politics, to control the action of the State, in whatever direction they please. The King is to persecute and the people to rebel at the bidding of the Kirk². There is no appeal from their decision as to the character of the policy that will promote God's glory or will hinder it. How far these claims would have been carried, if men such as Goodman had been given a free hand, may be gathered from some hints which he lets drop. One of the reasons for resisting Mary is her foreign policy; since it is plainly forbidden by God's word to make war in alliance with Spain 1 How to obey, 51, 58. Goodman's contention is that an idolatrous and persecuting king is to be regarded as a mere private man, to whom no obedience is due (139). This is on a par with Bellarmine's view that the Pope does not command subjects to disobey their sovereigns, for the Papal deposition ipso facto destroys the kingly character. 2 Ibid. Chap. xI. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 193 I 7 against France and "their own brethren the Scots," all Englishmen are bidden to throw off the yoke¹. Nor does Goodman stop here, but devotes many pages to a glorification of Sir Thomas Wyatt, and the praise of his rebellion². Here, then, in the writings of Cartwright and Goodman we have clear proof that the political claims of Presbyterianism were as oppressive, as tyrannical and as preposterous as those of Rome. The two systems, Papal and Presbyterian, are alike in that they both regard the State as the mere handmaid of an ecclesiastical corporation, and would, in the last resort, place the supreme direction of politics in the hands of the rulers of the Church. They differ only in the character of the theological systems, in the interests of which the policy of the secular government is to be regulated. The history of Scotland affords further evidence of the claims made and exercised under this system. And those who had most to do with the establishment of the Presbyterian Kirk in Scotland are most emphatic in their announcement of their pretensions to subject the policy of the State to their own caprice. John Knox. Knox declares that no idolater (by which is meant a person whose theological views differ from his own) ought to be promoted to any public office; that no oath can bind men to obey such an one; and that any prince, who after appointment becomes an idolater, may be justly opposed³. In the First Book 2 204 sqq. 1 How to obey, 173. 8 Summary of the proposed Second Blast of the Trumpet. Works, Iv. 539. F 13 194 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE of Dis- cipline. First Book of Discipline it is declared that rulers and ruled must all alike be subject to discipline¹, and that idolatry and all monuments thereof must be suppressed'; that punishment (death for choice) should be appointed for all such as disobeyed the superintendents, and for profaners of the Sacraments³. Now when these are regarded as directions from the Kirk to the State in order to guide its legislation, it will readily be seen how great is the power claimed. In subjecting all rulers to 'discipline,' a civil supremacy is in reality claimed for the Kirk; for excommunication carried with it civil disabilities; it was immediately followed by "letters of horning. "" Second Book of 1581. The Second Book of Discipline claims for the Discipline, spiritual power an indirect temporal supremacy, very similar to that claimed by Bellarmine for the Pope. The method of argument is not very different in the two cases. The magistrate commands ex- ternal things for external peace and quietness among his subjects; the minister handles external things only for conscience' sake. The magistrate is to command the minister to observe the rule com- manded in the world, and to punish the transgressors by civil means. The ministers exercise not the civil jurisdiction, but teach the magistrate how it should be exercised according to the word. Eccle- siastical power is distinguished from civil by the fact that it flows immediately from God. - 3 Ibid. p. 253. • Second Book of Discipline, 1. 11. Calderwood (111. 529 sqq.). 5 Ibid. 14. 6 Ibid. 5. d) 1 VII. 3. The First Book of Discipline is to be found in the Works of John Knox, 11. 183 sqq. 2 Ibid. III. m CHURCH OF ENGLAND 195 All this may seem little more than a declaration of the freedom of the Kirk, and of the divergent spheres of Church and State. It might be so in an age when all religious opinions are tolerated. But at a time when persecution was recognized as a duty, it amounts to a claim on behalf of the Kirk for complete supremacy. The civil magistrate is bound to suppress all teaching not recognized by the Kirk, to enforce its commands, to see to the execution of its views as to the administration of God's Word and Sacraments-all this, according to the theory of Knox and his successors, on pain of deposition. The Kirk is to be the nation in its spiritual capacity, yet over this vast body the State is to have no authority, but is merely in the position of an execu- tive appointed to execute the will of the office- bearers. If the Prince will not obey the officers of the Kirk, and employ all the machinery of govern- ment to execute their decrees, he is to be deposed. We are told that the magistrate is to assist and maintain and justify the jurisdiction of the Kirk. There is no qualification. The ministers, on the other hand, are to assist the Prince in all things agreeable to God's word¹. Thus to the ministers is left the final interpretation of the limits of obedience, and the magi- strate becomes the mere tenant-at-will of the Kirk. Further, in the Second Book of Discipline the magistrate is bidden to fortify the godly proceedings of the Kirk; to see that its public estate and ministers be maintained, and so to secure the Church against false teachers and hirelings, dumb dogs and 1 Second Book of Discipline, 1. 15. 2 Ibid. x. 2. 13-2 196 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE idle bellies¹; to punish civilly those that will not obey the censure of the Kirk, "without confounding always the one jurisdiction with the other?," i.e. maintaining his allotted position of subserviency. He is to make laws for the advancement of the Kirk without usurp- ing anything that pertains not to the civil sword³. These constitutions in fact invest the Kirk with the absolute freedom and right of establishing its constitution and discipline in matters small and great and then of employing the secular arm to enforce them on a reluctant nation. For where the ministry of the Kirk is once lawfully constituted, all godly princes ought to obey the voice and reverence the majesty of the Son of God. The Book proceeds to quote from the statute declaring that no other ecclesiastical jurisdiction should be acknowledged, but that which is and shall be in the Reformed Kirk and flowing therefrom". The belief in persecu- tion is It is this that constitutes the real objection from the statesman's point of view to the Presbyterian system, and the justification of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings and of much that seems the conflict arbitrary in the treatment of religious bodies the real cause of 1 Second Book of Discipline, x. 3. 2 Ibid. 4. 3 Ibid. 7. 4 A power in the Prince of reforming the Church when cor- rupted is indeed admitted (Ibid. 7), but this is merely a saving clause by which a Revolution in favour of Presbyterianism may be admitted. Knox in attacking the Roman Church where estab- lished asserts emphatically the claims of the civil magistrate (Letter to the Queen Regent, Works, Iv. 443). Like the Pope, he will admit the power of the civil magistrate, on condition of its being exercised in subserviency to himself. • Second Book of Discipline, xx. 16. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 197 : } Church by the State. The acts of Henry VIII. and between Elizabeth may appear harsh, and the submissio and State. cleri may be regarded as depriving the Church of its due rights. Yet no less could have been claimed at the time by any self-respecting monarch. For at that time toleration was not recognized as a principle, and it was a maxim that the nation. in its spiritual capacity forms one corporation, subject to one ecclesiastical jurisdiction and one system of discipline. Under such conditions it can never be other than dangerous for the State to give the spiritual power a free hand. For it will fetter the action of the State in a thousand ways and will be repeatedly claiming to "handle external things for conscience' sake." It may, as in Scotland, set up an inquisitorial jurisdiction in every village, and demand the assistance of the State in punishing any and every breach of what it regards as the moral law, from adultery to Sabbath-breaking. It may claim, as in Scotland, that the royal pardon shall never issue for capital crimes; it may demand, as in 1582, that no alliances shall be made with Roman Catholic powers¹. The Papacy in the middle ages claimed to regulate international differences, and was constantly encroaching upon the sphere of the State. But hardly at the period of its proudest exaltation did it claim to make the civil power so 1 Calderwood, III. 685. The General Assembly demanded that "no society, league or friendship be made with Papists in France, Italy, Spain, or other countries, by common or particular outset." The whole tenor of the articles presented at this time to the King is expressive of the determination of the Kirk to unfettered supremacy. 198 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE completely its slave or to interfere so minutely with the private life of individuals, as did the maintainers of "the discipline." However, opinions may differ as to which of the two systems was the more meddlesome and irritating tyranny. But there can be no doubt that, with whatever differences in degree, both are alike in kind. Each puts forward a claim by Divine Right to subject the secular power to the spiritual, to make the clergy the ultimate arbiters of political action. The claim of clerical- missible. And the claim cannot be admitted. The English ism inad nation had ever been jealous of clericalism. It had refused to surrender the right and liberty of the English Crown to the Popes, and had upheld its independence in matters of politics, unawed by the majestic traditions and splendid imperiousness of the mediæval Papacy-this at a time, when the spiritual authority of the Pope was unquestioned. England had in the past no quarrel with the religious pretensions of the Papacy; but she was no more inclined, than the French King or the Emperor, to admit its political claims. It was not likely that she would allow a similar claim, presented in the less lovely form of the Presbyterian discipline. In the Presbyterian doctrines, as developed by Melville in Scotland and Cartwright in England, there was however one distinction recognized, which went far to minimize its dangers. These writers all held the doctrine of the two kingdoms, and did not make the mistake common to all parties in the middle ages, and repeated by men so different as Laud and Luther. That error lay in treating Church and State as merely • 3070035 Jes LUK margfa ¿ CHURCH OF ENGLAND 199 different departments of the one great society, and with this view either an ecclesiastical or a civil tyranny is almost inevitable. Knox held the older view. In the same way the doctrine of the indirect power of the Papacy, as developed by Bellarmine, leaves it possible at least in theory to admit the freedom and inherent rights of the civil State¹. macy. Against either claim the same controversial The State can only method was necessary. It was needful to claim on meet its behalf of the secular power complete supremacy and opponents by claim- the institution of God. Not until the danger was ing entire past of a relapse into Popery or Presbyterianism, supre- can the notion of Divine Right be said to have accomplished its work. The case of France is precisely similar. On the one hand, the Papacy claimed to excommunicate and depose the King, and to keep the rightful heir out of his inheritance. On the other hand, the Huguenots made themselves the mouthpiece of a recrudescent feudalism, and strove for an imperium in imperio with quasi- sovereign rights in their strong places. In the result both in France and England, the central power succeeded in establishing its supremacy, even to the point of persecuting the teachers of all doctrines which it regarded as harmful. power has the The passages cited as evidence of the Presby- The terian theory may seem patient of a different inter- spiritual pretation. They may be defended as mere humble never advice to the State from persons acting with purely material spiritual weapons and claiming no coercive authority. sword John Knox himself could not wield the sword, but disposal. 1 Cf. Appendix III. at its 200 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE : was only able to advise subjects in certain cir- cumstances to depose their prince. The Kirk neither possesses nor claims the use of the material sword. It merely demands that it shall be used in its interests. Precisely. Yet the position of the Papacy in regard to European nations was at no time different. Save in the Papal states, the Pope had no direct material power. The army under the immediate command of the Pope or his delegates would scarcely have been sufficient to crush the smallest of recalcitrant sects, and could have made no head against a hostile nation. When the medieval Papacy is called a tyranny, it is too often forgotten that how- ever mischievous its effects on political action, it was emphatically an instance of government by consent. Whether or no the Popes from Gregory VII. to Boniface VIII. wielded an authority that was both despotic in its nature and oppressive in its incidence, it is certain that their despotism did not rest upon physical force, but upon purely spiritual or moral sanctions. The Papacy never as a matter of practice wielded or claimed to wield the material sword. It merely demanded that physical force should never be employed, save with its approval. Presbyterianism made precisely the same demand. All that the Pope can do by a bull of excom- munication is to declare, as God's vicar, that men are no longer bound in theory and for conscience' withhold sake to obey their sovereign. They may not im- probably be bound to obey him in practice and by the strength of the material sword. The English Catholics, or those of them who favoured the The spiritual power can only grant or the moral sanctions of govern- ment. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 201 I with claim that the moral is on their deposing power, were so bound; they were "subject for wrath." But, admitting the Pope's claims, no one will be bound for conscience' sake, so soon as he has launched a bull of excommunication. The And so object, therefore, of the opponents of either system Presby- must be to assert, that, despite the Papal or terianism. Presbyterian attempt to exercise the deposing power, Hence the sanctions of conscience still remain, and that supporters of the the moral claim of the State to the allegiance of its State must subjects may not be impaired by ecclesiastical censure. Throughout the Middle Ages, in the Wars sanction of the League, in the plots against Elizabeth, it has side. been repeatedly proved that the character of men's civil obedience will be affected by other motives. than the material sword or the legal sanction of government, "wrath." The success, however partial, of the Popes or of the Presbyterian leaders has proved that the moral sanction, conscience, is a real power in strengthening or loosening the bonds of allegiance. This sanction the supporters of clerical- ism claim to manipulate at their pleasure. The defenders of the freedom of the State are therefore perpetually driven to assert, that it is not lost or gained according to the theological opinions of the ruler, that the State has a Divine Right to exist despite the disapproval of the Church, that obedience to the secular power is due not merely for "wrath but for conscience' sake." Obedience not merely for wrath, but for conscience' sake has been asserted to be the right of the Church alone. The moral claim to obedience, as distinct from the physical power of enforcing it, does not in itself belong to the State, Gay 202 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE say the supporters of clericalism, save in so far as the State is the necessary instrument of the Church. The theory of the Divine Right of Kings is the contradiction of this; it asserts that the State has a claim to obedience on moral and religious grounds, that it has a right to exist as in accordance with human nature and God's will, and is based on some- thing better than the right of the stronger. Cleri- calism makes capital out of its position as the guide of men's consciences, and would subject states and politics to a meddlesome control. Hence, if political security is to be obtained, conscience must be as- serted to be on the side of civil obedience, and universal supremacy by God's grant asserted for the State. Otherwise ecclesiastics will at once step in and claim to decide the cases in which resistance may be lawful. The State Yet in doing this the State makes large claims. asserts its It first asserts its absolute competence to prescribe authority in matters forms of religious belief or at least of practice, and of reli- gion. to set up or abolish forms of ecclesiastical organi- zation. It is only when the State consents to be guided in this matter by experts, i.e. the Church, that any religious body will allow such a claim in its fulness. Yet the omni-competence of the State had to be asserted, and asserted as of Divine Right. It would doubtless be supported in the main only by those who feel morally convinced that the State will not as a matter of fact prohibit their own religious belief. Ja Erastian language This is in part the explanation of the Erastian of certain language of certain Caroline divines. They exalt CHURCH OF ENGLAND 203 * ! -- the supremacy of the Crown; they declare its com- supporters of Divine petence to prescribe forms of faith; and claim Divine Right. Right for these powers. By this is merely meant a claim of the secular power to be free in theory; there is not intended or implied any claim that the State in practice shall decide religious matters arbitrarily or without consulting the heads of the Church. Doubtless much of Barrow's Treatise of the Pope's Supremacy or Jackson's Treatise of Christian Obedi- ence is Erastian in tone. Yet in reality what they were aiming at was the legal omnipotence of the sovereign power. An exponent of the same view at the present day might well take as an illustration of the theoretical powers of Parliament the undoubted fact that at any moment it might legally abolish the Christian religion and introduce Mohammedanism under the sanction of torture. Yet such a writer would not be held to mean that Parliament could effect this change, or that it would dream of attempt- ing it. Such an act would overpass what have been called the external and the internal limits of sovereignty¹. Similarly in the seventeenth century, against the clericalism of Rome or of Geneva the omni-competence of the State was asserted. Against the claim of Pope or Presbyter to obedience by Divine Right the Divine Right of Kings must be elaborated. Against the claims to dissolve the bonds of sentiment or conscience between governors and governed, conscience must be claimed for the secular government by the theory of non-resistance, and diffi- cult cases solved by the doctrine of Passive Obedience. 1 Dicey, Law of the Constitution, 72–78. 204 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE It may seem strange that men such as Laud, with high views of the position of the Church and the power of the priesthood, should have asserted so strongly a theory, which, as frequently expounded, involves the assertion of the authority of the Crown over the forms of Church government and doctrine. But it must be borne in mind that Laud, like Parker and Whitgift, was well aware that the political supre- macy of the State over the Church was too well- established a principle to disappear, nor did he grasp the doctrine of the two societies. It could only change hands. He knew that if this supremacy were not retained by Charles, it would pass over to the Par- liament, and would be wrested into the protection and establishment of Puritanism. Laud was not ignorant that the Church of England "as by law established" had its strongest supporter in Charles. Although the Roman controversy was not over, he must have felt that the danger to England from that side was daily diminishing. The supremacy of the Crown might be extolled to any extent by a Caroline divine. For it was known that, as a matter of fact, so long as it remained in the hands of the King, it would be used to promote the welfare of the Church. It was not needful to demand passionately that the King should maintain the true religion and prohibit false teaching. Nor was it necessary to fetter the royal prerogative in order that the Church might be free. Knox had been driven to both these courses. But in England the King might be trusted to maintain the status quo and to guard against the aggressions of Puritanism. In England the royal authority was La CHURCH OF ENGLAND 205 I ར favourable, in Scotland it was hostile to the dominant religious system. If James VI. ever felt free to throw off the yoke of the Kirk there could be little doubt that he would do so; indeed he made various. attempts to strengthen his authority over it¹. A shrewd suspicion of this disposition must tend to drive the leaders of Presbyterianism into hostility to any doctrine of the nature of the royal supremacy, even irrespective of their previous theory. James would be dangerous to the Kirk. His freedom to touch it must therefore be denied. On the other hand the greater the freedom of Charles I. the better would it be for the Church of England, or at least for the particular view of its character and ritual taken by Laud. From the time of the Elizabethan settlement onward the royal supremacy was the bulwark of the Church of England against Puritan innovations. Thus the taunt is not justified, that the theory Unprin- cipled of the Divine Right of Kings was merely the fiction servility of a time-serving hierarchy, intent upon gaining cannot fairly be court favour, whatever might happen to the Church. attributed For the belief in this theory was the most trust- to the Anglican worthy security for the permanence and stability of clergy. that order of things which the clergy had learnt to love. They were not serving their King instead of their God; the best defence of the Church was the support of the Crown. Nor is it a cause for blame to the clergy that the theory of Divine Right found in them its strongest and most numerous body of supporters. The theory is, as has been shewn, 1 Gardiner's History of England, passim. 206 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE essentially anti-clerical. Yet for this reason it was necessary, if it were to be effective, that the doctrine should be in the main formulated by a body of clergy. The claims of a system of clericalism, such as the Papal or Presbyterian, might indeed be denied by laymen; but they could not be effectively refuted save by clergy. The element of truth in the Papal claim made it essential that it should be met by clergy rather than laymen. For Bellarmine and Knox were right in asserting that only the spiritual power can give the authoritative decision as to whether men were bound in conscience to obey their rulers. The question as one of conscience must be decided by the spiritual authority. It was not in claiming for a religious body the decision of the moral and religious question, whether or no obedience is due to the State on religious and moral grounds, that the Jesuits erred. Where they were mistaken was in asserting that the secular power as such had no moral claim to obedience apart from the theological accuracy of the opinions which it enforced. The assertion that obedience is a religious duty in all states, irrespective of the opinions of the ruler, was not merely the sole method of rendering politics free from ecclesiasticism; it could only be made effectively by a body of men representing the spiritual authority. None but the clergy could meet the Pope on his own ground. It was vain to denounce ecclesiasticism in politics, unless the leaders of some religious body asserted that the possession of religious truth was not the one road to political wisdom, and that a national Church might be truly CHURCH OF ENGLAND 207 of God's appointment without making the civil magistrate its vassal. That the doctrine in this country was in an especial degree the product of the Church of England and her divines is undoubted. Yet it was equally the product of the Gallican Church. Indeed the Gallican liberties are one of the chief sources whence the doctrine could be drawn¹. For the ideal of the Divine Right of Kings in matters of theology is an assertion within limits of the rights of a national Church. The Pope had claimed a superiority which rendered nugatory the name of national Church. The Presbyterian system, while asserting national independence of Papal sovereignty, would have yet set up within the nation an organization which would have dwarfed the State and hindered the growth of the nation's life. A Geneva on a great scale would not have been a national Church. Before the Church should have established its position, the nation would have disappeared. Even Independency, which seems to leave the whole matter free, implies a denial of the right of the nation as a whole to an ecclesiastical organization. Had it ever become universal, there could not have been a single religious communion claiming to represent the nation on its spiritual side. If by a national Church be meant a religious The theory body which, representing the whole nation yet belongs to a national Church. 1 See supra chap. vi. The connection between the conceptions of Divine Right and a national Church appears strongly in the collection of treatises made by Pithou, Les Libertez de l'Église Gallicane, 208 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE Signifi- cance of Passive Obedience. leaves its political life free to develope, unaffected by the upas-tree of clericalism, there can be no doubt that the theory of Divine Right was in- separably connected with the ideal of a national Church in the seventeenth century, and that it was necessary to secure its realization in the face of Papal or Presbyterian or Separatist pretensions. For the theory of Divine Right is a religious as well as a political dogma. The stress laid upon the duty of Passive Obedience is a proof of this. Non-resistance, as an element in a utilitarian system of politics, would probably be taught without qualification. Little would be said of Passive Obedience, even though it should not be forbidden. This is actually the case with the Leviathan. But, where absolutist theory is es- sentially religious, it is inevitable that men should consider the cases where disobedience to law is a religious duty. For, when civil obedience is inculcated as a part of God's Law, the case cannot be ignored of the government's endeavouring to persecute the true religion. Under certain condi- tions martyrdom is a recognized duty, and this implies the duty of disobedience to the commands of the Sovereign. Unless the qualification be taken into account, no Christian could proclaim the doctrine of indefeasible hereditary right. Men did not desire the exclusion of James because they expected that he would be a tyrant, but because they knew that he was a Papist. Those who opposed his exclusion were forced to lay stress upon the duty of Anglicans in the possible case of his persecuting their religion. W CHURCH OF ENGLAND 209 The doctrine of Passive Obedience hampered, in more ways than one', the supporters of the Divine Right of Kings. They were taunted with shewing their want of faith in their sovereign, since they were ever considering the chance of his being a heretic and a persecutor. It was declared that no wise upholder of the doctrine of resistance would dream of inculcating the duty of disobedience as a general rule, whereas to judge by their language the supporters of Divine Right regarded the case for passive obedience as one of constant recurrence. Besides passive obedience was little better than active resistance2; and its supporters might be branded as advocates of rebellion. Hobbes wrote that since the Incarnation is the central doctrine ¹ Sanderson, one of the acutest minds who wrote on behalf of Divine Right, is fully aware of the danger, and endeavours to minimize to the utmost the duty of Passive Obedience. In all doubtful cases he declares the responsibility to rest with the magistrate, and active obedience to be due. He allows that, when the conscience is clear as to the iniquity of the magistrate's command, obedience must be withheld, but even here disobedience is sin; and the case is one of the choice between two evils. "In such a case certainly he may not obey the magistrate; yet let him know thus much withal, that he sinneth too in disobeying the magis- trate; from which sin the following of the judgment of his own conscience cannot acquit him. And this is that fearful perplexity, whereof I spake, wherein many a man casteth himself by his own. error and obstinacy, that he can neither go with his conscience nor against it, but he shall sin" (Judgment in One View, 156). 2 Hobbes' Answer to Bramhall, 127. "Passive Obedience signifies nothing except it may be called passive obedience, when a man refraineth himself from doing what the law hath forbidden. For in his lordship's sense the thief that is hanged for stealing hath fulfilled the law, which, I think, is absurd." See also De Corpore Politico, chap. vi. F. 14 210 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE of the Christian faith, the prohibition of that belief and that alone can justify men in refusing to obey the laws¹. No case of the persecution of one Christian body by another can exempt men from the normal duty of active obedience. Further, it might be said, that even in the last resort the case was not clear, for the Apostles, who declared that God must be obeyed rather than man, were eye-witnesses of the Resurrection; their case was therefore peculiar. Moreover, Elisha had bidden Naaman go in peace, when he talked of bowing himself in the House of Rimmon. Taunts of this sort could easily be levelled at the believers in Passive Obedience. That there was, indeed, some justification for these taunts, is shewn by the so- phistical quibble with which the doctrine is wrested to cover the case of the Revolution and of the acquiescence of the clergy in William's reign. The doctrine of passive obedience could not have loomed so large save to men for whom politics was a branch of theology. The cause of its playing so great a part in the doctrine of Divine Right is that the latter is bound up with the defence of the Church of England against its foes. At this time, indeed, all theories of politics either have a religious basis or are framed with the practical object of defending the true faith. Politics and theology are as yet intimately connected. And, though in the writ- ings of Locke and Sidney we see politics seeking to free themselves from their theological vesture, it 1 Leviathan, II. 43; the passage is quoted in Appendix III. 2 Behemoth, 86. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 211 use the for was purpose for which it existed. was is not yet cast away. When the theory of Divine Right is thus seen to be connected with the existence of the Church of England and with its position as a Church, at once anti-papal and anti-presbyterian, we shall surely see some justification of the action of the clergy in 1688. The theory of the Divine Right James II. of Kings is framed for the defence of the nation tried to against Roman claims. It is a weapon against the Papacy, although it may be used other purposes. James saw that the weapon two-edged, and attempted to use it against the His Church, in whose defence it was formed, and in failure favour of the very power it was fashioned to attack. natural. What wonder that the sword broke in his hands! Whether or no the interpretation of the theory set upon it by James was logically justified, it ran directly counter to the intention of all who had taken part in the making of it. The Anglican clergy were moved in their action by the clear conviction that no one could have intended that the great anti- papal weapon should be used in favour of the Pope. They must have felt that James was following in the footsteps of Queen Mary, and was attempting to use the royal supremacy in order to render it a nullity for evermore. They refused him their assistance in this attempt. Who can blame them? In neither politics nor theology are men of any age aware of the whole extent of the ground which their theories may logically be held to cover. Nor will they ever hesitate about refusing to carry a belief to its theoretical conclusion, when the conclu- sion conflicts with the purpose for which the doctrine forged theory to thwart the 14--2 212 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE was first framed. There are many nowadays who profess the doctrine vox populi vox dei. But it can hardly be maintained, that they are prompt to acknowledge an unfavourable verdict of the con- stituencies as of divine prompting. If the worship- pers of democracy are at times betrayed into reading diaboli for dei, or into employing anti-democratic institutions in order to maintain their position, are we to find great fault with the supporters of non- resistance in the seventeenth century, who found that for once they had been mistaken, and that on occasion it might be well to exhibit the virtue of non-resistance, not to a Romanising king, but to a Protestant invader? The theory of Divine Right had a great work to do in assisting Englishmen to free themselves from the Papal yoke. The proof that the work was done was not reached until, in their fear of Rome, men were ready to cast aside the very weapon which had hitherto aided them in the struggle. Work of the So far remark has been made of the service doctrine. performed by the theory of Divine Right, in as- serting the profound truth that political institutions per se are not displeasing to God as the author of nature; that they ought to be something more than the instruments of ecclesiastical authority; that the statesman is not bound to take his policy from the priest; that the State as such is an organism with a life of its own, and is subject to laws of developement distinct from those of the Church; that the rulers of the Church will not necessarily be possessed of political wisdom above the common, and may not without danger be CHURCH OF ENGLAND 213 Olga trusted with the tremendous power of deciding on questions of national policy with reference to the aggrandizement of that organization (which itself has an earthly side), to whose service they are devoted; or in modern phrase that the "clergy should not meddle with politics." It is thus clear, that to the derided Anglican clergy of the seven- teenth century are due many of the most cherished principles of modern life. They may not justly be charged with pursuing a time-serving and servile policy. Their aims were not dictated by the in- terests of a class or section, but were patriotic and pre-eminently characteristic of the defenders of a national Church. They cannot truly be charged with deserting their principles the moment that they became inconvenient, for their conduct at the time of the Revolution, if inconsistent with the letter of their doctrine, only proves how deeply imbued they were with its spirit, and exhibits their thorough loyalty to the essential principle which their theory was framed to express. All this is true, and has been too often left out of account in the abuse that has been levelled at the believers in Divine Right. clerical Yet it must not be forgotten that much was due The to that very ecclesiastical theory of politics against theory had which men strove in the seventeenth century. a value. That doctrine also had a practical work to perform; despite much in it that was false and exaggerated and seems to modern notions preposterous beyond measure, it has brought about the recognition of one of the most important principles that can guide the statesman. For the claims of Pope or 214 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE It is an of assert- ing the rights of Presbyter to control the secular power in the in- terests of the spiritual enshrined in the only form possible to those times the principle of the rights of conscience. In ages when the enforcement of con- early form formity by the strong hand is a recognized principle, when all nations profess the same form of religious conscience. belief, or when the maxim cujus regio ejus religio has become accepted, the only possible method of asserting the rights of conscience and the claims of truth is for the Church to claim superiority over the State. It is inevitable at such times that the perennial problem of Church and State shall take the form of a struggle for supremacy; for neither can admit the entire authority of the other without the gravest danger on the one hand to truth, on the other to the free developement of national life. If the State be admitted to be omni-competent, while the persecution of error is preached as a duty, an Emperor or King with a theological turn of mind may commit the Church to a heresy and endanger God's truth for all time¹. For ex hypothesi it is recognized that the State is supreme in all departments of life; that it is the duty of the State to enforce conformity; and that resistance is un- justifiable. The State may therefore compel the propagation of heresy, and stamp out completely the true faith, for the notion is unfounded, that persecu- tion always fails. If the rights of conscience and 1 On the element of justice in the claims of the Church see the remarks of Dean Church in the letter to Cardinal (then Archdeacon) Manning of July 1844 (Purcell, Life of Cardinal Manning, 1. 696). 2 Mill, On Liberty, 16. ༣ ་ CHURCH OF ENGLAND 215 the claims of truth are to be respected at all, the Church must make herself the guardian of them and claim supremacy over the State. So long, of course, as persecution is a recognized principle, truth cannot be secure. But it is at least a step in the right direction that the power, which has physical force on its side, shall submit to take its views of truth and error from the power, whose force is moral and spiritual only. It is better that the Church should direct the State, as to what forms of faith to enforce or to persecute, than that the State should prescribe religion proprio motu. Even this imper- fect condition of things is a tribute to the rights of conscience, to the claims of truth, and to the existence. of human interests other than those which are merely material and earthly. Toleration involves the principle, that religion is a department of life which the State has no moral right to control, that opinion may not be coerced. Persecution by the State at the bidding of the Church contains the germ of this principle; for it arises from the notion that the State as such cannot meddle with opinion, but must take its views from those who know. It forms the necessary transition between the State-religion of the Roman Empire and the modern ideal of freedom of opinion. In the first stage, the State prescribes a religion of its own and compels all men to worship the Emperor. In the second, the State recognizes that it is incompetent to decide upon questions of religious belief, and must go to the spiritual au- thority to find truth; but it still regards the enforcement of truth as a duty, and persecution as K 216 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND THE its proper function. The third stage is that of complete toleration of all forms of belief, when the State has given up its claim to meddle with opinion, and regards religious questions as beyond its com- petence. Now the third stage was not reached at the period which is here being discussed. It will therefore be readily seen that in order to secure the principle which is characteristic of the second stage, and to prevent a relapse into the first, the Church must ever be proclaiming its supremacy in matters of faith and denying the right of the State to meddle therein save at its bidding. This must inevitably lead to some such claim of political authority as was put forward under the Papal or Presbyterian system. If the State admits the right of the Church to dictate to it the true faith to be enforced and to prescribe forms of ecclesiastical organization and discipline, the Church will be found continually encroaching upon the State; many matters, which are of civil import, will be treated as constructively ecclesiastical; and, in the last resort, all freedom will be denied to the State, and its unspiritual character will be made the basis of a claim for its enslavement. The State must then assert its independence; and the form of the assertion is the subject of this essay. The conflict in- evitably toleration Nor is there any means, whereby the conflict can be brought to a close, until the principle of lasts, until toleration be generally accepted. Only when the becomes a State has resigned the claim to make religion recognized co-extensive with its authority, can the Church with safety withdraw from its pretensions to make politics subservient to ecclesiasticism. When that be the principle. CHURCH OF ENGLAND 217 1 case, the State, by giving up the claim to enforce truth at the point of the bayonet, will have freed the Church from the risk of destruction. The claims of the State to omnipotence may hence- forward be admitted. The Church will no longer be in danger with every chance current of thought, that may sway the sovereign one or number. There is no longer any need for the Church to proclaim its supre- macy over the State, for its activity is recognized as free from State interference. The State is sovereign. It may legally do what it pleases. No co-equal jurisdiction exists. No clerical organization may dictate to it. That is the principle underlying the sophistical reasoning and obsolete philosophy of the supporters of the Divine Right of Kings. Con- science must be respected. Beliefs are free. Men's forms of ecclesiastical organization must be of their own choosing. The State must not force their faith or practice. Religious toleration is to be a practical limit upon the exercise of the sovereign power. This is the principle, which out of numberless impossible claims and anarchical opinions has been won for modern citizens by those who assert the Divine Right of Pope or Presbyter. Neither side saw clearly or completely what was the essence of its claim. Neither side realized that toleration alone could set the conflicting claims at rest, and permit of both Church and State developing without injuring one another. Both sides argue with passion, with sophistry, with an uncritical assumption of God's being on their side, which must seem to us Pharisaical. Yet each side was right in its main Puter 330 12 3/30 ME. 218 PASSIVE OBEDIENCE ETC. contention. The State has a right to exist apart from the favour of the clergy; and politics should not be governed by ecclesiastical considerations. On the other hand there are departments of thought and action with which the State may not interfere without the gravest injury to the highest interests of humanity. Both sides were fighting for principles which have long been admitted to be rooted in right reason and utility. To throw ridicule upon the antiquated forms in which these principles found expression and did their work, to blame the royalist for servility or the Papalist for bigotry is to blame men for defending a just cause with the only weapons that were available. That there was too much of passion and prejudice on either side may be admitted. Even modern controversies are not quite without them. But they are frequently wanting in those solid results, which give such cause for gratitude to the controversialists of the middle ages and the Reformation. The more closely the subject is studied, the greater will be the debt of gratitude acknowledged alike to those, who by sup- porting the Divine Right of Kings have ministered to the stability and independence of the English State, and to their opponents, to whose labours we owe it that liberty of thought has become a recog- nized principle of modern life. CHAPTER IX NON-RESISTANCE AND THE THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY It is as a phase in the conflict of Church and Political State that the theory of the Divine Right of Kings the theory. possessed its greatest significance and produced its most memorable results. Yet it has a place also in the history of the developement of the theory of government, and must be considered in relation to those political problems which occupied men's minds in the seventeenth century. It is true, that with the possible exception of Hobbes, all the political theorists up to the end of the seventeenth century either have religion for the basis of their system, or regard the defence or supremacy of some one form of faith as their main object. Hardly any political idea of the time but had its origin in theological controversy. To Roman writers in the main are due the theories of the State of nature and of the original compact'. Popular rights and ec- clesiastical supremacy are bound up with one another. 1 See especially Suarez, De Legibus, III. 4; Mariana, De Rege, 1. 1, 2, 8. In the last-mentioned chapter the question discussed is "Reipublicae an Regis major potestas sit?" The course of the argument is singularly instructive, and much of it might have been written by Locke. It is notable that, although deciding 220 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Yet since all these theological controversies have a political aspect, it is possible to isolate this aspect for the purposes of enquiry and to investigate the purely political side of the theory of Divine Right. There will be the less danger in this course, since the markedly theological character of all seventeenth century politics has already been sufficiently dwelt upon. Further, in the deluge of political literature that poured forth in the seventeenth century, it can hardly be but that views of every sort shall be found here and there in reluctant combination. An attempt to disentangle the main threads of controversy can lay no claim to comprehensive accuracy. Lines of thought apparently inconsistent will at times be united through individual idio- syncrasy. Methods of argument will change sides. Sentiments and opinions will be subject to kaleido- scopic permutations. A sketch like the present can do no more than describe general tendencies of difference or resemblance between opposing schools. It may give a rough estimate of what was the characteristic drift of thought on either side. But it cannot lay claim to finality. Nor must it be forgotten that individual writers may well be found whose personal equation obscures the main lines. This chapter can only describe general tendencies. in Chapter 2 that monarchy is the best form of government, Mariana would yet surround his king with all sorts of limitations, so that he really leaves the sovereignty with the people, and thus falls into the error of supporting a "mixed monarchy." "Pos- tremo, quod caput est, Principis malo coercendi potestatem in republica residere." It is needless to say that, in Mariana's view, one of the main limits on royal authority is set by the freedom of the Church. Cf. From Gerson to Grotius. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 221 of controversy, and causes them to overleap the barriers of thought which separate opposing parties. Still there are certain well-marked differences in conception and standpoint between the combatants on either side; each party appears to represent certain distinctive tendencies. It seems reasonable to attempt the exposition of these characteristics, after thus premising that isolated cases may be found in which they are not exhibited. It will then be necessary to consider, whether or no the theory of. the Divine Right of Kings was something more than the expression of an absurdly romantic senti- ment of loyalty; how much it has in common with other political theories of the time; whether, when it differs from them, it differs from them for the worse; and whether it contained within it notions. of the State, its powers and functions, which modern. thought has not discarded. نا I. notion of sistance. There is no more universal characteristic of the Univer- political thought of the seventeenth century than sality of the notion of non-resistance to authority. “To non-re- bring the people to obedience" is the object of writers of all schools. When resistance is preached, it is resistance to some authority regarded as subordinate. Nor is the resistance permitted at the pleasure or judgment of private individuals. It is allowed only as a form of obedience, as execut- ing the commands of some superior and ultimate 222 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE authority, God, or the Pope and the Law. It has been shewn already that the Papal theory is in truth a doctrine of obedience to a monarch. Great indeed was the indignation evoked by the airy manner in which Bellarmine or Mariana disposed of the claims to obedience of the secular prince, and fostered principles of popular sovereignty. Yet at least some Anglican writers were capable of seeing that all these notions are developed as part of a theory of obedience, and not of liberty, and that the text, "They that resist shall receive to themselves damnation," so far from being discarded or explained away, is interpreted as proving the political supre- macy of the Pope. As Bishop Jackson puts it, "The principle wherein the Romish Church, the Jesuits, and we agree is this; that none may resist the higher powers; that obedience, at least passive or submissive from the outward man of our bodies, lives, and estates is due to the higher powers; the question is...which be the highest powers on earth'." So with the Presbyterian view. The main object of the discipline is obedience, in Cartwright's view². The strong expressions about duty to the civil magistrates which seem inconsistent, when read by the side of claims to depose them, are explained by the view, held in common with Papalists and Wycliffe, that resistance for mere oppression's sake ¹ Jackson, Treatise of Christian Obedience (Works, 111. 971.) 2 Cf. the following, "Under the name of the Saints are con- tained all the rest of the Church, which do not exercise any public office or function therein, whose duty as in all others sometimes is only this, to suffer themselves to be ruled and governed by those whom God hath set over them." Declaration of Discipline, 185. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 223 is not justifiable, and that no private person may resist the Sovereign. Only the Kirk, as inspired by God, may direct the removal of an "idolater," in order to secure "freedom," i.e. supremacy for itself. Neither Papalist nor Presbyterian (except George Buchanan) contemplates the resistance of indi- viduals¹; nor does either make any approach to the modern notion, that obedience may be settled by utilitarian considerations. utilitarian not held teenth Even with those who go further than this and Modern look at politics from a more purely secular stand- theory of point, God's cause is almost invariably the sole obedience occasion of lawful resistance. Clearly, the notion of in seven- the Divine right of insurrection was not one, for century. which any considerable number of persons were contending in the seventeenth century. Remark has been made of the emphasis laid in the Vindiciae contra Tyrannos on the duty of passive obedience incumbent upon private individuals. So long as a tyrant, however oppressive in his acts, is supported by the constituted authorities and estates of the realm, obedience to him is a duty. Nor was the notion confined to France. In England it found expression in the theory that resistance to the Crown is lawful, only if it be enjoined by the inferior magistrate. It was pretended that the Parliament took up arms against the person only of the King, but in support of his authority. This shews how loth men were to believe that what was legally wrong will ever 1 Mariana is apparently an exception with his theory of the duty of tyrannicide. De Rege, 1. 7, 8. 2 Supra p. 114. 224 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE be morally right. At this time some shadowy legality is always pretended for acts essentially revolutionary. Prynne's elaborate treatise is written with the object of proving that Parliament at the beginning of the Civil War had the law upon its side. The author has no notion that tyranny can justify the abrogation for the nonce of law. The same notion appears more strongly in 1688, in the fiction that James, having abdicated the throne, the English legal and constitutional system is being developed with no breach of continuity. There is evidence yet more conclusive. Johnson, writing on behalf of the Exclusion Bill, declares deliberately that Christians are bound to submit to persecution in the case where the laws permit it. When the laws of God and our own country interfere and it is made death by the law of the land to be a good Christian, then we are to lay down our lives for Christ's sake. This is the only case where the Gospel requires passive obedience, namely, when the laws are against a man?" So widespread was this notion, that one writer at the time of the Revolution subjects the Whig theory to the following reductio ad absurdum. According to the Whig view, if the King persecutes the true faith, he may be resisted. Now on this view if the law took a similar course it might be resisted. But no Whig will admit that this latter case would make resistance justifiable. Therefore it is absurd to claim the right in the former case where the King is persecutor (< ¹ The Sovereign Power of Parliament and Kingdoms. 2 Julian the Apostate (Johnson's Works, 33). 1 THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 225 against the law¹. Nor, again, is the main force of the royalist attack directed against the contention, that resistance to the law may in certain circum- stances be justified. Royalists are not concerned to prove that the law may not be resisted on any pretence without grievous sin. Nobody doubts this. Their main position is quite different. They set themselves to prove, that laws derive their binding authority from the King alone, and therefore that he may not be resisted when he breaks them; for he, as the source of legislation, is himself above positive law, and resistance to the 'sovereign' is always sinful. The real controversy between Royalists and Whigs concerns the existence of a sovereign one or number not subject to law³. The vexed question of Julian the Apostate was a case in point. The Whig 1 Christianity a Doctrine of the Cross, 75. 2 See especially the above-mentioned pamphlet, and compare the following passage: "The plea is the same on either side; the Pope says as long as the Prince governs according to the Laws of God and the Church (of which He is the interpreter) so long the censures of the Church do not reach Him; and say the People, as long as the Prince governs according to the Laws of the Land (and of the meaning of those laws themselves are the interpreters) so long are they bound to be obedient; but as soon as the King doth anything that may contradict the Pope, then he is (deservedly say the Romanists) excommunicate, deposed and murdered, and when he usurps upon the People's liberties, then he ought to be deposed by the people; the arguments on either side are the same and for the most part the authorities." History of Passive Obedience (1684), 84. 3 "There is no authority upon earth above the law, much less against it," (Johnson, 30) expresses the whole contention of the Whigs, which is opposed to the theory of sovereignty as well as to Divine Right. F. 15 226 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE 8 K argument is that the submission of the early Christians to persecution was owing to the fact that it was legal, while their (alleged) resistance to Julian was due to the illegality of his oppression¹. Even Locke evades the difficulty by denying the omnipotence of "the legislative" in all states. He will not declare, that resistance to law is ever justifiable. He merely denies, that laws which transgress certain funda- mental principles, are laws "properly so called"." So with Algernon Sidney. He declares that an unjust law is not law at all, and gives as in- stances the persecuting statutes of the Lancastrian period. No other view was possible to him; for elsewhere he is content to bow before the majesty of law. In one eloquent passage Sidney declares that this [Law] is he to whom we all owe a simple uncon- ditional obedience." Milton in his Tenure of Kings and Magistrates perhaps comes nearer than most of his contemporaries to modern utilitarian views. Yet he places the sovereignty in the people by a funda- mental and unalterable law; and thus by a confusion between natural and positive law, similar to that (C Gale ¹ Johnson, Julian the Apostate, "The first Christians suffered according to the laws of their country, whereas these under Julian were persecuted contrary to law," 28, Answer to Jovian, Answer to Constantius the Apostate. 2 Second Treatise of Civil Government, Chaps. 11, 18. 3 Discourses Concerning Government, III. § 11. 4 Ibid. § 25. 5 Ibid. § 42. • Tenure of Kings and Magistrates, Prose Works, II. 11. "The power of kings and magistrates is nothing else but what is only derivative, transferred and committed them in trust from the people ...in whom the power yet remains fundamentally, and cannot be taken from them without a violation of their natural birthright.” THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 227 made by Locke and Sidney, he thinks to escape the danger of asserting a doctrine which then seemed so preposterous as that resistance to law may ever be morally justifiable. The law to which obedience is due may be Canon Law, 'Discipline,' Positive Law, Custom. But obedience to what is conceived as law of some sort, truly and not metaphorically speaking, is the universal maxim. Nearly all teach the duty of obedience to positive law, for the law of the Church is equally positive law if its claims be admitted. That some of these writers are feeling their way towards the purely utilitarian theory of obedience held in modern times is undoubtedly the case. But they had none of them reached it. One and all would have scouted the bald proposition, fundamental in utilitarian politics, that a law having all the notes of law "simply and strictly so called" may yet be disobeyed, if it be oppressive beyond measure. The practical teaching might not greatly differ from that of a modern utilitarian, for on most of these theories there would be ample grounds for pronouncing any law, to which grave objection is taken, as lacking in some essential property of law rightly so-called. Yet the theories of the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries are as wide apart as the poles. With very few exceptions, all political thinkers in the seventeenth century regard as absolute the claims of law, as they define it, to unquestioning, unvarying obedience; they teach that to the ultimate authority in the state, whatever it be, non-resistance is the last word of duty. i 15-2 228 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE II. Causes of this general belief in the duty of obedience to law. Nor is the explanation far to seek. The history of the Middle Ages is filled with the struggle between government and anarchy. According to unvarying the Papal theory, secular governments are the anar- chical powers, which would teach men to disobey their true lord in obedience to an inferior authority. From the point of view of national statesmen it is, on the one hand, the Pope claiming the deposing power, the clergy demanding immunities, on the other hand, the feudal lordships, private jurisdictions, livery and maintenance, that prevent or check the unquestioned supremacy of one all-embracing system of law. In the Wars of the Roses the evils of this latter tendency exhibit themselves for the last time. They produce the reaction in favour of despotism and peace at any price. For a long time after this, men will have ceased to regard liberty or constitu- tional rights as of any importance compared with strong government and the suppression of private war. Obedience is in the eyes of all men the supreme duty of the patriotic citizen; and law the one element essential to the welfare of the state. K Nor is it of statute law that men are thinking; but of the Common Law, which, though containing The Common Law con- ceived as much that may have originally been directly enacted, sovereign. yet possesses that mysterious sanctity of prescription, which no legislator can bestow. The Common Law is pictured invested with a halo of dignity, peculiar to the embodiment of the deepest principles and to the highest expression of human reason and of the THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 229 law of nature implanted by God in the heart of man. As yet men are not clear that an Act of Parliament can do more than declare the Common Law¹. It is the Common Law, which men set up as the object of worship. They regard it as the symbol of ordered life and disciplined activities, which are to replace the licence and violence of the evil times now passed away. Instead of local custom or special privilege one system shall be common to all. Instead of the caprice of the moment, or the changing principles of competing dynastic policies, or the pleasure of some great noble, or the cunning of a usurper, there shall rule in England a system, older than Kings and Parliaments, of immemorial majesty and almost Divine authority. "Law is the breath of God; her voice the harmony of the world." And the Common Law is the perfect ideal of law; for it is natural reason developed and expounded by the collective wisdom of many generations. By it kings reign and princes decree judgment. By it are fixed the relations of the estates of the realm, and the fundamental laws of ¹ [Judicial Records and Acts of Parliament] "are but declara- tions of the Common Law and Custom of the Realm touching Royal Government," Jenkins Redivivus, 1; the repeated attempts beginning with 42 Ed. III. c. 1, to declare certain Acts of Parlia- ment unrepealable are another proof of this. Cf. also Bonham's case (Reports 118 a). "When an Act of Parliament is against common right and reason or repugnant or impossible to be per- formed, the Common Law will control it and adjudge such Act to be void." Majestas Intemerata contains a long legal argument directed against the omnipotence of Parliament, and contending that "the statute is but declarative" (8). "An Act against payment of tithes is regarded as void" (16). : 230 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE the constitution. Based on long usage and almost supernatural wisdom its authority is above, rather than below that of Acts of Parliament or royal ordinances, which owe their fleeting existence to the caprice of the King or to the pleasure of councillors, which have a merely material sanction and may be repealed at any moment. It is not wonderful that men should have thought of the Common Law as sovereign by Divine Right; or that they should have deemed that it owed its authority to something higher than the will of the Sovereign. In the days when English Law first took shape, men had spoken of it as superior to King and Parliament alike, and had dreamed of no sovereign's sanction as needful to make it binding. And so we find many in the seventeenth century who retain the notion, and think, that the word "Law, Law" is enough. For them law is the true sovereign, and they are not under the necessity of considering whether King or Lords or Commons or all three together are the ultimate authority in the state. III. In With the But this was no longer true to the facts. Legis- Reforma- tion a true lative activity had much increased of late. theory of Tudor times it effected the most far-reaching series of changes known in English history. The central possible in power had asserted its supremacy over aristocratic England. privilege and made good its independence against sove- reignty becomes the Papacy. 1 "Truly for these many years last past have the lawyers en- slaved both the king and the people by the charm of 'Law, law'." The Church's Eleventh Persecution, 7. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 231 At last there was room in English politics for a complete theory of sovereignty. The vast increase in the powers and activity of the legislator could not fail to drive men to seek for the sanction of the law in his will. They were forced to consider the question, whether Kings are anterior to law, or law to governments. Here there is a distinction capable of splitting into two parties the believers in the Divine Right of the law of the land. On the one hand those who believe that custom is the main element in law, and law therefore the king-maker, naturally claimed to make the Judges, as inter- preters of the law, the supreme power in the state; while, like Bracton, they themselves failed to see the necessity of a sovereign one or number and honestly believed that no power in the state is exempt from legal limitation. On the other hand, those who have grasped the notion, now first made apparent by facts, that there must be a sovereign in the state, who may give to laws their efficacy, will claim that he is ipso facto above the laws, and cannot be subject to their coercive power. The Inevitable quarrel between the Crown and the Judges was not only the forerunner of the greater quarrel between between King and Parliament: it was inevitable in the of the nature of things. The Judges, as professors of the and the Common Law, claimed for it supreme authority, and Common had their claim been admitted, would have made themselves the ultimate authority in the state. For no one denied their right to interpret the law. The King, realizing vividly that there must be a sovereign, claimed naturally enough the position asserted for contro- versy supporters Crown Law. 232 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE the Judges. What the Judges really asserted was that all constitutional questions could be settled by a reference to custom, and that they alone were competent to declare it. This, as Mr Gardiner points out, would have given into their hands the decision of the great struggle of the seventeenth century¹. Coke, like most of the opponents of the King, had not really grasped the conception of sovereignty; he main- tained a position, reasonable enough in the Middle Ages, but impossible in a developed unitary state. For his claim and that of all the Common Lawyers was to personify the Common Law as sovereign, and to deny that character to any person or body in the state. Had his ideal been reached, and questions of interpretation (which made the Judges sovereign) settled once for all, England would have been in the condition of the Punjaub under Runjeet Singh, as described by Sir Henry Maine, where the person habitually obeyed" never made a true law and was deemed incapable of making one'. The fact, lamented by Clarendon, that the "professors of that great and admirable mystery, the Law" were on the Puritan side, was inevitable". For their view was towards a state of things that had ceased to exist, and they sought to explain the constitution of England as Bracton might have done. But the King had per- ceived that with the growth of legislative activity and << 1 For accounts of Coke's views and the various controversies which culminated in his suspension, see Gardiner, History of England, II. 35-43, 242, 279, III. 1-25. 2 Early History of Institutions, 379 sqq. 3 9 History of the Rebellion, Iv. 38–41. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 233 : the victory of the central power over its enemies, sovereignty had become a fact, and past history justified him in laying claim to all that was in- volved in the new state of things. It is the King and his supporters, be it observed, who first saw the change. Parliament, unwilling at first to claim the sovereignty, denies that it exists. On the other hand, if the King had been permitted to retain all his traditional prerogatives, the general recogni- tion of the idea of sovereignty would have made the government a tyranny; as Maitland said, it was only the lack of this recognition that saved England from falling into despotism in the Middle Ages. Now that the truth was soon to be recog- nized by the nation at large, Parliament was forced to make new claims and by degrees to grasp at supremacy, lest it should lose old rights or even forfeit equality. With many modifications, the controversies between Whigs and Royalists right up to the Revolution hinged on this question of sovereignty. One side has ever before it the vision of law conceived as a system existing by Divine Right, its origin lost in the past, independent of circumstances and men's caprice, superior to Kings, and controlling Parliament. The other side lays stress on the conception of a sovereign raised above all laws with power to abrogate them, who alone can give binding force to enactments and invest custom with legal sanctions. The supporters of the Crown are repeatedly found arguing that the King must be before and above the law, or how can it be binding? They are enraged at the stupidity of their opponents, 234 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE This question forms the main ground of contro- versy up volution. to the Re- who cannot admit so obvious a fact. The novelty of the notion of sovereignty is the explanation of the otherwise unaccountable views entertained by those judges who favoured the Crown's claims as to the King's extraordinary power¹. They saw that law can never bind the 'sovereign' in any state, and they were therefore driven to enlarge the meaning of prerogative to an alarming extent. The very fact that the idea of sovereignty had only then disengaged itself from a belief in the supremacy of custom, would compel all those, who were imbued with the idea, to treat of the King's prerogative, as the basis and essence of the whole system of law, rather than as an aggregate of exceptional powers and discretionary authority allowed to him by well-established custom. Sovereignty presented itself to these men with all the force of a discovery, and in their enthusiasm for the abstract conception, they used language which justified their opponents in declaring that they were interpreting the law, so as to give the King a truly arbitrary, i.e. capricious authority. The doctrine of sovereignty was perhaps mis- conceived in some of its details, or not grasped with absolute precision. Yet certainly, from the point of view of political theory, the controversy between Royalists and Parliamentarians differs merely in its practical object, from the questions, which every student of Austin is driven to ask himself, "At what point does custom become law? And how is it made 1 See especially the judgment of Chief Baron Fleming in Bates' case printed in Prothero's Documents, 340, and of Berkeley in Hampden's case in Gardiner's Documents, 46. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 235 such?" The point has been much debated of late years; yet it may be doubted whether there is any substantial agreement among writers on jurispru- dence. If thinkers, whose only object is scientific investigation, are not yet agreed as to what is the true answer to these questions, there is no great cause to blame the disputants on either side in the seventeenth century. The problem as to the precise value of the maxim, "Whatever the sovereign per- mits, he commands," will not improbably continue to perplex us till the end of time. But this much is certain. The facts of English history had for the first time rendered complete sovereignty a necessity in English national life. The question, in whom the sovereignty should ultimately be vested, could only be decided by a century of struggle. The sove- reignty of whatever person or body was the highest authority in the English State became a practical fact at the Reformation. Only those who were the least hampered by tradition would be gifted with the clearness of insight necessary to perceive this. All whose imaginations were dominated by the past would fail for a time to observe the change. The leaders of advance in this matter were the believers in Divine Right. The omnipotence of Parliament is doubtless real- ized sufficiently at the present day by many persons, who would be at a loss to understand some of the details of the theory of sovereignty. It is not sur- prising that the first perception of the notion takes at first a practical, rather than a scientific form. For most men the idea will be suggested by the G 236 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE observed fact of the existence of a sovereign. They will not frame the theory, and afterwards observe the facts. Now it is unlikely that those, whose gaze was turned to the England of the six- teenth century, could suppose that sovereignty was invested in any other person than the King. Here and there, a man like Prynne or Sir Thomas Smith may be found arguing that not the King, but Parliament is truly sovereign¹. Yet most men will arrive at the idea of sovereignty because they will seem to see it encircling the diadem of Henry VIII. or Elizabeth. As was shewn above, the course of circumstances would lead men to suppose that the sovereignty was vested in the Crown and not in Parliament. The perception of this fact inevitably led to the exaltation of the position of the King, 1 The very fact that Prynne knows that his treatise will seem a dangerous paradox is proof that his views were not generally accepted (Sovereign Power of Parliaments, To the Reader). Bishop Sanderson, again, considers the mere words of the oath of supre- macy as quite sufficient proof that the sovereignty is vested in the King, and not the Parliament (Preface to Ussher's Power of the Prince). The personal character of allegiance, as defined by all the Judges in Calvin's case, was another bar to men's dreaming of Parliament as the actual depositary of sovereign authority. The views quoted above as to the possibility of avoiding Acts of Parlia- ment would similarly hinder the growth of a belief in Parliamentary sovereignty. Nor is there as yet one imperial Parliament; it is to the King, not the Parliament that inhabitants of England, Scotland and Ireland are united in allegiance. If the three are to make one realm, it can only be because the King is sovereign. The United Parliament of Cromwell made Parliamentary sove- reignty a possibility. It is noteworthy that theories of popular sovereignty in the seventeenth century are not in general theories of technical sovereignty vested in Parliament, but doctrines of the rights of the people in the last resort. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 237 and to a depreciation of the rights of Parliament and the rules of Law. Only as this took place, would those, who were determined to stand by the rights of Parliament and by the ancient conventions of the constitution, gradually rise to the conception of Parliamentary sovereignty, and find in the privilege of Parliament a treasury of omnipotence not inferior in elasticity and controversial convenience to the undefined possibilities of royal prerogative¹. IV. Divine G the seven- teenth The Divine Right of Kings on its political side The was little more than the popular form of expression Right of for the theory of sovereignty. As an abstract theory Kings is the form the idea is never likely to be widely prevalent. But taken in sovereignty seen, as a fact, vested in a person or body of persons may lead men to frame a theory far century by more generally intelligible and practically effective the theory of sove- than the academic analysis of the notion in Austin, reignty. or even in Hobbes and Bodin, can ever become. This is the case with the Divine Right of Kings. Evidence of the fact may be found in plenty. Many of the most strenuous supporters of the Divine Right of Kings declare that similar rights belong to all established governments, and that non-resistance to their authority is equally a duty. On the other hand, the opponents of the theory are frequently found attacking not so much royal authority, as the idea of sovereignty. Moreover Hobbes, who has the 1 Clarendon traces the process by which the privilege of Parlia- ment was extended by imperceptible degrees to cover an assumption of complete sovereignty. History of the Rebellion, passim. 1 238 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE reputation of being the first Englishman in the seven- teenth century to formulate the complete theory of sovereignty, did not analyse it as a purely scientific notion, but had with his contemporaries the object of proclaiming the duty of invariable obedience and non-resistance to the sovereign in all states. The analysis of sovereignty is only incidental to the practical object of inculcating non-resistance. So with supporters of Divine Right. Divine Right of amp with Kings with non- resistance and the duty of non-resistance. to all established govern- ments. Bishop Overall's Convocation Book was avowedly compiled in the support of monarchy. The object of confused the book is to assert the Divine Right of Kings, Yet it is of all established governments that this Divine authority is really asserted. True, arguments in favour of the superiority of monarchy are drawn from the patriarchal theory; yet the statement is made that after rebels have organized a government, its authority is from God. This statement is flatly subversive of the in- defeasible hereditary right, and was on that ground distasteful to James I. It is evident that there was confusion in the minds of the compilers, and that the element in their doctrine which was grasped with lucidity was the idea that some sovereign power existed in all states, that this sovereign power owed its authority to Divine ordinance, and that resistance to it is a sin. Kated Hickes, who became a non-juror, wrote his Jovian in the midst of the Exclusion Bill controversy. Yet he distinctly asserts that all established governments 1 Overall's Convocation Book, Canon xXVIII. James' Letter is printed in the preface. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 239 are from God, and that the Biblical prohibitions of resistance are fully as applicable to the subjects of a republic as to those of a monarchy. The work of Dudley Digges, The Unlawfulness of Subjects taking up arms against the Sovereign, is still stronger evidence that the most important elements in the theory of Divine Right are the conception of sovereignty and of non-resistance to the sovereign, whether King or Parliament. Except for the addition of the religious sanction to obedience, and for the use of scriptural illustrations, we might be reading a popular abridgment of the Leviathan. The theory of the origin of the state held by Hobbes is definitely adopted. The author does not assert that kingship as such is viewed with any special favour by God. Arguments based on the Old Testament and patriarchal society are dismissed as irrelevant¹. All that is claimed is that England is, as a matter of fact, a monarchy, and that resistance to all established governments is a sin. Ussher, again, argues that sovereignty is a necessary natural fact2. Even Laud declares that he has no will to except against any form of government assumed by any state. Although Filmer's sense of the need of unity in the state leads him to regard monarchy as the only true form of government', yet in another ¹ The Unlawfulness of Subjects taking up Arms, 16. 2True it is that in several states there are admitted several forms of government." "If this be so, and that nature seeketh always to preserve itself, we may justly conclude that Magistracy is rooted in the Law of Nature and so in the Author of Nature, that is God himself." Power of the Prince, 12, 13. 3 Sermons, III. (Works, 1. 85). 4 Observations on Aristotle. 240 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE The con- ception not grasped by the opposite party. place he speaks of the supreme power in any state, monarchy or republic, as nothing but the original power of the father¹. Doubtless such works as the Convocation Book and Jovian exhibit less grasp of what is really involved. in the theory of Divine Right than is the case with the True Law of Free Monarchies or the Patriarcha. There is confusion in the minds of the writers, yet they believe themselves, and have always been commonly regarded as, supporters of Divine Right. The essence of the theory must therefore lie in those doctrines, upon which they lay stress in common with the more accurate expounders of the notion. Those points, which are obscured or ignored by so strong a non-juror as Hickes, can at most be regarded as organic details" of the theory, rather than as its main and vital principles². (C ŠATI, A POTENT Still more clearly is it evident that the real question in dispute is the fact of sovereignty, and the origin of legal authority, if attention be paid to the repeated attempts made to convince Whig theorists, that no state can be without an ultimate 1 Patriarcha, 23. 2 The writings of the non-juror Leslie are the most vivid ex- pression of royalist theory after the Revolution. It is plain that he is moved by no hatred of republicanism, but merely by the dread of anarchy. "There is no medium possible betwixt non- resistance upon any pretence whatsoever and a full licence to resist upon every pretence whatsoever. Because every man is left to judge of the pretence. So that the whole dispute is Whether government or anarchy?' (The Best Answer.) "For the word King, I mean no more than the supreme authority." (Best of all.) See Appendix. "" THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 241 authority, which, because it is sovereign, must be technically arbitrary. "The name of tyranny signi- fieth nothing more nor less than the name of sovereignty," says Hobbes'. "There is a necessity that somebody must be trusted, if you will not trust one, you must trust more" declares Digges². "There is no such thing as a free state in the world" is the thesis of another. Laud writes, "Turn the knot which way you will, all binding to obedience will be grievous to some." Another asks, What State can these rebels have that may not degenerate into a tyranny"?" Indeed, during the troubles of the Commonwealth the notion might easily be generated that tyranny is no less possible under a Parliament than under a King. It is a pertinent question, "The will of one man is contrary to freedom, and why not the will of five hundred"?" Royalists writing on this matter habitually speak with the half-amazed irritation of a teacher, trying in vain to get wilfully stupid pupils to realize how chimerical 1 Leviathan, 392. Hobbes characteristically adds "saving that they that use the former word are understood to be angry with them they call tyrants." In Behemoth, 112, Hobbes shews that all governments are really arbitrary: and goes on, "The true meaning of Parliament was that not the King, but they them- selves should have the arbitrary power not only of England, but of Ireland and (as it appeared by the event) of Scotland also." 2 The Unlawfulness of Subjects taking up Arms (79); cf. also p. 43, "A necessity to grant impunity to some in all governments.” *ang pada mig 3 Royal Charter granted unto Kings (Chap. XIV.). 4 Sermons, VI. (Works, 1. 180): cf. with this Mr Sidgwick's Remarks on the "coercion of well-intentioned adults," Elements of Politics, 623. * EIKON AKAAETOΣ, a reply to Milton's Iconoclastes. • Ibid. There is much more in the same strain. F. 16 242 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Locke's Treatise an attack on the idea of sove- reignty. is the dream of a perfect state with no power in it exempt from legal limitation. Yet more is this apparent in the most striking exposition of the opposite theory. Locke's treatise is expressly directed against the notion that there is any sovereign power in the state. He realizes that the legislative is supreme, yet he sets himself the task of fencing it about with limitations of many kinds, such as the duty of respecting liberty and property, etc.¹ Locke does not say that the trans- gressing of these limits is invariably inexpedient or even universally iniquitous. This may be true; certainly it is tenable. But he tries to prove that such action would be illegal. If the Legislative' oversteps the bounds which Locke has laid down for it, its authority is at an end, and the state is dis- solved. Perhaps it would be hard to mention a single Parliament since the Reform Act which has not over- stepped the limits of its competence according to Locke, and by so doing dissolved the state, and broken the continuity of our institutions and the whole system of law and government. The more closely Locke's treatise is studied, the more clearly will it be seen that it is an attack directed far more against the idea of sovereignty, than against the claims of absolute monarchy. The notion of legal omnipotence is abhorrent to him; and he is guilty of a confusion between law natural and law positive, from which the extremest and most reactionary royalist would have been free. an 'UR 1 Second Treatise, c. 11. Johnson's writings are dominated by a disbelief in the theory of sovereignty. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 243 Milton. Algernon Sidney's Discourses concerning Govern- Sidney and ment, and even Milton's Tenure of Kings and Magistrates, exhibit an almost equal want of insight. The definite ground assumed is that of Rousseau, that the people is sovereign, that this sovereignty comes from God and is inalienable. All governments are in their view merely officials carrying out the will of the sovereign people, and they may therefore be removed at any time¹. This view is apparently also that of Mariana and Suarez, and is far more consistent and logically defensible than the common Whig theory. ་་་ Yet this view is also untenable, for in no state, at that time or now, can the legal sovereignty be said to be vested in the people. It may be true that it ought to be so vested; but it certainly is not the case in any modern state. The sense in which Milton and Sidney spoke of sovereignty being vested in the people is one which proves them incapable of realizing the notion of sovereignty with accuracy. It is with them little more than the expression of the belief in a general right of insurrection against intolerable oppression. To such a belief there would -be no objection, if they did not use their loose interpretation of the term sovereignty, as a ground for denying the existence of the thing. They deny the fact of sovereignty save in a perfect democracy. This may be an ideal, but it is not the expression of existing conditions. That the people ought to be sovereign is a tenable view. But to assert that they are so as a matter of fact, and that any state, in which Tenure of * 1 Discourses Concerning Government, Chap. III. Kings and Magistrates, 14. 16-2 244 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Theory of compact. they are not so regarded, is not truly a state, is to be guilty of a gross confusion of ideas. Milton's view that 'to say the king is accountable to none but God is the overturning of all law and all government¹" would logically lead to the denial of law and government in the Roman Empire or the French kingdom. The confusion of Sidney's thought is yet more startling. After propounding the theory of popular sovereignty he goes on to assert, quite in the Austinian manner, that the power of the lawgiver is arbitrary. He then proceeds to argue that this power is in England vested in the Parliament. The inconsistency is glaring. The people is sovereign; yet a small number of them assembled in Parliament have the 'arbitrary,' i.e. sovereign power of making laws. Even if Parliament be held, which it cannot be save in a loose sense, to govern in the name of the electors, and if sovereignty be ascribed to them, yet the electorate was very far from being identical with the people when Sidney wrote. Even the theory of the original compact affords evidence that the popular party had not clearly grasped the notion of law and sovereignty. Austin shews how untenable is the notion, that a compact can be binding with no sovereign to enforce it. The widespread prevalence of the theory may therefore be taken as evidence, that the men who held it 1 Tenure of Kings and Magistrates, 12. 2 Discourses Concerning Government, III. §§ 21, 45, 46. Sidney regards Filmer's exposition of sovereignty as proving nothing but "the incurable perverseness of his judgment, the nature of his heart and the malignity of his fate always to oppose reason and truth.” THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 245 believed in law as resting mainly on moral sanctions, as independent of physical force and possessed of Divine authority. The theory that government and obedience result from a binding compact could only be credited by men, who instinctively regarded law as anterior to the state. V. respect law From all this it appears that all parties in the All parties seventeenth century are at bottom united in their unite to respect for law and in anxiety to defend government; law, but differ as although they differ as to the nature of both. Law to nature must be supreme, anarchy at all costs must be pre- and sove- vented. This is the dominant thought of influential reignty. writers on all sides. Yet one party in their reverence for law would seek to invest it with a quasi- sovereign authority, and would deny to present and future generations the power of substantially changing it. For it is law, as a product of custom and ancient statutes hardly distinguished from custom, that is reverenced by the Whigs. The other party had deeper insight. They saw that in no civilized state can law exist without a lawgiver, and they deduced the necessity of a true sovereign. Both sides agree in inculcating non-resistance to the power which is regarded as the ultimate authority, whether law or lawgiver. Doubtless the supporters of the monarchy made mistakes. They pushed to extremes their doc- trine of the theoretical omnipotence of the sovereign power, and seemed at times indisposed to recognize the importance of practical limitations on the exercise of sovereignty. Of what have been called "internal - 246 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Funda- mental Law. Indefeas- ible here- ditary right. limits" on the sovereign power, restrictions imposed by temperament and environment, they admit the wisdom. But their theory of non-resistance forbids. them to allow of any external limits. Yet it remains. true that the royalist party had in general far clearer notions on law and government in a modern state, than had their opponents, who are often incapable of distinguishing between natural and positive law, and are ever haunted by the vain illusion of placing legal limits on the sovereign power. Once the fact is grasped that the Divine Right of Kings in its philosophical aspect is merely the form given by circumstances to a doctrine of sove- reignty, many of its most characteristic notions will present themselves in a fresh light. The phrase "fun- damental law," of which so much is heard, signifies what a modern philosopher has classed among "the fundamental conceptions of politics¹," and indicates merely belief that, if the state be truly such, there must be a sovereign and subjects. Hickes' division of laws into laws positive and laws imperial is another way of expressing the same notion; laws imperial merely mean those facts, which are inherent in the nature of the state, and which must exist before laws properly so called arise. The view that hereditary right is indefeasible is another element in this conception. Or rather it is the form given to that notion of the inalienable 1 Sidgwick, Elements of Politics, Chap. II. It need hardly be said that, in the view of all orthodox supporters of Divine Right, the statutes of the Tudor period altering the succession are one and all ultra vires and void. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 247 *-* character of sovereignty, which (however insignificant practically) is yet sure to arise with the conception of sovereignty. It is doubtless a limitation on the sovereignty to deny the power of the sovereign to alter the form of government. Yet it would be hard to find a better sanction for many branches of so- called constitutional law at the present day, than that the courts will enforce them. So with in- defeasible hereditary right; so long as the view could be maintained that the courts would enforce the doctrine, it was not unnaturally regarded as a part of constitutional law. S Parlia- grant A Din The doctrine that the rights of Parliament are Power of derived from the Crown only as matters of grace ment due and favour, was characteristic of the mind of King to royal James, and became the ground of controversy may be both in his own case and that of Dr Cowell. It recalled. afterwards became the accepted principle with the royalist writers. The doctrine is really an expression of the sense that sovereignty is indivisible as well as inalienable. So it is used by Bodin¹, who has an elaborate proof that the so-called power of the estates of the realm being merely grants from the sovereign does not imply any diminution or division of his power. He seeks to shew that in the case of England the assent of Parliament to new laws is not really indispensable. It is a maxim, that the donor of a right or privilege may reclaim it at any moment, because sovereignty being indivisible and inalienable, no sovereign right can be irrevocably resigned. Thus it seemed natural to assert, that ¹ De la Republique, 139. 248 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Hobbes and the clergy. because King John granted Magna Charta, all the powers resigned by him still inhere in the King and may be recalled. The repeated historical proof that the Crown was at one time seised of such and such rights, and that it still possesses them in theory, is evidence of the hold upon men's minds of the notions of the indivisible and inalienable character of sovereignty. They cannot conceive that the King can really have lost any prerogative, which can be clearly shewn to have once belonged to him¹. In the theory of the Divine authority of govern- ment all sides are agreed. In some form most men hold that non-resistance is a religious duty. It is the theory of sovereignty which differentiates the royal- ist writers from the popular side and unites them with Hobbes. For the Leviathan contains not only a theory of sovereignty, but also a demonstration that monarchy is the best form of government, that the English state is in fact a monarchy, and that re- sistance to the sovereign is never justifiable. Thus, then, the affinity between the theories of Divine Right and that of Hobbes' was far closer than is often supposed. VI. But how are we to explain the intense ab- horrence with which Hobbes was regarded by the believers in Divine Right? Many causes of this dislike may be found. His philosophy, his 1 Majestas Intemerata is a striking instance of this feeling. The author cannot conceive that the King has lost any rights which ever belonged to him. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 249 alleged heterodoxy, his hatred of the Universities, his contempt for Aristotle (of whom Filmer has so great an admiration), his unrelieved Erastianism, his scorn of merely passive obedience, would all tend to deepen the dislike. But the head and front of his offending is different. In the first place his system of politics is purely utilitarian. It contains far less of the religious sanction, which men of that day demanded for all governments, than do the writings of the opponents of non-resistance. His point of view is eminently modern; and his thought, therefore, for that very reason tends to be out of relation to that of the time in which he lived. It has been shewn above that in many ways his connection with his contemporary theories of politics is far closer than was once thought. Yet at bottom his system is divided from all others of his time by a far deeper gulf than that by which they were separated from one another. Alone among the men of his time Hobbes realized, that politics are not and cannot be a branch of theology. The fact that he passed to the other extreme, and committed the error of treating theo- logy, as though it were a branch of politics, was unlikely to render him a more acceptable figure¹ · ¹ To Hobbes religion was nothing but a "law of the kingdom," enforced for the sake not of truth but of peace, about which there must be no controversy. The duty of the clergy is solely to preach obedience. The Anglican divines could not be expected to view with favour a man who wrote in this style. "We may justly pronounce for the authors therefore of all this spiritual darkness in religion the Pope and Roman clergy, and all those besides who endeavour to settle in the minds of men this erroneous doctrine, 250 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE in the eyes of those, who sought their theory of obedience in S. Paul and found the justification of monarchy in the vision of Nebuchadnezzar. Right Yet there is a still greater cause of divergence between Hobbes and the other royalist writers. His theory of government was based upon the in Divine original compact. This notion was, however ridicu- lous, the one clear conception of the opponents of Divine Right and lay at the root of such consistency of theory as they possessed. There is, indeed, on the Whig side some more or less hesitating recognition of the principle of utility, notably in the case of assert, the organic character of the state. Theory of original compact denies, believers that the Church now on earth is that kingdom of God mentioned in the Old and New Testament" (Leviathan, 383). Now the belief of all contemporary theorists of whatever party was the exact converse of this; they looked to Scripture for a complete theory of politics. The dominant thought of Bellarmine and Suarez is that Christ must have appointed for the Christian Church the most perfect form of government; and that political theory may safely be founded thereon. The very first paragraph of the De Romano Pontifice is to this effect; Suarez takes the same ground as a proof of the excellence of monarchy, (De Legibus, III. 4). Mariana is willing to use the tenable opinion of the council being superior to the Pope in order to prove the subjection of the King to the community; although he guards himself against the retort from the opposite and more common view of Papal autocracy by asserting that the Pope's power comes direct from God, while that of the King comes from the people (De Rege, 1. 8). Similarly it has been shewn that for most Anglican divines politics are founded upon theology; e.g. Sacheverell's sermons, especially "The Poli- tical Union," which is far abler than the better known production, are a striking instance of the belief. "It is impossible for it [govern- ment] to subsist upon any other bottom than that of religion." Hobbes would have transposed religion and government; that he arrived at the same conclusion as other royalists is as nothing to the fundamental difference of principle. THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 251 - W Locke, and this connects them with the thought of the future and with the speculations of Bentham and Mill. Yet the basis on which rest all the theories of popular rights in the seventeenth century is not utility, but the original compact. It is against the original compact that the supporters of Divine Right inveigh most strongly. For it is the expression of a diametrically opposite standpoint to that of the Royalists. Amidst whatever mass of sophistry and error, the conception of the organic character of the state dominated the believers in Divine Right. The theory of compact, whether held by Whigs or Hobbists, is the denial of this. To them the state is an artificial creation. To Filmer or Hickes or Leslie it is a natural growth. In Locke or Sidney or Milton the original compact limits all forms of governments and reduces the state to a mechanical instrument, that may with ease be destroyed and manufactured afresh. In the view of Hobbes the machine of state, when created, is indeed to last for all time, but it has no quality of life, no principle of internal developement. According to the Whig view the sovereign people may repeatedly upset the constitution of the state, and might, if they were better men, do without one at all. The state in fact is a necessary evil. The popular theories of the seventeenth century are a survival of the notion proclaimed in its nakedness by Hilde- brand, but hinted at by Aquinas, and more or less dominant in all the Papalist writers, that the state is a consequence of the fall existing for the hardness of men's hearts. Far different from this is the 252 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE conception of the supporters of Divine Right. Political society is natural to man; government and therefore obedience are necessities of human nature. The uncritical appeals to the Scriptures, to the patriarchal theory, to past history are all governed by this one luminous thought, that the state is no mere artificial manufacture, but a natural organism, and that a wise handling of its problems can arise only from the recognition that it has distinct laws of develope- ment, which may not be transgressed by tinkering it, as a machine. The logical issue of the popular theory is to treat the state as a lifeless creation of the popular will with no power of developement and with no source of strength in sentiment or tradition. No theory of government was ever more untrue to the facts of life than is that of Locke, and the difference between him and Filmer in this respect is all in favour of the latter. In Filmer's theory there is, indeed, a touch of unreality, which is not found in many of the less famous supporters of Divine Right. But there can be no doubt that the method of believers in Divine Right was far less unhistorical than that of their opponents. The contrast is ex- pounded with striking force of satire and reasoning in the numerous writings of Leslie. Even Filmer's theory is based upon the notion that what has always existed must be natural to man and of Divine authority, and is therefore immutable. Further, it is worthy of remark, that the sup- porters of Divine Right differed from their opponents in being the nearer to the truth. For both sides agreed in teaching invariable non-resistance to the THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY 253 ultimate authority, and are therefore in error ac- cording to the modern views. Neither side admitted the Divine Right of insurrection, as it is very generally held now. Both sides used uncritical methods and misinterpreted Scripture or evaded its meaning. Nor did the supporters of the Divine Right, or at least the majority of them, contend that monarchy is the only lawful form of government, and that all republican states ought to set about changing their constitution. Neither side possessed a utilitarian theory of politics. It is possible that on the popular side an individual here and there might be found, who taught a theory of utilitarian obedience; while on the side of the King some men might be found, who denied God's protection to any government save a monarchy. But in the main this was not the case. Against those who fail to perceive the true nature of law and sovereignty the royalist writers point out with truth the necessity in every state for some supreme authority above the laws. Against those who assert that the state is the artificial creation of an impossible contract they proclaim the profound truth that government is natural and necessary to mankind. The Divine Right of Kings is the expression of the supreme truth of political thought, Φύσει ἄνθρωπος ζῷον πολιτικόν. Men pride themselves on at last realizing the truth that the state is organic, or hail with enthusiasm the attempt of Austin and other modern writers on jurisprudence to clear up notions of law and government. They have then little right to charge with triviality those who announced the 254 NON-RESISTANCE AND THE Burke. Divine Right shews a belief in the moral basis of the state. same truths in opposition to theories of law, that had ceased to represent facts, and to a system of politics only less unreal and absurd than that of Rousseau. It is true these notions found forms of expression that had relation to an order of things that has long since passed away. But if as against Rousseau prating of the rights of man, of natural equality, of popular sovereignty, men still pay reverent gratitude for the polemic, in which Burke proclaimed the historical character of constitutional life, the organic growth of the state and the value of senti- ment and "prejudice," what right have they to blame Filmer or Leslie, who insist against Locke with equal truth that all men, so far from being born free and equal, are born slaves, that government has its roots deep in the past and that the state has a life which may not lightly be touched? Lastly, the theory of the Divine Right of Kings was the form in which was expressed the sense of the need of some bond of moral sentiment and conscience other than the belief in its utility to attach men to any government. Burke-felt the same need and expressed it in tones which yet ring in men's ears. He knew that the influences of sentiment and tradition are stronger than the cal- culations of interest to bind a people's allegiance to its government, and that no constitution can be stable which makes a merely utilitarian appeal on men's assistance. He was not ashamed to say that the dead weight of custom, "prejudice," was the weapon which all states should have in their hand. For he felt that an emotional tie must add strength | ! 255 THEORY OF SOVEREIGNTY to the civic reason in order to make it an enduring support. Now the theory of Divine Right was the expression of the same truth in forms suited to the seventeenth century. It may be that our debt of gratitude to the men of that age is no less great than that which all are willing to acknowledge to the great thinker of the last century. Nor should we be chary of giving their due to the protagonists in a struggle of which we are enjoying the fruits, merely because their fundamental principles won ultimate triumph only through the defeat of the practical maxims deduced from them, or because their methods of argument lack the persuasive charm and their style is without the majestic flow, which have given to Edmund Burke his unfading laurels. "It is most true that all available authority is Mystic in its conditions" says Carlyle'. Into the true nature of the bonds, which unite men in govern- ment and subjection, Filmer and Leslie and Sache- verell perhaps had a deeper insight than the modern journalist or member of Parliament. In some form or other "loyalty to persons springs immortal in the human breast," and must always survive as the basis of society, and obedience for conscience' sake remain the chief support of government. The Divine Right of Kings is partly the expression of truths concerning society and the state of deeper and more universal sig- nificance than the trivialities of modern party politics. 1 French Revolution, II. 2. 2 Cardinal Newman, Letter to the Duke of Norfolk (80). 8 There can be no firmness without law; and no laws can be binding if there be no conscience to obey them; penalty alone could, can never, do it." Laud, Sermon IV. (Works, I. 112). True meaning of Divine Right. CHAPTER X CONCLUSION It will have appeared from the foregoing investi- gation that the theory of the Divine Right of Kings was something different in import and value from the collection of purely ridiculous propositions per- versely preached by a servile church, which some have elected to represent it. It was able to gain currency by appealing to some of the deepest instincts of human nature. It gathered up into itself notions of the sanctity of the medicine man, of the priestly character of primitive royalty', of the divinity of the Roman Emperors and perhaps of the sacredness of the tribunician power. Yet the doctrine of Divine Right owes much to the common sentiment of Christians as to obedience; and it 1 That this feeling had not died out in the seventeenth century is proved by the following words put into the mouth of Charles; On their denying his majesty his chaplains: "It may be, I am esteemed by my deniers sufficient of myself to discharge my duty to God as a priest; though not to men as a prince. Indeed I think both offices, regal and sacerdotal, might well become the same person, as anciently they were under one name, and the united rights of primogeniture." Eikon Basilike. This feeling was quite common at the time. CONCLUSION 257 found its most effective material in the practice and teaching of the Christian Church in early ages. The sentiment of obedience to government, as of Divine authority, subsisted as a vague notion until the attempt of the Papacy to make use of the notion in its own interests, led men to examine the value of current maxims on the subject and to assert the independent authority of secular governments, in a theory which is in its essential meaning a doctrine of liberty-the freedom of political societies from subjection to an ecclesiastical organization. clerical It is as an anti-clerical weapon of independence An anti- that the theory had its greatest value and fulfilled theory. its most noteworthy function. In opposition to the claims of the Pope to sovereignty by Divine Right, men formulated the claims of the King to sovereignty by a right that is not inferior. Thus the doctrine is anti-clerical. Yet since it was directed. against a theory of clericalism, it was inevitably formed or supported in the main by divines. And the form of the theory was necessary to its success. It would have failed in its object, had it attempted to give to Parliament rather than to the King the sovereignty which it denied to the Pope. Against the traditional splendours of the tiara it would have been vain to set up any lower dignity than the Crown. Indeed no such aim could have been con- ceived in imagination. It would have been an anachronism. The one country, in which the resist- ance to the Papal yoke was of purely popular origin, threw off allegiance to the Papacy only to fall under the dominion of a power equally ecclesiastical F. 17 258 CONCLUSION in its aims and more galling in its incidence. In the sixteenth century it was well if a King had the strength to cast off the Papal yoke, without rivetting another clerical authority on the state. Certainly none but a King had the power. The theory Again, we see that the theory was necessary as forms the a transition stage between medieval and modern necessary transition politics. It is a far cry from the conception ex- medieval pressed in the Holy Roman Empire, that theology and is the source of political theory and that the state between modern politics is an aspect of the Kingdom of Christ, to the modern view that politics and theology have little or no relation to one another. Politics are frankly secular nowadays. Even where religion is invoked as a sentiment, theology is not expected to solve the problems of statesmanship. Political theory has ceased to be anything but utilitarian, although it may be a question how far this change is an improve- ment and whether it is likely to be lasting. At any rate, in some form or other utilitarianism governs political thought at the present day. But for this to be the case, a long course of developement and conflict has been needful. Before political life can free itself from what may be called the theocratic stage, it must assert for itself a coequal right to exist with theology. It must claim that politics have a proper and necessary function to perform in the developement of the human race, and that there- fore their independent existence must be as much a part of the Divine plan for mankind as is the science of theology or the organization of the Church. That the state is the realization of a true idea, and •*@_madridős FLANGE 44%gth! 429 Glasty?7900 (PPGAVERU #56e9 mes $ CONCLUSION 259 has a necessary place in the world, is the claim, which was explicitly or implicitly denied by the Papalist, and only made good through the theory of Divine Right. For it is only when the claim is put forward by Divine Right, that it can have any practical efficacy against a sovereign claiming, as God's vicegerent, the overlordship of all kings and princes. That secular politics are as truly God's ordinance and that political organizations have as much claim to exist with His approval as the contro- versies of Churchmen and the rules of the Canon Law, is the least that can be demanded by all sup- porters of Divine Right. in the Re- In the Middle Ages all departments of thought The theory were conceived as subordinate to theology in such a an element way that the methods of theology fettered and formation. strangled free developement in science or art or literature. The Reformation is the assertion of the claims of the human spirit to carry on independent work in all branches of enquiry and activity, under the consciousness that truth cannot contradict itself and that the results of every sort of labour carried on with appropriate means and for worthy objects will tend to unity at the last. Now in politics the rise and prevalence of the theory of the Divine Right of Kings is the same phenomenon. Theology had attempted unreasonably to dominate politics, and had committed men to an unphilosophical basis and an uncritical method. The only way to escape from the fetters imposed Its form by traditional methods, was to assert from the old necessary. standpoint of a Scriptural basis and to argue by the 17-2 260 CONCLUSION accustomed fashion of Biblical quotations, that poli- tics must be freed from theology and that the Church must give up all attempts to control the State. The work of the Reformation was to set men free in all departments of thought and enquiry from subjection to a single method and a single subject. In the case of politics the achievement of this result was possi- ble only through claiming at first theological sanc- tion for the non-theological view of politics. Only when the result is achieved will politics be free to develope theories which shall be purely philosophical or historical. Not till then will it cease to be needful to find Scriptural authority for political theory, or Biblical counterparts to the ideals of government. Politics were able to enter upon their modern stage, only because the theory of Divine Right having done its work had emancipated them from mediæval fetters and had in so doing become obsolete itself. Political value of Again, it has appeared that the anarchy of the the theory. Middle Ages developed in men's minds a sense of the need of law and of the duty of obedience. Further, Obedience the Reformation and other causes had contributed to law. to develope so highly the legislative activity of the state, and the checks imposed upon its action by custom or the Pope or feudalism had been so ROTECTIO generally removed, that a theory of sovereignty had become the natural expression of facts, and the sense arose, that law has its authority as being a command of the sovereign. The perception or the denial of these facts has been shewn to be the main point of political controversy between the believers in royal and in popular rights. 1 CONCLUSION 261 state an organism. The other chief source of difference is that be- The tween an artificial and a historical conception of the state. The believers in Divine Right taught that the state is a living organism and has a characteristic habit of growth, which must be investigated and ob- served. Their opponents believed the state to be a mechanical contrivance, which may be taken to pieces and manufactured afresh by every Abbé Sieyes who arises. Moreover, it has appeared that the doctrine of The theory Divine Right effected its object. The political The political fulfilled its object. claims of the Papacy have disappeared. Whether or no Rome has technically receded from her preten- sions, the temporal supremacy is not now an object for which the most ultramontane Romanist will contend. The claims still put forward by the Vatican to the temporal power in no way involve a claim to political supremacy over all princes. The doctrines of the deposing power and the plenitudo potestatis have vanished rather than been disproved. It would not be within the dreams of a modern Papalist to assert them, nor would there be the smallest likelihood of any Roman Catholic nation admitting them, if they were asserted. The claim to infallibility has been long since explained as in no way involving a weakening of civil allegiance¹. 1 See Cardinal Newman's Letter to the Duke of Norfolk; also Life of Cardinal Manning, 1. 399. Perhaps the Pope's complaint, that Brandenburg was erected into a kingdom without his consent is the last instance of any attempt to assert the temporal supremacy, unless the coronation of Napoleon be regarded in that light. (Lamberty, Mémoires, 1. 383.) 262 CONCLUSION Further, practical influences, among which the Union. with Scotland is probably not the least important, have contributed to reduce to a minimum the claims of the other ecclesiastical body, which disputed with the Roman Church for the palm of imposing upon the state the more stifling touch. The omnipotence of civil governments all the world over is a fact no longer disputed-with one limitation. From the claim by Divine Right put forward by the Church to a freedom which meant supremacy, has grown the doctrine of toleration, by which alone, as a practical limit upon state action, religious freedom can be secured without clerical supremacy. BENGAL The theory That the Divine Right of Kings was not merely to the Re- useful, but necessary to the political side of the formation. Reformation, appears to be clearly proved by the evidence. Confirmation of this is afforded by the fact that the theoretical presentment of antagonism to the Papal claims had taken in earlier ages a form, which differed but little from the theories of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. With the Restoration the last chance of Presbyterianism: becoming dominant in England disappeared. The Revolution finally removed all danger from the side of Rome. Only then did the theory of the Divine Right of Kings cease to be useful. As a matter of fact, from a doctrine with a practical aim it begins at this time to pass into a romantic belief enshrining a sentimental regret for the past, and has perhaps a value in literature which it has lost in theology and politics. Perhaps we may see in Burke the survival in substance and transformation CONCLUSION 263 in form of the fundamental principle, which gave to the theory of Divine Right its political value. The raison d'être for the rival theories was removed by the statutes of Toleration and Catholic Relief. On the other hand, as soon as the notion of the original compact had done its work in England by giving men what they regard as an intellectual justification for the Revolution, it too began to disappear and to give place to the purely utilitarian theory of politics, which became dominant through the influence of Bentham. JONEZ it was no VERON The theory of Divine Right did not lose its The belief popularity because it was absurd but because its died, when work was done. There were just as good reasons for longer useful. disbelieving in its validity in 1598 or 1660 as there were at the Revolution. Certainly some writers were well acquainted with them even at the earlier date, a fact proved by such a treatise as that of Parsons. The Divine Right of Kings ceased to have practical importance, not because its doctrines were untrue, but because its teaching had become unnecessary. The transition stage had passed. The independence of the state had been attained. Politics having made good their claim to be a part of the natural order had no longer need of a theological justifi- cation. moulded Again, if the theory be regarded on its purely Doctrine political side, the conceptions which it enshrined has are become part of our common heritage. To the English sense of the organic character of the state and of the duty of obedience are due the existence of "law- abiding citizens" to-day and that dislike of all violent sentiment. Ag 264 CONCLUSION breaks with the past, which has ever been the peculiar glory of England, "Where freedom slowly broadens down From precedent to precedent." It was due to this doctrine that the English Revolution was the most peaceful in history and that English institutions have been developed with scarcely a breach in continuity. To modern ears the 'abdication' of James II. must ever seem a fiction only the more dishonest that it was transparent. Yet the phrase was a pledge, that the old laws and customs of the realm should remain, and that no cataclysms should disturb the orderly developement of the national life. The phrase was false, but the sentiment which it expressed was profoundly true. on Its effect Nor again has the doctrine of non-resistance been beneficial. anything but salutary in its results. It has, indeed, been superseded by a theory of utilitarian obedience, which, although it may be true, is likely to be fraught with greater dangers than could have attended the firmest faith in passive obedience. It is easy for modern politicians to regard the inculcation of invariable non-resistance as mere nonsense. Yet most sober thinkers would admit that only in the extremest cases can resistance be justified. It may be that obedience is owed to the law on account of its utility, but no one will make every disutility in the law a ground for disobedience. It is not doubtful that a sense of the duty of obedience must be widespread, if stability is to be secured for the state. We are willing enough to admit that "force is no remedy," and that in general a certain senti- CONCLUSION 265 ment of loyalty is needful to the well-being and security of all governments. On what grounds then can we blame those who found expression for iden- tically the same views in the maxim that men must obey not only for wrath, but for conscience' sake? A modern thinker has declared that laws and govern- ments need some other sanction than that of military force. Those who endorse the aphorism "You can do anything with bayonets except sit on them" can have little reason for blaming Laud when he declares "There can be no firmness without law; and no laws can be binding if there be no conscience to obey them; penalty alone could never, can never do it¹." That government can worthily perform its function only when obedience is enshrined in the hearts of the governed, that laws are vain without loyalty, was the truth for which the men of the seventeenth century were contending, when they asserted that all resist- ance was damnable. That government of any kind was better than anarchy, they were well assured. Tyranny was in their eyes a more supportable con- dition than disorder. But whether or no it can be maintained that no caprices of autocracy and no oppression of democracy can make resistance to a King a right or defiance of Parliament (or the County Council) a duty, all will agree that the widespread prevalence of a law-abiding sentiment is essential to the stability of the state. It is well that most men should regard resistance to laws, however unjust, as practically prohibited by the moral law. If there be cases of resistance," they are best ignored. 1 Laud, Sermons (Works, 1. 112). (C 266 CONCLUSION Dangers of utilitarian A Now it is hard to imagine a more effectual theory. method of propagating this view than is the theory of Divine Right. Nor is it at all clear that the widespread popular acceptance of a purely utilitarian basis for obedience may not lead to great dangers in the future. Englishmen have cause for gratulation, that, in a time when the tendency is to loosen the bonds of allegiance and to proclaim (generally out of season) the morality of insurrection, there should still exist in the minds of the great majority of their countrymen a deep sense of the majesty of law and of the duty of obedience. This sense is the priceless legacy bequeathed to our own day by the believers in the Divine Right of Kings. AARON'S ROD BLOSSOMING OR JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 HAD fortune placed you with a listening ear in the parts of Westminster towards the close of the year of grace 1646, and you had encountered some Parliament man at discourse with a Divine of the Assembly, ten chances to one you would have heard from them high language about the Jus Divinum. But what did this jus divinum denote? A modern would surely reply, the Divine Right of Kings. But though that answer might be right, it would most probably be wrong. For it is only not certain, that the topic of their debate would have been the Divine Right of Ruling Elders, or some other part of the Presbyterial discipline, as against those who would allow it merely on grounds of expediency; or would deny the organic connections of the whole corporate system. As Robert Baillie complained a little earlier, “All of them were ever ready to admit Elders in a prudential way, but this seemed to us a most dangerous and unhappy way and therefore was peremptorily rejected. We trust to carie at last with the contentment of sundrie once opposite, and silence of all, their divyne and scripturall institution. This is a point of high consequence; and upon no other we expect so much difficulty, except alone on 268 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 Independencie; wherewith we purpose not to medle in haste, till it please God to advance our army, which we expect will much assist our arguments¹.” This was written at the end of 1643. But it was in 1646 that the issue of the Solemn League and Covenant came near to realization. Unfortunately for its upholders, it was the 'new model' that won the successes rather than the Scots' Army, called in by Pym. At the time when the fortunes of Parliament were at their lowest Pym had negotiated an alliance with the Scots, and the latter, who were as Baillie. said for a 'religious covenant,' bound the English by the terms of the Solemn League and Covenant to establishing uniformity in religion and Church govern- ment in the three kingdoms; and the reformation of religion in England and Ireland in doctrine, worship, discipline and government according to the word of God?, and the example of the best reformed Churches. Thus the Scots had grounds, so far as treaties are binding, to look for the establishment of the full Presbyterian system in this country. Nominally they did secure this by the ordinances passed from 1645–8, which set up the Directory of Public Worship, pro- hibited the Prayer-Book, and ordered the erection of the whole system of courts-though always under Parliamentary control. So far as the extirpation of Prelacy and the Book of Common Prayer, there was now no real difficulty on the Parliament side. But as 1 Baillie's Letters, 11. 111. 2 By this qualification inserted by Vane, he was held to have tricked the Scots and to have secured England against the absolute adoption of the Presbyterian model. JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 269 regards strict Presbyterianism the situation was quite different. Scotland was a foreign country and not all even on the Puritan side, who were opposed by the settlement by law established,' had a mind to see religion entirely dictated by an external power, with less right on its side than ever had the Papacy. Besides this, there was in Parliament a very strong lay element. Men like Selden, a convinced Erastian, were resolved not to subject the individual to any ecclesiastical authority without appeal. It was alleged that the Presbyterian system involved an inroad on the civil authority and was a menace to the natural liberty of the state. Besides this, there was the great fact of Independency. The army which was 'assisting the arguments' of the Divines was that of Fairfax and Cromwell. Between Indepen- dents and Presbyterians lay a gulf in theory wider than that between Presbyterianism and Episcopacy. The congregational theory, so abhorrent to the strict Presbyterians, asserted a doctrine of popular sovereignty. The whole body of the Christian people is in their view the subject of Christ's commission, while the Presbyterian doctrine was no less aristocratic than episcopacy; that is, it asserted, that the whole power of government was in the hands of the officers, although some of these officers, the elders, were lay- men. In the phrase of a later day the people have nothing to do with Church laws except to obey them, as indeed many from Pope to clericalist might say to-day. Again, Presbyterianism was a definite belief in an organic kingdom of the Church, with a hierarchy of courts, parochial, classical, synodal. 270 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 This is warranted not only by God's Positive Law, but even by Nature's Law. The Church is a company of people, who are not out-lawed by Nature. The visible Church being an Ecclesiastical Polity, and the perfection of all polities; doth com- prehend in it whatsoever is excellent in all other bodies. The Church must resemble the Common- wealth's government in things common to both and which have the same use in both. The Law of Nature directs unto diversities of Courts in the Commonwealth and the greater to have authority over the lesser." But Independency denied this. It declared each particular congregation to be an entire Church. Inside this limit it would admit the jus divinum of ruling elders and excommunication. But of the subjection of one Church to a group it knew nothing. Independency did not assert, as some suppose, the liberty of the individual; but it claimed the sovereignty for each particular Church ; and it included not merely the officers, but the whole body of members, as bearers of the power. It might claim similar freedom from the secular power; but it could not with its view of the rights of each congregation lay claim to more than tolera- tion. Anyhow, it was from their disagreement with the decisions of the Assembly, that some ministers were first called Dissenters, a term which has a different connotation from the older Non- Conformist. As Baillie complains: "The Indepen- dents here finding they have not the magistrate¹ so << A S 1 The magistrate here as in all the seventeenth century means the supreme civil authority. JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 271 [ obsequious as in New England turn their pens to take from the magistrate all power of taking any coercive order with the vilest heretics." Ultimately, although the Presbyterian system was set up by the authority of Parliament, it was only with such allowance of appeal to the civil power, as was highly distasteful to the true blue Presbyterian. Moreover the dislike of Englishmen to 'the holy discipline' prevented the system working to any extent even in the Commonwealth. With the Pro- tectorate Independency came to its own; and the watchword of Cromwell was universal toleration, ex- cept of course for Popery and prelacy. This liberty with its exceptions was laid down by him as 'a funda- mental' and was enshrined in the Instrument of Government and the Humble Petition and Advice. Both in detail and in principle this controversy is of high interest. It involves nearly all the topics which became important in the discussion of Divine Right. Even though it may seem to the student of political doctrines predominantly theological, enquiry will show this to be an error. So I must ask your forbearance, if the relevancy of some of this matter is at first sight a little doubtful. Let me read the title-pages of one or two of the books, rich and rare, like so many title-pages of that golden century. I will take three, the Jus Divinum of some London ministers, the Divine Right of Samuel Rutherford, and Aaron's Rod Blossoming of George Gillespie : "Jus Divinum Regiminis Ecclesiastici Or The Divine Right of Church-Government Asserted & 272 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 evidenced by the holy Scriptures According to the Light whereof (besides many particulars mentioned after the Preface) 1. The nature of a Divine Right is delineated 2. The Church government which is of Divine Right is described 3. The Description in the severall branches of it is explicated & confirmed 4. The Divine Right of Ecclesiastical Censures, Officers, & Ruling Assemblies is manifested. In all which it is apparent, That The Presbyterial Government, by Preaching & Ruling Presbyters, in Congregationall, Classicall, & Synodall Assemblies may lay the truest claime to a Divine Right, ac- cording to the Scriptures. By sundry Ministers of Christ in the City of London." Here is another:-"The Divine Right of Church Government & Excommunication or A Peaceable dispute for the perfection of the holy Scripture in point of Ceremonies & Church-Government, in which The removal of the Service-Book is justified, The six Books of Thos: Erastus against Excommunication are briefly examined, with a Vindication of that eminent Divine Theod: Beza against the Aspersions of Erastus, the Arguments of Mr William Pryn, Rich: Hooker, Dr Morton, Dr Jackson, Dr John Forbes, & the Doctors of Aberdeen; touching Will- Worship, Ceremonies, Imagery, Idolatry, Things Indifferent, An Ambulatory Government; the due & just Power of the Magistrate in matters of Religion, & the Arguments of Mr Pryn in so far JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 273 as they side with Erastus are modestly discussed. To which is added A brief Tractate of scandal, with an Answer to the New Doctrine of the Doctors of Aberdeen touching Scandal By Samuel Rutherford." And once again: "Aaron's Rod Blossoming or The Divine Ordinance of Church-Government Vindicated, So as the present Erastian Controversie concerning the distinction of Civill & Ecclesiasticall Government, Excomunication, & Suspension, is fully debated & discussed, from the Holy Scriptures, from the Jewish and Christian Antiquities, from the consent of latter Writers, from the true nature & rights of Magistracy, & from the groundlessness of the chiefe Objections made against the Presbyteriall Government in point of a domi- neering arbitrary unlimited power. By George Gillespie, Minister at Edinburgh For unto us a child is born, unto us a son is given & the government shall be upon his shoulders Isaiah 9. 6 Let the Elders that rule well be counted worthy of double honour And the spirits of the Prophets are subject to the Prophets for God is not the author of confusion, but of peace August. Lib contra Donatistos post collationem cap 4 Ne forte aut indisciplinata patientia foveat ini- quitatem, aut impatiens disciplina dissipet unitatem Published by authority." Now let me cite an extract from a protagonist on the other side. Mr Coleman of Norwich preached F. 18 274 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 before the House of Commons a sermon at its monthly fast entitled 'Hopes deferred and dashed,' which was the subject of much criticism and became a main ground of controversy. Passages in it afford good evidence both of his own views and those which he was opposing. Take, for instance, the following: "I could never see how two coordinate governments exempt from superiority and inferiority can be in one state, and in scripture no such thing is found, that I know of." He descants on the exorbitant pretensions of the ecclesiastical power over the civil, as shewn by the claims of Paul V in his controversy with the Venetian republic, and argues that a like danger rests in the Presbyterian claim. "This you will say was too high, but who shall hinder it, if Jus Divinum be the weight that sets it going." He goes on to assert the claim of all true Erastians in any age, that the civil magistrate is a governor in the Church, Church and State being assumed as aspects of one society. "A Christian magistrate as a Christian magistrate is a governor in the Church; all magistrates, it is true, are not Christians, but that is their fault; all should be and when they are, they are to manage their office under and for Christ. Christ hath placed governments in his Church; of other governments besides Magistracy, I find no insti- tution, of them I do in Romans xiii. I find all government given to Christ, and to Christ as mediator. And Christ as head of these given to the Church. To rob the Kingdom of Christ of the magistrate and his governing power I cannot JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 275 excuse, no, not from a kind of sacrilege, if the magistrate be his¹" Another writer asks, "Why should a Common- wealth be denied the appellation and privilege of a Church?" In Jus Divinum the same view is stated from the standpoint of an opponent. "That grosse absur- dities would follow, should not these two Societies, viz: Church and Commonwealth be acknowledged to be really and essentially distinct from one another. Then the Commonwealth as the Commonwealth is the Church, and the Church as the Church is the Commonwealth. Then Ecclesia and Repub- lica are termini convertibiles. Then all that are members of the Commonwealth eo nomine become members of the Church. Then the Common- wealth being formally the same with the Church is as Commonwealth the mystical body of Christ. Then the officers of the Church are the officers of the Com- monwealth, the power of the Keyes gives them right to the Civil Sword, and consequently the Ministers of the Gospel, as Ministers are Justices of the Peace, Judges, Parliament men, all of which how absurd Let the world judge?." It was to this claim to the identification of Church and Commonwealth that Presbyterianism was essentially opposed. William Hussey at the close of his Plea for Christian Magistracy puts the Erastian case. Let these be the questions: 1. Whether Christ gave any more government 1 Hopes Deferred and Dashed, pp. 26, 27. 2 Jus Divinum, 83. CC 18-2 276 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 to Ministers than is contained in preaching and baptizing? Neg. 2. Whether he gave any government to the Church at all? Neg. 3. Whether a Commonwealth professing the Gospel be a visible Church? Ass. 4. Whether any member of such a Common- wealth rightly ordered where he hath his consent to making Civill Laws may hold himselfe free from such Laws in matters of conscience? Neg. 5. Whether the people have any power to choose their ministers? Neg." Reflection on this controversy will help us to understand the atmosphere in which men conducted the discussion of the Divine Right of Kings. That doctrine is not a monster dropped from the blue to assist the advocates of tyranny. Its shape bears witness to the temper in which all these topics were argued. That was the great age of Jus Divinum. We must set the Divine Right of Kings beside the Divine Right of Ruling Elders, of the Papal autocracy, of episcopal orders, and even of the common man. It is the notion of some inherent claim above all in- stitutional and civil arrangements. In the debate at Putney in 1647 Colonel Rainborow, the mouthpiece of the Levellers, explained in words which even now might teach us a little. "I think that the poorest hee that is in England hath a life to live, as the greatest he; and therefore, truly, Sir, I think its cleare that every man that is to live under a Govern- ment ought firstly by his own consent to put himself under that Government, and I do think, that the Judg JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 277 poorest man in England is not at all bound in a strict sense to that he hath not had a voice to putt himself under." Here he asserts as before all laws and apart from any rights of property, the Divine or natural and inherent right of man as man. Naturally he was opposed by the whole weight of those who stood for that which was to be the ruling principle for centuries, the Divine Right not of Kings, but of the propertied classes; and Ireton at once replied: "Give me leave to tell you that if you make this the rule, I think you must fly for refuge to an Ab- solute Natural Right and you must deny all Civil Right; I am sure it will come to that in the con- sequence¹." Gillespie puts the same in his preface: "To the candid reader. This truth that Jesus Xt is a king and hath a kingdom and government in his Church distinct from the kingdoms of this world and from the civil government hath this commendation and Character above all other truthes that Xt himself suffered to the death for it, and sealed it with his blood; for it may be observed from the story of his passion, this was the only point of his accusation that was confessed and avouched by him- self, was most aggravated, prosecuted and driven home by the Jews, was prevalent with Pilate as the cause for condemning him to die, and was mentioned also in the superscription upon his Cross.... This was the thing which Herod and Pilate and many other princes, potentates and states do look upon 1 The Clarke Papers, 1. 301. 278 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 with so much fear and jealousy as another govern- ment coordinate with the civil.' >> Or as Rutherford says: "If the Church be a PERFECT, visible, society, house, city and kingdom, Jesus Christ in esse et operari; then the Magistrate when he cometh to be Christian, to help and nourish the Church, as a father he cannot take away and pull the keys out of the hands of the stewards." Secondly, it is well to regard a little the Latin form of the phrase. Better than the English 'right,' the word 'Jus' brings before us the predominantly legalist atmosphere, in which politics were debated for so long. Partly this is due to the influence of the Roman civil law, and to the fact that the classical maxims alike of popular and absolutist theories were drawn from thence, such as 'quod omnes tangit ab omnibus approbetur,' 'quod principi placuit legis habet vigorem,' and so forth. Feudalism also had tended to the treating of all political prin- ciples as legal rights, and indeed as partly private. That was at the back of the contract theory of the origin of the state. Contracts are binding only by law. The original compact could not have been plausibly propounded, except to an age so deeply steeped in legalist feeling, that it was unable to picture a society anterior to all law. Thus it was forced to the doctrine of a natural law and a natural state above and behind all laws; and if needful over- riding them. So in regard to the Divine Right of Kings. Its purpose, and indeed its power no less than its weakness, were to assert for monarchy some claim higher than that of mere expediency, to found it either JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 279 on a direct command of God, or upon natural rights, independent of mere consent. The notion of funda- mental law, superior to all statutes, runs through the whole controversy of the seventeenth century. It was put into the forefront of the case for King Charles by Edward Hyde. It governs the attack on Strafford by Pym; and it is at the bottom of the notion of indefeasible hereditary right. Neither English nor French believers in legitimism would have asserted, that the King's power of the law could set aside the order of succession, though the will of Louis XIV. went near to it. In one aspect the theory of Divine Right is an attempt to set the King above all positive law, to treat him as sovereign in the Austinian sense. In another it is an attempt to set up hereditary, absolute monarchy, as a funda- mental law of the state, beyond the competence even of the Crown in Parliament to change. The same can be seen in the dislike of the Presbyterian party to all attempts to justify their system on any other footing than that of the Jus Divinum. They feared, moreover, that such admission might bring in its train many other offices, which they hoped they had abolished for ever. They dared not admit any such principles of developement, or the right of the Christian Society, as seemed involved in the Roman or Epis- copal system. They were forced to claim that "Ruling Elders distinct from all preaching elder Deacons are a Divine ordinance in the Church of God now under the New Testament¹." The claim is that ruling 1 The Divine Right of this Church Officer, the mere Ruling Elder, is much questioned and doubted by some because they find 280 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 elders are an inherent element in a Church 'simply and strictly so called.' So with the Divine Right of Kings. In the strictest view monarchy is inherent in the idea of the state, a deduction from its unity; other systems tend to anarchy; although it is with many rather a sovereign one or number, that is so held to be inherent, not in all states a hereditary king. Divine Right always implies something resting on some basis higher than immediate needs. For in any other sense Divine Right is a meaningless phrase. To all, who are not atheists, any right that is real must be in some sense divine, and government an ordinance of God. To see clearly the implications of a doctrine, it is commonly useful to learn what is the theory which it combats. The Divine Right of Kings or Bishops or Presbyterianism contradicts the notion that it is a merely human right arising out of consent and circumstance; and may therefore be dispensed with. In the case of kingship the essence of the not the Scriptures speaking so fully and clearly of the Ruling Elder, as of the Preaching Elder and Deacon. By others it is flatly denied and opposed, as by divers that adhere too tenaciously to the Erastian and Prelaticall principles; who yet are willing to account the assistance of the Ruling Elder in matter of Church government to be a very Prudentiall way. But if mere Prudence be counted once as a sufficient foundation for a distinct kind of Church officer we shall open a door for invention of Church officers at pleasure; then welcome Commissioners and Committeemen, &c.; yea let us return to our vomit and resume Prelates, Deans, Arch- deacons, Chancellors, officials, for Church Officers; and where shall we stop? "Who but Christ Jesus himself can stablish new officers in His Church?" The whole Puritan idea encountered by Hooker is in these last words: "Certainly, if Scriptures lay not before us grounds more than prudential for the Ruling Elders, it were better never to have mere Ruling Elders in the Church.” JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 281 My doctrine is the sense that kings are immediate su- periors under God, and do not derive their power by the mediation of Popes or anyone else. It is an anti- clerical weapon framed to assert the inherent right of the secular power, and to place it parallel with, instead of subordinate to the Pope. For the Papacy, with its claim to a jure divino sovereignty, tended to deny such rights in any real sense to the sister power. Moreover in its conflicts with the Imperial Power, the Papacy was strangely assisted by the Roman Civil Law; for the lex regia, of which it takes note, while it gives to the Emperor absolute power, gives it to him only as a delegate of the sovereign people. Thus, however great power be claimed for the Emperor, it was always possible to say that he had it only by a voluntary transference from the Roman people, and not directly from God. In the translation of the Empire from Greeks to Romans, when the Pope put the crown on the head of Charles the Great, and earlier in the deposition of Childeric with (at least) the concurrence of Pope Zacharias, there were other instances to the hands of Papalists, which, skilfully manipulated, fortified the claim to treat kings and emperors as reigning not indeed without the grace of God, but with that grace me- diated through the ecclesiastical authority. We can trace the beginnings of the two views in some of the expressions used in the conflict between Hildebrand and Henry IV.; they develope in the struggle between the great Hohenstaufen Emperors and the Papacy; and it flowers into a great literature in the final medieval contest between Pope John XXII. and 282 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 Lewis of Bavaria. The Reformation developed the contention on both sides, though the doctrine of the 'indirect' power of the Papacy, as expounded by Bellarmine, was an attempt to safeguard the latter from a mere claim to universal monarchy, and to admit, however meagrely, the inherent and non- ecclesiastical character of the civil state. The gist of the doctrine of the Divine Right of Kings lies in this anti-clerical, anti-Papalist character. It might almost be said that the anti-constitutional side, as developed by James I. or Filmer, was an after- thought. But in England the King had made himself the champion of the Prayer-Book and died the martyr of episcopacy. Hence in his son's reign it is the clergy who were the foremost supporters of the doctrine, and hence it came by many to be thought of as their property. It was a strange irony that owing to the great Rebellion this theory, anti-clerical in essence, should have taken on a sort of clericalist tinge, which in popular apprehension it never lost. It was not strange that James II. failed in his attempt to use it as a means of Papalist reaction; he made the not uncommon error of taking the logical meaning of the theory when stated in words, as though it were equivalent to its practical import. In words the Divine Right of Kings implied sheer absolutism with the exception of the succession; in reality it was an assertion of the inherent right of the civil as against the ecclesiastical authority. James II. tried or was thought to be trying to use the absolutist theory in order to restore the very power, that of the Pope, against which it had been forged. Naturally he JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 283 failed and learned to his cost that theories must be interpreted according, not to the most that they can logically be held to imply, but to the atmosphere in which they were developed. The essence then of the Divine Right claim is, that it asserts an inherent, underived (so far as men are concerned) authority for civil society. In its later stages the notion of direct Divine institution sinks, if not out of sight, at least out of significance, as compared with the sense, that it is Divine because it is natural. In the argument with the supporters of the original compact, the Royalists were constantly claiming that the state is a natural growth, as against their opponents, to whom it was a manu- factured article. In this controversy of the Presby- terians with their Independent or Erastian adver- saries, it is curious to see how often Rutherford and others are led to speak of the Church as organically articulated. There is another passage with which the transition from Divine to natural right is con- sciously attempted. It is worth quoting. "Is there not a jus divinum in the light of Nature? In the present case of Church government that which is agreeable to the true light of nature must needs. be confessed to be jure divino. Though light of Nature be but dim, yet it will lend some help in this particular, e.g. Light of Nature teaches (1) that as every Society in the world hath a distinct govern- ment of its own within itself, without which it could not subsist, so must the Church, which is a Society, have its own distinct government within itself, without which it cannot subsist no more than any T 284 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 other Society; (2) that in all matters of difference the lesser number in every Society should give way to the greater, and the matters controverted and concluded in by the major part, else there could never be an end; and why not so in the Church¹?" Here it seems is the Divine Right of majority rule. But it is obvious that, when we have got so far as this, Divine Right will soon become the name for natural right, and the transition to modern politics begins; unless, indeed, that be held to lie in the change from natural right to pure utilitarianism. For the notion at bottom of the Divine Right or the natural rights theory is the same. It asserts either for the King or for the state or for the individual or for the general will or for the right to work, to a living wage, or equality of opportunity, or what not, some supreme overriding principle, which is superior to all institutional rights and ought to be their criterion, not their creation. On reflection all who try to see in politics some grounds other than those of mere historical developement or immediate expediency, will be found in some degree to share in the notion. of natural rights. Let us now pass on to some further thoughts, which the controversy for the Divine Right of Pres- bytery suggests. Much light is thrown by it on the other controversy for the Divine Rights of Kings. Martin Luther used to boast, and with some justice, that no one had done more to promote high views of princely rule than himself. By this he meant the power of the territorial prince, not that of the imperial 1 Jus Divinum, 11. JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 285 government. This expansion he effected in more ways than one. By introducing further division within the Empire he shattered all hope of any real control of the small states by the central power, and the local princelings were free to develope into sovereign states, aided by the force of religion. Secondly, he shattered or enormously weakened the one serious force that could hold in check the rising authority of the state; while the functions of government were enormously widened with the growth of modern ideas. Thirdly, in his Appeal to the German nobility he turned deliberately to that power, the lay prince, which, no less than the hierarchy, existed within the Church, and sought its aid for the work of Refor- mation. Thus all competing agencies were shattered, and the whole power given into the hands of the 'godly prince'; and the clergy (as Luther afterwards began to see) reduced to a lower position than they had held for centuries. Himself a revolutionary, Luther had scarcely any notion of popular freedom. At least from the time of the Peasants' Revolt he threw all his influence on the side of the territorial prince. So far as concerns religion the theory of this revolution was set forth in the theses of Erastus, and was shared substantially by nearly all the Re- formers, whether English or Continental. Between Luther, Laud, and even John Knox, there is less to choose in this matter than is usually imagined; all allowed very large powers to the 'godly prince,' and claimed it to be his duty to suppress idolatry. None, not even Knox, had reached to the point of con- ceiving the Church and the State as two distinct 286 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 societies; and however high they might desire in practice to place the persuasive function of the hier- archy, whether Prelatic or Presbyterian, all regarded the lay power in a much higher light than had the mediæval ecclesiastical theory. England especially was dominated by the notion of Church and State, as different aspects or departments in one society, and the authoritative position of the civil magistrate was proclaimed against Papist and Brownist alike in the Ecclesiastical Polity of Richard Hooker. In the latter half of the sixteenth century the Presbyterians began to develope the notion of the two kingdoms, as stated by Andrew Melville in his famous sermon before King James: Therefore, Sir, as divers times I have told you, so now again I must tell you there are two kings and two kingdoms in Scotland, that is King James. the head of the Commonwealth, and there is Christ. Jesus the King of the Church, whose subject King James VI. is, and of whose kingdom he is not. a king, nor a lord, nor a head, but a member." Robert Browne, the founder or forerunner of Sepa- ratism, asserted also the entire independence of the two spheres in his tract Reformation without Tarrying for any. In similar case were the Anabaptists. Thomas Cartwright and those of the Puritan party who attempted to set up the Presbyterian discipline, and to force it on the people through Parliament, did indeed set up the doctrine of the two kingdoms, and thereby astounded a man like Archbishop Whitgift, to whom such a notion seemed inconceivable. The (C JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 287 other side, whether Presbyterian or Jesuit, regarded the high notion of the sacredness and omni-com- petence of the state as "Machiavellistica et Turcica." Probably it was his sense of this doctrine of the distinctness of the two societies as an inroad upon the sovereignty of the state, that led James I. to his utterance that "Presbyterianism agreeth as well with monarchy as God with the devil." He may, of course, have meant thereby only the same thing as 'no bishop no king,' that unless in each diocese there be a monarch, you can hardly keep one in the king- dom. Yet it is more likely that this phrase referred, not to the form of government of the Presbyterian system, but to its claim to inherent independence as of Divine Right. . Yet it is in this very claim that lies the service to true politics performed by the Presbyterian zealots. With the Divine Right of Kings in its developed and strict meaning few now will sympathise. Yet we may see in it one of the most potent factors in the developement of the modern world, if we regard its true objective, that of asserting, as against eccle- siastical pretensions, the Divine and inherent rights of the civil power, and the natural necessity of political society. Nor is there any danger to the free- dom of the Churches in this, provided the civil power makes no attempt at enforcing any single system of religion. On the other hand the Presbyterians and the Papalists were right in asserting the positive limits set to all state autocracy by the claims of religion. No Christian can logically believe in the entire supremacy of the civil power in the same way 288 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 of as a member of the Pagan Empire could hold to it. The doctrine of the two kingdoms carried the Pres- byterians to a higher point than the Papalist of the preceding age, for it enabled them to assert what was in theory a claim to complete independence, without denying the rights of the civil power or asserting that its authority existed only by grace the hierarchy. Even in regard to the establishment of a single religion they had reached in theory a point not very far removed from that of the poli- tiques in France. For the writers of Jus Divinum and The Divine Right of Presbyterian Government and Aaron's Rod Blossoming, while claiming for the civil magistrate the right to persecute, are at pains to assert that he is to persecute for civil ends, in order to promote the peace of the Commonwealth, and not because it is God's ordinance. They claimed that the King, as King, was an officer of the Church, and would have nothing of the "mixta persona" doctrine so popular with the Royalists. They gave up the notion that we have need to consider only one society which Church and State are separate aspects, or (if you confine your attention to the officers) different departments. They attempted to claim, at least in the English controversy, a purely ecclesiastical cha- racter for excommunication, and to exempt it from civil penalties. Yet they committed one fatal error. The real difficulty had been stated by Erastus in the previous century. Provided the Divine Right of the Church be of the highest kind, if only one religion be tolerated, [and neither Presbyterians nor Erastians contemplated anything but a state homogeneous in JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 289 religion,] then even censures merely ecclesiastical will produce dangerous results. Let me quote one passage: "He sayth the Minister is punishable by the Law of the land; here is the difficulty; if the Minister and Elder have power given of Christ to censure all Christians, and they use this power according as Christ hath committed to them, what is the magistrate above these officers, and can he make laws to bound and limit the laws of Christ? If they have power to bind may the magistrate loose? If they use this power may the Christian magistrate punish them? This were to allow Christ a very meane kingdom; that his owne subjects should control him; but you will say, if he commit any- thing worthy confiscation of goods or life or liberty, the magistrate may inflict it upon him; but, if he attempt to doe it unjustly, he is ungodly and the Ministers and Elders will excommunicate him, and their coordination maketh them their own judges. As soone as the magistrate shall distast any of their +ions, presently he is ungodly and send him to Satan, and then what party the eloquence of the clergy may find against the magistrate, if he should go about to restrain them, let wise men judge'." This argument is perfectly just on one condition, that only one religion be allowed in the state. It was their passionate intolerance that was the error of the Presbyterian party, no less than that of many of their opponents. They were not wrong in attacking, so far as they did attack, the Divine Right of the State to an authority, which included ecclesiastical jurisdiction. 1 Hussey, A Plea for Christian Magistracie, 7. HEAD F. 19 290 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 (C "" What they asserted is only what must be asserted by any religion, indeed by any moralist who be- lieves in the individual conscience, that there must be cases in which we must obey God rather than man. Mere civil law, even though set up by the general will, can never be absolute. It is the service of the martyrs of all ages and in every cause to say to the overweening claims to authority of the political ruler, from Nebuchadnezzar to Nero and thence to Bismarck, as they see the rising tide of Machiavellian statesmanship: "Hitherto shalt thou go and no further; and here shall thy proud waves be stayed." Where they were wrong was in the belief which they shared with many of the adver- saries, that religious toleration was a civil danger; and that while the State is distinct from the Church, it is nevertheless bound to take its orders therefrom in the paramount topic of what religion to prescribe. They were right in asserting that there were two kingdoms; where they were wrong was in denying that there might be twenty-two. Religious bodies in a state are harmless, if they are numerous. In the same way the civil ruler was right in claiming independence of the ecclesiastical authority, he was wrong in denying the distinctness of the Church, and in attempting to proscribe religions which he did not like; or, as in the words of one German prince- ling, that the "conscience of his subjects belonged to him." It would appear further that some at least of the Presbyterians understood the implications of this doctrine; i.e. that it does not merely concern the JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 291 relations between two societies, Church and State, each unlike any other, but rather the nature of human society in general. Is not all larger society composed of a myriad number of groups; and has not each of these groups, in so far as it be permanent, some real inherent power, which is something more than a mere delegation, which is recognized by the superior power, but not created by it? As it is put in Jus Divinum: (( 'It is granted that classicall or synodall authority cannot be by scripture introduced over a particular Church in a privative or destructive way to that power which God hath bestowed upon it, but con- trarily it is affirmed that all the power of assemblies which are above particular congregations is conno- tative and perfective to the power of the inferior congregations. "It is granted that the Highest Ecclesiasticall assembly in the world cannot require from the lowest a subordination absolute, and pro arbitrio at their own mere will and pleasure but only in some respect, subordination absolute being only to the Law of God laid down in Scripture; we detest Popish tyranny which claims a power of giving their will for a Law¹." The Presbyterians, however, did not see; and 1 Jus Divinum, p. 230. Cf. also the following passage from Baillie's Letters: "That which grieved Mr David was the matter of Church Sessions, which he maintains to have no divine right in particular, but to be only as a committee from the Presbyterie, to execute these arts of jurisdiction, which the Presbytery thinks fitt to commit thereto." III. 59, 60. A great deal of controversy takes place on this point, whether the Church Session has inherent or only delegated power. 19-2 292 JUS DIVINUM IN 1646 G until recent years few who have followed them were able to see the vast implications of their principle. That is the real crux of the question raised between the advocates of the two forms of the doctrine of Divine Right. Is the civil society a single power from which all rights proceed by delegation? In this case there is no real check upon tyranny, how- ever democratic the form of government. Or is the state merely the final bond of a multitude of bodies, Churches, trade unions, families, all possessing in- herent life, a real thing, recognized and regulated by the government, but no more the creation of its fiat, than are individual persons? That is the problem raised in the form suited to those days by this strange controversy about the rights of ruling elders. Once more is the same problem being raised, though in a different form and with wider issues. Religious bodies and their claims are ever with us; but a whole com- plex of converging forces, economic, social and political and moral make it urgent. I cannot develope it here without passing beyond historical frontiers. If you would like to study the topic in the abstract, Maitland's Introduction to Gierke's Medieval Po- litical Theories is a good beginning. In the concrete perhaps you will find it not unfruitful to study some book such as that on The Real Democracy, edited by Mr J. E. F. Mann, or some of those writers who deal with Guild-Socialism or Syndicalism. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM WAS Erastus an Erastian? The question is not superfluous. For party names are commonly mis- nomers. And while there is no more frequent term of ecclesiastical vituperation than Erastianism, yet it is hardly unfair to say that many of those who make use of it appear to think that the continual employment of Erastus' name, or its derivative, is sufficient compliment to his memory to excuse igno- rance of his life, his writings, and the controversy which was their occasion¹. But we cannot under- stand Erastianism in vacuo apart from the influences which produced it, and the name alone is presump- tive evidence of some relation between the doctrine and its alleged author. It may, therefore, be not superfluous to inquire a little into the influences under which the notions of Erastus were formed, and thus to gather their true import. Such an investi- gation may throw light on the problem of the relation between Church and State, as it presents itself to 1000 1 I find, for instance, in one of the most famous of theological encyclopaedias (Herzog) a statement to the effect that Erastus founded a sect in this country. 294 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM the minds of those who disbelieve in liberty of con- science. For, as we shall see, Erastus was concerned solely with the question as to the proper method and authority for enforcing ecclesiastical discipline in a State which was uniform in its religion'. He was not concerned either with the question as to the right to proclaim truth, or as to the coercive religious authority of a State which allowed more than one or persecuted the true faith. His views might have reference to modern Russia, but except constructively can have no bearing on English ecclesiastical con- troversies of to-day. He is concerned with moral discipline, not doctrine; with a uniform, not a tole- rant polity. But it may be convenient first of all to detail the facts of his life". Thomas Lüber was born at Baden, in Switzerland, on September 7, 1524. He thus came under the influence of the Zwinglian form of the Reformation, and at no time, so far as can be 1 Canon Perry's assertion that Erastus "wrote a treatise with the object of proving that in Christian commonwealths the secular authorities are the proper TEACHERS and administrators of religious discipline," appears to me a singularly unfortunate way, to say the least, of describing the Explicatio. Student's Eng. Church Hist. II. 12. 2 For these facts I would refer the reader especially to M. Bonnard's thesis, Thomas Eraste et la discipline ecclésiastique, Lausanne 1894. This is an admirable work based on manuscript as well as other sources, in which the author exhibits the whole growth of Erastianism, properly so called, and moreover gives in the footnotes frequent quotations from unpublished letters, which are most valuable. The chapter Die Kämpfe wegen der Kirchen- zucht in Sudhoff's C. Olevianus und Z. Ursinus' Leben und ausgewählte Schriften' is also valuable in a similar way, though short and very hostile to Erastus. I shall cite these books as B. and S. respectively. ( ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 295 proved, inclined to any other¹, nor does there appear to be any evidence that his politico-ecclesiastical notions were directly derived from Luther, as has been suggested; the presumption, as will be seen, is the other way. In 1542 he matriculated at Basel, translating his name Lüber into Erastus, without the grammatical error which was the hard fate of the great scholar of whom he was so nearly a name- sake². He attached himself to the philosophical faculty and studied classics, mathematics, and theo- logy. After two years a visitation of the plague led to his quitting Basel. Thence he went to Italy, where he appears to have been supported by a rich patron, spending three years at Bologna and six at Padua, and greatly distinguishing himself by his studies in medicine. In Italy he married a lady of noble birth, who, when a widow, was to marry the man, also an Italian, through whose action alone the fame of Erastus has survived. After this he spent some years as court physician at Henneberg. He rapidly attained distinction as an exponent of the most enlightened medical science of the time, and wrote works on this subject, larger and more numerous than the little volume by which we remember him. He opposed the views of Paracelsus, and was a great assailant of impostures, such as alchemy and astro- logy, though he was a believer in witchcraft, and did ¹ I say this, assuming that the question as to his alleged Arianism is decided in his favour. The very interesting letter of Silvanus reproaching Erastus with having been the cause of his apostasy, does not really contain any evidence as to the unorthodoxy of Erastus. S. App. B. p. 507. 2 Cf. Jebb, Rede Lecture, 'Desiderius Erasmus.' 296 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM not in that matter rise above his age¹. But his ability, at once general and special, was recognized by contemporary opinion, whether that opinion were friendly or hostile-and it was both. Beza at Geneva was a friend, and apparently remained so, in spite of the controversy. Bullinger and Gwalther at Zurich were not merely supporters, but intimates, into whose ears the troubles of the libertarians at Heidelberg were continually poured. And Erastus, universally recognised as the chief of his party, appears to have had one great quality of a leader, the power of at- tracting loyalty. Yet on the other hand he would appear to have been a mark for virulent hostility, and to have been treated with as much contumely by his opponents as Erastianism has been since hist time by many who have hardly heard his name². But, at any rate, he was an outstanding man as a scientific physician. And whether or no we agree with his views on ecclesiastical politics, there can be 1 This may be the cause why a modern writer tells us that he was not an enlightened man in the modern sense of the term. Personally I should say that in the only sense of the term which we have a right to apply to the sixteenth century Erastus was eminently an Aufgeklärter. 2 Cf. Bullinger's remarks to Dathenus, "Modestiam ergo in te, mi frater Dathene, requiro, ne forte non sine causa eam nobis iniicias cogitationem si quando potestatem consequamini in Ec- clesia excommunicandi, fore ut omnes, quotquot per omnia vestra non approbarint, atheismi sitis condemnaturi ac expulsuri ad ipsos usque religionis nostrae hostes truculentissimos." Explicatio, 358; and Gwalther to Beza, "Quid vero de iis, qui Heydelbergae hanc causam agunt, sperare possimus, satis nos una haec audacia admonet, qua suae sententiae subscribere nolentes atheismi ac- cusant, et eos quidem viros in quorum fide, doctrina, moribus nemo bonus aliquid unquam desideravit." Ibid. 379, 80. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 297 no doubt of the skill and lucidity with which they were propounded. In 1557 he received the appointment which was to fling him into such bitter controversy, and to carry his name down the centuries. His presence being sought at the courts of Dresden and Heidel- berg alike, Erastus preferred the offer of the Elector Otto Henry, who was founding a chair of therapeutics, and remained at Heidelberg until, three years before his death, he was driven out by an 'Erastian' religious revolution. His energies found scope in the work, so necessary, so arduous, and so frequent in universities, of drawing up new statutes and a fresh programme of studies. He was elected Rector of the University in 1558, and became also a member of the church council of Heidelberg, a post which he voluntarily resigned in 1564. This is some evidence of the weight he was already acquiring as a theologian. But we have more. The situation of religious parties at Heidelberg, when Erastus arrived there, was briefly this: The Elector was a tolerant Lutheran, and Heidelberg appears to have been a refuge for theo- logical eccentrics of all nations, just as in our century London has been for political exiles¹. In the city there were two parties, Lutheran and Swiss, in 1 Bullinger argues that Erastus' services to the exiles should be a good reason for treating him with consideration. "Si fideles labores eius non praecessissent, tibi aliisque exulibus vix tale patuisset hospitium, quali nunc frueris una cum aliis multis. Beneficia eius tum in peregrinos tum domesticos collocata, eruditio item eius eximia et singularis, denique vera eius et sincera pietas, ob quae a bonis laudatur omnibus, aliud sane ei destinarat prae- mium, quam nunc ipsi rependitur a nonnullis." Explicatio, 366. 298 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM sympathy. These again were divided into groups, the former into the strict party, and those who followed Melanchthon, the latter into Calvinists and Zwing- lians, of which last Erastus was the most distinguished lay representative. Each party in turn, we may say, gained the upper hand, tolerant Lutheran, Zwinglian, Calvinist, strict Lutheran. The Erastian controversy was the result of the conflict, closed as it was by a Lutheran revolution and the retirement of Erastus. The latter had early won the hatred of the Lutherans by his successful support of the claims of a certain Etienne Sylvius, who, presumably a Zwinglian him- self, refused to do the bidding of the theological professor Hesshus and attack the sacramental doc- trines of Catholics and Zwinglians alike. In 1559 Otto Henry died, and was succeeded by Frederic III., a man of austere piety and strongly anti-Lutheran in sympathy. Colloquies took place in 1560 between the parties, and Erastus secured the enthusiastic praise of the great Calvinist Olevi- anus, who declared that few theologians were his equals in learning and wisdom, and looked to gaining much advantage from his support'. He was so successful that in August the Elector definitely introduced the 'reformed' faith, and proscribed 1 "Utinam vir ille totum se abderet sacris literis ad quas pro- pendet eius zelus, sed nescio quo pacto vix medendi vocationem audet relinquere, neque reliqui senatores ecclesiastici tam sunt cordati ut eum extrudant in messem, licet maxima et pene incredi- bili ministrorum penuria laboremus, ipse vero incredibili dexteritate polleat. Ausim dicere Germaniam paucissimos habere tantae doctrinae et prudentiae viros theologos." Olevianus to Calvin, B. App. II. p. 203. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 299 alike Catholicism and Lutheranism'. In 1563 the 'reformed' catechism of Heidelberg, composed by Olevianus and Ursinus, was introduced, being sup- ported by Erastus, who is the probable author of the Büchlein vom Brotbrechen. Erastus also took part in the colloquy of Maulbronn (1564), and published two other books on the Ubiquitarian controversy. As has been seen, the anti-Lutheran Protestant party had triumphed in Heidelberg, and won the Elector to their exclusive support. It was natural that, so much being accomplished, those who looked to Geneva for guidance should desire the introduc- tion of that famous 'discipline,' which was for them almost the raison d'être of religious organization. By discipline is meant an organized Presbyterian police des mœurs, beginning with the parish or church as its unit, with a hierarchy of consistory, classis, provincial and national synods, all ecclesias- tical, all claiming to be jure divino, independent of the civil power, occupied in pronouncing sentence of excommunication upon all those persons whose lives, in some small² or large particular, had failed to meet with the approval of ruling elders, or did not submit to a friendly admonition or repent in time. This 1 The author of the historical introduction to the tercentenary edition of the Catechism is of opinion (pp. 43—5) that the Elector did not intend to break with the followers of Melanchthon or the confession of Augsburg, even by the introduction of the Catechism, but that intolerant Lutheranism refused to regard him any longer as anything but an enemy. 2 It is fair to say 'small,' for one of Beza's arguments for the necessity of the discipline is that the magistrate, if left to himself, might leave unpunished some offendiculum. Tractatus, 120. 300 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM was claimed to be of Christ's institution; if not a necessary note of a true church, at least its most desirable accompaniment. It flourished in Geneva, its birthplace, in the Netherlands, in France, and was for centuries the most overwhelming ecclesias- tical force in Scotland'. The divine right of the discipline was the occasion first under Queen Eliza- beth, and then under the Westminster Assembly, of furious controversy in this country. Now the life of Erastus might be described as a polemic against ruling elders. It was only in subservience to his design of protesting against what seemed to him a monstrous usurpation of arbitrary power that he developed so far as he developed at all-his theory as to the functions of the civil magistrate. It appears that so early as 1556 a suggestion was made for the introduction of excommunicating elders into Heidelberg. This, however, came to nothing. But Heidelberg being a camp of refuge, there came exiles from France and the Netherlands anxious, regardless of the carnal appetites of the population, to see this holy inquisitorial system at its work of saving souls and protecting the sacra- ment². Erastus declares that, irrespective of right, it seemed to him highly inexpedient to set about excommunicating a population who in reality needed conversion, for not one-thirtieth of the people were Ja 1 Buckle considered the effects of the system worse than those of the Spanish Inquisition. 2 Cf. Bullinger to Beza, Explicatio, 371, "Non sine causa mur- murant quod omnia fere administrat Princeps per Niderlandos sive Belgas, homines peregrinos, suis illis penitus praeteritis." ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 301 in sympathy with the new order of things¹; and it was scarcely politic to employ spiritual censures for not being good Calvinists against persons who had not yet become Calvinists at all-for the jurisdiction claimed was to be unaccompanied by civil penalties. Probably, however, Erastus did not believe in this limitation, for he declared in a letter that the disci- pline would be no whit better than the Spanish Inquisition, except that its supporters would hardly dare to quaff the cup of human blood for which they seemed to be thirsting². At first, Erastus tells us, he had accepted the prevailing views as to excommunication, as a divinely appointed prerogative of the Church, but when he came to study the authorities, ancient, mediæval, and modern, he saw that the reasons given were flimsy; then betaking himself to Scripture he found no sanction at all for it there, and the texts alleged in its support patient of, and indeed needing, a different interpretation³. Having thus convinced himself that the belief in ruling elders was a 'fond thing vainly invented,' 1 Explicatio, preface. Even Sudhoff (369) in this respect appears to side with Erastus, much as he dislikes his principles: "Die Ungunst der Verhältnisse, namentlich die aus Unverstand und Lauheit hervorgehende Opposition in den Heidelberger Kreisen des Hofes, der Universität und der Bürgerschaft, die Haltung der Züricher, trugen dabei weitaus die grösste Schuld, wenn auch zugegeben werden muss, dass eine Kirche welche, wie die pfälzische, zumeist durch den staatlichen Impuls entstand und gehalten wurde, in der ersten Zeit kein günstiger Boden für ein schnelles Gedeihen der Disciplin sein konnte." 2 B. p. 73, n. 1; cf. also p. 65, n. 2. 3 Preface to Explicatio. 302 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM Erastus was ready to do battle for the liberty of the subject and of the prince, in a word for the laity, against a clericalist party. "New presbyter is but old priest writ large" is the import of Erastianism as expounded by its author, save that he would class with the clergy those ecclesiastically-minded laymen who were likely to be eager elders. He complained that all the changes at Heidelberg were really the work of a camarilla of five men, foreigners, who had the ear of the prince and turned him to their own ends¹. Of these the most important were Dathenus, a Netherlander, and Olevianus, a refugee from Trier, who arrived in 1560, and at once raised the question and wrote to the Genevan authorities to ask advice. By 1562 he was able to report that the Elector re- cognised the necessity of introducing the discipline. Apparently, however, the matter was not easy, for he speaks of the opposition of those who cared for human wisdom, by which is probably meant Erastus, and of lawyers, who at Heidelberg, as later in England, opposed the introduction of a power which seemed to trench upon their own prerogatives?. Consiliarii omnes, nobiles, ignobiles, populus, aula, adver- santur, illi tamen fortiores sunt omnibus." B. 76, n. 3. Clandestina ineunt iam etiam cum principe concilia, qui in hoc totus est, ut contra voluntatem filiorum, conciliariorum, ministrorum, subditorum omnium, exceptis belgis et gallis, nescio quam disciplinam instituat.” S. 341, note. "Princeps pergit cudere excommunicationis formulam resistente toto consilio magno. Sed plus potest quinqueviratus." S. 342. All these passages are from letters of Erastus. 2 Calvin's remarks are notable: "Si tibi cum iureconsultis certandum est, scias hoc hominum genus ubique fere esse Christi servis adversum, quia non existimant se gradum suum posse tueri, ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 303 The steps of the introduction of the discipline were as follows: The Catechism (1563) laid down the principle of excommunication for the impenitent and hypocrites, and declares the excommunicate to be excluded by God from the kingdom of Christ¹. An ordinance expressing the same principles was issued in 1563, and another in 1564 went a little further towards organizing the discipline, but by its pro- visional character and through the final authority reserved for the central civil power came very far from meeting the views of Olevianus. Then in 1568 there came to Heidelberg an English refugee, George Wither, who had left this country owing to the Vestiarian controversy. Desirous of a doctorate he offered a thesis on the subject of the ceremonies, which was then agitating England. The theological faculty had no mind to quarrel with Parker and the Anglican Church, and so they forbad Wither to dispute on this subject, but suggested instead that of excommunication. Erastus bitterly complains that in their care for English susceptibilities the authorities recked little of setting their own city by the ears2. On June 10 Wither offered his theses si qua vigeat ecclesia autoritas." Calvin to Olevianus; Opera, XIX. Ep. 3869. 1 "Nach dem Befehl Christi diejenigen, so unter dem christ- lichen Namen unchristliche Lehre oder Wandel führen, nachdem sie etlichemal brüderlich vermahnet sind und von ihren Irrthümern oder Lastern nicht abstehen, der Kirche oder denen so von der Kirche dazu verordnet sind, angezeiget, und so sie sich an der- selben Vermahnung auch nicht kehren, von ihnen durch Verbietung der heiligen Sacramente aus der christlichen Gemeine und von Gott selbst aus dem Reich Christi werden ausgeschlossen." Fr. 85. 2 Preface to Explicatio. 304 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM in support of the discipline of excommunication as existing jure divino apart from the magistrate, and as including the power to excommunicate the prince. Erastus was not present, but one of his friends op- posed the theses, declaring the authority claimed to be utterly contrary to Scripture. The debate was adjourned, and on the second day Erastus was present. What the grounds of opposition were, is indicated in the notes, taken at the time, of Ursinus' replies to them¹. We gather that the arguments used were much the same as those of Erastus' theses, and that like them the main object was not to magnify the civil power, but to oppose the discipline. The discussion did not stop here. Erastus started working up commentaries on the subject. These he reduced later to the form of 100 theses. His opponents were infuriated, assailed him with a torrent of abuse, and attempted to prevent a man who was not a divinity professor from discussing theological topics. Eventually he reduced the theses to seventy- five, and circulated them in manuscript, sending a copy to Beza at Geneva. The latter naturally disagreed with Erastus, and wrote the Tractatus pius et moderatus de Excommunicatione, the longest and most important contemporary reply to Erastus. Though it does not belie its title, and is moderate and respectful in tone, it is uncompromising for 'the 1 Opera, 1. 301-6. 2 Cf. Rutherford's description of him: "One physician who in a cursory way diverted off his road of medicine, of which he wrote learnedly, and broke in on the by upon the deepest polemics of Divinity, and reached a rider's blow unawares to his friends." Jus Divinum, Epistle to the Reader. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 305 prerogative of Christ,' as later Presbyterians called it, and against laxity towards those accused of lèse- majesté to the kingdom of heaven. Erastus on the other hand received letters of sympathy from the Zwinglian divines at Zurich, more especially Bullinger and Gwalther, who quarrelled with neither side, but declared distinctly their general approval of Erastus' views. They added that, while not desirous of con- demning other churches, they would never be tam dementes as to introduce the discipline into their own city'. The poor Elector was overwhelmed with the controversy, and tried, like Laud and Charles in a later controversy between Calvinists and Arminians, to prevent either side discussing the matter further². He was not obeyed. Soon after, in 1569, he took a step which greatly pleased the disciplinarians. He married the widow of Bredenrode, the Belgian noble, 1 See the letters published at the end of the Explicatio. Bul- linger did not go far enough, perhaps, for Erastus, who urged the necessity of repressing the tyranny of these men, and bade him beware lest by his desire to be charitable to two Churches he should bring ruin upon many. Bullinger, it was said, had admitted that this power of excommunication did more than anything else to ruin Churches. What Bullinger and Gwalther both disliked was the confusing of ecclesiastical discipline with the Christian mysteries. 'Cives murmurant, Princeps affligitur, consiliarii importunis supplicationibus, et tantum non enecantur. Si hactenus omnino fuissem cum Belgis, iam cessarem, quia impie tyrannice impuden- tissime rem agunt." Jezler to Ulmer. B. 78, n. 1. (It is curious to note that the Arminian controversy in Holland was apparently one of the first cases in which the writings of Erastus were largely used.) F. 20 306 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM familiar to all readers of Motley. This event led naturally to the increased influence of Dathenus and his party. A further check to Erastus was the accusation of heresy levelled at Simonius, who was driven away. Various attempts, described as in- credibly base, were made to intimidate other sup- porters with exile, and not all were unsuccessful. The Elector now demanded from Ursinus and Zanchi their written opinions on the subject. Both supported the discipline, although Ursinus, who was very re- luctant to be drawn into the discussion, made so many qualifications in favour of the civil power, the consent of which was always to be necessary to excommunications, that had the real object of Erastus been to support the prince rather than to attack excommunication, he might have agreed with his adversary quickly, and indeed is said to have regarded this opinion with some sympathy¹. Zanchi's views 1 Ursinus, on the one hand, has no wish to give power to an oligarchy apart from the Christian community or the prince. But he will not, with Erastus, accept the individual's desire to receive the sacrament as sufficient evidence of repentance. Explicatio Catechesis, Opera, 1. 296 sqq., and Judicium, III. 802 sqq. He avers further that any discipline of the kind desired cannot be effective without the magistrates' assistance (as in 1646, powers to compel attendance, &c., would be needed). (a) "Si item sic intelligi vellent, quod non debeat esse aliquis peculiaris senatus in Ecclesia, qui vel excommunicare etiam blasphemos, vel constituere quidquam possit, invito magistro et populo Christiano, ego cum ipsis non contendero." Ursinus to Bullinger. B. 159, n. 1. (b) "Nam ut novus senatus constituatur, qui invitis etiam praecipuis Ecclesiae membris excommunicare possit aut alia gerere in Ecclesia, in ea sententia nunquam fui." Ibid. (c) "Nihil in hac re tentetur nisi tali consensu magistratuum ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 307 and arguments are much the same as those of Beza¹. But the disciplinarian party was determined, and Erastus speaks with disgust of their clandestine intrigues with the Elector to induce him, against the wishes of his children, his counsellors, and all his subjects save French and Belgian refugees², to lay upon their necks a burden which their fathers were not able to bear, in the support of a view held merely by men fired with the lust of power³. A catastrophe clinched the matter. In a negotiation between the Prince of Transylvania and the Empire for aid against the Turks, it had come out that Neuser ministrorum et populi vel totius vel potioris partis ut nullae neque politicae neque ecclesiasticae turbae inde oriri possint." Ibid. (d) "Claves non sunt ministrorum tantum, sed totius ecclesiae." Exp. Cat., Opera, 1. 298. Further, the whole tone of Ursinus' opinion,' insisting so strongly on the need of the consent of the whole Church as a preservative against tyranny, is on a par with the attitude of certain believers in majority rule, who ignore the fact that a majority may exercise a tyranny just as much as an oligarchy. 1 Opera, VIII. App. 139. Zanchi gives the magistrate the custody of both tables, the duty of reforming the Church, punish- ing idolatry, securing suitable ministers, but condemns of course those "qui mutant pro suo placito religionem, non ut servi Dei sed ut Domini ecclesiae sese gerunt." De Ecclesiae Militantis Gubernatione, VIII. 555. This shews how much power all in those days granted the prince. Knox would have said the same. Non filios non conciliarios, qui ei, uno excepto Ehemio, con- stantes advertantur omnes, non nobiles, non doctos, non plebeios, audit. Episcopus est aulae Dathenus." S. 344. "Summa est, Genevenses et Belgos oportet esse, seu velimus seu nolimus." Ibid. 341. 3 "Vestra igitur excommunicatio nil aliud est quam inane figmentum hominum imperare aliis cupientium." Erastus, Con- firmatio, III. 3, p. 196. 20-2 308 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM and Sylvanus had written letters expressive of anti- Trinitarian and even Mahomedan sympathies. The scandal brought discredit upon Erastus, and the need of repression was felt to be so great, that in 1570 the discipline was definitely established by Electoral ordinance, though even this ordinance left the ultimate power to the Elector. Erastus himself described it as tolerable¹. Neuser, it should be said, escaped, and became first a Mahomedan, then an atheist. Sylvanus was tried. There were different views as to executing him. Beza wrote strongly in favour of severity. He argued that repentance was all but impossible, and even if it were not, death would be the only sure way of saving him from like blasphemy in the future. The case dragged on. Eventually the Elector decided for execution, in virtue, as he said, of a special gift of the Holy Ghost, the guide into all truth. But there is no evidence to connect Erastus with these heresies. The discipline was not popular. Some refused to act as elders. Those who did act quarrelled. The masses hated the system and rendered it ineffective, as was the case throughout the greater part of England when it was established in the next century. The discipline was in fact Erastian in the worst sense of the word. It was imposed by the civil power at the bidding of foreign influence within and without the State, against the wishes of the great majority of the people. 1 B. 96, n. 2. 2 Er habe auch den H. Geist, welcher in dieser Sache ein Lehrer und Minister der Wahrheit sei." B. 92, n. 1. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 309 In 1572 Erastus was again Rector. It may be that, like Gibbon's hostility to the Revolution, of which Mr Bagehot says, "the truth is, he had arrived at the conclusion he was the sort of person revolu- tionists are likely to kill," that of Erastus to the discipline was inspired by a feeling that it would not leave him long unscathed. For he too was excommunicated for a couple of years, 1574-6. In 1575 he was accused of anti-Trinitarian tendencies, but was acquitted. In 1576 the death of the Elector wrought another change. A Lutheran reaction under his successor followed, the hostile parties were once more united, and Erastus resigned his professorship and left Heidelberg. Had he been an Erastian in the ordinary sense, he would not have done this. He went to Basel, where he was treated with distinction. Having lectured on ethics, he died in 1583. Let us now follow the fortune of his works, since it throws light upon their meaning. In the interests of peace his own contribution to the controversy and that of Beza had been kept in manuscript. Before Erastus died, however, he appears to have changed his mind. But this is not certain. In 1589 both Theses and Confirmatio (the reply to Beza) were published under the title Explicatio gravissimae quaestionis, utrum Excommunicatio, quatenus Re- ligionem intelligentes et amplexantes, a Sacramen- torum usu propter admissum facinus arcet; mandato nitatur Divino, an excogitata sit ab hominibus. The publisher called himself Baiocius Sultaceterus, and described his action as due to a death-bed wish of 310 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM Erastus and to the love of truth; more probably it was to the love of money. The place of publication was given on the title-page as 'Pesclavii.' Beza was annoyed, and declared that Erastus would never have sanctioned such proceedings. It appeared that Pes- clavium was really London, that the real editor was Castelfeltro, the husband of Erastus' widow, and that John Wolf was the real publisher. Now the disci- plinarian controversy had been raised some years back in England by Cartwright and Travers. Beza hinted at Whitgift's being at the bottom of a publi- cation which was so opportune¹. He said he was not. But he certainly knew about it. And from a statement of Selden in his De Synedriis, there would appear to be evidence that Wolf was rewarded the privy council. There can be little doubt that the treatise was published with the object of finally settling the disciplinarian controversy in England. Hooker shews himself well acquainted with Erastus, and goes into some of the questions he raises. In his main principles about Church and State he held Erastus', not Erastian, views; though he did not share his disbelief in the power of the keys. But 1 It was opportune, for Baillie speaks of Beza as afraid to answer Erastus' book (r. 227). This must, of course, refer to the Confirmatio. Cf. also pp. 265, 311. And the whole contro- versy of the Westminster Assembly is a proof of the ingenuity of the arguments of Erastus. Selden's De Synedriis is only a de- velopement of one part. Cf. Jus Divinum, or Collinges' Responsio Bipartita, in both of which Erastus is regarded as the most formidable opponent. * Selden gives a long account of the whole matter (De Syn. 1. 1016-21). Cf. what Beza says in his preface, and also the letters in Strype's Whitgift, I. 168, and App. III, 302. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 311 he is strongly imbued with a sense of the iniquity of excommunicating the prince. In the Arminian troubles in Holland the name of Erastus was invoked'. We have a treatise of Grotius De Imperio Summarum Potestatum circa Sacra, 1614, said to be entirely Erastian. Grotius, however, like Erastus, is guarded. He will grant to the magistrate no power to contradict the word of God, to promulgate new articles of faith, or to prohibit preaching or the sacraments. This would assuredly have seemed a poor and ecclesiastical view to writers like Hobbes and, perhaps, Selden. Further, Grotius, though he cites many supporters, among them Wolfgang Musculus, does not cite Erastus, nor do the views of the two about excommunication agree. The debates of the Westminster Assembly naturalised the term Erastianism in this country. In the attempt of the divines to draw up a scheme of uniform Presbyterian Church government, the greatest difficulty of all was raised by the claim to the power of the keys. The English Puritans were strongly Calvinist in the modern sense of the term. But they were loth to exert a power which they deemed arbitrary and unlimited, and to put it in the hands of an ecclesiastical body. The Independents objected, not to suspension of individuals in each congregation, but to any attempt to make parishes. 1 Arminius and his friends leant on the civil power, and were much attacked for having appealed to the superior magistrate against the ecclesiastical authority; see Articles of Synod of Dort, translated by Dr Scott, and History of Preceding Events, 137 and passim. 2 Opera, III. 214. 312 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 1 unite in a larger organization for the review of decisions¹. They appear to have been willing to admit a final right of appeal to the civil magistrate. This brought them very near to the Erastians². Many are the groans of Dr Baillie over the influence of these latter. He describes them as follows: "In the Assembly we are fallen on a fashious proposition, that has keeped us divers dayes, and will do so divers more, coming upon the article of the church and the church-notes to oppose the Erastian heresy, which in this land is very strong, especially among the lawyers, unhappy members of this Parliament. We find it necessary to say that 'Christ in the New Testament had institute a Church government distinct from the Civil, to be exercised by the officers of the church, without commission from the magistrate.' None in the Assembly has any doubt of this truth but one Mr. Coleman, a professed Erastian, a man reasonably learned but stupid and inconsiderate, half a pleasant, and of small estimation. But the lawyers in the Parlia- ment making it their work to spoil our Presbyterie, not so much upon conscience as upon fears that the Parliament spoil their mercat and take up most of their country pleas without law, did blow up the 1 "The proposition we stick on is that no particular congrega- tions may be under the government of one Classical Presbytery." Baillie, II. 139 (1644). 2 Neal's remarks are notable. Except that he calls Erastus a divine, he gives a very fair description of his teaching. The pastoral office, he says, was according to Erastus only persuasive, like that of a professor of the sciences over his students, without any power of the keys annexed. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 313 poor man with much vanity; so he is become their champion, to bring out in the best way he can Erastus's arguments against the proposition, for the contentment of the Parliament. We give him a free and fair hearing; albeit, we fear, when we have answered all he can bring and have improved with undeniable proofs our position, the Houses when it comes to them shall scrape it out of the Confession; for this point is their idol. The most of them are incrediblie zealous for it; the Pope and the King were never more earnest for the headship of the Church than the plurality of this Parliament. How- ever they are like for a time by violence to carry it, yet almost all the ministry are zealous for the Pre- rogative of Christ against them. We are at this instant yoked in a great and dangerous combat for this very thing. Often we have been on the brink to set up our Government, but Satan to this day hath hindered us. The ministers and elders are not willing to set up and begin any action till they may have a law for some power to purpose; all former ordinances have been so intolerably defective that they could not be accepted. The Erastian and Independent party joining together in the Houses to keep off the Government so long as they were able, and when it was extorted, to make it so lame and corrupt as they were able; yet at last yesterday an Ordinance came forth to supply the defects of all the former, that so without much further delay we might go to work. We laboured so much as we were able before it came out to have it so free from exceptions as might be, but notwithstanding of all we could do, it is by the 314 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM malignity of the forementioned brethren in evil so filled with grievances, that yet it cannot be put in practice. We for our part mind to give in a remon- strance against it; the Assembly will do the like; the City Ministers will give the third; but that which by God's help may prove most effectual is the zeal of the City itself. Before the ordinance came out, they petitioned against some materials of it. This both the Houses voted to be a breach of their privilege, to offer a petition against anything that is in debate before them till once it be con- cluded and come abroad. This vote the City takes very evil. It's likely to go high betwixt them. Our prayers and endeavours are for wisdom and courage to the City. I know to whom this matter has cost much labour. The Independents have the least zeal to the truth of God of any men we know. Blasphemous heresies are now spread here more than ever in any part of the world. Yet they are not only silent, but are patrons and pleaders for liberty almost to them all. We and they have spent many sheets of paper upon the toleration of their separate churches. At the last meeting we concluded to stop our paper- debates, and on Thursday next to begin our verbal disputation against the lawfulness of their desired separation. When we have ended, the Houses will begin to consider this matter. The most there and in the army will be for too great a liberty; but the Assembly, the City, and the body of all the ministry in the Kingdom are passionately opposite to such an evident breach of the Covenant¹." 1 Baillie, Journal, 11. 360, 1 (1646). ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 315 Mr Gillespie in his Aaron's Rod Blossoming (table of Contents) describes the genesis of the party thus: "The Erastian error not honestis parentibus nati. Erastus the midwife, how engaged in the business. The breasts that gave it suck profaneness and self- interest. Its strong food arbitrary government. Its tutor Arminianism. Its deadly decay and consump- tion, whence it was? How ill it hath been harboured in all the reformed churches? How stifled by Erastus himself? Erastianism refuted out of Erastus. The divers who have appeared against this error. How the controversy was lately revived." Rutherford occupies the greater part of Jus Di- vinum with an able answer to Erastus, and thinks that in answering him he has fully answered Prynne's objections¹. He describes the attempts of the Eras- tian party thus: "It is not an enriching spoil to pluck a rose or flower from the crown of the Prince of the Kings of the earth. Diamonds and rubies picked out of the Royal Diadem of Jesus Christ addeth but a poor and sorry lustre to earthly supre- macy; it is baldness instead of beauty." He makes use of the argument to be made famous by Pascal, "In things doubtful conscience hath refuge to the surest side. And Christian rulers would not do well to venture upon Eternity, Wrath, the Judgement to come, confiding on the poor plea of an Erastian dis- tinction, to encroach upon the Prerogative Royal of Jesus Christ." The arguments are much the same as in the case 1 Epistle to the Reader. 316 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM of Heidelberg, though there was a great deal more here about the civil magistrate; but Collinges in his Responsio Bipartita declares his opponents' argu- ments to be all derived from Erastus, "the first worker in that sort of brass¹." The extension of the term Erastian to mean not opponents of excom- munication, but upholders of the view that the magistrate could order religion as he liked and command obedience, was due to this controversy. Now of course its original significance has been largely forgotten. The Explicatio was reprinted in 1649 at Amster- dam. The theses (not the Confirmatio) were trans- lated into English in 1659 under the title of The Nullity of Church Censures. Another translation appeared in 1682. J In our own day the disruption of the Church of Scotland caused Dr Lee to republish in 1844 the old translation, with an elaborate preface of his own, vindicating Erastus from the charge of Erastian- ism as commonly understood, and the Church of 1 ¹ p. 20. 2 It is fair to say that Rutherford regards Erastus as more, not less Erastian than his followers, but I think he does not reflect (1) that Erastus' remarks as to the civil magistrate were obiter dicta; (2) that the power he gives him, as to sacra, would go to any Christian under a doctrine of the priesthood of the laity, held as strongly as Erastus undoubtedly held it; (3) Erastus always contemplates the magistrate not as changing religion at his will, but as the orthodox head of an orthodox church; (4) Erastus does not, as Rutherford thinks (513), ever say that it is the magis- trate's business to excommunicate apostates or any one else. He merely says that his objections to the discipline do not apply to them. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 317 Scotland from being either Erastian or a supporter of Erastus. G Having thus detailed the relevant facts, I proceed to a few points which may serve towards the elucida- tion of the problem with which I started, How far was Erastus an Erastian ? But a definition of Erastianism is necessary. Perhaps the theory is expressed in the barest and therefore most complete form by Selden in the words "Whether is the Church or the Scripture the judge of religion? In truth neither, but the State¹." Such a view is clear enough. It places all truth at the mercy of the civil power and utterly denies any rights of conscience to either individual or church. It places the claims of ex- pediency above those of reason. It makes political convenience the sole test of belief. And it is such a view as this that gives its locus standi to the hierarchical theory of the State; although, indeed, it might perhaps more fairly be said that it was the hierarchical theory and its consequences which pro- duced Erastianism by way of repulsion. Still, the great argument in favour of theories of ecclesiastical supremacy, whether propounded by Jesuits or Presby- terians or Fifth Monarchy Men, is always the same. In an age in which uniformity in religion is the political ideal, the spiritual organization must claim a deciding view in matters of faith, or religious belief will become merely a question of political convenience. The only safeguard for truth is a claim, which seems preposterous to those living in a world where toleration 1 Table Talk, Op. 11. 2067; cf. also 2016. 318 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM Đư has solved the problem. Theories of ecclesiastical supremacy may be bad, but they are better than the view which makes religion or atheism a mere political instrument, the shuttlecock of State or private in- terests. They are, in fact, the form which a regard for the rights of conscience takes in an age in which persecution is regarded as a duty. The Roman Empire had made of religion a mere political engine. In the inevitable reaction the Christian Church was led to put forth a claim nearly equally indefensible to dominate the civil authority. Then the Reforma- tion witnessed the uprising of the laity against this view. And nearly all supporters of change were willing to allow to the civil ruler more power in the direction of taking the initiative¹ in reformation than our own age would be disposed to do. Some went further. The Leviathan exhibits true Erastianism in its most full-blown form. Hobbes regards religion as under the absolute control of the State, which for its own ends may establish and prohibit what forms it pleases, and demand not only on loyal, but on moral grounds the obedience of every member. The con- science is in fact bound to any religion the State 1 Cf. even Knox' Letter to Queen Regent Mary, Works, IV. 433; and also Second Book of Discipline, x. 7, in Calderwood, III. 545. Knox, like the Pope, was willing to exalt the civil power, so long as it could be used as an instrument. A great deal of so-called Erastianism is little more than the extravagant support of the one power that could carry through or maintain the particular religious views of the writer; as a later writer says, "Only this honour the Presbyterians give to their magistrates, they must be the execu- tioners of their judgements to hang whom they condemn," and cf. the Confession of Puritan exiles in Holland. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 319 imposes. It is true Hobbes makes one reservation, in which a merely passive obedience is permitted, but it concerns only the case where the State denies the Incarnation, and is besides so contemptuous, that he leaves little doubt that he himself would regard conformity to any and every conceivable State- imposed religion or negation as a moral duty. The king is at once priest and bishop. Bishops have no right to call themselves so by divine permission, and the clergy ought to preach of nothing but the duty of civil obedience. But perhaps the simpler definition of Erastianism as the theory that religion is the creature of the State may serve; and I suppose that no one will deny that the word as commonly employed means at least this much. Now did Erastus teach this or not? If not, was his doctrine at all an approximation to it? And how, then, did the theory become attached to his name? To the first of these questions, I believe that the answer is in the negative; to the second an affirmative, although opinions will probably differ as to how far such approximation extends. And the third can be answered from the history of the con- troversies mentioned above. (1) We must always remember that Erastus did not write directly in support of the State, but had the object of crying down excommunication. Any views he expresses as to the functions of the magistrate are mere obiter dicta introduced in support of the main position. He is bound in fact to shew that morality will not suffer, if his views be adopted. And so he goes on to say that excommunication is 320 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM not only unscriptural and a usurpation, but that the magistrate can effect all that it aims at; not that he himself can excommunicate. His argument runs on these lines: (a) Excommunication was not practised among the Jews; (b) it has no authority in the New Testament; (c) in a state where every one is of the same opinion, (not excommunication, but) all coercive jurisdiction belongs to the magistrate alone. The argument is of the character of the times, and there is no need to go into it at length. The alleged instances among the Jews are disposed of. The Sanhedrin¹ is shewn to be a political not merely a religious body, and to have had coercive power. This point was elaborated by Selden in the De Synedriis². The passages from the New Testament cited as favouring the discipline are then examined and explained. The most important of these is Matthew xviii. 17. Erastus argues that Christ's 1 The Disciplinarians based their argument partly on the as- sumed fact that the powers of the Sanhedrin were continued in the Church, and that they were essentially ecclesiastical. Both Bancroft in his Survey of the Pretended Holy Discipline and Bilson in The Perpetual Government of Christ's Church appear to have held the same views as Erastus on the matter. 2 Baillie was very anxious to have him answered, e.g. "The Erastian party in the Parliament is stronger than the Independent, and is like to work us much woe. Selden is their head. If L'Empereur would beat down this man's arrogancy, as he very well can, to show out of the Rabbins, that the Jewish State was diverse from their Church, and that they had the censure of excommunication among them, and a double Sanhedrin, one civil, another ecclesiastical; if he would confound him with Hebrew testimonies it would lay Selden's vanity, who is very insolent for his Oriental literature" (11. 277). Gillespie was also very strong on this point. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 321 command has nothing to do with excommunication. It refers to private wrongs. The aggrieved party is to go either to the Sanhedrin or to a similar body acting in a non-Christian State as a court of arbitra- tion. If that fails, the erring brother is to be treated as a heathen and a publican. This means not that he is excommunicate, but that an action in the State courts may be brought against him. He will not act as a Christian, let him therefore be treated merely as a citizen¹. St Paul's delivering over to Satan of the erring Corinthian is also discussed. This is in- terpreted as a prayer for his removal from this world, not as excommunication. Lastly, Erastus declares that in a Christian State the magistrate is the proper person to punish all offences. He is not to excom- municate. That would be to give him a purely religious function³. He is merely to act on a law inspired by religious principles. Erastus does not touch doctrine, and therefore gives the magistrate 1 This argument appears in Musculus, Loci Communes, De Magistratibus, p. 631, Ed. 1611. 2 Lightfoot, Horae Hebraicae, shares Erastus' views on many of these points. 3 Cranmer indeed does this in his Questiones, N. O. 116, Re- mains and Letters, 117. "A bishop or a priest by the Scripture is neither commanded nor forbidden to excommunicate, but where the laws of any region giveth him authority to excommunicate, there they ought to use the same in such crimes as the laws have such authority in; and where the laws of the region forbiddeth them, there they have none authority at all; and they that be no priests may also excommunicate, if the law allow them there- unto." But to the whole of this is added: "This is mine opinion and sentence at the present, which I do not temerariously define, and do remit the judgement thereof wholly unto your majesty.”: F. 21 322 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM no power over truth. For he says that he is only considering the case where prince and people are all of the same religion, and that the true one. All this appears to me to shew that the views of Erastus are not relevant to modern Church controversies, which take place in a State which recognizes every religion, and which presuppose a 'magistrate' (Parliament) composed of persons of a thousand conflicting views. It is only through the ignoring the two provisoes : (1) that the true religion is supposed to be established and none other allowed in the State; (2) that the magistrate has no power to transgress the Word of God that it is possible to identify the views of Erastus with those of Hobbes or Selden. His objection is clearly to two governing coercive authorities in one State. "Ut in rebus profanis curandis ei non licet ter- minos et fines aequitatis, iusticiae, ac honestatis, hoc est praescriptionem legum et statutorum Reipub- licae, transcendere; sic in disponendis et ordinandis rebus sacris vel ad cultum Divinum pertinentibus longe minus ei licet ulla in parte a praescripto verbi Dei discedere: quod tanquam regulam in omnibus debet sequi, ab eoque nusquam vel latum pilum deflectere. Summa est, Magistratum in Christiana Republica unicum esse cui a Deo commissa sit guber- natio externa rerum omnium quae vel ad civilem vel ad piam et Christianam vitam pertinent; ius et au- toritatem imperandi ac ius dicendi neque ministris neque aliis ullis concessum esse. Intelligi hoc debet de ea Republica dictum, in qua Magistratus et sub- diti eandem profitentur religionem, eamque veram. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 323 In hac dico duas distinctas iurisdictiones minime debere esse. In alia, in qua videlicet Magistratus falsam tuetur sententiam, certo quodam modo tole- rabilis videri fortasse possit divisio rationum¹." "Oppugno tantum iudicium de moribus, quod hodie Ecclesiasticum nominant, distinctum a iudicio politici magistratus. Nempe duas iurisdictiones sive duo discriminata de moribus iudicia publica et ex- terna nego in una Republica esse oportere, cui pius Magistratus a Deo praepositus est?.” 2 Is this substantially different from Elizabeth's claim for herself in The Admonition to simple men deceived by the malicious? Erastus' magistrate is in fact merely a sovereign, "over all persons and in all causes within his dominions supreme," no more³. Further he says that in matters of faith the magis- trate will of course consult the leaders of theological opinion, who will teach him what is or is not the Word of God. And he admits it may be well that for moral offences he may delegate power to bodies composed at least partly of ecclesiastics or of persons elected by churches, who shall inquire into such offences and bring the offenders to justice. But he objects to the assumption of jurisdiction by the spiritual authority, which he deems essentially non- 1 Confirmatio, III. 1, pp. 161-2. In another place he says "Verbum Dei et Sacramenta nulli potestati subiiciuntur." 2 Ibid. Iv. 1. 3 "Non hoc dico, Deum voluisse magistratum sacrificare atque alia huiusmodi, quae sacerdotibus imperata solis fuerant, facere, sed illud assero Deum soli magistratui concredidisse curam et gubernationem tam sacrarum quam profanarum rerum. Ibid. III. 1, p. 163. 4 Ibid. 172. 21-2 324 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM political'. His opponents claimed without justice that their discipline in no way usurped the power of the State. He retorted by asking them why, if this was so, they required an act of State to intro- duce their discipline. He also objects to any attempt to introduce it among an unwilling population as too 'Erastian' in our sense, and as depriving the Christian community of its rights. They made the cardinal error of all clericalist parties in arguing that their decisions, being concerned with religious matters, were of a radically different order from those of other men. They claimed infallibility. "An apud solos Allo- broges homines non falluntur in iudicando?" asks Erastus pertinently. Beza's argument was that the sentence of the Church was merely declaratory, announcing upon earth a sentence of exclusion from Paradise previously passed in an invisible court above. This in his view differentiated the decisions of ruling elders from those of earthly courts. Erastus saw through this (unconscious) sophistry. He saw 1 Cf. the description of Baxter's views in Calamy's Life of Baxter, and his reasons for disliking the Presbyterians, Reliquiae Baxterianae, 142, 3. 2Si verum est Christum nomine Ecclesiae intellexisse totam multitudinem, falsum est magistratui hoc permitti, ut nolente Ecclesia hos ei Presbyteros imponat. Quanquam enim Magis- tratus praecipuum est Ecclesiae membrum, tamen ipsismet inter- pretibus non iussit Christus membro primario et principi judicare, sed Ecclesiae toti: in qua non facit alios aliis potentiores quod ad hanc rem attinet." Confirmatio, vi. 1, p. 329. 3 Confirmatio, III. 4, p. 223. 4 In excommunicating "Deum ipsum constituimus et presby- terii et huius iudicii auctorem, cuius dumtaxat minister et interpres fit presbyterium." Excommunication is really the supplement to an act previously done in heaven: "ut videlicet nihil aliud si ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 325 that the attempt to judge whether a man desirous of communicating was sincere or no in repentance involved an impossible claim to a knowledge of motive, and was therefore in this respect an encroach- ment on the divine justice, no less than it was in another a usurpation of human. It judged motives, i.e. it claimed infallibility; it affected reputation, i.e. it had a civil aspect¹. The fact is that the concep- tion of the Church entertained at that time by Presbyterians and Papalists alike is largely political, just as rigid predestinarianism is the theory of legal sovereignty applied to the actions of God. The Deity of Calvinism is Hobbes' Leviathan, with power un- checked by law, justice or conscience. To both Papalists and Presbyterians the Church is a State, the State indeed—though not all would have admitted so much². But Erastus saw the dangers of the system excommunicatio in terris quam declaratio alterius occultioris factae in coelis, ex qua nimirum merito colligatur eum qui in coelis eo quidem tempore non approbatur, indignum esse qui inter fideles in terris censeatur: quae posterior etiam declaratio in terris facta, rata est in coelis.” Beza, Tractatus Moderatus, 4. "Nos autem ...tam credimus rata esse in coelis, quam Christum scimus regnare in eorum ministerio quos ecclesiae suae hic regendae praefecit; neque haec legitima vero presbyterii iudicia secus arbitramur reformidanda, quam si filius ipse Dei aeternus illa ore suo pro- nuntiaret." Ibid. 8. 1 "Nos enim de solis illis loquimur, ut saepe monui, qui cupiunt cum Deo reconciliari; at hoc unum contendimus, non esse a Deo institutum Presbyterium, quod de cordibus hominum dicentium se poenitere iudicet, verene an false dicant; atque sic vel ad sacramenta admittant, vel ab eisdem removeant.” Con- firmatio, II. 1, p. 152. Cf. also 1. 4. 2 The developed doctrine of Presbyterianism does admit the theory of the two kingdoms; but this was hardly the position of either Calvin or Knox. Cf. the lecture on Ius Divinum in 1646. 326 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 2 it was proposed to introduce¹. He saw the power which the right of excommunication would give to ecclesiastical oligarchies in a community all of one faith. Excommunication in our heterogeneous modern world would have far less effect, although even here it might affect a man's business prospects and be therefore a proper subject for the courts to investi- gate. But in a society of uniform religious belief, if practised as had been desired, it would have been defamation of character raised to the level of a divine ordinance and relieved of every civil penalty. To claim such a power was certainly to claim what lay within the magistrate's functions, unless there was appeal to him, and that was the thing most disliked. There can be no reason why a preacher who spoke of certain individuals in his sermons should not suffer the pains and penalties of slander, if his allegations were unjustifiable. Excommunica- tion was the same sort of thing on a grander scale. It is not calculated to advance a man's prospects in this life to tell his neighbours that his prospects are ( ¹ He regards it as on a level with Papal oppression. "Haec enim vere fortis Deus fuit, qui omnes Reges et principes, omne robur, omnes conscientias, ipsam etiam sacrosanctam scripturam, Pontificis Romani pedibus subiecit. At nos, inquies, aliter in- stituimus, Pontificum factum non probamus. Audio quidem hoc dici, sed contrarium video et experior. Permulta alia in Ponti- ficibus recte reprehendimus; at eadem deinde fecimus et facimus, postquam nobis paulum confirmati videmur. Nolo exempla dis- sipatarum Ecclesiarum, iniquorum iudiciorum, et aliarum con- fusionum atque malorum, quae aetate nostra ex hac vel sola vel praecipue orta sunt, commemorare; quia sunt odiosa.' Confir- matio, v. 1, p. 298. 2 Ius Divinum, 632. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 327 unpleasant for the next, if they believe you. And it is noteworthy that this, though under different names, and not always explicitly stated, was the main ground of dispute at the Westminster Assembly. It was argued by the supporters of the discipline that the jurisdiction was in no sense coercive, but purely spiritual. Erastus is not much blamed in his own day for ascribing too much power to the magistrate. Beza says little on the subject, nor do any anti- Erastians deny in set terms that all coercive authority belongs to the State¹. They are rather concerned to shew that theirs does not conflict with it. Here indeed Ursinus breaks away from his party and asserts that the magistrate must be consulted and give his assent to excommunication. Prynne, a great disciplinarian and anti-Erastian, was attacked for supporting the discipline on what we should call Erastian grounds-on the ground, that is, that the government was supporting or was about to support the system, and every one must therefore obey it. He is asked, why he did not act upon that view in the days of prelatical tyranny2. Moreover the thing most hateful to the Presbyterians in England was the insistence by Parliament on a right of final appeal 1 Beza indeed declares the magistrate to have the custody of the two tables. Tractatus, 99. The real point between the two was not as to the power of the magistrate, but as to the divine origin of excommunication. We may compare, as showing the Erastianism of the anti-Erastians, the appeal of Ursinus at the end of his Judicium, begging the Elector to cause questions of new doctrine to be brought before him. 2 Cf. Certain Brief Observations on Mr Prynne's Twelve Questions. 328 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM to the civil power¹. They object to all limiting of excommunication and want to free it alike from exceptions and all other jurisdiction. There is indeed no doubt that in England the main force of the hostility was fear of clerical tyranny. Selden 1 "But we deny that (in a well constituted Church) it is agree- able to the will of Christ for the Magistrate either to receive appeals (properly so-called) from the sentence of an Ecclesiastical Court, or to receive complaints exhibited against that sentence by the party censured, so as by his authority upon such complaint to nullify or make void the censure." Gillespie, 253. "Great wrestling have we for the erecting of our Presbyterie ; it must be a divine thing to which so much resistance is made by men of all sorts; yet by God's help we will very speedily see it set up in spight of the devil.... Our greatest trouble for the time is from the Erastians in the House of Commons. They are at last content to erect Pres- byteries and Synods in all the land, and have given out their orders to that end; yet they give to the ecclesiastic courts so little power that the Assemblie, finding their petitions not granted, were in great doubt whether to set up any thing till, by some powerful petition of many thousand hands, they obtain more of their first desires. The only means to obtain this and all else we desire is our recruited army about Newark." Baillie, II. 317, 18 (1645). 2 To limit the censure of excommunication in matter of opinion to the common and uncontroverted principles, and in the matter of manners to the common and universal practices of Christianity, and in both to the parties' known light, is the dan- gerous doctrine of the Arminians and Socinians, openeth a wide door and proclaimeth liberty to all other practices and errors which are not fundamental and universally abhorred by all Christians, and tendeth to the overthrow of the Reformed re- ligion." The Reformation cleared, 21. "The Clergy, who, what Church forms soever they set up, will be ever imposing their private opinions in matters of religion for infallible truths, and incensing prince against people and people against prince, and one sort of men against another, making their followers to espouse and maintain their unjust quarrels, till they ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 329 declares that "Presbyters have the greatest power of any clergy in the world and gull the laity the most¹." become insensibly slaves to their ambition and boundless power, instead of attaining to any solid real or truly Christian refor- mation. Whether that wisdom and power of the Clergy which hath taken upon it in all ages to suppress heresy and schism by human laws and penalties, have not been a perverting and interrupting of that law of love amongst the members of Christ's body which he commands? And whether they, under the pretence of com- posing differences and settling a government over the body of Christ, by endeavouring to reduce all the members of the body to unity of judgement and uniformity of practice in matters of religion upon grounds of outward compulsion have not discovered in themselves that true spirit of schism described 1 Cor. 12 (which they would seem to extirpate), which despises all below it and envies all above it as unnecessary members, and fit to be cut off from the body, so defacing and dividing the body of Christ by labouring to make the whole body but one member, and where then is the body?" Twelve Weighty Queries, p. 8. ، 'Lay no more burden of government upon the shoulders of ministers than Christ hath plainly laid upon them; have no more hand therein than the Holy Ghost clearly gives them....I fear an ambitious ensnarement, and I have cause. I see what raised Prelacie and Papacy to such a height. When once they had a hand in the work they soon engrossed it, and then made it the main, the sole point of religion. 'Christian perfection,' saith one of them, 'doth not consist in almsdeeds and devotion, but in exalting the ecclesiastical jurisdiction, the true cement of that perfection. Coleman, Hopes Deferred and Dashed, p. 25. """ "O ye honourable worthies, open your eyes and see whither you are going or whither some are leading you. Once the Pope had your predecessors at his beck, and you may again, for you will lose your freedom under a Presbyterian domination. The Lord of heaven grant that England never see that day wherein Parliament must not meddle with Church government because a spiritual thing." Coleman, A Brotherly Admonition, p. 6. 1 Table Talk, Oр. г. 2064. One of Baillie's complaints was 330 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM That the discipline really aimed at a function not of persuasion, but of government is proved (1) by the argument of one supporter that its object was the external peace of the Church, not the mind of the member¹; (2) by another's argument that the proper persons to maintain order in the churches and prevent brawling are the ecclesiastical autho- rities²; (3) by a case of which both Erastus and Bullinger speak, where the presbytery, in their anxiety to secure jurisdiction, were actually driven into a course which led to the impunity of a man accused of unnatural vice³. that in a form of discipline at one time proposed it would have been possible for the ministers to be controlled by laymen in the kirk-session (III. 452). A good account of the clericalist character of Calvin's régime is given by Bancroft, Survey, chaps. II. and III. 1 Neither is it the internal or nearest aim of Discipline in Church government to work upon or rule the mind, which is not known to the Church or Church governors, but to procure the external peace of the Church, which may be obtained, the mind remaining still unconvinced." Answer to a Libel, 55. 2 "Suppose there should be any disturbance in the church assembled for the public worship of God by some drunkard or madman or any heretic, either by sporting or by railing or seducing or any abominable action, where lies the power to suppress it? Is it in the magistrates or in the church officers? I answer it is in the hand or power of the church officers first, because they were charged to keep the door, that there be no such occasion for dis- turbance in the midst of divine worship." An Answer to those questions, 15. Cf. Gwalther's letter, who states the case. "In palatinatu nulla prius scandala tam atrocia incidisse quam ea sint, quae seniorum illic constitutorum culpa acciderint....Quod si ergo novam in Ecclesia tyrannidem his principiis stabilire posse metuemus, quis nos absque causa id timere dicet?" Explicatio, 379. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 331 It is the competing jurisdiction and its clericalist character that frighten Erastus. Yet it must be allowed that he writes largely of the civil power. He quotes Musculus to the effect that the worst of heresies is to regard a Christian magistrate as on the same level with a heathen'. Nor can there be any doubt that like all the reformers he would have been ready (and indeed probably helped) to impose his faith by the help of the civil power upon an unwilling people. There is no hint of toleration in his writings, yet his crusade was one in favour of popular liberty as well as the civil power, against those who were duping the latter into assisting an attempt to crush both. If the thing is to be intro- duced, in Erastus' view the people as well as the prince should be consulted. Further there are one or two passages in which he says that the magistrate 1 Musculus, though in many ways more Erastian than Erastus, yet saves himself from the charge of enslaving religion to the State policy. "Horum consideratione manifestum redditur etiam si ad magistratus Christianos cura religionis pertineat, haud tamen illis competere, ut citra verbum Dei quicquam in religione con- stituant. Nequit enim fieri ut arbitrarii cultus Deo placeant, quia non sunt voluntati ipsius conformes: nec possunt conscientias hominum de eo certas reddere, quod Deo vere serviant, hoc est, rem gratam faciant." He goes on to show that Moses in the Old Testament, and the Apostles in the New, were given explicit directions, nothing being left to their arbitrary will. “Haec praecedentibus adiicere voluimus, ne damnabilem eorum magistratuum temeritatem approbare videamur, qui absque Verbo Dei quamcunque volunt religionis formam subditis suis proponunt, et pro potestate sua a Deo accepta authenticam esse servarique volunt: et si quis illam sequi recusaverit, mox contumaciae ac rebellionis damnant, quasi Christiana religio a potestate magistratuum et non magis ab infallibili divinorum elo- quiorum certitudine et auctoritate pendeat." Loci Communes, 646. 332 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM might teach, if he had time, which he had not, and might even act as a minister¹; yet Erastus was very anti-sacerdotal and bases these views on general principles about the priesthood of the laity. And even then we must remember the true religion is supposed to be established; there is no notion of a right in the prince to change religion at will. Nor is there any evidence that he would have put truth under the heel of policy, and like Hobbes have dragged religion under the Juggernaut car of reason of State. He regarded the function of the Church as purely persuasive. It is a pity that, seeing this, he did not go further and deny the right of the State to persecute, whether or no at the bidding of the Church¹. But at least it was liberty, not tyranny for which he contended. He could not be deceived by the specious pretence of spiritual illumination into regarding as harmless upon earth a jurisdiction, whose only virtue in the eyes of its supporters lay in the fact that it rested upon fear, that is com- pulsion, and therefore needed the sanction of the States. Indeed his views may be summed up in 2 Ibid. III. 1, p. 175. 1 Confirmatio, iv. 2, p. 265. 3 He did not, for instance, object to the rebuking of the magistrates in sermons. What he could not endure was the claim to examine them judicially. This, in his view, meant an assump- tion of governmental authority. v. 1. 4 If the truth that "" my kingdom is not of this world" be a valid reason for giving no coercive jurisdiction over morals to the Church, it is equally valid against any coercion in matters of belief by the State, irrespective of the question as to whether or no the State is advised by the Church. Cf. Confirmatio, p. 173. 5 Cf. Reformation cleared 23: "There cannot be so much as trial and examination of the offence without authority unless the ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 333 the following passage from the life of Baxter, hardly an Erastian in our sense. "The Erastians, I thought, were thus far in the right in asserting more fully than others the magistrate's power in matters of religion, that all coercive power is only in their hands, which is the full sense of the Oath of Supre- macy, and that no such power belongeth to the He could not pastors or people of the Church.” but approve their holding the pastoral power to be only persuasive, though authoritative and by divine appointment; and that pastors were officers of God's institution, who were not only to persuade by sermons general and special, but by particular oversight of their particular flocks; and could as the ground of their persuasion produce God's commission or command for what they said or did. But that as pastors they had no secular or forcing power; and that unless the magistrate authorised them as his officers they could not touch men's bodies or estates, but had to do with conscience only." This is also the exact line taken by Coleman. It is the impossibility of two co-equal jurisdictions in a State which strikes Erastus. And this is obvious. One of them must be final, so far as the State be (( party be willing to appear; that persuasion and jurisdiction, that the delivering over to Satan and thereby striking the conscience with the terror of God by the authority of Jesus Christ, which hath the promise of a special and strong ratification in heaven, and any other ecclesiastical way whatever, which must be inferior to this, and depend only upon persuasion on the one part, and free will on the other, can be supposed to be alike efficacious." Here the appeal to force is evident. 1 Reliquiae Baxterianae, 139; Calamy, p. 113. 334 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM united¹. In a State where the magistrate is non- Christian, and therefore ex hypothesi persecutes the Church, he would allow jurisdiction to the Church. But where this is not the case, he saw, like the Papalist, the need of unity. He, indeed, points out that the Popes had based their claim to a universal monarchy on the fact that since there was only one supreme authority, the inferior, i.e. the secular, must yield to the superior, the ecclesiastical power. Erastus held the modern view that the office of the Church as such is purely persuasive². But since he identified Church and Nation, he naturally added that the public policy must be inspired by Christian maxims, and would punish all sins as well as crimes, so far as needful. In a State where men are all of one faith, crime and sin become interchangeable externally, and many things forbidden by religious sentiments may be punished by civil means without injustice. Where this is not so, the attempt to enforce morality as such on the community is a form of persecution; but of course in such a case the jurisdiction of various religious bodies may appear in some form, for they may regard as wrong acts of their members which the State, looking to the whole variegated mass of the people and their opinions, must treat as indifferent. It may be added that what we know of the actual 1 Cf. Coleman. "I could never yet see how two co-ordinate governments, exempt from superiority or inferiority, can be in one State, and in Scripture no such thing is found that I know of." He explains, "Government I take strictly for the corrective." Hopes Deferred, 25. 2 He asks why the duty of ministers to teach is to be expanded into a right to judge (1v. 3). ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 335 working of the discipline lends confirmation to the views of Erastus, and proves it to have acted as a restraint upon individual liberty¹. The main object then of Erastus was not to magnify the State, nor to enslave the Church, but to secure the liberty of the subject. He regarded the discipline as a narrow and illiberal form of perse- cution, which if not entirely clerical was ecclesiastical to the core, and if allowed to work unchecked was 1 The following passage from the ordinance imposing the discipline in England (1648) gives some notion of the liberality of the system. The undermentioned classes of persons are to be excommunicated:"All worshippers of images, crosses, crucifixes, or relics; all that shall make any images or pictures of the Trinity or of any person thereof [this would condemn all religious art]; all religious worshippers of saints, angels, or any meer creatures; any person that shall profess himself not to be in charity with his neighbours; all persons in whom malice appears, and they refuse to be reunited...any person that shall upon the Lord's day use any dancing, playing dice, or cards, or any other game, masquing, wakes, shooting, bowling, playing at football, stool-ball, wrestling, or that shall make or resort unto any plays, interludes, fencing, bull-baiting, bear-baiting, or that shall use hawking, hunting, or coursing, fishing or fowling, or that shall publicly expose any wares to sale, otherwise than is provided by an ordinance of Parliament of the sixth of April, 1644; any person that shall travel on the Lord's Day without reasonable cause; any person, father or mother, that shall assent to the marriage of their child to a Papist, or any person that shall marry a Papist; any person that shall repair for any advice to any witch, wizard, or fortune teller." And see the whole story of the attempt to introduce the discipline into England in Neal, who was by no means unfavourable to the Puritans. Cf. also a letter of Gwalther's complaining that, whereas the episcopal excommunication was always accompanied by reasons, in Heidelberg persons had been excluded from the sacrament and no reason given. Explicatio, p. 387. 336 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM liable to ruin the State'. He asks pertinently enough, Who will be best obeyed, the magistrate or those who have power to excommunicate him? For though his throne be intact, and civil obedience be still preached as a duty, are men in a State, where all are earnestly convinced of their religion and all united, likely to pay much respect to one who has been, although desirous of taking part in the sacrament and de- claring himself repentant, excluded from it because the presbytery disbelieves his sincerity 2? What Erastus disliked was not only the attempt to steal from the prince his power, but also the arrogant assumption of ability to do God's office and read the thoughts of the heart. If a man desired the sacrament, was orthodox in his belief, and declared himself penitent, that was for men sufficient proof of repentance. For we can only judge externally, and cannot put our own authoritative interpreta- tion upon the sincerity of the act without claiming 1 Bancroft, Survey, 208: "There is but only this difference between them and the rankest Jesuits in Europe, that what the one sort do ascribe unto the Pope and his shavelings, the other do challenge unto themselves and their aldermen." 2 Dicitis quidem Magistratui excluso nihilominus obedientiam deberi. Sed quis credat me illi parere velle, cui ego vitae totius modum cum potestate et coactione praescribere me posse arbitror? Facile est obedientiam praestare ei, qui contra voluntatem tuam facere nihil ausit. Sane Magistratus quem sibi subiecit Presby- terium, nihil aliud est, quam servus Presbyterii: dum pro eius. arbitratu cogitur in quoslibet molliter, duriter, cruciatu corporis, exilio, vinculis, morte, etc. animadvertere." Confirmatio, v. 1, p. 301. Bancroft deliberately connects Buchanan's doctrine of deposition with the alleged right to excommunicate princes (Survey of the Pretended Holy Discipline, 204); cf. Knox, Exhortation to England, Works, v. 516. ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 337 infallibility. Thus excommunication usurps not only man's authority by its claim to jurisdiction, but God's by its assurance of certainty. The Popes had seen this, and argued logically enough that an ex- communicate King could not rule a Catholic people, and so they proceeded to claim a deposing power. Erastus feared lest the Presbyterate should do the same, and a glance at the writings of Knox will convince us that his fears were not unreasonable. It is then, I think, not so easy to answer the question, Was Erastus an Erastian? as many people imagine; or if we answer in the affirmative, we shall have to surrender a favourite nickname for our opponents. He was, I believe, less Erastian than Whitgift¹, perhaps less so than Cranmer², far less so than Selden or Hobbes³. Strangely enough, even Pareus uses phrases about the power of the magistrate in religion, which many would call Erastian. As Dr William Cunningham says, "Erastus is less Erastian than some who in modern times have been ranked under that designation, not perhaps without 1 See Defence of the Answer to the Admonition, Tractate xx., Works, III. (295-325), especially p. 306, where he quotes with approval "princes deciding in matters of religion, even in the chief and principal points." 2 See his works passim, more especially the Corrections of the Institution, Questions concerning the Sacraments, II. p. 117. 3 Cf. Lee, preface to the Theses, who says that Erastianism is not to be identified with the tenet of Hobbes that the civil power may establish whatever religion it pleases, and exact obedience to it, which the subject is bound to render for conscience' sake, or even set up any form of Church government it pleases, and change it as often as it likes (XLV. vi.). 4 Aphorisms, § XI. F. 22 338 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM some injustice to him, but most certainly with no injustice to them¹." But though this may be the case, it is not there- fore true either that Erastus was right or that his views have no relation to Erastianism or Byzantinism. He saw one side in a debate which had lasted for centuries, and even yet is hardly concluded. Taught by experience Erastus desired to prevent the es- tablishment of what seemed to him an ecclesiastical tyranny. In the course of his argument he asserted that in a State of one religion all that was needed for the enforcement of piety and morality could and ought to be done by the magistrate; and that for any other persons to assume a coercive control with- out appeal was a usurpation on the one sovereign authority. Yet the powers which he admitted to be the magistrate's were sufficiently large even within the limits laid down. And these limits could not endure. Erastianism is not rightly named, if we mean by it the explicit tenets of Erastus. Yet the attribution is not altogether wrong. For the word describes the actual and inevitable, if not the logical, development of his teachings when torn from their context and shorn of the careful qualifications with which he surrounded them. Erastus did not mean to do more than assert that all coercive authority is vested in the State. But he added to this the prevailing notion that the State must support one religion and tolerate no other. It was then not many steps to the theory of Hobbes that the State could support any religion it pleased out of motives. 1 Hist. Theol. 11. 572. G ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 339 of State policy and with no regard to truth. In fact the power which Erastus claimed for the Christian might soon be asserted to belong to the non-Christian magistrate, although such a claim was far enough from the thought of Erastus and from that of many Erastians. Erastus paved the way for a theory more imposing, more systematic, more antagonistic to reason than his own. For assuredly there is no less reasonable view than that which permits a magistrate to set up a Church on purely political grounds and to prohibit all others. This position, if ever thoroughly carried out, might be more de- structive to free inquiry than any ecclesiastical tyranny. It did not indeed, I think, directly follow from the doctrine of Erastus or the Erastian re- formers. But they might easily be misunderstood or misrepresented as if it did. The opposite (or ecclesiastical) view had held the field, though not unassailed, for centuries. The Re- formation was in one respect the uprising of the laity against the clergy; in another an assertion of State rights against a federal imperialism in Church matters. It was in fact individualist and particularist, as op- posed to a system which was socialistic and centralised. And the circumstances under which it took place made men rely very largely on the prince's authority as their most effective support. It made some re- formers, such as Erastus abroad and Anglicans and many Independents at home, dread the Presbyterian discipline as being the counterpart of that bureau- cratic clericalism from which they believed themselves to have escaped. The Erastians' aim, or that of 22-2 340 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM most of them, whether at Heidelberg or Dort or Westminster, was rather to protect the individual than the State, though the latter object was a good deal more prominent at Westminster. This indeed was the main cause of the later use of the word Erastianism as a term having no reference to excom- munication and a large general reference to State authority. The conflict was inevitable between Church and State, so long as persecution was to be enforced. For such enforcement required the aid of the State, which could not be expected to give it without being consulted. The remedy lay beyond the vision of Erastus and the men of his day, though not far beyond that of some of his op- ponents in the synod of Westminster. With liberty of conscience proclaimed as the State policy, the conflict of the two jurisdictions is at an end for all practical purposes. When the State leaves off the hopeless task of imposing one faith and worship by force, and the Church leaves off preaching perse- cution as a duty, there would be no cause for a serious struggle, and on the principles of Erastus no ground for interfering with the jurisdiction of religious bodies over their members: while the ex- istence of other religious bodies would prevent such jurisdiction doing serious civil damage to a man in cases where the whole community irre- spective of creed was not on his side¹. Excom- munication to be seriously effective needs the Sp 1 For instance, supposing for the sake of argument it were right to excommunicate a man or woman who had married a divorced person. Such an act might have effect on devout Churchmen, ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM 341 absence of competing Churches or systems. But this way out of the difficulty was not clear to Erastus. He, it may be thought, would unduly exalt the State. Certainly Erastians did, just as Olevianus, Knox, and the disciplinarians would use the State as the handmaid of the Church, with more outward deference, but with no more real respect, than Gre- gory VII. or Boniface VIII. Neither party could be at peace so long as Catholics and Protestants alike were agreed as to the import and efficacy of an auto- da-fé as the means of promoting the 'one faith.' For this view made the forces of Church and State ne- cessary to one another, and yet brought them into incessant conflict. The problem was not solved, it was transcended. The battle was over only when men saw that peace being the end of the State, social well-being would be attained by leaving all religious bodies the fullest liberty to organise, to de- velop, and to preach. To employ a familiar method, toleration was the higher unity in which were resolved the contrary, but complementary ideals of secular authority and spiritual independence. The victory was won by both sides and by neither. On the one hand, ecclesiastical pretensions, however preposterous, burnt into men's minds (and indeed their bodies) the sense that society needs some basis other than force. We owe to them the belief that a duty is laid upon men to secure freedom for the expression of spiritual aspirations, a freedom which might otherwise have but unless the general sentiment of the community, Churchmen, Dissenters, and Agnostics, was in favour of it, it would be unlikely to injure such persons seriously in their business or profession. 342 ERASTUS AND ERASTIANISM been sacrificed to the shock of national ambitions or the jealousies of competing dynasties. On the other hand, but for Erastus and his followers, even Hobbes and the supporters of the Divine Right of Kings, who insisted so strongly on the right of the State to be, on the essential need of political society to human well-being, and on the duty of preserving men against the evils of a domination, which on its own showing was human in administration and divine in its sanctions and claims, and therefore likely to be the more unrestrained in its tyranny, there might have been-there nearly was-an agelong enslave- ment of human thought and action to a system in some respects more narrow because more complete, less broadly human, less careful of culture and in- tellectual enlightenment, than was the system of the medieval world taken at its worst. BARTOLUS¹ AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS I THERE are two names which must be well known to anyone who has glanced at the margins of works on law and politics produced in continental countries, in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. With St Augustine, quoted by writers like Althusius more than anyone else, with Innocent IV. the "dominus canonistarum," the master of the Decretalists, a man never to be ignored in the history of thought, there stand out the great twin luminaries of Perugia, Bartolus and Baldus, his pupil, friend and adversary. They are pre-eminent among the forgotten. Grotius and Gentilis and Bodin not merely quote Bartolus, but are what they are largely because of him. Pages might be filled with the epithets of laudation from time to time applied to him. He is the mirror and lamp of the law, his name is not so much that of a man as the very spirit of jurisprudence. Some say that he is the sole authority superior to the Roman 1 I think it best to speak of him by the term by which he is everywhere known and criticised. It seems pedantry to call a man Bartolo, who was never known as such in the only circles which made him famous. But for those who like his full name it is Bartolo Bonacursi da Sassoferrato. 344 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT Rota, while in Spain if there is a defect of law, the opinion of Bartolus is treated as itself decisive. It was said that he held the primacy in the schools, while his authority even in the courts was sacrosanct, and neither professors nor judges dared to contradict his opinion. One writer ushers him into the modern world with the thought of the golden age, when Perugia gave a law to the nations. Ille super cunctos toto celebratus in orbe, Quotquot habent aliquod juris ab arte decus, Bartolus, Astreae datus olim munere ut essent Res hominum miserae prosperiore loco. Even when a later age finds hard of digestion his assertion that to deny that the Emperor is universal lord is probably heretical, it is with humility that his authority is questioned on a similar plea to the "some- times slumbering" of Homer. One author thought it needful to compile a harmony of his apparent inconsistencies; in the Concordantia Contrarietatum of Carolus de Nicellis, three hundred and thirty- seven of such difficulties are resolved. A Papalist writer of a later age¹ avows that his work is written for the benefit of those whose literature is limited, or almost limited, to the works of Bartolus and Baldus. If it was worth the while of a man who has the practical object of extolling the Pope's power to do this, it must surely be worth our while inquiring what sort of mind it would be that this exclusive devotion would produce. My 1 Thomas de Simanca in Roccaberti, Bibliotheca Maxima Pontificalis. OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 345 contention is that it is the kind of mind which for two or three centuries, at least, say from Jean Petit to John Locke, discussed political and cognate problems on a basis which was primarily legalist, and secondarily canonist and scholastic. These remarks are purely tentative, and I fear that to lawyers they may seem either erroneous or trivial or both. But I am convinced that someone will have to make a serious study of the contribution of Bartolus to our world; and a brief paper may at least make suggestions. How came it that it was sufficient to quote Bartolus, and in many cases to ignore his prede- cessors ? Why was Albericus Gentilis able to regard him as the chief of the old lawyers, even though he quotes Baldus more often? A perusal of the ordinary treatises (more especi- ally the continental, but our own Hooker affords an example) on the topics that line the borderland between politics, law, and theology will make clear that there is a certain common element in which all discussion takes place. This atmosphere is compact of a peculiar amalgam of law strictly so called, certain general ideas which are expressed in the civil and canon law, and some common principles of ethical and theological reasoning. All this is responsible partly for the internal structure of the modern state everywhere but in England, and to some extent here¹. It is avowedly the foundation of inter- national law, while for a long time it had a great deal more to do with the methods and subjects of 1 See particularly Maitland, English Law and the Renaissance. 346 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT political speculation than those who live after Bentham and Rousseau are willing to admit. Now, Bartolus (for we may include Baldus who depends on him) is the channel, or one of the main channels, through which this stream of tendency flowed into the modern life. A brief perusal of the writings of Albericus Gentilis, both the De Jure Belli and the Regales Disputationes, will make this point clear; but a glance at Whewell's edition of Grotius, or Bodin, De Republica, would illustrate it. What is the reason of this? That is the first question we must try to answer, and then we shall see some of the more important characteristics of his work. The cause of his influence is twofold, the old explanation, the man and the milieu. Born in 1313, the son of a lawyer, Francesco Bonacursi, he lived at the beginning of the age of transition in Italy, which was earlier there than anywhere else. The last flicker of imperial power which had given reality to the dreams of Dante was over. It was only ten years since Boniface VIII. had "died like a dog." The final victory of the Papacy (now at Avignon) over its imperial victims had been won. Bartolus was the very good servant of Charles IV., and had been on an embassy to win from him privileges for his adopted city and university of Perugia. The Italian cities had established their independence; the Papal and the imperial authorities were both very much in abeyance; and the age of the despots was ap- proaching. The scholastic philosophy had taken its most authoritative shape; and with the addition of the last extravagant' of the Emperor Henry VII. OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 347 the Corpus Juris Civilis had attained its limit, and become within its own covers nearly as strong a witness to the unity of history as the Bible. The Sext had lately been added to the Canon Law by Boniface VIII., and though the various collections of extravagants had not assumed their final form, the system was in all essentials complete. It is remark- able, by the way, that the best life of Bartolus should be by Lancellotti, a canonist himself of no mean repute, the author of Institutes of the Canon Law, sometimes printed at the close of Corpus. More- over, Bartolus had a practical, not merely an academic training. He had been assessor at Todi, where he was alleged (though it has been denied) to have incurred odium by over-torturing a youth; and also at Pisa; before he settled down to his lecture-room at Perugia, the city which was so anxious to retain him that it gave him and his heirs its freedom, lest he should be bought up by another place, like a professional' of a different order¹. This, then, was the situation. A practical, no less than a theoretical training placed a man of commanding abilities at the head of his profession in the days when the Roman law was becoming daily more influential (except in England), but when the Emperor's authority was less than ever, and his subservience to the Pope extreme. The Italy of that day was rapidly developing those conditions which were to make the international politics of modern Europe find their models in the balance established by 1 The documents, as also that conferring the doctorate, are printed at large in Lancellotti. 348 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT Cosimo de' Medici, and to cause the political philo- sophy of the Renaissance to bow to its prince in Machiavelli. Tyranny was becoming both a fact and a danger, while circumstances tended to an amalgamation of both sides of the law of the empire, civil and canon. The terms Guelphs and Ghibellines had lost their own meaning and become the mere symbol of political partisanship, and are so treated by Bartolus-party spirit for legitimate ends being justified by the cry of St Paul, “I am a Pharisee, the son of a Pharisee¹." The world then in which Bartolus lived was in the transition stage. We must remember that the predominance of Roman law is rather a modern than a medieval fact, the 'reception' in Germany dates from 1495. Hence it came about that any mind capable of that peculiar combination of scholarship and actuality, which can at once distil the learning of the past and assimilate the facts of the present, might easily preserve for future generations everything that was of living force in the period that was drawing to its close, and at the same time suggest some of the thoughts which should dominate the future. Such a mind was that of Bartolus. He was the heir of all the ages," and also in "the foremost files of time." First and foremost a Roman jurist, he was (6 1 Note his derivation of the terms Guelph and Ghibelline. "Sicut Gebellus interpretatur locus fortitudinis, ita Gebellini interpretantur confidentes in fortitudine scilicet tempore militum et armorum; et sicut Guelpha interpretatur os loquens, ita Guelphi interpretantur confidentes orationibus et in divinis." This is from the tractate De Guelphis et Ghibellinis which is really a treatise on civil factions and rebellion. OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 349 many other things besides. The law was to him not so much a pursuit as a passion. It was said that the whole civil law had been transformed into the very blood and sap of his being; and he speaks of laws, dry and impersonal though they appear to us, with a real affection, as deserving letters of gold, good, &c., as one praises a good child; in his discourse on his brother's doctorate he compares the noble edifice of jurisprudence to the many mansions of "our Father's house," with room for many and various individu- alities¹. Whatever problem he is solving, the question in his mind is always, what is it legally right to do— and this even in cases where laws fail and you go to theologians. Now this characteristic is at the root of the methods of political discussion right through the next four centuries, and is the explanation of much that seems to us ridiculous, alike in the theory of the divine right of kings, in the doctrine of the original contract, and in international law. The same notion is the vice of most systems of ethics, and is partly responsible for 'probabilism.' It is largely the determining element of the various attempts of the confessional era in theology to cry- stallise and jurify the mysteries of God's providence 1 "In domo patris mei mansiones multae sunt....Hoc est civilis sapientiae mansiones multae sunt, quidam enim ad legendum in civitatibus regiis assumuntur, quidam ad advocandum in curiis principum et regiis attrahuntur, alii ad consulendum in cameris assidue requiruntur, alii ad consilium principum assumuntur. Hi enim sunt quibus Respublica regenda committitur. Istae sunt hujus sapientiae mansiones, propter quas quilibet Jurista securus et gratiosus redditur" (Bartolus, Sermo in doctoratu domini Joannis a Saxoferrato, x. 223). 350 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT and man's freedom. Now it is this fact which enabled Bartolus to assimilate and utilise all other sources of knowledge open at this time, and also to influence departments of his life other than the purely legal. He had the childlikeness of the true scholar, and the susceptibility to mental im- pressions of a mind that was ever alive. There is no sign of his possessing the aesthetic sensibilities that we associate with the Renaissance. We are told that he took his food by weight and walked with his eyes intent, speculative rather than ob- servant. His gaze was in fact inward, and he absorbed intellectual rather than artistic culture. In this respect he was a medieval. Trained in the scholastic philosophy he had that habit of giving rational, even if erroneous, explanations of things, which will never be content with mere appearances. He supplies, for instance, philosophical grounds for all the colours of heraldry, thereby evoking the ridicule of Lorenzo Valla, who can see no value except that which meets his eye¹. His style may be, what the Renaissance scholar calls it, rather rustic than classical, less Latin than barbarian; but it is a style eminently sincere, direct, and expressive. Whether the laboured pedantry of Renaissance classicism was altogether an improve- ment may not be quite so certain as Valla thought. 1 Compare such books as Blackwood's Apologia pro Regibus, or still more, the stilted pedantry of the polite oration in favour of Mary Stuart published in Teulet's Relations Diplomatiques, and see on the whole subject Creighton, The Early Renaissance in England. 2 Valla's treatise is a little letter on the subject published as OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 351 The fact is that one of the results of the Renaissance has been to substitute journalistic im- pressionism for reasoning and thought. This is true, even of Erasmus and Luther. The scholastic philo- sophy may deserve much that is said against it, but it did make its votaries educated men and not mere "pickers-up of unconsidered trifles." All this is illustrated by Bartolus. The extent to which he had assimilated the teaching of St Thomas is shewn by his treatise De Testimoniis¹, also by the work I have already mentioned, De Insigniis et Armis. The latter is said by its German editor, Hauptmann, to be the earliest extant treatise on heraldry. It is very interesting to compare it with Valla's criticism, for they represent the clash of two worlds, and no mere personal difference. Bartolus sets forth the principles of heraldry and tries to determine a philosophical significance for every colour and every sign. Valla scoffs at the Latin, ridicules the notion of finding any meaning in the colour, such as gold representing the sun, the noblest of all colours, and demands what need there is of any order beyond that of mere caprice and individual taste. His words might have been written by a scholarly Englishman of the eighteenth century, who liked good Latin, but to whom the bare idea of meaning an appendix to the Apologia, which he wrote to secure himself against the charge of heresy. 1 See especially the passage about Prudence. It is noteworthy, by the way, that he declares expert witnesses to be really judges rather than witnesses proper. 352 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT in gesture or form was distasteful. In their dislike of all regulations they breathe the same spirit as Rabelais's vision of the Abbey of Theleme. Bartolus was perhaps too apt to find the universal in every particular, like that later philosopher who found the Idea incarnate in the constitution of the Prussian State. But at least he had a careful and reasoned view of things as a whole, and was not led astray by the cleverness which mistakes the novel for the true, and kills individuality by an excess of individualism. This little treatise illustrates another trait of the author, his naïf interest in himself. In order to illustrate his views about the quarterings on the shield in a coat of arms, he introduces a personal incident. The question is about the meaning of the left or the right side of the shield. He tells us of a dispute he had with the Jew who once taught him Hebrew¹. Bartolus had declared that the Jews must be barbarians, because they wrote "strange characters from right to left," and repeats the whole discussion about the effect of reading on the eye. In the same way he constantly introduces personal touches to illustrate the most abstract theme. Speaking of the Roman law of emancipation of children, he explains how a certain friar, Peter of Assisi, had a school for foundlings at Venice, and often made it a condition. of giving up these 'boarded-out' children that they should be actually adopted. This man, he tells us, was his first teacher and was of great piety. He owed him a debt of gratitude, for he taught him so 1 § 29, pp. 22-3. OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 353 well that at the age of fourteen he was able to learn civil law from Cino da Pistoia. Here he made such progress that he was able to go to Bologna and get his doctorate in his twenty-first year. Then he adds one of those touches which help us to stretch hands across the ages: Ex multo amore quem ad illius fratris Petri bonitatem gero, cum calamus hoc scribit, cordis oculus lacrymatur¹." I do not think anyone can read that for the first time in its place without loving the writer. How different from Wyclif, the most disagreeable beyond exception of all mediæval thinkers! Other touches come in at times: the De insigniis is written partly at least, as he says, because he had received from Charles IV. the right to bear arms. He tells us what they are-a lion rouge on or. He writes his treatise on the Ad reprimendum of Henry VII. in honour of his grandson Charles IV., who made him what we should call a Privy Coun- cillor, and granted him and all his heirs who were doctors of law the right to legitimate bastards. He spent a summer holiday at Tivoli, and this is the origin of his treatise De Alveo et Flumine. When- ever any law can be illustrated by a present fact or a case in his experience as judge, he tells it, e.g. the state of parties in Todi where it was the custom to put Guelphs and Ghibellines in equal numbers on the council. To illustrate the power of the Emperor before coronation he relates his embassy to Charles 1 VI. 53. I quote throughout from Lyons edition of his works, 1547. This little touch brought harm to Bartolus. In consequence, people said he must have been himself illegitimate. F. 23 354 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT and quotes the words of the charter he issued to Perugia. On the subject of banishment he speaks of the banished "of our time," when every city had its exiles, and proves that they lose civic rights only, not the common rights of Roman citizens. Common law means, of course, to him, here and always, Roman law; the idea of national law being common would have seemed a contradiction. His treatise on re- prisals, which had much to do with international law, was written to suit the actual facts of Italy. So with the work on the tyrant, written to point out and if possible, obviate, a very real, immediate danger. All this illustrates the freshness of his mind, and its constant attention to practical needs, even amid abstruse legal reasoning. His method, on the other hand, is the dialectical one of St Thomas, to state opinions on both sides with authorities, and then to give his own. This method has the great merit that it enables a man to use his selective powers without mere aiming at eccentricity, and that it prevents him, as a rule, overlooking considerations of importance. Lorenzo Valla may scoff at it, but as a means of reaching the truth, especially in legal matter, it is infinitely superior to the slipshod literary brilliancy which came in with the Renaissance, and has been on all non-scientific subjects steadily gaining ground from the days of Aeneas Sylvius to those of Mr Richard Le Gallienne. Here, then, is the man so far as I can see him. A born student with a child's delight in his subject and in himself, but a man's intellect a spirit alive with all the tendencies of the time, which had in D OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 355 Y them anything analogous to legal questions; a mind trained in the scholastic philosophy, with a faith in its method and a desire for rational explanations; a memory in which facts, personal, political, legal, stuck, observant of all existing political facts and discerning tendencies only beginning-essentially an "intellectual," yet without conceit, but not without vanity, with a strong grasp of the practical aspect of abstract reasoning, and no desire at all merely to weave metaphysical cobwebs; a mind alert, vivid, with an imagination indeed, but one occupied not about beauty of form or colour, but about law and government. Such a mind was eminently fitted to sum up in itself the long ages of legal development, and to suggest the lines of future advance. II. Now let us try to estimate the actual contri- bution of Bartolus in this respect. Bartolus may be described as an Imperialist- with a difference. That difference it is which made his views so influential in the future. At first sight he holds the theory of the world-monarchy of the Emperor as absolutely as Bozius held it of the Papacy. The Emperor has all laws in scrinio pec- toris; Imperial laws are the only laws which are universal; all else are merely particular facts. All rebellion may be condemned, because kings are really Imperial officers. Even the kings of England and France, whatever they may say, are subjects of the Roman Empire; it is (probably) heresy to doubt the universal lordship of the Emperor, and for that 23-2 356 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT reason is only natural in Jews, or Saracens or Greeks. Quod principi placuit legis habet vigorem is true, though it is decent to consult people. On the "digna vox" he admits that the Emperor is under the laws, but by self-imposed compulsion, not necessity, although he is bound to keep treaties with cities, because "pacta sunt de jure gentium.' This latter is the notion which both gave significance to the idea of the original contract and also enabled · Grotius to found his system. "" He clearly holds the usual maxims that whatever the sovereign permits he commands, and sovereignty is inalienable¹. But-and here comes in the positive 1 This is the most important passage on the subject: "Duo sunt genera gentium principaliter, primo populus Ro- manus, secundo populi extranei. Circa primum quaero quis dicatur populus Romanus....Diceres tu: cum modicae gentes sint, quae Romano Imperio obediant ; ergo videtur, quod sit parvus populus Romanus. Respondeo, quaedam sunt gentes, quae Imperio Romano obediunt; et istae sine dubio sunt de populo Romano. Quaedam sunt quae non obediunt Romano Imperio in totum, sed in aliquibus obediunt; ut quia vivunt secundum legem populi Romani, et Imperatorem Romanorum esse dominum omnium fatentur, ut sunt civitates Tusciae, Lombardiae et similes; et isti etiam sunt de populo Romano. Nam cum populus Romanus in eis exerceat jurisdictionem in aliquo articulo totam jurisdictionem retinet.... Quidam sunt populi, qui nullo modo obediunt Principi nec istis legibus vivunt, et hoc dicunt se facere ex privilegio Imperatoris ; et isti similiter sunt de populo Romano: ut faciunt Veneti. Nam cum illam libertatem ipsi habere se dicant ab Imperio Romano, et privilegio quodam modo precario tenent ab eo, et posset privilegium illud revocare, quando vellet; cum ei liceat mutare voluntatem suam....Quidam sunt populi qui non obediunt principi tamen asserunt se habere libertatem ab ipso ex contractu aliquo, ut provinciae, quae tenentur ab ecclesia Romana, quae fuerunt donatae ab Imperatore Constantino...adhuc dico istos de populo Romano OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 357 quality of Bartolus' mind-law is one thing and fact another. In the first place, writing in Papal terri- tory he has no doubt of the Pope's final supremacy; the people have no power now, however much the lex regia originally reserved to them; the electors alone elect, and the Pope alone can deprive; the Pope has only transferred authority to the secular prince'. The Pope is above the civil law. Any law esse. Nam ecclesia Romana exercet in illas terras jurisdictionem quae erat Imperii Romani, et istud fatentur; non ergo desinunt esse de populo Romano; sed administratio istarum provinciarum est alteri concessa....Jurisdictio in clericos est concessa totaliter Papae, desinuntne propter hoc clerici esse cives Romani? Et idem dico de istis aliis Regibus et Principibus, qui negant se esse subditos Regi Romanorum; ut Rex Francie, Anglie et similes. Si enim fatentur ipsum esse dominum universalem, licet ab illo universali domino se subtrahant ex privilegio, vel consimili, non desinunt esse cives Romani, propter ea quae dicta sunt; et secundum hoc quasi omnes gentes qui obediunt sanctae Romanae ecclesiae sunt de populo Romano. Et forte si quis diceret dominum Imperatorem non esse dominum et monarcham totius orbis, esset haereticus" (De captivis et postliminio, vi. 237). 'Primo fuit imperium Babylonis. Secundo fuit imperium Persarum et Medorum. Tertio fuit imperium Graecorum. Quarto fuit imperium Romanorum. Ultimo adveniente Christo istud Romanorum imperium incoepit esse Christi Imperium; et ideo apud Christi vicarium est uterque gladius, spiritualis et temporalis. Christus enim est Lapis abscissus sine manibus cujus regnum non dissipabitur de quo prophetavit Daniel....Dico ergo quod ante Christum Imperium Romanum dependebat ab eo solo; et Imperator recte dicebatur, quod dominus mundi esset, et quod omnia sua sint. Post Christum vero Imperium est apud Christum et ejus vicarium et transfertur per Papam in principem secularem" (Tractatus super "Ad reprimendum," x. 91). There is a passage in some sixteenth century writer-I think François Hotman, but cannot give the reference-which asserts that Bartolus had no real belief in the Papal right, but plane ludit, saying himself it was only because he was too near Rome to deny it. 358 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT that makes other folk more audacious or the clergy more timid is ipso facto invalid (what a pity it isn't so now!). A text of the Decretale is as good an authority to cite as one from the code. He proves that an oath to alienate any part of 'regality' is invalid by a quotation from Innocent III. in the Decretale. Elsewhere he finds sufficient authority in a gloss of Innocent IV. on a text of the Decretale¹. His treatise on the differences between civil and canon law is in no sense a treatise on the laws of two societies, but rather a disquisition, only less acrimonious-like that on the rules of the civil and military departments of India. Any one subject to the Church is in a sort a member of the Empire, and everyone who, willingly or not, uses its law. The truth is that the Code, as crystallised by Justinian, is not an ancient or merely secular document-it is post-Augustinian, and the conception in it of the place of Christianity is emi- nently mediæval. The Holy Roman Empire was in fact the creation of Justinian even more than it was of Charles the Great; and later Papalists are able to make great play with the ecclesiastical provisions of the civil law; and, indeed, this is doubtless the reason. why Bartolus tells us that even at Rome there were more legists than canonists. I do not mean that Justinian's views were Hildebrandine, but they were mediæval, and the law of the Church is a part of the - 1 It is to be observed that to Bartolus the Decretale is still known as merely a body of extravagants.' " OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 359 law of the Empire. Church and State are not sepa- rate societies, but the same community is one or the other according to the point of view, and there are of course special laws for one class—the clergy. All this goes to shew how Bartolus made straight the path of his successors. By treating the Papal and Imperial Laws as part of one system, and making the civil law a sort of ideal (often contradicted by facts) he paved the way for those who in a later age were to treat of laws in general, natural, ecclesiastical, civil, all as one part of the State; and while they acknowledged the supremacy of the civil law as a norm or ideal, found no difficulty in tempering it either by particular statutes or the principles of the canonists and theologians. The commentaries of the civilian Bartolus are the condition of those treatises, mainly Spanish, of the sixteenth century, of writers like Soto, Navarra or Covarruvias; or to quote the best known example, Suarez. What they made into one system Bartolus foreshadowed by his mode of treating the Corpus Juris Civilis. But this is not all. The Pope is not the only fact in the lawyer's universe. There are the states, more especially the Italian cities. Here Bartolus makes the great distinction, which Gierke himself declares to be of such importance in paving the way for the modern doctrine of sovereignty. He divides his states into those which do and those which do not as a fact recognise a superior. Law may be with the Emperor, but fact is with the cities; conse- quently even Imperial laws do not abrogate their 360 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT statutes, because they are merely facts, and the Emperor is presumed to be ignorant of facts. Since, moreover, these facts exist, in such places the whole sovereignty is imperialiter in them, as our own Richard II. thought; yet Bartolus was a true Italian, and never worried about the ultramontane, barbarian peoples. It was of Italian cities that he was thinking. This was the origin of his treatise on reprisals¹ written expressly to consider conditions in which states were de facto independent, and resting there- fore, as he says, rather on divine than positive law (whether civil or canon). That treatise had a good deal to do with the development of international law, and a perusal of it along with Albericus Gentilis or Grotius will shew how far this was the case. Thus, then, Bartolus qualified the purely legal character of the civil law by insisting on its wider aspects. At the same time that he treated of all questions on a basis largely legal, he prepared the way for the civil law to become the received juris- prudence of most countries by shewing it to be de 1 (6 Represaliarum materia nec frequens, nec quotidiana erat tempore quo in statu debito Romanum vigebat Imperium, ad ipsum enim tanquam ad summum monarcham habebatur regressus, et ideo hanc materiam legum doctores et antiqui juris interpretes minime pertractaverunt. Postquam vero peccata nostra meruerunt quod Romanum Imperium prostratum jaceret per tempora multa, et Reges et principes ac etiam civitates, maxime in Italia, saltem de facto in temporalibus dominum non agnoscerent, propter quod de injustitia ad superiorem non potest haberi regressus, coeperunt represaliae frequentari et sic effecta est frequens et quotidiana materia" (De Represaliis, x. 117). OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 361 facto independent of the Emperor. He combined it with the canon law and the scholastics in his com- mentaries, and paved the way for the universal systems of the sixteenth century out of which grew both modern politics and international law, while he definitely recognised the actual attributes of terri- torial sovereignty wherever they existed as a fact¹. Thus he helped forward the assumption of the family of the states independent, self-sufficient, yet recognising the common jus gentium, which is the foundation of modern Europe. Two only of his special treatises need be mentioned. The work De Regimine Civitatis is written, he says, because the universales domini often ask the opinion of lawyers or government; and though the universalis dominus has changed, the sovereign people seems still to do the same. It is written for lawyers, and though well aware of the views of Giles of Rome and Aristotle, he will take nothing for granted, but tests their opinion by the law and gives his own view. What is remarkable is the sanity of his judgment and desire to stick to his facts. He agrees that in theory monarchy is the best form of government, but we must consider place and circumstances. Unity, its great aim, must not be sacrificed to jus- tice. Like all true libertarians he puts character above efficiency. The pursuit of the latter as its 1 66 Equiparatio jurisdictionis ad dominum: Si princeps con- cederet tibi universaliter unum territorium, videtur tibi concedere universaliter jurisdictionem; quia sicut ille qui concedit universale territorium, videtur concedere jurisdictionem, quae est idem quod dominum alicujus rei particularis" (1. 53). 362 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT own end always leads straight to Machiavelli. He argues that we must consider, not abstract prin- ciples, but the probable effect of government on the citizens. States are of three sizes: a small city cannot afford a court without oppression, and ought to have a direct democracy—or rather the democracy should delegate power to officials. He knows nothing of a representative assembly. It is worthy of note that practical experience of the evils of excessive taxation and tyranny in a small city should be the real ground of this opinion. The second class of cities, with some territory beyond, like Venice and Florence, should be governed by an aristocracy, who will combine fair administration with the knowledge acquired only by a governing class. The third class, or country states, as we should call them, require a monarch. He prefers election to succession, as being magis divinum, for the heart of electors is in the hand of God (would he say so now?); otherwise unity will be impossible, and re- bellion will become inextinguishable. This is clearly the way in which facts reflected themselves in the writer's mind. The larger states, every one of them, only acquired unity by going through a period of despotism: Venice remained for ages a splendid ex- ample of a ruling aristocracy; and where the single cities fell into the hands of a tyrant, they endured the evils of pure monarchy with few or none of its advantages. It has been said that in this doctrine of the relativity of political theories Bartolus was in advance of his time and had little influence, and that Montesquieu was the first who took up the same g OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 363 notion¹. But I think that Savonarola had it, for he argues that while monarchy is the best form of government, as is proved by the Papacy, for Florence a democracy is the only way to secure justice; nor are there wanting other writers who are by no means exclusive in favouring one form of government. Indeed, one of Bellarmine's arguments for the Papal power was that Aristotelian arguments that might do for a city state could have no reference to what was in reality an empire. Machiavelli himself was really a republican, and only desired a prince as a saviour of society. At the same time, it is doubt- less true that Bartolus differed from most writers (like St Thomas) of his own or succeeding days in regarding circumstances, history, and size as of more importance in fixing the form of government than abstract reasoning and ideal perfection. But one thing is clear, he feared tyrants in the Italian cities. Probably his treatise On Tyranny 2 was the best known of his works to all but specialists. It is remarkable for what it omits no less than what it contains. Unlike the numerous writers of the next centuries, he does not discuss how far resistance to a tyrant in defence of religion is allowable; for he is concerned with tyranny in places at least nominally subject to the Emperor or the Pope. There is therefore in appearance none of the originality or 1 Cf. C. Salvemini, La Teoria del Bartolo da Sassoferrato sulle Costituzioni politiche in his Studi Storici. 2 On the whole history of the treatment of tyranny cf. Lossen's valuable lecture, Die Lehre von Tyrannenmord in der christlichen Zeit. 364 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT brilliancy which startles the reader of John of Salisbury two centuries earlier, or the audacity of Jean Petit nearly a century later. Yet for all that Bartolus' tractate was of great influence; for it fixed the method of discussion for a couple of centuries. He introduced the great distinction, not to be found in St Thomas or earlier writers, between the tyrannus absque titulo and the tyrannus de exercitio. The former is the usual Greek tyrant who gets power without the laws. But Bartolus, as always, was con- cerned with facts, and wanted to point out the actual danger of tyranny under the forms of law, whether it be mere despotism or oppression. He feared alike a Cosimo de' Medici and an Eccelin Romano. Con- sequently he dwells much on the point that tyranny has many disguises, and points out its various forms. It is, by the way, notable that the suppressing con- gregationes etiam licitae is one of these. These evidences of the tyranny, and still more the two kinds of tyrant, are the commonplaces of discussion for three centuries; and Albericus Gentilis recognises this in one place. It is noteworthy that Bartolus decides that a tyrant absque titulo is guilty of treason as offending against the Lex Julia de Majestate, while a tyrant de exercitio falls under the Lex Julia de Vi Publica. G Can this have any reference, remote or indirect, to the temper of the mind which condemned Charles I. for treason against his people? At any rate Bartolus' view of a tyrant as to some extent a rebel-of course against a 'prince'-must be taken in connection with his treatment of rebellion and declaration that a OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 365 rebel may be killed at sight without process of law. This occurs in the tractate on the Ad reprimendum of Henry VII., and must surely have had to do with the views of Jean Petit. The latter held, as we all know, that a tyrant-by which was meant a traitor— might be killed by anyone; and this view was con- demned by the Council of Constance. Now, though Jean Petit says distinctly he is not a jurist, and omits to quote Bartolus as an authority, it seems almost certain that the great authority of the latter and the general influence of his views must have had a real, if unconscious or at least indirect effect on the mind of Jean Petit¹. However this may be, there is no doubt that one chief point in that great dis- cussion which filled the sixteenth century, what must be done with a tyrant, turned upon Bartolus' dis- tinction between the man who was legally a usurper and the king who was actually an oppressor, and that later writers consciously depend on him. Fur- ther he must have the credit of foreseeing and desiring, so far as possible, to ward off the danger of that age of the despots in Italy, from which not all its culture can ever remove the stains of cruelty and corruption. Moreover, Bartolus saw the evils of the ungoverned state of Central Italy with the Papacy at Avignon. He deplored the multiplicity of tyrants in Rome, "formerly the best, now, alas! the worst governed city in the world." He saw with a reflect- ing eye the evils of his day rampant or incipient. He distrusted the attempt to lay down purely abstract 1 Jean Petit's writing and the relevant discussion fill a whole folio volume of Dupin's edition of Gerson's works. 366 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT systems of politics, which has been the besetting sin of reformers from the days of Dante, who had just written the swan-song of the empire, to those of Rousseau or Karl Marx. He demanded practical remedies, by which he meant, not mere rule of thumb, but forms and measures of government carefully thought out with a view to actual and historical circumstances. He had no illusion about schemes of perfect justice and freedom, but desired those which under particular conditions would, in all probability, have the best normal effect on human life and character. He is thus removed at once from the system-monger and the Machiavellian. Neither abstract reason nor a conscienceless saviour of society came within his view; yet he knows that without intelligence human affairs will fall into con- fusion, that the sentiment of philanthropy is not enough; and he is aware, like Machiavelli, that circumstances alter cases, and desperate conditions may require desperate remedies. He is the type of the sane reformer who considers and reasons upon facts; for Machiavelli's own doctrine, so positive in appearance, if rigidly interpreted, becomes, and in- deed became, only another system, that of 'reason of state' supplanting conscience and abolishing law, both natural and civil. It is, however, by a jeu d'esprit that many people have known Bartolus best; the title is Processus Satanae contra Divam Virginem coram Iudice Jesu. This once famous work is a specimen of that medi- æval humour which is to us both grotesque and OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 367 unintelligible, and at times seems almost blasphe- mous. The little book is the supposed account of a trial with Christ as Judge between Satan and the Virgin Mary. Satan demands the condemnation of the human race, and the Virgin defends and eventu- ally secures acquittal. The piece, as fooling, appears very poor. It illustrates, however, the way in which the Virgin had entirely supplanted Christ, to the mediæval mind, as the real mediator; for our Lord appears as judge merely. It also illustrates the way in which the rules of the civil and canon laws are treated as equally binding authorities, and of course the forensic view of the Atonement, which perhaps reaches its limit in this piece. There is an interesting citation of the famous text "Quod principi placuit legis habet vigorem." The judge has fixed a Wed- nesday for the hearing of the case: to this the Devil objects as being a dies non. But he is told that the prince is above the rules of law, and on the doctrine of imperial pleasure the date is retained. But is this tract Bartolus' work at all? It is printed so in all collections. But an editor in the seventeenth century denies the fact. And although Savigny in his extremely unilluminating account of Bartolus appears ignorant that the authenticity has been questioned, I think that it can hardly be genuine. Goldast points out that the date alone (1311) makes the attribution to Bartolus impossible; for he was not born till (1312), although many authorities make him earlier. This alone is not conclusive, for nothing would be easier than for a couple of X's to slip out in the manuscript, and he might easily have written 368 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT it in 1330. If he did, we may feel that at any rate the quality of undergraduate squibs has improved since the day of Bartolus. The same writer also points out how the mistake occurs; which, he says, was due to interpreting the letters BAR as Bartolus, whereas it really meant Andreas Barbatius. The objection to this is that Barbatius appears to have been later still in date, though there may have been one earlier. So far as internal evidence goes, it seems to me against Bartolus; the whole thing is thin and jejune and pedantic; it neither has the gravity nor the sense of reality nor the freshness and vitality which occur in his other work, and it seems to me altogether the work of an inferior mind. This of course is not conclusive-the minds of students, and of some who are not students, were very much inferior when they were undergraduates to what they became afterwards. At the same time I think the balance inclines slightly to the negative side. There is one more interesting piece of higher criticism in regard to Bartolus. This comes from the pen of L. P. Lancellotti. He, too, was a Perugian of the sixteenth century, and he is concerned to defend his countryman Baldus from an unmerited slur. The story is this. On one occasion Baldus and Bartolus had a dispute on a point of law. The latter cited a particular passage of the Code; Baldus alleged that it was a misquotation. Bartolus, whose memory was like a phonograph, felt sure he was right, and recourse was had to copy. This con- firmed Baldus to the great discomfiture of the older man. But he was not so easily outdone. He felt G OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 369 so certain of his recollection that he suspected foul play, and accordingly sent or went to consult the original MS. at Pisa. He triumphed, and was able to shew that Baldus had been tampering with the MSS., merely to secure a dialectical victory. There- upon Baldus was flogged, some said on the nose, others said elsewhere, others in effigy; others that Bartolus begged him off. At any rate, Baldus al- luded to it in his own writings, for in commenting on the law he used the words "Propter hanc legem ego fui factus episcopus." This alluded to the habit of putting on the floggee a cap something like a mitre. Lancellotti subjects this story to a criticism which for lucidity, persuasiveness, and weight might be the work of Dr Driver or the Bishop of Ely. He points out how many discrepancies there are in the story of the flogging; how difficult it must have been to tamper with all the MSS. in so large a uni- versity as Perugia. He adds that had Baldus been so deeply humiliated, he would be unlikely to have spoken in such constant terms of praise of his master whenever he mentions him. Two passages in which he seems to take a more hostile line are examined and explained-for nobody ever supposes he held the same legal views on every question. Lastly Lancel- lotti relates how he met someone in Rome and defied him to find the above-mentioned passage in which Baldus cryptically related his misfortunes. This friend declared it to be well known, but after long searching gave up the task in vain. Then he points out how Bartolus did have a dispute with someone over a point, and they both agreed without arrière pensée G F. 24 370 BARTOLUS AND THE DEVELOPMENT to go to Pisa and consult the original-only there was no forgery, no flogging, and no Baldus in the matter. The intellectual power and ingenuity of this criticism and its thoroughness are far in advance of the age or of the importance of the actual subject. But they are perhaps worth noting. Yet the world to which such things could matter has long vanished. Arid indeed seem to us the controversies of men who are barely names. "Dust and ashes, dead and done with," the matter of the charge, the subject of the dispute, and the doctored antagonists. We hardly care to imagine that crowded lecture-room which Bartolus one day declared to be empty because his real audience, Baldus, was absent: nor does it interest us to be told that once the pupil so browbeat the professor that he had to take a day to consider the point, being unequal to immediate reply. He whose fame filled Europe with its echoes has not now even his collected works at our great university libraries. Gone are the law-schools of the middle ages-gone, it seems, more than their archi- tecture, their religion, or even their dress. The world of ideas in which they lived seems strange to us; nor can we conceive it needful for a lawyer even to consider the question of what were the property rights of Lazarus when he rose from the dead¹. Bartolus' treatment of this topic is, I should say, another reason against his having written the Pro- cessus: the tone is quite different. It is hard for us to gain even a mental image of that mind, so eminently doctus in utroque jure, which held in its 1 As a matter of fact, Mr. H. G. Wells in When the Sleeper Wakes does consider a very similar question. OF EUROPEAN POLITICAL IDEAS 371 grasp the scholastic theology, the civil and canon law; which quotes Justinian, De Summa Trinitate et Fide Catholica, to prove that gold is the highest colour in heraldry, and surveys the affairs of the whole human race from a standpoint at once more and less juristic than that of the modern lawyer. For when everything is seen under legal forms, the notion of law is itself wider and more universal than that of modern legalism. If you narrow theology and refrigerate ethics, you humanise law by the process. The point is that Bartolus, in spite and perhaps because of our having forgotten him, is alive in the world of to-day, alive in its international code, in its notions of territorial sovereignty, and the tone of political discussions at any rate but recently ended. To influence the modern world the apparently closed system of the civil law had to develope and embrace fresh elements. Like the Roman Church, in Newman's phrase, "She changes that she may remain the same." One of the chief minds which helped in this neces- sary developement was that of Bartolus: he helped to make it possible to 'receive' the civil law, and while acknowledging allegiance to the ancient world to adopt more or less unconsciously much that was of Christian and mediæval origin; he influenced the political Renaissance of Europe, and he helped to make it a true developement, even where it was dis- guised under the form of a revolution. I do not say that his work was always beneficial, or that freedom did not, as Stubbs says, suffer in all places and at all times by the Roman law; indeed some of our dangers to-day arise from a conception of societies and of the 24-2 372 BARTOLUS individual, which is abstract and Latin instead of Teutonic and real. But at any rate, the world did so develope, and Bartolus was one, if not the main link in the chain of causes. How far his mind was great or truly original let others say, more skilled in law. But I am sure that he is one of those minds which help to carry over to one age the thoughts of another, and transmit by transmuting the intellectual heritage of their day. And so he unites us both to the world he lived in, and the law he interpreted. He speaks to us from kinship with the schoolmen on the one hand and the Caesars on the other. He helps us to see how the bed of that river Tiber, on which he once discoursed, has carried along with its soil the hopes and the thoughts and the dreams of men for longer than we care to think. Even England could not quite escape the influence of the Roman law; and even Roman law could not remain merely Roman or purely legal, and these two facts are the key, not indeed to the reality, but largely to the form of the intellectual world even of to-day. In the structural develop- ment of society and the fundamental topics of human discussion there has been more continuity than in outward history; and despite all their differences the thoughts of men form a more living unity than their empires or even their roads. Bartolus may or may not be interesting, or great, or important; but I am sure that he is significant. I am sure that it is by trying for a little to think his thoughts that we shall be better able to know ourselves¹. 1 The Lyons edition ends with a colophon with the device Γνῶθι σεαυτόν, while each volume begins with the lion among bees "de forte dulcedo." APPENDIX A EXTRACTS FROM STATUTES RELATING TO THE SUCCESSION THE progress of the idea of inherent right and the complete decay of the doctrine of election may be illustrated from the statutes passed between 1483 and 1603, which attempt to settle or declare the succession. (1) In the titulus regius, which gave the Crown to Richard III., we see the two notions of elective kingship and title by inheritance blended together. It is noteworthy that the statute seems to regard Parlia- ment in the light of a supreme court competent to declare the law without appeal, rather than as a legislative body creating new law. Parliament claims no right to alter the succession, but merely to declare it, so as to remove perplexity. "We consider that ye be the undoubted son and heir of Richard, late Duke of York, very inheritor of the said crown and dignity royal, and as in right King of England by way of inheritance;...and by this our writing choose you High and Mighty Prince, our King and Sovereign Lord. To whom we know it apper- taineth of inheritance so to be chosen…………….. We pray and require your most noble grace that according to this 374 EXTRACTS FROM STATUTES election of us the three estates of this land; as by your true inheritance you will accept and take upon you the said Crown and royal dignity with all things thereunto annexed and appertaining as to you of right belong- ing as well by inheritance, as by lawful election....... Albeit that the right title and estate which our Sovereign Lord the King Richard the Third hath to and in the Crown...of England...been just and lawful as grounded upon the laws of God and of nature; and also upon the ancient laws and customs of this said realm and so taken and reputed by all such persons as been learned in the above said laws and customs; yet nevertheless for as much as it is considered, that the most part of the people is not sufficiently learned in the above said laws and customs, whereby the truth and right in this behalf, of likelihood may be hid and not clearly known to all the people, and thereupon put in doubt and question. And over this, how that the court of Parliament is of such authority and the people of this land of such a nature and disposition, as experience teacheth, that manifestation and declaration of any truth or right made by the three estates of the realm assembled in Parliament, and by the authority of the same maketh before all other things most faith and certain, and quieting of men's minds removeth the occasion of all doubts and seditious language, therefore &c."-Speed's History, 724. (2) The statute granting the Crown to Henry VII. is far different in its businesslike brevity of tone. In this the authority of Parliament to do what it wills with the succession is unmistakeably implied. "Be it ordained established and enacted by authority of this present Parliament that the inheritance of the Crowns of the Realms of England and France with RELATING TO THE SUCCESSION 375 all the preeminence and dignity royal to the same appertaining...be, rest, remain, and abide in the most royal person of our now Sovereign Lord, King Henry the Seventh and the heirs of his body...and in none other.”—Statutes of the Realm, 11. 499. (3) The statute declaring Elizabeth queen, although it admits her title by descent, and is fulsome in tone, yet has no scruple about regarding an Act of Parliament as the true title to the Crown. The second clause ratifies Henry's testamentary disposition and thus traverses the doctrine of hereditary succession. "Your highness is rightly, lineally and lawfully descended and come out of the blood royal of this Realm of England in and to......whose princely person ......the imperial and royal estate, place, crown, and dignity are and shall be most fully...invested and incor- porated,......as the same were since the Act of Parliament made in the thirty-fifth year of King Henry the Eighth. ......For which causes...... we beseech that it may be enacted, That as well this our declaration...as also the limitation and declaration of the succession contained in the said Act (35 Hen. VIII. c. 1) shall stand the law of this realm for ever."-Statutes of the Realm, IV. 358; Prothero's Statutes, 21. (4) Lastly, the statute recognizing the title of James I. is saturated with the notion of inherent birthright, and knows of no other title. The act carefully guards against granting the succession, but claims merely to declare it. "A most joyful and just recognition of the immediate, lawful, and undoubted succession of Descent and Right of the Crown. "We (being bounden thereunto both by the laws of God and man) do recognize and acknowledge (and 376 EXTRACTS FROM STATUTES thereby express our unspeakable joys), that immediately upon the dissolution and decease of Elizabeth...the imperial crown of the realm of England...did, by inherent birthright and lawful and undoubted succes- sion descend and come to your most excellent majesty, as being lineally, justly, and lawfully next and sole heir of the blood royal of this realm as is aforesaid." Statutes of the Realm, Iv. 107; Prothero's Statutes, 251. APPENDIX B EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII. AND IX. 1. Popery, as involving a belief in the deposing power, a disloyal doctrine. "I will not say (though it has been said) the Romanists' faith is faction and their religion rebellion; but this I must say, that they teach and broach such doctrines as are very scandalous to Christian religion, and very dangerous and destructive to Kingdoms and States; as having a direct and natural tendency to sedition, rebellion, and treason."-Duport, Sermon on the Fifth of November, 64. "I do not, I will not, say All our Romanists are enclined to rebellion; I doubt not but there are many faithful and loyal subjects among 'em ; but this I must say, As long as they own a foreign jurisdiction, either spiritual or temporal, which they must do if they are thorough-paced; and as long as the Pope usurps the power to depose and dispose, to depose Kings, and dispose of their Kingdoms, and to absolve subjects from their oaths of supremacy and allegiance; so long the Romish religion must needs have a natural tendency to disloyalty; and therefore, if Papists be good subjects, 378 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS no thanks to their Popery; and I fear, 'twill be hard for 'em to be good Catholics at Rome, and good subjects at home; for if they be so, it must be only durante bene placito, so long as the Pope is well-pleas'd, but if once he be angry with Kings and call 'em heretics, then have at 'em fowlers, let 'em look to themselves."—Ibid. 68. "The Reformation of our Church was laid upon the subversion of one of the most fatal and pernicious principles to government, that any religion can main- tain, namely the precarious conditions of allegiance to the true and lawful sovereign, upon the falsehood and ruin whereof our constitution both civil and eccle- siastical was founded and established."-Sacheverell, The Political Union, 54. The following passage shews how the whole con- troversy between the temporal and spiritual authority must be viewed from the standpoint of an age, when the enforcement of uniformity in religious practice was. regarded by all parties as the duty of the State. "No king or prince by their [the Romanists'] doctrine can truly be accounted a freeman or denizen in the State wherein he lives, seeing no king can have so much as a voice or suffrage in making those ecclesiastical canons, unto which he, his people, all his laws temporal and spiritual are subordinate and subject. For no man could think him to be a freeman in any corporation, that has no voice in making the temporal laws by which he is to be governed or at least in choosing such of them as have interest in the making of Public Laws." Jackson, Treatise of Christian Obedience (Works, III. 909). "The Jesuits the principal authors of resistance to all higher powers."—Ibid. 971. "The deposing doctrine and placing the power in the people is but the spittle of the Jesuits which our DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 379 Whigs and Dissenters have picked up."-Leslie, The Wolf stripped of his Shepherd's Clothing, 4. "Your mobs are all papists, they are for the deposing power, which is perfect popery."-Leslie, A Battle Royal, 174. Papal supremacy divests the prince of his absolute sovereignty, of his legislative power and renders mon- archy insecure of possession or succession, by bereaving it of the guard of the laws, of the strength of alliances, of the fidelity of their people. Papal supremacy destructive of the people's liberty and property.—The Common Interest of King and People, Chap. VII. "These men cry out against Popery, and yet profess, what all good Protestants esteem the most malignant part of Jesuitism."-Dudley Digges, The Unlawfulness of Subjects Taking up Arms, 64. 2. Identification of Papists and Dissenters. "It is most manifest, that all our late horrid civil wars, rapines, bloodshed and the execrable and solemn murder of His Late Majesty, and the banishment of our present sovereign were effected according to the fore-contrivance of the Papists, by the assistance which the Dissenters gave them and the opportunities they had to preach them into rebellion under the pretence of a thorough Reformation, that all late commotions and rebellions in Scotland sprung from the same counsel and conduct."-Foxes and Firebrands, 32. "Let us now come to take a view of the younger antagonists of monarchy, the popular supremacy of Presbytery, that Lerna Malorum, that revived hydra of the Lake of Geneva, with its many-headed progeny, Anabaptists, Quakers, Levellers &c., all which unnatural offspring are as kind to their dam as vipers, and as 380 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS inconsistent with monarchy, as they pretend to be with the Papacy (with which Presbytery jostles for universal supremacy) or any of them with Loyalty, Royalty or true religion."-Nalson, Common Interest of King and People, 201. 'The Puritans were mere tools to the Jesuits (as they are to this day), from them they learned the deposing doctrine, and to set up the private spirit against the Holy Scriptures, and all the authority of the Church." Leslie, The Rehearsal, No. 84. K "Sure the hand of Joab, the Jesuit with his King-killing doctrine, was in all this, and every one of the regicides had a Pope in his belly, to give him a dispensation, and absolve him from his oath of alle- giance."-Duport, Sermon on Thirtieth of January, 11. "Those fratres in malo, those red-hot fiery zealots. o' both sides; your furious hair-brained fanatic, and your perfidious disloyal Loiolite: I join 'em together, Bithus cum Bachio, for I know not which is the worse o' the two; and I think they plough with one another's heifer."-Ibid. 22. "Do you think our Roman Catholics, at least the Jesuits, were idle spectators all the while and had not a hand in the 30th of January, as well as in the fifth of November? Is it not well known that the train to entangle us in that horrible snare, and intrigue of the late confusions, was laid by a great Cardinal minister of State, and perhaps the whole conclave?...... Is it not yet apparent, that the Popish emissaries and in- cendiaries were sent hither on purpose under the name of Anabaptists, Seekers, and Quakers, and I know not what to blow the coals and foment the flames of our late dissensions?"-Duport, Sermon on Fifth of November, 72. DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 381 "Our factious, fanatic, turbulent, and schismatical spirits are but the Jesuits' journeymen."—Ibid. 76. Clericalism of the Presbyterian System. "Their [the Presbyterians'] Church government is pernicious to Civil Power, grievous to such as must live under it, and apt to distort the Common Peace." -Leslie, The Trojan Horse of the Presbyterian Govern- ment Unbowelled, 3. They claim power to abrogate the laws of the land touching ecclesiastical matters, if they judge them hurtful or unprofitable.......They require the civil magistrate to be subject to their power."-Ibid. 5. (C "It may be that the general disaffection to regal power, in these distractions, may render some men less apprehensive of the dangerous consequences of this doctrine, and the former claims; as supposing them to have no other drift than to clip the wings of royal prerogative. But this is a gross and dangerous mistake and whosoever shall be invested with that Civil Power, which shall be taken from the King, be it the Parliament or whosoever else, must look to suc- ceed him in the heavy enmity which this Presbyterian power will exercise against the Civil Power (when it doth not comply with them), in what hands soever it be placed. For these encroachments of theirs are not upon the King as distinguished from other magistrates, but upon the civil magistrate in common whosoever he be."—Ibid. 8. "The King and Parliament must be subject not only to their general assembly, but (in subordination to that) to the dictates of every petty parochial session, where their personal residence and abode shall be. Lastly if the King and Parliament will govern contrary to their 382 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS will and pleasure, their principles will allow them to incite the people to resist them."-Ibid. 8. (( 'They determine that the temporal magistrate is bound to punish adultery with death by God's own law.......They hold it unlawful for the civil magistrate to pardon capital offenders."-Ibid. 9. (C By their platform they may deal with all civil causes for a spiritual end, which the Pope usually expresses with this clause In ordine ad bonum Spirituale, and these men by the same effect in ordine ad bonum ecclesiae. But both he and they do by this distinction usurp upon the Civil magistrate."-Ibid. 10. "This discipline which they do so much adore is the very quintessence of refined Popery, or a greater Tyranny than ever Rome brought forth, inconsistent with all forms of civil government, destructive to all sorts of policy, a rack to the conscience, the heaviest pressure that can fall upon a people, and so much more dangerous because by the specious pretence of Divine institution, it takes away the right, but not the burden of slavery."-Bramhall, A Warning to the Church of England, 2. That it [the Discipline] exempts the ministers from due punishment.-Ibid. Chap. IV. The Disciplinarians cheat the magistrate of his civil power, in order to religion.-Ibid. Chap. VII. (C They ascribe unto their ministers a liberty and power to direct the magistrate even in the managery of civil affairs.”—Ibid. 25. (( 'They assume a power in worldly affairs indirectly and in order to the advancement of the Kingdom of Christ."-Ibid. 26. "The Parliament will restore to the King his negative voice; a mere civil thing. The commissioners DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 383 of the Church oppose it, because of the great dangers that may thereby come to religion. The Parliament name officers and commanders for the army; a mere civil thing. The Church will not allow them because they want such qualifications, as God's word requires, that is to say in plain terms because they were not their confidents. Was there ever Church challenged such an omnipotence as this? Nothing in this world is so civil or political, wherein they do not interest themselves in order to the advancement of the Kingdom of Christ."- Ibid. 27. "This is the Presbyterian want, to subject all causes and persons to their consistories, to ratify and abolish civil laws, to confirm and pull down Parliaments, to levy forces, to invade other Kingdoms, to do anything respectively to the advancement of the good cause and in order to religion."-Ibid. 31. Chapter VIII. That the Disciplinarians challenge this exorbitant power by Divine Right. Chapter IX. That this discipline makes a monster of the Commonwealth. "We have seen how pernicious this discipline (as it is maintained in Scotland and endeavoured to be introduced into England by the Covenant) is to the Supreme Magistrate, how it robs him of his supremacy in ecclesiastical affairs, and of the last appeals of his own subjects, that it exempts the presbyters from the power of the magistrate, and subjects the magistrate to the presbyters, that it restrains his dispensative power of pardoning, deprives him of the dependence of his subjects, that it doth challenge and usurp a power paramount both of the word and of the sword, both of peace and war, over all courts and estates, over all laws civil and ecclesiastical, in order to the 384 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS advancement of the Kingdom of Christ, whereof the Presbyters alone are constituted rulers by God, and all this by a pretended Divine Right, which takes away all hope of remedy, until it be hissed out of the world; in a word that it is the top-branch of Popery, a greater tyranny, than ever Rome was guilty of. It remains to shew how disadvantageous it is also to the subject. (6 First, to the Commonwealth in general which it makes a monster, like an amphiscian or a serpent with two heads, one at either end. It makes a coordination of sovereignty in the same society, two supremes in the same Kingdom or State, the one civil, the other ecclesiastical, than which nothing can be more pernicious either to the consciences, or the estates of subjects, when it falls out (as it often doth) that from these two heads issue contrary commands."-Ibid. 35. The striking similarity of this passage to the argument of Ockham against the Papacy is plain. Chapter X. That this discipline is most prejudicial to the Parliament. Chapter XI. That this discipline is oppressive to particular persons. Nalson, Common Interest of King and People, Chap. IX. Presbytery in reality as great an enemy to Democracy and Parliaments as to monarchy. A short view of their tyrannic consistorian government over the magistracy, clergy and laity. Of the latitude and power of scandal to draw all affairs into the consistory.......The small difference betwixt a Jesuit and Geneva Presbyter. Both aim at supremacy. “We shall find that it is absolutely inconsistent with all government (except its own oligarchic spiritual tyranny) and even that adored Democracy, which it pretends to hug and embrace with so much tenderness DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 385 and affection....... The real design is to dash a Parliament against a King, to break them both in pieces; and like the ape in the story to make a cat's foot of the House of Commons, to pull the nut out of the hot ashes of rebellion, into which they shall have reduced the monarchy; for when once by that assistance they shall have procured their own establishment, they will render it as absolute a slave, as they would do monarchy."-Ibid. 241. "It is not the persons or names, but the superiority of the authority, against which this faction of Geneva levels all its aims."--Ibid. "These saints who pretend to a power of binding Kings in chains will without scruple so claim the honour of shackling the nobles in fetters of iron."—Ibid. 242. "It is the desire of sovereignty under the colour of religion at which they aim; and to which whatsoever is an obstacle, whether King, Parliament, Prelates, Lords, or Commons, shall all be declared anti-Christian and unlawful powers."-Ibid. 244. "The great assembly and the moderator for the time being is the absolute and supreme sovereign power of the nation, where Presbytery bears the sway."- Ibid. 247. "They [Presbytery and Jesuitry] are both inconsistent with monarchy and indeed with all government; over which they pretend a power and jurisdiction by Christ, the one for the Pope, the other for the Presbytery; from which there lies no appeal.”—Ibid. 257. Chapter X. Presbytery as destructive of the People's liberty and property as it is dangerous to monarchy and all government. "No person whatsoever, let him pretend never so much religion, sanctity, or innocence, can possibly be a good subject, so long as he continues a true Presbyterian F. 25 386 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS or of their offspring; in regard they always carry about with them as the main of their religion such principles, as are directly contrary to monarchy and destructive of loyalty; to which he can never be a firm, true and assured friend, who owns a power superior to that of his prince within his dominions; and that such a power may of right depose him, and take away his crown and life, which has been proved to be the avowed doctrine of the consistorians of Geneva, Scotland, and England, both in point and practice."-270. "That Presbyterian popular consistorian supremacy, is, and ever will be, the unchangeable, irreconcilable enemy of monarchy, law, liberty, peace, property, and the true Protestant Catholic religion."-279. (C Having thus taken the whole civil government into their own hands as the Pope has done, and by virtue of the same distinction in ordine ad spiritualia they followed him likewise in that which is a natural consequence of the other, to exempt themselves from being accountable to the civil power even for civil crimes."-Leslie, The New Association, Part II. 33. 4. The Divine Right of Kings in reality a defence of all secular governments against ecclesiastical aggres- sion. "It shall suffice to note that the Romanist makes an unequal comparison and sets the terms of his proposition awry, when he compares spiritual power indefinitely taken with power royal or monarchical, which is but a branch though the highest branch of power civil or temporal. The question should be betwixt authority spiritual or ecclesiastic indefinitely taken; and between power civil or temporal alike indefinitely taken. Power temporal or civil thus taken DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 387 is immediately from God, and government temporal itself in some one kind or other (that is Monarchical, Aristocratical or mixed or &c.) is de Jure Divino, as well as power spiritual or ecclesiastic is."-Jackson, Treatise of Christian Obedience (Works, III. 903). "That this nation should be governed by a King, another by peers and nobles, another by the people, or by magistrates of the people's choosing, either annual or for term of life, this is not determined Jure Divino by any express or positive law of God, but is reserved unto the guidance of his ordinary Providence, who sometimes directs one people or nation to make choice of this form, another to make choice of that. But the choice of government being made by the people or imposed upon them by right of war, to yield obedience to the form of government or power established, this is de Jure Divino positively and peremptorily determined and enjoined by the law of God. And whosoever doth resist the form of government established in the commonweal, whereof he is a member, be it of this form or that, he doth resist the higher powers; and by resisting them resisteth the ordinance of God."- Ibid. 963. 5. Inevitable conflict between temporal and spirit- ual powers, so long as the principle of toleration is unrecognized. "It is indeed impossible that a coordination of these powers should subsist; for each will be continually encroaching on the other, each for its own defence and support will continually be struggling and clambering to get above the other; there never will be any quiet till one come to subside and truckle under the other; whereby the sovereignty of the one or the other will be 25-2 388 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS destroyed; each of them soon will come to claim a supremacy in all causes and the power of both swords; and one side will carry it....". -Barrow, Treatise of the Pope's Supremacy, 144. The divergence of this view from that of Barclay, the representative of strict Gallicanism, is noteworthy. Barclay strongly emphasizes, that need of two coordinate authorities, which Barrow denies to be possible. "A free Church in a free State" was the ideal of the Gallican writer; the Anglican is aware, that the dream is incapable of realization. 6. Connection of English politics with French con- troversies. "This pretence of the King's authority against his person was hatched under the Romish territories and made use of in the Holy League of France."-Falkner, Christian Loyalty, 356. 7. The theory of Hobbes regarded as dangerous, notwithstanding his practical conclusions, owing to his basing it upon the original compact. "Though Mr Hobbs sometimes hath over-large expressions concerning the power of governors; yet he having before laid the same formation for the original of political government, doth also undermine the safety and stability of governors and government....... But as these positions are framed upon such suppositions, as look upon man in his beginning, to stand without due respect to God, and the rules and notions of good and evil; so the dangerous aspect they have on peace and government doth speak the folly of them, and they will be sufficiently in this particular confuted by DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 389 asserting the divine original of sovereignty."-Falkner, Christian Loyalty, 409. "I consent with him about the rights of exercising government, but I cannot agree to his means of ac- quiring it. It may seem strange I should praise his building, and yet mislike his foundation, but so it is, his Jus naturae and his regnum institutivum will not down with me; they appear full of contradiction and impossibilities."-Filmer, Observations touching the original of government, Preface. / 8. The patriarchal theory of kingship based on a belief in the state of nature and in Scripture as the only authentic testimony for it. Natural rights are Divine rights. The original state of nature shewed to be a state of government and subjection not of independency.- Leslie, The Rehearsal, No. 55. "The first state of nature to which all our whigs do refer, makes clearly against them, and is wholly on your side, who plead for government and the divine institution of it; against that original independent state of nature, which the whigs do suppose, but can never prove, unless they can find some other original of mankind than the holy Scriptures have told us.". Ibid. No. 56. "If being born under Laws and a government whose legislative has an absolute despotic and unaccountable power over our very lives as well as our estates without staying to ask our consent, if this is to be free born, then all the world are so and ever have been so since Adam: otherwise not one, unless a King be born after his father is dead."-Leslie, The New Association, Part I. 15. 390 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS (6 C Supposing therefore that Adam was universal monarch or civil governor over the whole race of mankind, during his long life this will not prove he had a Divine right to be so?' Will it not? Then I am very sure no after-King can claim it. If Adam had no Divine Right, what right had he?"-Leslie, The Finishing Stroke, 18. "I go upon fact plainly recorded in Scripture."— Ibid. 38. "The Rehearsal had blamed those who went to heathen authors for the original of government, because none of their histories reached so high, and they knew not how the world or mankind begun.......The only and the certain account of it,......is to be found in the Holy Scriptures."-Ibid. 89. "The Rehearsal places the original of government in the positive institution of God, though at the same time he shews it to be consequential, and most agreeable to the frame of our nature, as being all deduced from one common father. Which patriarchal or fatherly authority is not only founded in Nature, but most expressly and originally in the first institution of government placed by God in Adam."-Leslie, A Battle Royal, 128. J "A family is a little kingdom, but a kingdom is nothing but a great family. Therefore such a state of mankind, where all are upon the level and the consent of every individual made necessary to the erection of government, as Locke and others suppose it, because that every man is freeborn and that no man's life and liberty or property can be disposed of but by his own consent, I say such a state cannot be called the state of nature because nature implies fathers and mothers; it may be called a state of mankind, but not of such DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND 1X 391 men as we are, but of a shower of men rained down from the clouds or new created in multitudes, like the beasts, fish, and fowl at the beginning and no one dependent upon the other. So that even the Hottentot cannot represent this state, which yet is necessary to make the people the original of government."-Ibid. 128. "But to them that believe the truth revealed in Holy Scripture, 'tis strange they should make question about it, seeing the world began in one man, that lived nigh one thousand years, at puberty the first hour; so that he could not have a less monarchy than any now extant in the world considering the vast increase there may be from man and woman in a perfect state of health examined by the surest rules of progression. Against him should anyone in the world rise up, it had been rebellion and parricide. Nothing but the authority of God would justify the suspension of obedience to him the natural father of the world."-Leslie, Obedience to Civil Government clearly stated, 14. The divergence between Leslie and the French School is shewn in the different views taken of Nimrod. To the French school he is the founder of monarchy, to Leslie he is the first instance of a successful usurper. "If it [Self preservation] were a natural law, it would be a sin to resign it over to any.......Self Preservation is only an instinct.”—Ibid. 72. 9. Gulf between Adamic society and modern times bridged by theory of prescriptive right. "Possession gives right, tho' wrongfully come by,...... [if] there is none who claims a better right than the possessor."-Leslie, The Sham Sermon Dissected, 2. 10. Question of source of Law. There must be a 392 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS supreme lawgiver. A sovereign needful to invest laws with binding authority. "Laws must be made by Kings. Therefore Kings must be before Laws."-Leslie, Cassandra, 22. Kings were kings before there were Laws....... The King's Power is antecedent to Law which hath its force. from him."-The Apostate Protestant, 41. "He gives the prince no right but what is vested in him by law. Tho' his right is prior to the law, for he gives sanction to the law, and who gave him the right to do that? And here we are enjoined to give the prince no more than what is vested in him by law. Then he can no more give sanction to any law; unless we can find a law before there was any King, to make that King, and give him a right to give sanction to laws. for the future."-Leslie, The Sham Sermon Dissected, 5. "This manifests the fundamental error in politics, of those persons who make laws to have a priority, before Kings and governors; as if the laws made Kings and magistrates, when in truth God and nature vested primo- geniture with the right of Kings and magistrates; and they made the first laws."-Nalson, Common Interest of King and People, 13. "There can be no laws, till there be some frame of government, to establish and enact such laws; nor can anything have the force or power of a law, or oblige men to obedience, unless it does proceed from a person or persons, as have a right to command it, and authority to punish the disobedience or neglect of those who ought to be subject to it."-Ibid. 14. "[The common law] follows in time after government, but cannot go before it, and be the rule to government by any original or radical constitution."-Filmer, Anarchy of a Limited and Mixed Monarchy, 267. (6 DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 393 11. There must be in every state a sovereign, not bound by positive law. 'There must be a dernier ressort or there can be no government. And where there is in an assembly that assembly is one body, as one person."-Leslie, Cassandra, 23. (( Hoadly. We are free because the government cannot hang us on what they please but they are bounded by law, and we must have a fair trial, and by our peers too. Hottentot. So you are free, because you are hanged by a jury! But what think you of an Act of Attainder, which can hang without any trial or giving you any reason for it? Hoad. This is part of our constitution, that the Parliament should have such a power in extraordinary case. Hott. Yet you are free! And these cases happen, as oft as the Parliament pleases. They are not tied to any rule, but may make use of this power, whenever it comes into their heads. Hoad. Well, but the King cannot hang us at his pleasure. Hott. That is, you are not at the mercy of one man, but of five hundred. O delicate freedom."-Leslie, A Battle Royal, 142. "After laws and society come in, all under it are born slaves, that is under the absolute dominion of what you call the legislature in every society. And whether that be in the hands of one or more it is all the same as to the destruction of liberty. For what is it to me, whether I am hanged by the command of one or of five hundred?”—Ibid. 159. "Every government has absolute power over the 394 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS lives, as well as estates of all their subjects without asking their leave or making any contract with them. They are born in subjection, without conditions."—Leslie, The Best Answer that ever was made, 8. “Without a last resort there can be no government. And if this be in the people, still there is no government. And if you stop short of all the people, then wherever it rests, there is 'absolute unaccountable' &c."-Ibid. 15. "These men have strange notions of monarchy, and of absolute government, which, as I have often said, is the same in all sorts of governments whatsoever. All the difference is in whom this absolute power shall be placed, whether in one, in a few, or in many?". Leslie, The Rehearsal, No. 59. "All governments in the world must be arbitrary, in some hands or other; for there must be a last resort in every government, and that must be arbitrary and unaccountable, as having no superior upon earth."- Ibid. No. 36. "If any man can find us out such a kind of govern- ment, wherein the supreme power can be, without being freed from human laws, they should first teach us that......a legislative power cannot be without being absolved from human laws."-Filmer, Observations upon Mr Milton against Salmasius. "A necessity to grant impunity to some in all governments to avoid confusion."-Dudley Digges, Un- lawfulness of Subjects, 43. "If, as Mr Locke says, and says he has proved it, No man can subject himself to the arbitrary power of another, no man can subject himself to any government of what sort or size soever. Nor can there be such a thing as government kept up in the world.”—Leslie, The Rehearsal, No. 38. DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 395 "In all kingdoms or commonwealths in the world, whether the prince be the supreme father of the people. or but the true heir of such a father, or whether he come to the crown by usurpation, or by election of the nobles or of the people, or by any other way whatso- ever; or whether some few or a multitude govern the Commonwealth; yet still the authority that is in any one or in many or in all these is the only right and natural authority of a supreme father."-Filmer, Patriarcha, 1. § 10. "The true debate amongst men is not whether they shall admit of bonds......but who shall impose them; the question is not an servirent, sed an uni vel pluribus; it is commonly called liberty, to serve more masters."-Dudley Digges, Unlawfulness of Subjects taking up Arms, 29. 12. Sovereignty indivisible. Anarchy of a mixed monarchy. "They know very well that there can be no sharing of power, it must be one and entire; and the contest for it is anarchy and confusion."-Leslie, The New Association, Part II. 11. "All power is one indivisible whether in the hands of one or many."-Leslie, Cassandra, 23. "He lays his stress upon a constitution like ours. And as he has dressed our constitution, we may well say there is not a constitution like ours upon the face of the earth. He has made it up of coordinate powers, all opposition, nonsense, and contradiction."-Leslie, The Sham Sermon Dissected, 5. "It doth not follow, that the form of government is, or can be in its own nature ill, because the governor is so; it is anarchy, or want of government that can 396 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS totally destroy a nation."-Filmer, Observations upon Mr Milton against Salmasius, 494. "This mixed monarchy, just like the limited, ends in confusion and destruction of all government.”—Filmer, Anarchy of a Mixed and Limited Monarchy, 272. "There cannot be such a thing as mixtum imperium ......because if there are divers supreme powers it is no longer one state. If the supreme power be but one,......this must be placed either in one man,.... or in some nobles......or if the civil constitution of a state directs us to appeal to the people, this is an absolute and true democracy."-Dudley Digges, Unlawfulness, 77. "I have shewn before that a mixed monarchy is a contradiction."-Ibid. 168. 13. Theory of Divine Right a defence of govern- ment against anarchy, far more than an apology for monarchy. "The endeavouring to settle sure and lasting founda- tions of government in opposition to these popular no principles, of sedition and eternal confusion, is all the reason I know that has stirred up the wrath of these orators of the populace."-Leslie, Cassandra, 1. 41. "[Government] in the largest sense is a communion of superiors and inferiors united for the safety of the whole; to disunite them is overturning it."-Leslie, Obedience to Civil Government clearly stated, 8. "The reasons against Kings are as strong against all powers, for men of any titles are subject to err, and numbers more than fewer."-Ibid. 63. "This doctrine may disturb the present, and threaten all future governors and governments whatsoever.” Ibid. 64. DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 397 66 'All the arguments used to justify self preservation, are grounded only on supposition that men may be wronged or oppressed by God's magistrates or rulers; and therefore conclude as well against all civil govern- ment, as against the magistrate in being."-Ibid. 90. "If the last resort be in the people, there is no end of controversy at all, but endless and unremediable confusion."-Leslie, The Best Answer, 14. "It is unlawful to resist him or them in whom the supreme authority (that is all the legal power of the kingdom) is placed, and no dispensation......can excuse such resistance from the sin of rebellion. Upon this pillar not only monarchy stands firm, but all other governments are equally supported."-Dudley Digges, Unlawfulness of Subjects, 10. "Liberty to resist those in whom the law places jus gladii, the right of the sword, destructive to the very nature of government."-Ibid. 8. "This argument [of equality] doth not conclude for one form above another but equally destroys all."- Ibid. 29. Hoadly. He is ever representing me as maintaining such principles as are inconsistent with the safety of all government."-Leslie, Best of All, 8. "Obedience is due to commonwealths by their subjects, even for conscience' sake, where the princes from whom they have revolted have given up their claim."-Ibid. 27. (( "The power of the people which you set up is equally destructive of commonwealths as of monarchies. …………….And with that it is impossible for any government to subsist."—Ibid. 30. "I was the more willing to make this observation, that when I speak of sovereign princes I may not be 398 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS maliciously traduced as if I spoke of them exclusively and not of other sovereigns, as if monarchy were of sole Divine right. For want of this distinction other writers have had this invidious imputation laid upon them; but this reason of not resisting the sovereign, because he is God's vicegerent and only subject to Him, is a common reason of passive obedience to all sovereigns, as well as unto Kings, and unto Kings, as well as unto any other sovereigns."-Hickes, Jovian, 240. 14. Necessity of Divine institution for government. "Now I say that none has or can have any power or authority, but what is given him by some other, except God alone, who is the sole fountain of all power and authority on earth as well as in heaven. And therefore that God not having given man power over his own life, nor in his natural state over the life of any other man; consequently the power of life and death (which is necessary in all government) could never have come from the gift or grant of the people in their natural state. But that the positive institution of God is necessary to found government, and invest magistrates with the power of life and death. And that without this, no obligation of conscience can be laid upon any man to submit to any government whatsoever."-Leslie, The Best Answer, 9. "I have you consider that there is no authority but what is derived from God. It would be to set up another God to suppose any other or independent authority."-Ibid. 18. "What man is he who can by his own natural authority bind the conscience of another? That would be far more than the power of life, liberty, or property. DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 399 Therefore they saw the necessity of a divine original of government."Leslie, The Rehearsal, No. 37. "R. Whatever founds government must be superior to it, and above it. Government must derive its original and whole authority from it, and must be accountable to it, and dissolvable by it, at its pleasure whenever it thinks fit. "Now human cannot be superior to human, therefore government among men cannot be derived from mere human authority. This is so very obvious that all governments whatever and of whatever sort, and among all nations and religions, do pretend to a divine right....... On all hands it is confessed that no government can stand without a divine original right, and authority; for what else can give one man power over another, over his life, liberty, and property?"— Ibid. No. 53. 15. The views of Hobbes on Passive Obedience. "Having thus shewn what is necessary to salvation, it is not hard to reconcile our obedience to God, with our obedience to the civil sovereign; who is either Christian or infidel. If he be a Christian, he alloweth the belief of this article, that Jesus is the Christ; and of all the articles that are contained in or are by evident consequence deduced from it: which is all the faith necessary to salvation. And because he is a sovereign, he requireth obedience to all his own, that is to all the civil, laws; in which also are contained all the laws of nature, that is all the laws of God; for besides the laws of nature and the laws of the Church, which are part of the civil law (for the Church that can make laws is the Commonwealth), there can be no other laws Divine. Whosoever therefore obeyeth his Christian sovereign, is 400 EXTRACTS ILLUSTRATIVE OF POINTS not thereby hindered, neither from believing nor from obeying God. But suppose that a Christian King should from this foundation Jesus is the Christ draw some false consequences, that is to say make some superstructions of hay, or stubble, and command the teaching of the same; yet seeing S. Paul says, he shall be saved; much more shall he be saved, that teacheth them by his command and much more yet, he that teaches not, but only believes his lawful teacher. And in case a subject be forbidden by the civil sovereign to profess some of those his opinions, upon what just ground can he disobey? Christian Kings may err in deducing a consequence, but who shall judge? Shall a private man judge, when the question is of his own obedience? Or shall any man judge, but he that is appointed thereto by the Church, that is by the civil sovereign that representeth it? Or if the Pope or an Apostle judge, may he not err in deducing of a consequence? Did not one of the two, S. Peter or S. Paul, err in superstructure, when S. Paul withstood S. Peter to his face? There can therefore be no con- tradiction between the laws of God, and the laws of a Christian commonwealth. "And when the civil sovereign is an infidel, every one of his own subjects that resisteth him sinneth against the laws of God (for such are the laws of nature), and rejecteth the counsel of the Apostles, that admonisheth all Christians to obey their princes, and all children and servants to obey their parents, and masters, in all things. And for their faith it is internal, and invisible; they have the licence that Naaman had, and need not put themselves into danger for it. But if they do, they ought to expect their reward in heaven, and not complain of their lawful sovereign, much less DISCUSSED IN CHAPTERS VIII AND IX 401 make war upon him. For he that is not glad of any just occasion of martyrdom, has not the faith he professeth, but pretends it only to set some colour upon his own contumacy."-Leviathan, 111. 43. "Whatsoever a subject, as Naaman was, is compelled to do in obedience to his sovereign, and doth it not in order to his own mind, but in order to the laws of his country, that action is not his but his sovereign's, nor is it he that in this case denieth Christ before men, but his governor and the law of his country."-Ibid. 42. 16. The views of Dudley Digges on the Patriarchal Theory. "Though it be most true that paternal authority was regal, and therefore this of God's immediate constitution, and founded in nature, yet it is not much pertinent to the present decision, nor can it necessarily concern modern controversies between Rulers and people. Be- cause it is most evident, no king at this day, (and much less other governors) holds his crown by that title, since several paternal powers in every State are given up, and united in one common father who cannot pretend a more immediate kindred to Adam, than all the rest of man- kind.”—The Unlawfulness of Subjects, 16. F. 26 INDEX Anabaptists, 286 Anglican Church supports doc- trine of Divine Right of Kings, 206; defended against charge of servility, 205; conduct of, at the Revolution, 211; se- cured recognition of great principles, 213 Arthur of Brittany (the " case of the king"), 24, 80 Baldus, 343, 345, 346, 368 Bartolus, his life, 346-7, 352-3; his intellectual character- istics, 348-55 ; practical nature of his thought, 366; his conception of Law, 349 sqq.; how far an Imperialist, 355 sqq.; his views on the Papacy, 357-9; his views on the relation of the Empire to other states, 359-60; his views on Tyranny, 363-6; his treatise De Regimine Civitatis, 361; his doctrine of the relativity of political theories, 362 sqq.; his in- fluence on later thought, 346, 348, 359, 360-1, 370-2; his Processus Satanae, 366-8, 370; relations with Baldus, 343, 345, 346, 368-70 Benedict XIII. (Pope), 111 Bodin (Jean), views of, 126; influence on England, 129 Boniface VIII. (Pope), 41, 49,110 Bracton, rights ascribed by, to the king, 31, 34; misunder- stood in seventeenth century, 39 sqq. Charles I. (of England), 204, 364 Charles VI. (of France), 111 Charles the Great, 281 Childeric, deposition of, its im- portance in French theories, 107, 120; in Papal theories, 281 Church and State, theory of Divine Right a phase of the conflict between, 44 sqq., 219; inevitable conflict be- tween, 216, 340, 387; a single society or two societies, 274, 275, 285 sqq., 359 Church cannot allow uncondi tional freedom to the State, 214, 287 Civil Law, influence of Roman, 278, 281, 360; independent of Roman Emperor, 360 Civil War, influence of, on belief in Divine Right of Kings, 141 INDEX 403 Clericalism attacked by theory of Divine Right, 44, 179 sqq., 255, 281, 386; in Presby- terian theory, 137, 186 sqq., 381; excuse for, 213, 317-8 Constantine, donation of, 47, 58 Coronation Oath alleged as evidence of compact, 9, 58, 122 sentiment, 166; work effected by, 212, 259; success and failure of, 261 sqq.; anti- clerical, 257, 281; a doctrine of freedom, 257; expresses belief in organic character of the State, 250, 261, 283; forms a transition between medieval and modern politics, 15, 258, 284; phase of con- flict between Church and State, 44 sqq., 216, 219; expresses belief in moral basis of political allegiance, 254; asserts inherent au- thority of monarchy and the civil power, 278 sqq., 287; lies at bottom of English respect for law and order, 263; cause of orderly cha- racter of constitutional de- velopment, 168, 264 Divine Right claimed in all theories of seventeenth cen- tury, 177, 276, 396 Divine Right of Man as Man, 277 "Discipline," the Presbyterian, 299; introduced into Heidel- berg, 304; in England, 271, 300, 308; aimed at govern- ment, not persuasion, 330; restraint upon individual liberty, 335 Dissenters identified with Pa- pists, 133, 180 sqq., 379; and Non-conformists, 270 Divine Right of Kings, not merely absurd, 1; analysed, 5; arguments for, 7; involves idea of sovereignty, 13, 235 sqq., 279; formed against Pope's claims, 44 sqq., 90, 100, 179; against Presby- terianism, 195; found in France, 120 sqq.; held by Wycliffe, 67 sqq.; by Richard II., 74; tends to become prevalent under Tudors, 93 sqq.; completely formulated by James I., 137; becomes popular during civil troubles, 141 sqq.; affected by Ex- clusion Bill, 147; basis of, changed by Filmer, 149 sqq., 282; passes into theory of natural rights, 152 sqq., 389; after 1688 lingers on as a Divine Right of Ruling Elders, 267, 270 sqq., 300 Edward I., 26, 66 Edward II., 27 Elizabeth (Queen), 86, 236, 322 Empire, translation of the, 47, 48, 121 Erastian language of supporters of Divine Right, 202 Erastianism, and the Reformers, 285; defined, 317-9; in Eng- land, 311-7; in the Arminian controversy, 311; and Inde- pendency, 311, 313 404 INDEX Erastus, how far an "Erastian," 293, 309, 316, 319 sqq., 337 sqq.; his life, 294-309; op- poses the introduction of the discipline of Heidelberg, 300 sqq.; his life a polemic against ruling elders, 300; his views on excommunica- tion, 288, 301 sqq., 319; does not argue for toleration, 294, 331; his main object the liberty of the subject, 302, 335; only concerned with a State which is uniform in its religion, 294, 322, 338; allows very large power to the magistrate, 331, 338; his Theses, 304; the Theses published, 309; translated into English, 316 Exclusion Bill, 147 Filmer, Sir Robert, effects a change in the basis of theory of Divine Right, 148 sqq.; his writings a transition to theory of natural rights, 152, 252 France and the Papacy, 63; influence on England, 129, 388; politics in, 107 sqq. Gallicanism, 110 sqq.; 146, 207 Government, all forms of, sup- ported as against anarchy by theory of Divine Right, 237 sqq., 396; defended by all thinkers in seventeenth cen- tury, 245 Harold, Earl, 21 Heidelberg, under Elector Otto Henry, 297; under Elector Frederic III., 298 sqq. Henry IV., claims of, 80 Henry VII., 84 Henry VIII., 78, 85, 197, 236 Henry IV. (of France) and Legitimism, 109 Hobbes, on sovereignty, 248; hatred felt for, by believers in Divine Right, 248 sqq. ; and the Original Compact, 250 sqq., 388; his relation to Erastus, 322, 332, 337, 338, 342 Huguenots, 113 sqq., 199 Independency and Presbyterian- ism, 268-71, 311, 339 Innocent III., 48, 68 James I. formulates theory of Divine Right, 137; relation to Parliament, 140 James II. errs in trying to em- ploy theory against its original purpose, 211, 282 Jesuits attacked on political grounds, 104, 181 sqq.; identi- fied with Dissenters, 180, 380; with Presbyterians, 186, 384 John (King), 24 John XXII. (Pope), 44, 46, 73, 281 Julius II. (Pope), 111 Jus Divinum, 267, 270, 276, 278, 279 King, personal and political capacity of, 28, 108; struggle of, with lawyers, 231 sqq.; re- garded as sovereign, 233; as INDEX 405 God incarnate, 17; as of Divine descent, 18; supreme landowner, 22; position of, under Tudors, 88 sqq. Law, nature of controversies concerning, 225, 391; the Common Law, 228 League, the Holy, 108 Legalist atmosphere of political speculation, 278 sqq., 345 Legatine Council, 19 Locke, views of, similar to French, 113; contrasted with Filmer, 156; does not recog- nize fact of sovereignty, 242 Louis XII., 111 Mary Stuart, 86, 101 Maulbronn, Colloquy of, 299 Moral basis of obedience, 206, 254, 265, 398 Natural rights, theory of, con- nection with Filmer, 152; Divine Right, 152, 283, 389; futility of, 254 Non-jurors testify to change of theory of Divine Right into a sentiment, 166 sqq. expressed by theory of Divine Right, 250 sqq., 261 Original compact, theory of, its absurdity, 1; found in France, 113 sqq.; forms main dif- ference between Hobbes and supporters of Divine Right, 250; treats State as artificial contrivance, 251 sqq., 283 Obedience, in Papal theory, 51; partial in Imperialist doc- trine, 61, and in Wycliffe, 70; unlimited in Tudor theory, 88 sqq.; regarded by all as duty of private individuals, 115, 221; taught by all, 219; in French theory, 121; pas- sive, importance of, 207 sqq., attacked by Hobbes, 399 Organic character of State Papal claims, 14, 25, 44 sqq.; a theory needed to meet them, 53 sqq., 90, 100, 179; and popular rights, 101, 184, 219, 376; identified with Dissenters' pretensions, 180, 379; excuse for, 213, 287 Patriarchal theory not of es- sence of Divine Right of Kings, 8, 150; use made of by Filmer, 148 sqq.; transi- tion to natural rights, 152, 389 Petit (Jean), 364-5 Presbyterianism, clericalism of, 137, 186 sqq., 381 sqq.; justi- fication of, 213, 287; Divine Right of, 276 sqq.; intoler- ance of, 289; and Indepen- dency, 268, 271, 311, 339 Primogeniture, origin of, 22 sqq.; triumphs with Richard II., 80; claimed by Henry IV., 81; opposed by Papacy, 101; sentiment in favour of, grows up, 103; strengthened by Exclusion Bill, 147 Putney, debate at, in 1647, 276 Reformation, connection with theory of Divine Right, 15, 89, 262; increases royal power, 91, 284-5, 318, 339 406 INDEX Relativity of political theories, doctrine of, 362 sqq. Richard Duke of York, 82 Richard III., 85 Rousseau, 9, 152, 243, 254 Scotland, influence of France on, 130 sqq. Shrewsbury, Parliament of, 74, 77 Sidney (Algernon), relation to Filmer, 154; criticised, 243 8qq. Solemn League and Covenant, 268 Sovereignty, theory of, in con- nection with theory of Divine Right, 13, 145, 237, 279; impossible in England in Middle Ages, 30; arises in Papal theory, 49; in Imperialist, 55 sqq.; grows in modern times, 90; con- troversies on, 225 sqq., 392 sqq. Sovereignty of the people, 243 Toleration, the solution of the conflict between Church and State, 216, 263, 290, 340-2 Tyranny, 363-6 Unction, belief in sacramental grace of, not essential to theory of Divine Right, 8; believed in by Richard II., 79 Unity, the soul of govern- ment," in Papal theory, 45; in Imperialist, 55; in modern, 90; made an argu- ment for monarchy, 56, 127 Utility, basis of theory held by Ockham and Marsiglio, 61; in Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, 114; recognized by Locke and Sidney, 154; in connec- tion with natural rights, 161; taught by Nalson, 163; views of obedience on purely utili- tarian grounds held by none in seventeenth century, 223 "" Westminster Assembly, the, 267, 300, 311, 327, 340 Whig theory artificial, 240; differs for the worse from theory of Divine Right, 253; illogical, 243 22 1921 f... CAMBRIDGE: PRINTED BY JOHN CLAY, M.A. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN C APR 25 1985 FEB. 12 1987 stralia Jo - 11JJ ܕܐ ܝܐܐܕܕܓ Holy FEB 02-1987 A TE 1989. AN 1/8/9923 Học sinh n DATE DUE LOCAL MINISTERING SEP 18 1987 JAN 189909 I FEB 27 RECO APRICO JUL 2 3 1000 AUG 1992 JUN 2 8 1995! DEC 1 2 1995 UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN "Cam Wat 3 9015 00244 4522 2. Endica Herb (D) ཐ་ um DO NOT REMOVE OR MUTILATE CARDS : BARA and