MORAL PHILOSOPHY: TIIEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ETIICS. BY JOSEPH HAVEN, D.D., L. L. D., PROFESSOR IN CHICAGO THEOLOGICAL SEMINARLY; LATELY PROFESSOR OF INTELLECTUAL ANT) IMOI'AL i'PII.LOSOIPIY IN A MIIERST COLLEGE; AUTiOI{. OF " ME.NTAL PtIlLOSOPtIY." SHELDON & COMPANY, NEW YORK & CHICAGO. I I INCLUDING I I . I ______________________im Dr. Haven's Valuable Series of School and College Text-Books. I.NTALT PMILOSOPHIY.... $2 00 MORAL PHIILOSOPHY.... 1 75 HISTORY OF ANCIENT AND WODERN PHILOSOPHY. (In press). I t~~~~~~~~~~~ ~ ~e I' Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1859, by GOULD,ND LINCOLN, In the Clerk's Office of the District Court of the District of Massachusetts. . I: _ _ II GIFT OF DEAN A. S, WHITNEY 7 - I ell",; V PRIEFACIE. THE present volume is the result of the author's studies while Professor of Mental and Moral Philosophy in Amherst College, and was originally prepared as a course of lectures to the senior class ill that Institution. It was intended as a sequel to the author's treatise on Mental Philosophy. The favorable reception of that work by the public has induced him to give this also to the press, with the hope that it may be of service to the cause of Education. Few departments of science have so rich a literature as Moral Philosophy. And yet, by general concession, there are few good textbooks of the science. Of the treatises now most generally in use in our schools and colleges, some appear deficient in thorough scientific discussion of the principles and true theory of morals; others, again, in practical detail. In some of them, under the title of Moral Philosophy, topics are discussed which more properly pertain to Psychology, - as, for example, the phenomenon of Conscience, and the probe lems of the Will, -while the history of ethical opinion ,.,4 .T\ i'; PREFACE. one of the widest and richest fields of investigation -has almost universally been overlooked. It has been the aim of the author to give, as far as possible, a science of morals, and not merely a treatise on moral subjects. With a view to this, the principles which lie at the foundation of the science are first discussed, as concisely as may be, in the opening division of the work; and in the subsequent division these principles are considered in their application to the practical duties and relations of life. Of the several classes of duties, that class which pertains to the state — or Political Ethics - has received in these pages a fuller discussion than is usually given in works of this kind; yet not fuller, perhaps, than its relative importance demands. It has seemed to the author that the youth of a free country should be carefully instructed in the first principles of civil government, and in the rights and obligations of the citizen. It is the proper province of Moral Philosophy, which treats of the various duties of life, to do this. Yet, strange as it may seem, no branch of moral science has probably received less attention, in this country, than Political Ethics. J. H. CHICAGO, AUGUST 1859 viaI CONTENTS. INTRODU C TION. rage PROVINCE OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY,.. 15 DIVISION FIRST. THEORETICAL ETHICS. CHAPTER I. THE NATURE OF RIGHT,. SECTION I. - RIGHT IN ITSELF CONSIDERED,... SECTION II. —RIGHT AS DISTINGUISHED FROM OTHER IDEAS OF SIMILAR IMPORT,...... CHAPTER II. THE GROUND OF RIGHT,. CHAPTER III. 'rIE RULE OF RIGHT, N.KTURE AND ... 21 21 23 27 . 50 CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. Page . * * 519 THE PROVINCE OF RIGHT,....... 59 SECTION I.-WHAT IS A MORAL ACTION?.... 59 SECTION II.-IN WHAT CONSISTS THE MORALITY OF ANY GIVEN ACT?.. CHAPTER V. FACULTIES OF MIND COGNIZANT OF RIGHT,. CHAPTER VI. HISTORIC SKETCH OF OPINIONS RESPECTING THE NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT,..... DIVISION SECOND. PRACTICAL ETHICS. PRELIMINARY ANALYSIS AND CLASSIFICATION, PART I. DUTIES TO SELF. CHAPTER I. SELF-SUPPORT, CHAPTER II. SELF-DEFENCE, x 63 67 71 89 92 95 CONTENTS. CHAPTER III. Page 100 SELF-CONTROL, CHAPTER IV. SELF-CULTURE, PART II. DUTIES TO SOCIETY. CHAPTER I. DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE, CHAPTER II. DJUIE llo fP AlNllNli O LBRU lYVbiDLi.I 1... SECTION I. - SLAVERY DEFINED,......... SECTION II. - SLAVERY, AS THUS DEFINED, A MORAL WRONG, SECTION III. - EFFECT OF SLAVERY ON TIHE NATIONAL MORALS, AND THE NATIONAL WEALTH,... SECTION IV.-_ARGUMENTS IN FAVOR OF SLAVERY,.. CHAPTER III. DUITIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY,........ SECTION I.- FOUNDATION OF TIlE RIGHT OF PROPERTY,. SECTION II.- ADVANTAGES OF THE INSTITUTION OF PROPERTY, SECTION III.-MODES IN WHICH PROPERTY MAY BE ACQUIRED, SECTION IV.-DIFFERENT KINDS OF PROPERTY,.. ~ SECTION V. - CRIMES AGAINST PROPERTY...... xi 104 .. 107 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY, 116 its 121 126 130 142 142 148 154 157 ioQ CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. Page 167 169 170 DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION, SECTION I. - SLANDER DEFINED,...... SECTION II. - WHAT THE LAW OF REPUTATION FORBIDS, SECTION III. - REASONS FOIZ OBSERVING THE LAW OF REPUTATION..... CHAPTER V. DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY,. SECTION I.-TRUTHFULNESS IN COMMON DISCOURSI,. SECTION II. -VERACITY AS REGARDS PROMISES,.. SECTION III. - VERACITY IN RESPECT TO OATHIS,.. PART III. D U T I E S TO T H E FA M I LY. CHAPTER I. DUTIES OF TIIE MARRIAGE RELATION, CHAPTER II. DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL, RELATION,. SECTION I.-DUTIES OF PARENTS,. SECTION II.-DUTIES OF CHILDREN, ~ xii . 174 . 176 . 177 . 184 190 198 . 206 .. 206 . 214 CONTENTS. E PART IV. DUTIES TO THE STATE. CHAPTER I. Page 221 22.3 228 NATURE AND FOUNDATION OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT, SECTION I. ORIGIN AND OBJECT OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT, SECTION II. - FOUNDATION OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT,. SECTION III.-HISTORIC SKETCH-DIFFERENT OPINIONS AS TO THE NATURE OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT, CHAPTER II. VARIOUS FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT, SECTION I. - ANALYSIS OF THE SEVERAL FUNCTIONS AND FORMS OF GOVERNMENT,..... 244 SECTION II. - HISTORICAL SKETCH OF FORMS OF GOVERNMENT, 249 CHAPTER III. DUTIES OF THE SUBJECT TO THE STATE, CHAPTER IV. DUTIES OF THE STATE TO ITS SUBJECTS, CHAPTER V. DUTIES OF STATE TO STATE,.. SECTION I. - GENERAL RELATIONS AND DUTIES OF STATES TO EACH OTHER,....... SECTION H. -ETHICAL RELATIONS OF REPUBLICAN STATES TO EACH OTHER,....... 2 xiii 239 .. 243 ... 271 .... m 308 308 322 CONTENTS. PART V. DUTIES TO GOD. CHAPTER I. Page 326 OF THIE FEELINGS TOWARDS GOD,.. CHAPTER II. OF OBEDIENCE, CHAPTER III. SECTION I. -OF PRAYER, -........ SECTION II. - OF THE SABBATH,....... I.- PRESUMPTION IN FAVOR OF A SABBATH. II.- INSTITUTION AND AUTHORIiTY OF THE SABBATH. CONFLICT OF DUTIES, AUTHORITIES, xiv .. 332 OF WORSHIP, 337 338 346 .. 350 .. 363 MORAL PIILOSOPIIHY. INTRODUCTION. NATURE AND PROVINCE OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. JMoral Philosophy, what. - Moral Philosophy is the science which treats of morals -the science of right. Natural Philosophy teaches us the laws of external nature; Intellectual Philosophy, the laws of the human mind; Moral Philosophy has to do with the laws of human conduct and duty. As thus defined, it is equivalent to Ethics. It may be termed, also, the science of duties, inasmuch as right and duty are, as regards moral action, one and the same. Term used in a wider sense. -By the earlier English writers the term Moral Philosophy was used in a much more extended sense, to denote in general the science of mind, in distinction from physical science - whatever treats of intellectual in distinction from material things. As thus employed, it includes psychology as well as other sciences; and this use is still, to some extent, prevalent. NATURE AND PROVINCE Thus many of the works of English and Scotch philoso phers on psychology are termed Mioral Philosophy. By French writers, also, the morale is frequently placed in contrast with the physique. Indeed, the dividing liile between mental and moral sci ence has not, as yet, been very closely drawn, for the most part, by those who have written upon either. Many of our own most popular works on Moral Philosophy treat of topics which properly pertain to psychology, as, e. g., the nature of Conscience, the Sensibilities, the Will, and other topics of like nature. These are faculties of the mind, and, as such, it pertains to psychology to explain and unfold them. Moral Philosophy, so far as it has occasion to make use of these phenomena, must go to psychology for the facts and the explanations, just as it must go to astronomy for the facts and laws of planetary motion; or to logic for the laws of thought and forms of reasoning. Its proper office is to teach, not logic, nor astronomy, nor psychology, but the science of right -of duty. It has to do neither with the affections, the emotions, nor the will, except so far as these are involved in the investigation and statement of duty. Intimate connection of Xental with Moral Philosophy. -The connection between the two sciences is indeed very intimate; and for this reason they should be all the more carefully distinguished. The very idea of right is to be sought among the primitive conceptions of the mind. To perceive and judge of the right, is one of the most important oflices of the reflective power of the mind. The 16 OF MORAL PHIIILOSOPHY. emotions, affections, desires, furnish a powerful class of motives to human action, whether right or wrong. The will, or the power of voluntary mental action, constitutes the basis of human accountability, and lies, therefore, at the foundation of ethics. HIence, not improperly, the faculties now designated have been termed, by some philosophers, the active and moral powers of man. Dugald Stewart thus designates them. In regard to the faculties now under consideration, a correct psychology is absolutely essential to a correct science of moral duty. In another respect, also, is the connection of the two sciences intimate. Duty pertains, first and chiefly, not to the external conduct, but to the responsible, intelligent mind, whose thoughts, feeling, and volitions find their expression in that outward conduct, and determine its moral character. To teach me what are my duties, is to teach me what thoughts and affections I ought to cherish; what purposes and volitions I ought to form and put forth; in a word, what ought to be my entire mental activity, as exerted in the various relations of life. Mental science contents itself with ascertaining what are the varied phenomena of mental action; moral science, while relating chiefly to the same department of observation,i.e., the human mind,- inquires not so much what are the laws and operations of its various faculties, as what they ought to be. General divisions. - The science of morals properly divides itself into two parts - the theoretical and the 2* 17 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. practical. Before proceeding to discuss the various du. ties which pertain to the well-ordered conduct of life, it is necessary to inquire first into those general principles on which, as a basis, morality rests, -as, e. g., the nature of right, the ground of right, the rule of right, the province of right, -and in what consists the moral quality of actions. This inquiry into, and discussion of, the general principles which lie at the foundation of morals, may be termed the theoretical part of the science. The way will thus be prepared to take up and discuss, in their order, the several duties that devolve on man in the various relations of life; and this may be termed the practical part of the science. 18 DIVISION FIRSTo THEORETICAL ETHICS. TIHEORETICAL ET11ICS CHAPTER I. THE NATURE OF RIGHT. ~ 1.-RIGHT IN ITSELF CONSIDERED. Essential Attributes. -The term right expresses a simple and ultimate idea; it is, therefore, incapable of analysis and definition; nor does it, like many other ideas, stand in need of definition in order to be understood. It expresses an eternal and immutable distinction, inherent in the nature of things, not the creation of arbitrary power, whether of man or God. Wherever there is voluntary action of any intelligent rational being, there is always, and always must be, a right and a wrong; and all moral action is, of necessity, either the one or the other. The distinction is one universally recognized. The idea of right lies among the simplest furniture and first principles of the human mind. It manifests itself with the dawn of reason and intelligence. It' is not an idea of the schools, a distinetioii known only or chiefly to metaphysicia.ns; but is the 1)roperty alike of the learned and the simnple, of the child and the philosopher. Opinions may vary widely as to THE NATURE OF RIGHT. what is, and what is not, right action; what one system or one age pronounces to be right, another system or another age may decide to be wrong; but, as to the essential difference between the right and the wrong, as ideas, or principles of action, no age or system was ever at a loss - no mind, however feeble, was ever confused. This Idea, whence derived.- It is a question of some importance how we come by the idea of right. Some have attributed it to fashion and education, as did Locke and his followers; others to the laws, human or divine, which ibrbid or sanction certain actions; others regard it as the product of a special sense, whose office it is to take cognizance of moral distinctions, as the eye perceives color, and the ear sound. Others again regard the idea of right as a simple and ultimate one, and as such underived, a primary original conception of the human mind, not innate, but connate, an elementary dictum of reason. The universality of the idea,- its early manifestation in childhood, prior to education, and the influence of example,- as well as the clearness and strength with which it manifests itself, in all conditions of society, and under all the varying circumstances of life,-these things go to show that the idea of right is founded in the constitution of the mind, and not derived from any source external and adventitious. Nor can those who take the opposite view give any satisfactory account of the origin of this idea; since, to attribute it to education, leaves the question still open, where did the first man, the first educator, derive his idea of it; while to ascribe it to law, human or divine, is still wider of the mark, inasmuch as law always presupposes the right, as the foundation on which it rests. To attribute, then, the origin or the idea of right to law, is to place the foundation upon the building, instead of the building upon the foundation. And as to the theory of a 22 THE NATURE OF RIGHT. special sense, whose office it is to take cognizance of the right, it is sufficient to say, that there is no10 evidence of any such special faculty of the mind, nor is any such needed. For the further investigation of this topic, the reader is referred to the author's treatise on Mental Philosophy, in which the question, and its several theories, are more fully discussed. i 2.- RIGHT, AS DISTINGUISHED FROM OTHER IDEAS OF SIMILAR IMPORT. Right and Duty. - Right and duty are not precisely synonymous terms, yet are nearly equivalent. We are always under obligation to do that which is right - it is our duty. The right in morals once ascertained, the doing of it is, under all circumstances, a duty. Right is the foundation of obligation, and coextensive with it. It is the rightness of the thing that creates its binding force, and makes it obligatory upon us. There can be no moral obligation to do what is not in itself a right thing to be done. Still, right and duty, though coextensive, are not of precisely the same import. Right is the abstract, in itself considered. Duty is right, considered in relation to us as personal agents- as doers; obligation is the binding power of the right over us, which makes this or that a duty. Another View. -Some writers make a further distinction between obligation and duty than that which I have now indicated - making obligation more comprehensive than duty. Thus a man may be obliged, by force of circumstances, or by the laws of the land, to do what is not right. Such is the view taken by Whewell, in his Elements of Morality. That which is here called obligation, however, is not really such, but rather compulsion, or necessity. No combination of circumstances, and no power of law, can 23 THE NATURE OF RIGHT. create moral obligation. In morals, that, and that only, conveys obligation which bears the high seal and impress of right. Whatever goes beyond this, or violates this, whatever power and pressure of circumstances it may draw around it, whatever sanction and authority of law, - can never bind the conscience, or impose on the spiritual nature of manthe restraints of a moral obligation. Law may come in, with its sanctions and penalties, to secure the performance of the right; it may cast the heavy sword of power into the scale that hangs in doubtful balance; or it may require and enforce the wrong; but in neither case can it create a moral obligation which did not previously exist. Had there been no law, it would still have been my duty to do the right. It is still my duty, even though the law forbid. Obligation and duty are coextensive. Right and Rights. - The term right varies in significance, according to its use, as an adjective, or as a noun; or, more properly, according to its use in the singular, or in the plural. Right is the principle that should regulate my conduct towards others; my rights are what I may justly expect and require from others, in their intercourse with me- what they ought to do as respects me. That which is my right, is another's duty; and that which is my duty, is another's right. Every right, then, has its corresponding duty. It is my duty, for example, to obey God; and that obedience he has a right to require. It is my duty to obey the state in all its just and proper requirements- in all things not inconsistent with higher obligations; and this obedience the state has the right to demand of me. Inl like manner, all my rights look to the corre sponding duties of others; and all my duties, to the rights of others. There would be no rights, were there not in the first w 24 THE NATURE OF RIGHT. place such a thing as righty. From this, obligation results, duty results, and so rights exist. VTiew of TVhecell and others. -If, with Whewell and others, we make rights to depend for their existence on the laws, it follows that there are no rights except those which society recognizes and creates through the mediuam of law; and were there, for any reason, no longer any law, no man would any longer have any rights;-which is by no means the case. Law may define and prescribe my rights; it may enforce them, see that they are respected and observed; but it does not, and cannot, create them. They are founded in the principles of natural justice, and of universal and immutable right. Were there no laws - were the institutions of society swept away-there would still be rights, so long as there were intelligent and rational beings in existence sustaining certain relations to each other. Suppose, for example, two persons cast ashore upon a desert island, where, beside themselves, is no human beingwhere, of course, is no state and no law. Each of these persons has still, by the law of nature, certain rights, inalienable from him; as, e.g., the right to his own person, his own labor, his own property; and were the other to wrest these from him, he would be guilty of a manifest wrong of palpable injustice. Those who take this view, moreover, go upon the supposition that the laws are based upon right and justice - as unquestionably they should be, but unfortunately are not always. There may be, in the course of human affairs, iniquitous, unjust laws; such things have been, and will be again. Such laws, according to the view in question, however, create rights and impose duties. In such a case I have, according to this theory, the right to demand of others what it is not right for me to demand of them; 25 THE NATURE OF RIGHT. while, on the other hand, it is my duty to do what it is not rigyht for me to do. If it be replied, that in this case the rights supposed are merely legal rights, and not moral ones, I answer, that, according to the theory, all rights are legal ones, and must be first legal before they can be moral. It is the law that creates- rights, moral or other. The morality presupposes and depends upon the legality, as the quality presupposes the substance. To distinguish in this manner between a right which is merely legal, and one which, in addition to that, is also moral, is to step back from the theory that it is law which creates rights. The truth is, neither right nor rights are dependent on law for their existence. There are rights which are not defined by law- which, possibly, are forbidden by law. All rights exist before they are thus defined. Both my duties and my rights depend for their existence on right; and this again depends, not on society, nor law, but is founded in the eternal and immutable nature of things. The rights, so called, which are established by law, may or may not coincide with moral rights. However this may be, Moral Philosophy has to do, not at all with legal rights, as such, but only with moral. With jurisprudence, as distinct from morals, it has no more to do than with constitutional law, or the science of government. 26 GROUND OF RIGHT. CIIAPTER II. GROUND OF RIGHT. Principle of Obligation.- Duty implies obligation. To say that it is my duty to do a given thing, is to say that I ought to do it. Were there no such thing as obligation, there would be no such thing as duty. It is evident then, at a glance, that the principle of obligation is an essential element in morals: it meets us at the threshold, it lies at the foundation of the science on which we are entering. Such is the constitution of the human nmind, that no sooner do we perceive a given course to be right, than we recognize also a certain obligation resting on us to pursue that course. It is a conviction of the mind inseparable from the perception of the right. Given the one, and we cannot escape the other. Ground of Moral Obligation. - The question arises here, What is the ground of this oughyt? -li. what constitutes it? What is that, in any given action, that imposes on me the obligation to do the same? I ought to do this and that: WTay ought? Whatever answer we may give to this question, we must come back ultimately to the simple position -we ought, because it is right. The rightness constitutes the obligation. The question, then, virtually resolves itself into thisWhat constitutes right? This is a question of no little moment. It has received, at different times, and by different authors, widely differ 27 GROUND OF RIGHT. ent answers, and these various answers constitute so many different theories of morals. They lead us over an inter esting and most important field of inquiry, involving one of the deepest problemns in the whole range of philosophical thought. In the preceding chapter, I had occasion to refer to the source —of our idea of right, and also to the question, What constitutes our rights? The question now before us is quite distinct firom each of these. We are now to inquire, not whence comes the idea of right, but what is right itself? not what makes rights, but what makes right? Principal Tlteories.- The principal theories of morals, or grounds of obligation, proposed by different writers, may be reduced, perhaps, to these four: 1. Utility; 2. Law; 3. The nature and character of God; 4. The eternal and immutable nature of things. Each of these has been regarded as the true ground on which to place the dis tinction of right and wrong, and the consequent moral obligation. The two former of these, again, have each a twofold aspect: Utility, as the ground of right, may denote either the happiness, the pleasure accruing from a given course (which is itself a species of utility), or the more direct advantage resulting firom it. Ori, if we place the matter on the ground of legal enactment, the law which makes the right and the wrong, may be nman's law, or it may be God's. We have, then, these divergent paths opening before us, each proposing to conduct to the true solution of our problem, each trodden by many a mighty man in the domain of thought: the uttilitarian theory, with its twofold aspect, the pleasure and the advantage of the thing; the leygal theory, twofold also, a,s of human or Divine authority; the kheory which makes the Divine character the foundation 28 GROUND OF RIGHT. of right; and, finally, that which bases it on tIre immutable and eternal nature of things. Let us, then, examine these several theories in their order: I. The Utilitarian.- Utility as denoting Pleasure. Understanding by this term, in the first place, pleasure, rather than advantage, the doctrine is this: - the reason why we pronounce one thing right, rather than another, is, that we find the one act to be attended, uniformly, with pleasure to the doer; the other, with pain. One contributes to his happiness, the other detracts fi'om it. Now, the pursuit of happiness, it is contended, is the grand motive and spring of all human action; and if it be once established that the actions which we call right are such, invariably, as to promote our happiness, no other reason need be assigned why we thus regard them. And this, it is contended, is the case. If we select any instance of what we call right action, we find it to be an action which is accompanied with pleasurable emotion. And this is the ground of our approval, the reason why we pronounce the action right. Now, it is not to be denied, that to do right brings with it a present satisfaction and true happiness. Such is the constitution of our nature. The question is, whether this tendency to produce happiness is what mnakes a given act right. Is the thing right because it produces happiness? or does it promote oour happiness because it is rigyht? WVhich is the true statement? When I pronounce some past act of my life to be right, and approve it as virtuous, is it because I remember that it gave me great pleasure?and when I cherish the feeling of self-reproach and remiorse, in view of past conduct, is it on the ground that the given action was accompanied with unpleasant and painful sensations? 3* 29 GROUND OF RIGHT. The Theory not satisfactory. - The simple statement of the question would seem sufficient. We feel instinctively that our decision and approval rest on far other and higher grounds. Virtue and happiness are by no means identi cal. We have different terms for them, and mean different things by them. The one cannot be resolved into the other. If it be true that all right things are pleasant, it does not follow that all pleasant things are right, much less that their pleasantness makes them right. Many are the propensities of a corrupt nature, the indulgence of which is attended with present gratification, which still are evil and only evil; and in their pleasantness consists the very strength of the temptation they present. The man who yields to the force of such temptations, however, by no means approves the course that he pursues. He goes to the commission of the wrong, not with a conviction that he is doing right, but under a protest firom his con science, and with a feeling of self-reproach and self-con demnation. This ought not to be, according to the theory now under consideration. He ought rather to approve his conduct, on the ground that he was seeking therein his own happiness; and his self-approval ought to rise and increase in proportion to the pleasure he receives. As deni oting Ial(pi)zess of the Community. -Nor is the case mnaterially altered by substituting the happiness of others, in place of personal happiness, as the ground of lriglht. No doubt right action contributes to the happiness of the community, and swells the sumrn total of the world's enjoyment; but is it this that constitutes the rightness of the act? Is the noble consciousness of doing right, with all its power to sustain the spirit of a man under thl)e pres sure of the heaviest calamities and the gloom of the dark est hour, merely this- the conviction that somehow, in consequence of what he has done, men will, on the whole, -3 0 GROUND OF RIGHT. enjoy themselves better? Independent, and irrespective of all such considerations, is there not a far nobler satisfaction in having done that which was right, in itself considered, and for its own sake? The view now considered was the distinctive tenet of the ancient Epicurean philosophy; and has been held, in later times, by Hume and Shaftesbury in England, and by their followers generally. As denoting A(vantage. -Considering, now, utility as denoting advantage or expediency, we come upon somewhat different ground, -capable, however, of attack and defence by essentially the same arguments. In fact, the former view may be regarded as a modification of the latter; the one specific, the other generic, in its form;-pleasure being itself a species of advantage, at least in the opinion of those who make it the rule of right. Hence, very generally, the advocates of the former view are advocates also of the latter. Still the latter is, of the two, the broader and higher ground. Self-love, according to this view, is the grand motive of human action. Men do what they think for their advantage. Now, it is found by experience that a certain course of conduct is for the advantage, and the opposite for the disadvantage, of the doer. Hence they come to regard the one course as right, and to be pursued, -the other as wrong, and to be avoided. In a word, it is the utility or expediency of the thing that constitutes the ground and reason of its rightness. Such is the doctrine of Bentham and his followers. And here it is admitted on all sides that virtuous action does contribute to the advantage, in many ways, of the doer. The question is, whether this is what makes it virtuous - whether this constitutes its rightness. Is it right because expedient, or expedient because right? 31 GROUND OF RIGHT. Consequences of this Theory.- Let us see what follows from this theory. (1) If expediency is the ground of right, then interest and duty are identical in idea- synonymes for the same thought. To prove a given action right, all that is necessary is to show that it is advantageous to the doer. The samne act performed from the same motives, with the same spirit and intentions, is right to one man, and wrong to another; nay, is right to one and the same man, at one time, and wrong at another, according as it turns out for his advantage or not. We can never be sure that we are acting virtuously, until we know how the action is to affect our personal interests. Men have acted from the highest and purest principles, yet have been in reality far firom virtuous, because what they did proved not for their own interests. They ought, therefore, to cherish feelings of self-reproach and remorse in view of their conduct. (2) It follows from this theory that there is no such thing as intentional wrong-doing. Men always act, it is said, from the principle of self-love. They do what they think is for their own advantage. Finding by experience that certain actions tend to their advantage, they come to regard such actions as right, and the opposite, for the same reason, as wrong. What have we here for a syllogism? Man acts always with reference to his own good. To act with reference to one's own good, is to act right; therefore, man invariably acts right! He may mistake, and do what is in the end disadvantageous; but it was a mistake, an error of judgment, and not an intentional wrong. This is on the whole a very favorable view of things, and may serve to relieve somewhat the sombre aspect in which the world and poor erring human nature present themselves to a certain class of minds. Men are not so bad, after all. They do as well as they know how. They mean to be selfish, and to consult their own interests; and if they 32 GROUND OF RIGHT. sometimes come short of duty in this respect, it is an error of the head and not of the heart. (3) It follows, also, that there is no such thing as disinterested vi?wtte. Utility is the ground of rectitude, the foundation of obligation. We ought, therefore, to give a man credit for his conduct, just in proportion as we perceive him to have been governed throughout by a regard to his own personal advantage. To act thus is to act right, and to comply with the claims of duty. There can be no virtue which springs not from this source. The more fully a man promotes his own interests, and seeks his own personal advantage, in all he does, provided only there be no direct violation of the rights of others, the higher esteem ought we to cherish for that man in our hearts. On the other hand, where an action is of such a nature that we are not quite sure whether the man was really seeking his own advantage, or that of others, in what he did, we ought to withhold our approbation. But, strange to say, selfish as the world is, it does not so decide. It does sensibly diminish our moral approbation of any act, to see, or suspect even, that self-interest was the leading motive of conduct; it heightens our admiration and esteem, to perceive that the act was performed without the least regard to that, but from entirely different motives. Contra(licts Consciousness. -And this leads us to remark, in general, that the theory under consideration contradicts the facts of consciousness. If utility were the ground of moral obligation, the foundation of right, then, whenever we recognize such obligation, we should be conscious of this element as the basis of it- should be conscious of perceiving the tendency of the given act to promote the personal happiness or the personal advantage of the doer, and that our conviction of obligation in the 33 GROUND OF RIGHT. case arose from that circumstance; whereas, in fact, we are conscious of no such thing, but in many cases of directly the reverse. The sense of obligation exists, not only irrespective of the idea of happiness or of advantage to be derived from the given act, but often in opposition to it; the desire of happiness, or of personal advantage, drawing us-in one direction, the sense of obligation in another. It is not true that duty and interest are identical. We have different names for them, we mean different things by them. We are conscious of acting, now from one, now firom the other, of these principles. It is not true that men never intentionally do what they know to be wrong. This was the capital defect in the ethical system of Socrates, and also of Plato, who make virtue a matter of science, and sin to be mnerely ignorance. Whose consciousness does not testify the opposite of this? Who will not say, with Ovid, "Video meliora, proboque, deteriora sequor;" or, with Euripides, "I know that what I am about to do is evil, but desire is stronger than mny deliberations." Surely the poets, in this case, are more nearly right thni the philosophers. Who has not reason to say, with Paul, "That which I do, I allow not." Neither is it true that we act always firom personal and selfish considerations. We are conscious of the opposite conscious of doing that which is right, because it is right, and not for the sake of personal advantage. Nor in such cases is the verdict of conscience against us; but, on the contrary, it is precisely such actions that draw forth the testimony of her warmest approbation; so far fiom reproaching us for not acting with more direct and uniform reference to our own advantage, copscience more fre 34 GROUND OF RIGHT. quently condemns us for having acted from no higher principle. We cannot but regard the facts of consciousness, then, as altogether at variance with the theory under consideration. Utility as denoting Goo(s of thle greatest number. - Suppose, now, we give the term utility a still wider extension, meaning by it, not the advantage of the indcividual merely, but the good of the greatest number - does it become in this sense the foundation of right and of moral obligation? There are still insuperable objections. In the first place, how can it always be known what will promote the interests of the greatest number? The tendencies and results of actions are often hidden from human perspicacity. We do not know how they will affect the interests of any considerable number of persons. A lI.borIious calculation of consequences would in most cases be necessary, in order to such a conclusion; and even then we could never arrive at certainty -never be sure that our reasonings and conclusions were correct. We should be in suspense, therefore, as to the morality of actions, unable to decide whether they are right or wrong, until we could first know their ultimate bearing on the general welfare. Such a calculation of consequences is quite beyond the capacity of the mass; only the more enlightened and far-seeing are competent to form such judgments, and even they not with any certainty. Only the few, therefore, are competent to formn ideas of right or wrong, and apply them to human conduct, while the vast multitude are left without any such faiculty to guide them. At variance with -Facts. - Furthermore, it may be justly objected to this theory, in the form in which it is now stated, that it is directly at variance with the facts in the case, As a matter of fact? we do not always calculate tho 8 GROUND OF RIGHT. consequences of an action before we pronounce it, in our minds, right or wrong. We are conscious of no such procedure. We do not stop to know what bearing it is likely to have on the public welfare. We do not raise the question at all. We neither know nor care. Instinctively we decide as to the propriety and rightness of the given act; we approve and condemn without reference to consequences, and on other grounds than that of expediency. It is fatal to this theory of utility, in whatever form it is stated, whether as referring to the happiness of the individual, or the happiness of the community- to the advantage of the individual, or the advantage of all, that, so far from being conscious ordinarily of any such considerations, in our estimate of the morality of actions, we are conscious of quite the opposite. Our moral decisions are often pronounced under circumstances which preclude the possibility of all such prudential considerations. Narrate to a child, just old enough to understand you, some story of flagrant injustice and wrong - the flush of indignation, the glow of resentment are visible at once on that cheek; the decision of that moral nature, its verdict of disapproval and condemnation, is to be read at once in that eye, that brow, that clenched hand -the whole mien and aspect of the miniature man. Has it been calculating the expediency and utility of the thing- the consequences to society of what its outraged nature condemns? Utility presupposes Obligation.- But there is a further objection to making utility, in any of its significations, the ground of moral obligation. It is that all these principles as thus applied, virtually presuppose the existence of moral obligation, and therefore cannot be the ground of it. I perceive such a coursec to be conducive to happiness; therefore, says the advocate of this view, I am under obligation to pursue that course. But why therefore? Why .86 GROUND OF RIGIIT. ought? Suppose I choose to do that which is not, on the whole, for my happiness, -what then? Whose business is it but my own? Either there is no manner of obligation in that case, or else it lies out of and back of the principle nowv supposed. The same may be said of utility in the sense of advantage. It presupposes an obligation to do what is seen to be usefil and advantageous; and the question still remains, What is the groused of that obligation which the doctrine of utility presupposes? II. Thteory of Tegal E)tactment.- Let us look, now, at the theory which places the foundation of moral obligation on the ground of positive etactmet. Laws have been made, human and divine, requiring, forbidding, etc. Hence our approval and condemnation of actions, and our conviction of obligation. The just and the unjust, the right and the wrong, ill human conduct, are simply its conformity, or want of conformity, to law. Of those who take this ground, some look no higher than to hut)ian enactment as the ground of rectitude and the foundation of moral obligation. The laws of man make the right and wrong of things, and are the sufficient and ultimate standard of morals. There is no higher law. No other reason need be given why I should do, or not do, a given thing, than that the laws of.my country require it. Such, among the ancients, was the doctrine of the Soph ists. Plato, in the "De Legibus," and Aristotle, in his "Ethics," make mention of the doctrine as maintained by some in their day. Among the moderns, Gassendi and IHobbes are almost the only writers of distinction who have had the.boldness to avow, and the consistency to maintain, a doctriue at once so shameless, so obnoxious to the common sense and common honesty of mankind, and so destructive of the 4 37 GROUND OF RIGHT. first principles of morality. Occasionally, indeed, the spectacle is presented of some one, more patriotic than discreet, who, in his zeal to defend the constitution and laws of his country, so far forgets himself, in the pressure of the exigency, as to take the general position that the laws of the land are to us the final court of appeal, and that we are to look no higher for authority. Even such persons, it is to be presumed, are not fully aware of the true nature and legitimate consequences of this doctrine, nor of the company they keep in maintaining such a position. They would shrink, it is to be hoped, from the doctrine, reduced to its simple elements, and affirmed, as a principle in ethics, that ntighyt makes righyt,- a sentiment that even a German rationalist has pronounced infernal, - and from the atheism that discards the Deity, and overlooks the moral nature of man, while proclaiming human law as the standard of morals and the foundation of right. Objectio.? to this View. -If it were of any use to reason against a doctrine so little deserving the name of philosophy, or the notice of a calm reply, it were sufficient, per. haps, to ask how it is possible, on this principle, since law is itself the source and foundation of right, to compare one law or code with another,- those of Draco, e.g., with those of Solon or Lycurgus; the edicts of Nero with those of Constantine; and because one system is mild and humane, another barbarous and inhuman, pronounce one to be more right and just than the other? If law is i'cs own authority; if it makes right;;f back of it there is no appeal, no ultimate standard of rectitude,-then, of course, everything which is once enacted, and obtains the sanction of established law, is right and binding, no matter what it may be, - one equally so with another, - and it is absurd to make a distinction between them. The commands of the veriest despot are as just and right, as obligatory on 38 GROUND OF RIGHT. the conscience, as those of the wisest and mildest ruler. Law is law, and that ends the matter. A law morally wrong is an impossibility, an absurdity. Inasmuch as laws vary, moreover, in different lands, what is right in one country is wrong when you cross a river or a mountain; what is a virtue ilk Holland is a sin in Belgium. .)ivine Law as the grounid of Right.- Much more rea sonable and philosophical is the view of those who regard the divine will and law as the foundation of moral rectitude. This view was maintained by Occam, among the scholastics -by Paley, and many others, among the modsrns. Yet even to this view insuperable obstacles arise. Objections to tais VTiew. - 1. If this view be correct, then wl have only to suppose the will of Deity to change, and what is now wrong becomes instantly right, -the good and the bad, the virtuous and the vicious, change characters at once. We have only to suppose him other than he is, and to have commanded other than he has, to have reversed the decalogue; and the things now commanded would then have been wrong, and the things now forbidden would have been right. Murder, adultery, false witness, theft, covetousness, would have been virtues, commendable and obligatory; while to honor our parents, and to love our neighbor as ourselves, would have been morally wrong. In other words, there is no difference, in respect of moral character, between these actions in themselves considered; the difference lies wholly in the fact that one is commanded, and the other forbidden; they are right or wrong only as they are, or are not, the will of Deity. It is no answer to this to say that God is holy, and therefore will not command that which is evil; nor, that he is immutable, and therefore will not change. The question is not as to the matter of fact, but as to what would 39 GROUND OF RIGHT. be true, in case he and his law were not what they are. If it were possible for God to throw around sin the sanction of his law, would it, because of that sanction, cease to be sin, and become holiness? Does the rightness of an act consist wholly and simply in its being lawful? 2. It follows, also, that, had there been no divine law to establish the character of actions, human conduct had been neither virtuous nor vicious, neither good nor bad; but all actions would have been alike indifferent. To hate our neighbor, to take his property, his good name, or his life, would have been not only allowable, but equally as commendable and meritorious as the opposite. Nothing would have been unjust, nothing wrong. 3. There is no propriety or sense in speaking of God's law as just and good; in affirming that his statutes are right, his commandments holy, etc.; for moral approbation is wholly misplaced and uncalled for. It is without meaning. For, if there is no standard of right, and no ground of obligation but the law itself, how can its requirements be any other than right and binding, whatever they may be? To say that his statutes are just and right, is to say, simply, that his statutes are his statutes. MIore than this: when we speak of the law as holy, just, etc., do we not attribute a moral character to the law itself? But how can this be? If the law creates moral distinctions, how can law itself possess a moral character? - how can it be either right or wrong? This is to suppose right created, and yet to have existed before it was created. 4. Further, for the same reason, we are shut out, on this principle, from attributing to Deity himself any moral character. Law is the foundation of right, and law is from God. Back of his will thcre is no law, and, of course, no ground of rectitude. God has himself, therefore, aside from his own law, no moral character, no virtue; for, be 40 GROUND OF RIGHT. yond his own will and pleasure, there is no law imposing obligation, and constituting for him the right and the wrong. One thing is as right as another for him; everything is equally right; and, strictly speaking, nothing is, for him, either right or wrong. It is language without meaning when we say, with one of old, "Holy, holy, holy Lord God, just and true are thy ways." Before he enacted the first law, there was no such thing as right. It depended entirely on his pleasure whether to enact that law. There was no obligation to enact it; for no law, as yet, existed to create obligation. Suppose he had not done it? - right would not have existed, and, of course, in that case, could not have pertained to the divine character. Not until he creates the right by making law, can he by any possibility possess a moral character; and even then, it is a moral character which he himself creates, and imposes upon himself by arbitrary enactment. IIad he made a law precisely the reverse of the actual one, it would have been equally right and binding, and himself equally as holy. But it is difficult to see how the thing made can put the mnakor himself under obligation; how from his own work he can derive the foundation of a character which he had not in himself prior to the work. It is difficult to estimate the intrinsic excellence of that holi, ness which owes its origin to a purely arbitrary enactment; which might just as well never have been made, or have been entirely other than, and the reverse of, what it is;-a holiness which, when strictly viewed, amounts merely to this, -that the being who possesses it does what he (loes. Law as the Basis of Obligation.- It may be supposed, perhaps, by some, that the divine law, while it may not absolutely create the distinction of right and wrong, does nevertheless create the obligation on our part to do, or not to do, the things required; that it is to me the sufficient 4* 41 GROUND OF RIGHT. reason why 1 ought to do thus and thus. This is a view entitled to a careful consideration. I must do thus, because such is the will of Deity. The question is now as to this word because. Granting that the will of Deity is as affirmed, what has that to do with my conduct? - wherein and how does that place me under obligation to do what the Deity wills? Where lies the binding power of the law itself? Manifestly not in itself, as law, but in something else. There must be something to make the law binding, or it can bring with it no obligation to obedience on my part. And in saying this, we really aban(lost the position, that law is itself the basis of obligations. This something we may find in one of three things. It may be in the character of the law given, - a holy, just, and good law, and one which we ought therefore to obey. But this is to place the ground of obligation, not in the law itself, but in something else, viz., moral rectitude. I am bound to obey, not because there is a law, but because there is a holy and just law. Or we may trace the binding power of the law to the relation which the Deity sustains to us. He is our creator, preserver, benefactor; and as such, has the right, it is said, to control and govern us. But does this, we reply, give him the right to govern and control, irrespective of moral distinctions? If it does, then right and wrong are the mere arbitrary creations of his will,-a view which we have already considered and rejected. If it does not, then the ultimate ground of obligation is to be found in the rectitude of the divine requirements. In either case, it is not the law itself that constitutes the obligation. Does, then, that which constitutes the binding force of the divine law consist in this: that the Deity is in himself such a being as he is, the greatest, the wisest, the best; and therefore his will is obligatory on other beings? This again 42 GROUND OF RIGHT. is to recognize moral distinctions as lying back of the law itself, and as giving to that law its character and its force. When you say that God is good, just, holy, the best of beings, and, on that account, ought to be Obeyed, you abandon the position, that law itself creates moral distinctions, and that it contains in itself the ground of obligation. HIis being and nature are prior to his law, and the foundation of it; and if his being and nature are themselves good, then certainly it is not his law that makes them so; and if it is from them that our obligation to obedience springs, then certainly not from the law itself. Whatever view we take, then, of this matter, we are compelled to give up the positioni that the divine law is the ground of moral obligation. An action is right, not because God wills it; on the contrary, he wills it because it is right. View of -)-. Chalmners. -The distinction between the rightness and the lawfulness of an act, is admitted by some, who still place obligation on the ground of law. This is the case with Chalmners. In general, it may be remarked, that no writer breathes throughout a higher moral tone and purpose, or utters truth with more eloquence and earnestness than lihe. His style is an avalanche broken loose, a sea of expression, rolling, sentence after sentence, wave upon wave, with a loftiness and force quite irresistible. It is the style of the orator, however, rather than of the philosopher; indicating fervor and strength of feeling, rather than precision and clearness of thought. There is a certain nobleness of sentiment that wins our admiration. We feel sure that some leviathan is ploughing up those waters, and making them to boil; but it is a leviathan not willing to be caught and classified for purposes of science. In the present case, Dr. Chalmers, if we understand him, derives obligation from the divine law, but riyht from the 43 GROUND OF RIGIIT. divine character; thus separating the two. While he rejects the view of Paley, that makes the divine command the foundation of right, hle still makes that command the foundation of our obligation to do the right. Not until Deity interposes with his authority in its behalf, does the right become obligatory. Objection to this VTiew.- It is difficult to perceive the justness of this distinction. In the first place, it limits the term obligation to a strictly fo)eissic use, a sense to which it is by no means restricted. A wider sense belongs to it. We are under obligation, ethl)ically speaking, to do many things not specifically requiredI by law. But, more than this, it seems to divorce obligation from right, as if right did not carry in itself a corresponding obligation, but was dependent on law to come in and give it authority; or as if, on the other hand, obligation might somnetimes, or might at least be supposed to, run counter to right. Right and Obligations, how related.- We cannot think such a distinction either necessary or allowable. On the contrary, we regard right and obligation as coextensive, and on a common basis. The foundation and origin of the one, is also the source and foundation of the other. Given, the right, and there is given along with it the obligation to do the right. We cannot conceive them separate; the former without the latter; a right thing which we are under no obligation to do, or a wrong thing which we are under no obligation to avoid. This obligation is universal, absolute. complete. Law cannot add to it, or make it more perfect than it already is. Law may indicate and enforce, but cannot create moral obligation. Show me t' at a thing is right, and you show me a reason, and the best of all reasons, why I outght to do it. The moment I perceive the rightness, I perceive also the obligation. If the one is founded in law, 44 GROUND OF RIGHIIT. so is the other; if the divine character is the foundation of the one, it is the ground of the other also. Matters of ab Idifferent Vatq -e.- It is admitted that, in respect to matters in themselves indifferent, as, for instance, the ceremonies of a ritual observance, law may impose an obligation not previously existing. But such is not the case now under consideration. We are concerned, in this discussion, only with such matters as come under the cognizance of the moral faculty, as being in themselves right or wrong; and the question is, What constitutes the obligation to do, not a thing indifferent, but a thing which we perceive and know to be riight? Our answer is: The very rightness constitutes the obligation. The question returns then, On what does the 2righttness depend? Not on utility, not on law. An action is riight, not because expedient; but expedient, because right. It is right, not because God wills it; on the contrary, he wills it because it is right. What, then, constitutes rightness? III. The.)ivinie Xcattere the Source of Right.- It may be said that right and wrong lie not in any of these things, - not in the pursuit of happiness or of personal advantage; not in law, human or divine,- but in the meature and character of God himself. This, as we have already stated, is the view of Chalmers. It is the view, also, of many others. We have discussed so fully the previous theories, that there is no need of dwelling long upon this. The same objections that lie against the theory of divine law, as the source of obligation and the ground of right, apply with equal force to this view. God's law is but the expression of his will; and his will is but the expression and transcript of his character. It is his nature in action. To say that his law constitutes right, then, is virtually saying, inii another forn, that his nature and character are the ground of right; and, 45 GROUND OF RIGHT. whatever objections lie against the one view, are, in reality, equally objections to the other. Objection to this liew. - If right or wrong depend, ultimately, on the character of God, then we have only to suppose God to change, or to have been originally other than he is, and our duties and obligations change at once; -that which was a virtue, becomes a crime; that which is a crime, is transformed into a virtue. Had he been precisely the reverse of what he is, he had still been, as now, the source of right, and his own character would have been as truly good, and just, and right, as it is now. This is, virtually, to rob him of all moral character. We may still say that he is holy, and that his ways are right; but we mean by it only this, when we come to explain, - that he is what he is, and does what he does. The holiness of his acts consists, not at all in the essential character of the acts themselves, but only in the circumstance that they are his acts. It does not meet this objection to say that God is'holy, holy by a necessity of his nature, -and that he can never be otherwise: that is not the question; but simply, whether his being what he is is the ground of all rectitude and of all obligation; whether that which he does is right because it conforms to his character, or whether his character is holy because it conforms to the right. This is a very important distinction. We have this objection, then, to the view which re. solves virtue into the divine character, and makes right inherent originally in the divine nature: that while it seeks to honor God by making him the source of all excellence, it really takes away from his character the highest excellence and glory that can pertain to it - that of confor'ming to the right. 1V. The Eternal Nature of Things as the Ground of 46 'I GROUND OF RIGHT. Right.- We seem to be driven, then, to the only remaining conclusion, that right and wrong are distinctions immutable and inherent in the nature of things. They are not the creations of expediency, nor of law; nor yet do they originate in the divine character. They havo no origin; they are eternal as the throne of Deity; they are immutable as God himself. Nay, were God himself to change, these distinctions would change not. Omnipotence has no power over them, whether to create or to destroy. Law does not make them, but they make law. They are the source and spring of all law and all obligationI. Reason points out these distinctions; the moral nature recognizes and approves theln. God's law, and will, and nature, are in conformity to these distinctions; else that law were not just and right, nor that nature holy. Our moral nature is in conformity to these distinctions; hence we approve and disapprove, as we do, the various actions of men. The deeds are right, not because we approve them; on the contrary, we approve them because they are right. They are right, not because they are commanded; but they are commanded because they are right. Even.Deity subject to the Law of Right.- There is a sense in which Deity himself is subject to this eternal and immutable law of right. There are things which it would not be right for even Deity to do. So fully does his moral nature approve the right and abhor the wrong, that tho Scriptures declare it impossible for him to do evil. There is no purity like his; no approval of the right, no condemnation and abhorrence of the wrong, so strong and intense as his, in the whole universe. This, his moral nature, is to him a law, the highest possible and coinceiva ble, placing him under obligation, not indeed to another, but to himself, to adhere ever to the eternal principles of right, and truth, and justice, I 47 Y GROUND OF RIGHT. This View honors God. -In their anxiety to honor and exalt the Divine Being, some have shrunk from the idea that there is any law or obligation resting on the Deity to do one thing rather than another,- that there is, or can be, anything which it would be wrong for him to do. But, which most honors and exalts God -to resolve the distinction of right and wrong into the arbitrary decisions of his will, thus leaving him without moral character, or to regard that distinction as immutable and eternal, extending even to the throne and will of him who layeth the beams of his chambers in the waters, and hangeth the earth upon nothing? Which most honors him- to make his nature and his will the foundation of right, or the eternal principles of right and justice the foundation of his character and his law? Which gives the noblest and most exalted conception of the Divine Being? Which of these two views imparts the loftier significance to that sublime anthem of the angels, that goes up unceasingly before his throne, and shall yet go up from the entire universe: " HOLY, HOLY, HOLY Lord God Almighty, which was, and is, and is to come?" and to that song of the redeemed that stand upon the sea of glass: "Just and true are thy ways, thou king of saints. Who shall not fear thee, O Lord! and glorify thy name?" Objection stated and answered.- It may be said, perhaps, that to make right and wrong inherent in the nature of things, is virtually to place their foundation and origin in God; since the nature of things depends, after all, on him. He who made all things, is the author of their nature also. This objection derives its force from the somewhat indefinite expression, "nature of things,"a p)hrase used with great latitude of meaning. As used to denote material objects and their qualities, it is true that both things and 48 GROUND OF RIGHT. the nature of things are the work of God; as used to denote finite intelligences, the same is true,-they are the work of the Divine Initelligence, they and their original nature. But when we speak of things and the nature of things, as applicable to this discussion, we do not, of course, refer to material objects, nor yet to spiritual intelligences, but to the actions and moral conduct of intelligent beillgs, created or uncreatedl, finite or infinite. We mean to say, that such and such acts, of an intelligent, voluntary agent, whoever he may be, are, in their very nature, right or wrong. Now, God does not create the actions of intelligent, firee agents; and, of course, does not create the nature of those actions. To say that the moral character of an act is created by Deity, is simply to beg the question in dispute. The Theory asserts what. -When we say that right and wrong are inherent, then, in the very nature of things, we imply assert that certain courses of conduct are, in their very nature and essence, wrong- certain others, light; that they are so, quite independent and irrespective of the consequences that result from them, or of the sanctions and authority with which they may be invested; that they are so, not because of the laws, either human or divine, that give them force; that they would be so, were there no law, or were it the opposite of what it is; that even the actions of Deity himself fall within the range of this universal principle; and that it does not depend on his will, or even his nature, much less on his power as Creator, to establish or abolish this immutable distinction. We say it is in the very nature of things that the whole is greater than a part; that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points; that two straight lines cannot enclose a space. We cannot conceive the opposite to be true. It does not depend on the will of Deity whether 5 I I 49 GROUND OF RIGIIT. these things shall be so or not. Ile does not create these relations. They are eternal and necessary truths. In like uanner, there are certain truths pertaining to the conduct of all rational and intelligent beings,- certain moral distinctions, which we regard as immutable and eternal,inherent in the very nature of things. And on this firm, eternal basis rests the foundation of our moral obligation. CHAPTER III. THE RULE OF RIGHT. Question stated. -What makes a thing right is one question, and how do we knowt it to be right, is quite another. The former was discussed in the preceding chap. ter; the latter is now before us. What rule have we by which to judge of the moral quality of actions? —what standard? - what means of information? The decision of the former question is not necessarily the decision also of this. That which is the ground of right, and the basis of moral obligation, is not, of necessity, the source of out knowledge respecting the right, and the rule of our duty. The An2sqer. -It is a sufficient answer to the question before us, to say, in general, that the will of God must be regarded as the rule of right and the standard of duty to man. The divine will, while it is not the source and ground of right -as already shown -is nevertheless the source of our knowledge of right, the rule of duty to us. It does not create right, but reveals it, makes it known. That will itself reposes upon the right, and is conformed to it. That will is our law. Such is the character of the Divine Being, i .,) 0 TIIE RILIE OF RIGhIT. and such, also, our relation to him, as Creator, Governor, Benefactor, as to make his will binding upon us, and that law, which is holy, just, and good, our rightful and only proper rule of action. That Will, how revealed. This rule is made known to us in various ways. It is given, first of all, in the moral nature of man himself, who is endowed with the faculty of distinguishing between right and wrong, and is so constituted that, by the law of his nature, he approves the right and disapproves the wrong, whenever perceived. It is given also in the constitution of nature, in the ordering and arrangement of things about us; which constitution and arrangement are such as to indicate clearly the will of the Deity as to the course which we should pursue. It is given yet more fully and clearly in that revelation which he has made of his will in the sacred Scriptures. I. In the Moral Ncture of lactn. - Such is the constitution of the mind as to fit it for taking cognizance of moral distinctions, and, what is more, for approving the right whenever perceived, and condemning the wrong. And this moral nature and constitution of the human mind is firom God, and is in itself an indication of his will. It may not,'of itself, point out with clearness and definiteness, in all cases, what actions are right, and what are wrong; this may be, to some extent, a matter of opinion and judgment-a matter of belief rather than of positive knowledge; yet, within certain limits, the moral nature of man decides without hesitation as to the character of given actions, and approves or condemns accordingly. It is seldom at a loss as to the great dividing lines which separate the kingdoms of right and wrong, of crime and duty. An instance of flagrant injustice or ingratitude, related in the hearing of a child, or of a savage, unbiassed by education and the restraints of civilization and society, 51 4'* THE RULE OF RIGHT. calls forth at once his disapproval, and awakens his indignation at the wrong. It is the voice of nature, essentially the same ill all climes and ages of the world, approving the right, condemning the wrong. It is the voice of God, speaking through the moral nature and constitution which he has bestowed upon his creatures. Thus it is, that they which have not the law, "are a law unto themselves." II. In the Consttiztio)n of Nature. - The will of the Creator is farther revealed-in the constitution and nature of things about us. It is impossible for one of ordinary intelligence and habits of observation not to perceive a fixed connection between virtue and happiness, vice and misery, in the world. Certain courses of conduct are uniformly attended with certain results. It is the natural tendency of a certain manner of life to produce misery and evil consequences; it is the tendency of an opposite course to produce opposite results. And from this alone might be inferred, with sufficient clearness and certainty, what is the will of the Creator, as to the course which his creatures shall pursue. These results are intended, not accidental; and they are intended as an indication of the divine will. A Case supposed. -Let us suppose, for example, the question to arise in the mind of an intelligent heathen, having no other than the light of nature to guide him, whether a life of sensual gratification- the indulgence, without restraint, of the merely animal appetites- were agreeable to the divine will. Hle finds such indulgence to be attended with momentary gratification, followed by subsequent misery; that it results in injury to the powers of body and of mind; that its tendency is to suffering, poverty, vice, crimei. Hie observes these facts. He perceives them to be the legitimate and inevitable results of the constitution of nature, a part of the system of things; '52 THE RULE OF RIGHT." and if hlie acknowledges the system itself to have had an intelligent originator and designer, can lie be at a loss as to the intention and will of that Creator in the case supposed? It is in this way that we may learn firom the constitution of nature what is the will of our Creator. All nature has its laws. AIan, as a part of the great system of nature, is no exception to the rule. Both his physical and his spiritiial being have their laws. These laws are to be learned, in either case, by observing the results and tendencies of different actions; and the laws of our moral nature, thus ascertained, constitute what we may call a system of natural religion. Whether this is really Law.-And here the question may arise, whether that which we call law in such cases - as in the expression, laws of our moral nature- is really, after all, of the nature of law, properly so called; or whether it is merely advice or admonition. Certain courses of conduct, it is admitted, tend to produce misery and ruin, while other courses promote the happiness of all concerned. This is to be construed, however, it may be said, not as a law prohibiting and commanding, but as simply an indication, or admonition, as to the course which it is wisest and best for us to pursue. The suffering which follows wrongdoing is not a punishment of the wrong, but simply a warning against its future commission. I reply: it is of no consequence to the present argument whether it be the one or the other- whether punishment or merely warning- whether law, or merely advice. In either case, it is a sufficient indication of the will of the Creator respecting the course which his creatures should pursue. It shows plainly enough what his wishes and instructions are -what he meant by constituting us as he did. 53 .5* THE RULE OF RIGHT. mot mere Advice. -As a matter of fact, however, the indications to which I refer are not merely advisory, but, in many cases at least, prohibitory; not mere warning, but punishment. The suffering comes after, and often long after, the wrong has been done, as in the case of those youthful follies which produce their results in subsequent years, when the evil is accomplished, and the constitution already hopelessly impaired. The consequences, in such a case, are not fully known until it is already too late to remedy the evil. Nay, the man may already have reformed, and his life may be one of active and noble useful ness; yet, nevertheless, the punishment, long delayed and slow of approach, but sure as the established laws of the universe, shall by-and-by overtake him. The fires which youthful folly and vice have kindled are not always extinguished by the tears of subsequent repentance, but burn on, slowly consuming, until the whole structure lies in ruins. There is a point, moreover, beyond which even reformation becomes hopeless, not to say impossible. All further warning and admonition, in such a case, are useless; yet the suffering, which is the inevitable result of wrong-doing, is none the less inflicted. Now, in these cases, the misery which is consequent upon vice cannot be intended as warning or admonition, 'for it comes too late; the evil is done. It is not advice, but law; not warning, but penalty. If it be said the suffering is intended as a warning to others, I reply, so is all punishment; but is none the less punishment on that account. III. In -Revelation. - The will of God is further made known in that revelation which he has given us in the sacred Scriptures. The sources of information already considered are at the best impeifect and defective. There was need of another, a more direct, a more complete and 54 THE RULE OF RIGIIT. explicit declaration of the divine will. In the Scriptures we have this needed revelation. They supply the defects of the previous sources of information -make known to man what he most needs to know respecting himself, his ilaker, and the uncertain future, and bring to bear upon himn motives to obedience and a right life, such as could be drawn from no other source. It cannot be denied that man's moral nature teaches him much; much also the constitution of things around him; and it may be firily conceded that an honest, sincere inquirer after truth, having no other means of information than the light thus derived, but disposed to make the best use of the instruction thus obtained, would not be likely to go far astray in his views of what constitutes a right course of life. Yet, in both the sources of information already considered, there are, it must be confessed, serious deficiencies, such as render a further and better revelation of the divine will an absolute necessity of the race. .M[ass's Moral Natttre -Defective. -As to the moral faculty, while it enables us to comprehend the right and the wrong as made known to us,-while it causes us to perceive and feel our obligation to do the right and to avoid the wrong, - it does not of itself point out to us precisely what our duties and obligations are, - precisely what is, and what is not, the right thing - the thing to be done. This we are left to learn, for the most part, in other ways. Conscience is not itself, strictly speaking, a revelation. Given, the right, or the supposed right, and conscience holds us to it, presses upon us the obligation, approves our obedience, chastises our disobedience with' its scorpion lash. In regard to the question, What is duty?- what, to-day, and for me, under present circumstances, is the right thing to be done? -it has no special revelation to make, other than to form a judgment, the best it can, in view of all the 55 TIlE RULE OF RIGHT. circumstances of the case, aided by the light of reason and experience. Conscience, psycliologic.tlly viewed, is in fact simply the judgmrent, or reflective ficulty of the mind, exercised upon nmoral themnes. As thus employed, it has no advantage of infallibility, or absolute correctness, more than as employed on other matters. Hence, as in all our' judgments, so in these, we are liable to err, we do err; we mistake the path of duty, not seldom, even where we seek to go right. Now, it is just here that additional light is neededsome clearer, more explicit revelation of duty and the will of God. Conscience is satisfied if only we do what we suppose to be right; but how are we to know with any certainty what is right? A Case stl)posecl.- I can conceive, for example, an intelligent and right-minded heathen, convinced of his obligations to the Supreme Power, and disposed to yield that homage and worship which are due from the creature to the Creator, yet at a loss to know what worship would be acceptable to Deity. I can readily suppose him to be satisfied of the guilt incurred by a life of sin, and of the necessity of making some expiation for that guilt, but ignorant of the way in which the anger of a just God against the evil-doer may be appeased. I can conceive him interrogating conscience in vain to know what, in these circumstances, he is to do. Conscience has nothing to say, except to accuse him of violated obligation, and of ever-accumulating guilt. What shall he do? Shall he offer the most costly sacrifice? - shall he cast his child into the Ganges, or himself into the flames? The man needs some other instruction, some other light than nature, and reason, or his own moral sense, afford, in order to discover the path of life. System of X(ittture also lhsuffcient. - As respects natural 56 THE RULE OF RIGHT. religion, or the constitution and nature of things about us, that, too, must be confessed, in some respects, an insuffi cient guide, of itself, to the right course of life; and such we find it has always proved in the history of the world. It has never fully met and answered the wants of the humnan mind. Much may be learned from it, but not all that man wishes to know. It is invaluable and yet insufficient. It teaches only by experience; and that experience often comes too late, -comes when the evil is done, and there is no remedy, -as in the case of the youth who squanders in idleness and profligacy the best years of his life, and finds out too late the loss he has incurired. That experience, moreover, is drawn wholly firom the presezt world, the state of things in which we find ourselves here placed; it knows nothing, teaches nothing, with respect to the futture, except by inference; it gives no certain knowledge with regard to anything beyond the present life, or whether, indeed, there is anything beyond. I may i)ffer, fi'om what I observe of the connection between virtue and happiness, sin and misery, in the present life, that if there be a future state of existence, the same law will hold there; but I cannot kJowt this, much less that there is a future existence. Nor can I learn, firom anything in the constitution of nature, the true remedy; or whether there is any remedy for the evils of sin, any escape from its guilt. These are matters which; most of all, I wish to know; yet on these points nature is silent. Now, the force of sinful passion, and an evil nature in man, strengthened, as that nature and those passions are, by indulgence and habit, must ever prove too strong for the restraints of such a system as this. It will keep no nation, no age, effectually in check. And such proves to be the case. Both the religious and the ethical systems of the pagan world- systems which flourished in the palmiest 57 THE RULE OF RIGHT. days of the most cultivated and refined nations of an tiquity show conclusively that natural religion is not enough. Neither in the one nor the other do we find clear and adequate conceptions of the Supreme Being, of the future state, of the way of pardon to the erring and the lost; neither in the one nor the other do we find any restraining power, effective and sufficient to keep a people or an age from the grossest corruptions and sins. Under all these systems, ethical and religious, the tendency of the nations was firom bad to worse. The Deficierncy Remedied.- Something other and better was needed,- some more explicit revelation of the divine will and of human duty, some influence more powerful to restrain men from known sin, was needed, and was given. In the sacred Scriptures we have that which we seek in vain among the philosophies and the mythologies of the world, - that knowledge which neither natural religion nor the unaided reason and nmoril sense of man can furnish. It is not the province of AIoral Philosophy to unfold and state in their order the great tiuthls made known in revelation, much less to present the arguments by which such a revelation is established. It is the business of Theology to do this. It is sufficient to our present purpose to say, that the Bible reveals God and his attributes more perfectly than they could otherwise be known to man; that it fully and explicitly and positively makes known his will, that law which is to us the true rule of duty; that it reveals in all its grandeur and power the doctrine of the future,- a life beyond the narrow confines of the present, in which men shall be rewarded or punished, according to the deeds done and the character formed in the present life; above all, that it reveals to sinful man the way of escape from guilt and ruin, through HIM who is the way, the truth, and the life, 58 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. CHAPTER IV. PROVINCE OF RIGHT. Two Questions.- In further discussing the science of right, two questions present themselves. 1. What is a mnoral action/ or, in other words, what sort of actions are propl)erly so called? 2. In5 what consists the morality of any given act? Where lies the virtue or the guilt of it? These questions comprise a topic which has not been discussed in the preceding chapters, viz., the province of right. We will take them in their order, as now stated. ~ 1.-WHAT IS A MORAL ACTION? Not all Actio)z Moral.- What class of actions are properly called mnoral? Not all human actions. Some actions have no moral quality. I start at the accidental falling of a window, or discharge of a musket. A person unconsciously talks in his sleep, or in delirium, or, it may be, rises and walks about, performs certain actions, takes the property, or perhaps the life of another, or puts an end to his own life. These are not properly moral actions. They are involuntary, as in the instances first mentioned, -or irrational, as in the cases last specified,- and in neither case do we attach praise or blame to the act. It has no moral quality. Morality pertains to what. -Morality, the quality of virtue or guilt, of praise or blame, pertains only to the actions of intelligent and rational beings, and only to the voluntary actions of such beings. By action, I mean to in 59 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. elude, of course, the various forms of mental activity, and not merely the putting forth of physical power. It is not merely when I move my limbs, raise my hand, or bring into use some one of the bodily organs, that I act; when I think, when I cherish an emotion, affection, or desire; when I put forth a volition, even though the external act should for any reason not follow that volition- in all these cases I act. All these are so many forms of mental activity; and when we speak of moral action, it is to the activity of the mind, primarily and chiefly, that we refer. An external bodily act is moral only so far as it involves and proceeds from some activity of the mind. Otherwise it has no more morality, no more desert of praise or blame, than the movement of an axe, or hammer, or any other mere passive instrument. The body is the instrument of the mind. Implies Intelligence. -A moral act is always an intelligent act. The being who performs it must be capable of comprehending himself, and his own activity; must know what he is about; must understand the bearing of what he does; must act with reference to some end, and having in view the means necessary to secure that end. Mere brute instinct differs firom this, lacks this; works blindly; comprehends not itself, nor what it does; works from impulse, not from intelligence. The brute is incapable of moral action. Implies Reason. - A moral act is always a rational act. A mind destitute of reason may still act intelligently, may act with reference to a given end, and adopt the means best fitted to secure that end. The insane man does this, and often displays no little sagacity and wisdom in the accomplishmenrit of his purposes. He knows what he is doing, and why he takes this or that means to accomplish his purpose. He acts intelligently, but not rationally. Hiis 60 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. mnind is disordered in its action. And so far as this is the case, he is not responsible for his actions. They are not properly moral acts. It may be, and often is, extremely difficult to decide in such cases whletlher, and in what degree, the mind really is insane, and therefore irresponsible; under cover of this doubt and difficulty, many a crime doubtless goes unpunished; but where it is evident that reason no longer keeps her throne, by common consent the actions of s'uch a mii-d are regarded as having no moral character. IrTnplies Volition. -A moral act is always, I suppose, a voluntary act. If any act is strictly involuntary, not proceeding firom any choice or intention of the doer, mere accident, or mere instinct, or muscular reqiction, - as the springing when a window falls, or the closing of the eye when a blow is suddenly aimed at it - actions which are not only without intention and volition, but which no pubpose or effort of will could wholly prevent, - such an act, surely, has no moral character. It falls not within the province of right. That only is a moral act which is vol. untary, freely put forth of choice and purpose- which we could have refirained fiom doing, had we chosen. On the same principle, so far as our thoughts and emniotions are strictly involuntary, not within our 6wn control, they cannot properly be classed among our moral acts. It is a principle of the plainest justice, that a man is to be held responsible only for such actions as lie within his power to do or not to do. No law can place me under obligation to perform an act which it is wholly out of my power to perform,-as, e. g., the lifting of a mountain; nor yet to refrain from doing what I cannot possibly, by any effort or volition of mine, avoid doing. To such acts neither virtue nor guiltattaches- neither praise nor blame. Whatever mental activity is of this sort, strictly involuntary and 6 61 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. beyond our control, is to be classed in the same category with involuntary muscular movements or contractions. To a great extent, however, both thought and feeling are moral acts, since indirectly, if not directly, it is in our power to shape and control them. I cannot, indeed, by a direct act of will, call up or prevent any thought or feeling; but still it is in my power to determine the general course andl direction of both. I cannot, perhaps, avoid certain emotions, in view of certain objects presented to the senses or to the thoughts; but I can avoid the perception of those objects; can shut the eye and the ear upon them; can fix the thoughts upon other things, and thus avoid the emotions which they are fitted to awaken. In so far as I fail to exert this control over my own mental activity, in so far I am responsible; in so far the act is of a moral char acter. Implies a Moral Faculty.- If I mistake not, there is still another element involved in all moral action - viz., a capacity for perceiving moral distinctions, a power of distinguishing between right and wrong. This we may call the moral faculty. Where this is entirely wanting, I cannot conceive of praise or blame, virtue or guilt, as properly attaching to the conduct. Such a being is certainly not a proper object of law, nor of reward and punishment. This is the case with the brute, and it is the crowning difference between the brute and man. The former has no conception of right or wrong in conduct- no idea of obligation -no feeling of self-approval, nor yet of regret, and remorse, for anything it has done. The brute has no conscience, and, for that reason, is not a moral being. If the human mind is ever reduced to such a condition, whether in the state of idiocy, or in certain forms of insanity, as no longer to possess the power of recognizing and feeling moral distinc 62 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. dons, its acts, in such a case, could not be called moral acts: they have no moral character. ~ II. - IN WHAT CONSISTS THE MORALITY OF ANY GIVEN ACT. Question stated.- When any act is perceived to have a moral character, whether right or wrong, the question may still arise, In what consists, or where lies, the moral quality - the virtue or the guilt - of that act? Wherein does the virtuous act, for example, differ from any other? This is quite a distinct question from the one discussed in the preceding section, and deserves special considera tion. Does the morality pertain to the external act, the physical movement which performs what the will intends; or does it lie in the volition, the simple act of will which immediately precedes the external act? Or is it in the resolution, previously formed, to put forth such a volition when the proper time shall come? Or in the thought of the mind which lay back of all this, and which led to the resolution, and so to the deed? Or, if not in any of these, then is it to be found in the intention, or design, with which the act is performed? Not in the External Act. -Evidently not in the external, physical act does the morality lie. That, in itself considered, has no moral character. The bodily organism is merely the instrument of the intelligence, which animates and controls its movements; and those movements, in themselves, have no more moral character than the movements of a saw, or any other merely passive instrument. Accordingly, the same external act, as performed by different actors and under different circumstances, may vary exceedingly in its moral character; and that variation 63 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. may run through the whole scale of morality, from the deepest degree of guilt to the highest degree of virtue. Let us suppose a ease - the taking of human life, for example. It is done in malice, or for gain. That is murder. It is done by the executioner, in obedience to law. That is a simple act of justice. It is done to save life. That is self-defence. It is done by accident, without design. -That is no crime. Yet in all these cases the external act may be the same, the instrument the same, the effect produced the same. Evidently the moral quality lies not in the external act. Not in the Executttive Volition.- Nor yet does the morality pertain to those mental states which immediately precede, and give rise to, the external act; since these are, necessarily, the same, whatever the moral character of the act. The volition which immediately precedes and produces the movement of the arm by which a blow is struck, is one and the same thing, whether that blow results in murder, or in the execution of justice, or in accidental homicide, or in self-defence. In any case, it is simply a volition to strike a blow by the movement of the arm. And so, also, of the resolution which precedes the direct volition, or effort of the will. Whatever imparts moral character to the act, taken as a whole, imparts it also to these constituent elements of the act; but in themselves, neither the external movement, nor the direct volition to move, nor the resolution or purpose to put forth such a volition, have any distinctive moral character. There is something else always to be taken into the account before we can determine the moral character of any of those elements which are involved in a moral act. Consists in the Intentions.-That which gives character to the act, and which alone determines its moral quality, is the-intention or design with which the act is performed. 64 PROVINCE OF RIGHT. In the ease supposed, it was the intention of one man to commit murder; he struck the blow for that purpose, with that design; and this intention constitutes his guilt. Hence he would have been really guilty of murder, in the sight of Him who knows the secrets of the heart, even had the blow failed to accomplish its purpose. The intention, the design was- murder. The intention of another man was the simple discharge of his duty as an officer of justice —a right intention, and so a right act. The design of another was to defend himself, or others, fi'om lawless violence; and if we are satisfied that this was really his purpose, and that the act was necessary to that end, or even that he believed it to be so, we justify him at once from the imputation of crime. Still another man intended by the blow merely a certain mechanical effect; but the instrument which he wielded for that purpose, glancing from its intended course, struck down a bystander. The result was accidental. He who struck the fatal blow had no such design, and this being once ascertained, there is no longer the charge of guilt. We act upon this Rule.- In estimating the character of actions, we always proceed upon this principle. We look at the intention, the design of the doer; we seek to know what the person meant; and if we are satisfied that no wrong was. intended, we exculpate him from blame; otherwise we hold him guilty. It is not so much the actual result as the intention that we look at. So, in respect to our own conduct, it is not so much what was actually accomplished, for good or ill, as what was designed and attempted, that forms the standard by which we estimate our own guilt or innocence - our good or ill desert. The good man, sacrificing and toiling much for some worthy end, but all to little purpose, consoles himself by the reflection that his actions are to be weighed, not by their 6* 65 .PROVINCE OF RIGHT. success, but their design; that he deserves well who meant and endeavored well. Where we are satisfied, on the other hand, that an act, however desirable in itself, is prompted by no good intention, we hesitate to assign it the rank of a virtue. A ruler requires the loyalty, love, and obedience of his subjects. That obedience they may render, however, not from loyalty or love, but from fear, or the desire of gain. With such obedience he is not satisfied. It is an obedience rendered, not for the sake of honoring or serving the ruler, but with a purely selfish design. There is no virtue in such obedience. The case is the same with respect to the parent and his children, and with respect to man in his relations to the Supreme Ruler. God looks at the heart, scans the purposes of man; and as is the meaning and intention of the man, so, in his sight, is the man himself. Virtue what.- On the principle now established, we may define morality or virtue to be the doing right, intentionally, and because it is right. That alone is strictly a virtuous act which is done voluntarily - done as right, and because it is believed to be right; in other word(s, which is done from a sense of duty. Whatever neglects, overlooks, or violates this rule, whatever other character it may possess, is not of the nature of true virtue. "That is a virtuous action," says Chalmers, "which a man voluntarily does on the simple ground that he ought to do it." 66 FACULTIES OF THE MIND. CHAPTER V. FACULTIES O)F THE MIND COGNIZANT OF RIGHT. To explain in detail the operations of the several mental faculties, is the province of Psychology. To this it per. tains to treat explicitly of the moral faculty, the power of the mind by which it perceives and recognizes moral truth, and also of the emotions awakened in view of such truth. So intimately, however, are these themes related to the Philosophy of Morals, that it seems necessary to consider them briefly in this connection. For a more full discussion of the nature and power of Conscience, the reader is re ferred to the sections which treat of these topics in my work on Mental Philosophy. Analysis of Conscience. - When any moral act - ou own, or that of another - is presented to our thoughts as an object of distinct consideration, the process through which the mind passes is somewhat peculiar, and will be found, if I mistake not, to comprise several distinct steps or elements, essentially the same in all cases. There is, in the first place, an impression, or perception, more or less clear and decided, that the act in view is a right or a wrong act - whichever it may be - a recognition of it as such. This is an exercise of judgment, an intellectual operation. The proposition, or affirmation of the mind, in view of the case, is "That is right," or "That is not right." This decision is more or less clear and positive, in proportion as the act contemplated is more or less strongly marked in its features and general character. In 67 FACULTIES OF THE MIND some cases we hesitate, and form a doubtful opinion; in others, the decision is instantaneous and positive. No sooner is this decision reached, than there follows another mental state,- the conviction or perception of obligation in respect to the act contemplated. The prop osition now is, "I ought," or "I ought not." This, too, is an intellectual process, a conviction, a judgment; not un accompanied, however, with feeling, which is the case indeed with most of our intellectual operations. That which awakens intellectual activity, awakens also some degree of feeling. Hence, we speak of feeling the truth of a proposition, or the force of an argument; of feeling our obligation to do this and that. A careful analysis, however, will show that the feeling, in this case, is distinct from the intellectual perception; that it succeeds, and is based upon such perception, and derives fiomn it whatever character and strength it possesses. This idea of obligation, it may be further observed, relates to the past, as well as to the future. I ought to have done, or I oughlt not to have done, this or that, - an act, the scene of which lies among the years that are long past, and in lands, it may be, remote. It extends also to the actions of others. We form our opinions, and pass our judgment, on the character and conduct of those about whom we read or hear. These persons ought, or ought not, to have done thus and thus. Further Analysis.- When the obligation to a given course is perceived, there follows yet another state of mind, -the approbation or disapproval of the conduct, according as it conforms to, or violates that obligation. This approving or condemning verdict is also an act of conscience, or the moral faculty - one of its specific and appropriate functions. Like the preceding, it is strictly, in the first instance, an intellectual act, an exercise of judgment, 68 COGNIZANT OF RIGHT. a verdict given in view of the case as presented to the understanding; followed, however, immnediately, in many cases, with the strongest emotion. It is a verdict on which depends much - often, everything that is of value in life. Herein lies the power of an approving or accusing conscience. The proposition now stands, "I have done well" -"I have done ill;" and in that siniple verdict, calmly rendered, but seldom reversed, lies a sustaining or condemning power, greater than that of thrones and armies - a power that can look danger and death in the face, and defy a world in arms- a power that can make the guilty man tremble, though surrounded by all that wealth, and station, and princely dignity can confer. Summary.- These several momenta comprise the essential elements of what is usually termnled conscience, or the moral faculty. As thus analyzed, conscience is simply the intellect perceiving and judging of moral truth, together with a corresponding excitement of the sensibilities, in view of the objects thus contemplated. The term is used, however, to denote not nmerely, or so much, the act itself, the process of mind now a,nalyzed, as the power of thus perceiving and judging. Nor is it a power, a capability merely, which can be exercised or withheld at the pleasure of the possessor. It is more thai that-a constitution of the mind in virtue of which it shta, under ordinary circunmstances, perceive, and feel, and act thus - shall recognize such distinctions and obligations, and shall, in view of the same, pronounce such verdicts. Psychologically viewed, it is not so much a distinct faculty of the mind, coordinate with perception, memory, imagination, etc., as a distinct exercise, or department of action, of the general faculty of judglment, and of the power of feeling, as employed with reference to one particular class 69 FACULTIES OF THE MIND. of truth, viz., moral. The mind is so constituted, that in view of such truth, it shall act as now stated, recognizing the right and the wrong of human conduct, measuring its actions and those of others by this standard, and approving or condemning accordingly. This power we call the moral faculty. Authority of Conscience.- With regard to the authority of this faculty, it is evident that, with the view now given of the nature of conscience, it is impossible to consider it as in any sense an infallible guide. It is a moral judgment, accompanied by a moral feeling, and, like all other judgments and feelings, is liable to err. It is, in this respect, on the same footing with all the other powers of the human mind. Not one of them is infallible. A man may act conscientiously, and still be in the wrong. His judgments are not sure to be right. At the best, he is liable to err;-and the fact that he goes according to the dictates of his conscience, does not free him from this liability. He must, indeed, abide by the decisions of conscience, and govern his conduct accordingly; but he must see to it that those decisions are intelligently formed. He must bow to the authority of conscience; but he must also take heed that his conscience is not a blind guide, but one on whose eye and on whose path falls the clear light of nature and of reason, and the still purer light of God's word. 70 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT. CHAPTER VI. HISTORIC SKETCH OF OPINIONS RESPECTING THE NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT. IT is often of the highest service, in our investigation of truth, to know the opinions which have been held by oth ers, and the results at which other minds have arrived, as regards the matters in question. Especially is this the case with regard to the questions which have occupied us in the preceding chapters. A brief outline of the various opinions which have been held by writers of different periods, both ancient and modern, as to the nature and foundation of right, may give us a clearer view of the matter discussed, and serve to fix in our minds the principles advanced in the preceding chapters. We begin with the philosophy of the ancients. Doctrine of Socrates.- Socrates may be regarded as the first of the ancient philosophers who gave special attention to the nature of virtue. His teachings lay the foundation of scientific ethics; but only the foundation. His doctrine of right is a peculiar one. Virtue is nearly synonymous with knowledge, in the Socratic system. The doing, is consequent upon the knowing, of what is good, and best to be done. Nothing is virtuous in conduct, which is done without discernment. Hence, no man is voluntarily vicious. He does as well as he knows. As to the question what things are right, and what are wrong, the teachings of Socrates do not furnish an explicit answer. He refers us to the laws of the land in which we may happen to live, for the establishment of specific ethi 71 IISTORIC SKETCH. cal rules; and while lihe does not expressly teach that the foundation and groun)d of right is its'ttility, still he has much to say of the utility of virtue. DI)sciples of Socrates.- 1. THE CYNICS. -Virtue, according to the Cynics, consists in a life according to nature; a complete independence of all arbitrary and conventional laws and usages; the absence of, and entire freedom from all wants and all desires; complete superiority to all these things. To such an extent did they carry this doctrine, as to render both themselves and their philosophy objf.cts of general aversion and contempt. 2. THE CYRENAICS. - With the Cyrenaics, on the contrary, pleasure is the chief good, and virtue is to be coinmnended and pursued, as cond(ucing to this result- the means to this end. Socrates had given prominence in his teachings to the happiness which virtue affords. Aristippus, looking solely at this, makes happiness the chief end of man, and recommends moderation, self-control, self-Lculture, as the most direct means to the attainment of this end. -Doctrine of Plato. -Plato holds fast the Socratic notion of virtue as science - a thing to be learned. In respect to the highest good, he takes a middle ground, between the conflicting schools just mentioned - neither admitting, with the Cyrenaics, that pleasure is the chief good of life, nor, with the Cynics, rejecting it entirely, as unworthy of regard. The idea of the good and the evil, according to Plato, is not (ldei ved immediately from sense, as are our perceptions of external objects, but constitutes, along with kindredl ideacs, as of the beautiful, etc., a distinct and peculiar I)rovxinee of knowle(lge, an apriori faculty of the mind. As back of the senses, and their perceptions, there lies a power that can compare and contrast these perceptions 72 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT. one with another, - a power of the soul superior to sense, and independent of it, -so, in like manner, thle soul, by its own inherent activity, conceives and distinguishes the beautiful and the odious, the good and the evil. This faic ilty is what, in the different schools of modern philosophy, passes under the name of original, or intuitive conception, original suggestion, the reason, etc. In one point, the ethical philosophy of Plato seems to us defective. The conception of' chty - the right, as such, in distinction fiom thle merely good - is nowhere distinctly and prominently broughtt out, but lies quite in the background. This is a defect, however, which pertains equally to the Socratic ethics. Doctri)e of Aristotle.- The great mistake which, from Socrates onward, has prevailed respecting the nature of virtue, that it is one and the same with knowledge, is, in the philosophy of Aristotle, for the first time, distinctly set right. Virtue is with him not so much an intellectual element and process, as a moral one; it is not a knowing, but a doing. The doing, according to Socrates and Plato, is consequent upon the knowing; if a man knows the good he will do it. With Aristotle, on the contrary, the knowing is consequent upon the doing; the more a man does, and seeks to do the right, the better he will know the right. To make virtue a merely intellectual affair, overlooks, according to Aristotle, an essential element of our nature, -i. e., the moral element, the natural instinct of the soul, which demands and strives for the good, and which approves and is satisfied with that only which is right in human conduct and endeavor. Virtue is not so much, then, a thing to be learned, as a thing to be done or practised, in the following out this natural craving and instinct of the soul. It is by the practice of virtue that we become virtuous. Virtue is the habit of doing right. Nature lays 79 7 73 HISTORIC SKETCH. the foundation in so constituting the mind that it craves and approves the good; reason and intelligence build on this foundation; habit confirms and binds together the whole. Our good and evil dispositions are originally in our own power; but when once formed, by habit, to virtue or to vice, they are no longer under control. The highest good, the chief end and motive of human endeavor, Aristotle concedes to be happiness in some form. But, then, what is happiness? Not the gratification of the senses, stlirely; for, in this resrpe,(t, llill is ill no way slil)erior to the brute. The true li:l,l)illess foir maniii is the higliest activity of his intelligent nitte, thle iunrestr.lined enei'(y of well-being and of well-doiiig, which satisfies -ill the conditions of his mental and moral nature. It is the perfect activity of a perfect life. In practical matters, virtue lies in pursuing the right mean between opposite extremes. Thus justice is the moral mean between doing wrong and suffering Wrong. This mean varies with circumstances and individuals. -Doctrine of the Stoics.- The Stoics make much account of law and order in the universe. Everything must conform to the order of nature. The highest law of human action, the highest end of life, is to shape our conduct according to the universal law of nature, and live in harmony therewith. Live according to thy rational nature, is the practical maxim, or rule of life, of the Stoics. But pleasure is not a good - has no moral worth - is to be disregarded and despised. It is no end of nature, but something accidental. It is not an activity, but a passive state of the soul, a limitation of that activity which alone the true blessedness. External good of every kind is morally indifferent; virtue alone is real good. Actions, of course, are to be regarded as good or evil, not according as they result in advantage or disadvantage to the doei; 74 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT. not according to their tendencies and consequences, but in themselves. A certain course of conduct is to be approved and pursued' not because it conduces to health and happiness, but for its own sake. Health, wealth, happiness, are indifferent and worthless- to be preferred, perhaps, to sickness, poverty, and the like, but not to be considered as good in themselves. The good man is he who governs himself according to reason; the bad man is he in whom reason is not awakened, but instinct has the mastery. And, inasmuch as every man is under the dominion of one or the other, the good man is wholly good, and the bad man wholly bad. Nor are there any degrees of virtue,- all good acts are equally good, and all bad acts equally bad. The system of the Stoics was, it must be confessed, rigorous and severe. As compared with the ethical philosophy of Aristotle, it strikes one as ideal, and impracticable. .)octrine of the Epicureans.- Quite the reverse of this was the ethical system of the Epicurean school. In common with most of the preceding schools, they make the highest good consist in happiness; but then, the chief element of happiness is pleasure, -so that this may be regarded as the highest good. By pleasure, however, they do not mean merely the gratification of the present moment, but that which will ensure the happiness of the whole life. Even pain, if it will lead to a greater pleasure, is to be welcomed. The pleasures of the soul, accordin,gly, are of greater account than those of the body merely, since the former are lasting, and the latter momentary. And, what is more, pleasure is inseparable from a virtuous life. There can be no true and lasting happiness without virtue. As thus defined, the system of the Epicureans is equally removed from that of the Cyrenaics on the one 75 HISTORIC SKETCH. hand, who regard pleasure as the chief good, but mean thereby chiefly the pleasures of sense, and from that of the Cynics and the Stoics on the other, who regard all pleasure as a thing to be despised. .Ethical Philosophy of the 2oderns.- Thus falr our attention has been directed to the ethical doctrines of the ancients. Turning now to more recent times, we shall find the same great questions arising for discussion, which we have found agitating and dividing the ancient schools, - e. g., the nature of virtue, and the ground of right - whether right and wrong are independent principles, or whether they are to be estimated according to the results, the advantages and disadvantages to which they lead. In tracing these doctrines, I can refer only to the views of the more prominent authors and schools of philosophy. Early English MVoralists. - Since the prevalence of Christianity, and the purer views of morality which it could not fail to introduce, the idea of right as an independent principle of action -the idea of duty, in distinction from the merely good-has been brought more prominently to view in the systems of morality. The same is true, also,.. of the principle of conscience. The nature and authority of conscience have been mnuch in dispute; but by general agreement it has been regarded as the foundation of moral science. A great part, in fact, of the ethics of the seventeenth century consists of the discussion of cases of conscience. The Reformation, doubtless, led the way to this, by teaching that the conscience cannot be safely entrusted to the keeping of the church and the clergy, or subject to any human authority; but that every man is individually responsible for his own belief, and his own actions. As early ns the twelfth century, indeed, we find Abelard teaching that the fundamental rule of duty is the divine will, as revealed in conscience and in Scripture. 76 NATUIRE AND GROUND OF RIGIIT. The early English moralists take essentially the same ground. Jeremy Taylor, in his liule of' Co)scieitce, makes the authority of conscience the basis of his system of morals, and quotes with approbation the saying of St. Bernard: " Conscience is the brightness of the eternal light, the spotless mirror of the divine majesty, and the image of the goodness of God." The doctrine of Taylor is, that as God is present, governing the world by his providence, so he is present in our hearts by his laws, governing us by conscience, which is his substitute, or representative. This gives to conscience not merely a place as the foundation of morals, but clothes it, in a sense, with a divine commission and authority. This view of conscience as, conjointly with Scripture, the ground and acknowledged basis of morality, seems to have been very generally entertained by the leading minds of the seventeenth century in England. Theory of robbes. - This view was not without antagonism. A powerful opponent arose, at once subtle and bold, in the person of Thomas Hobbes, the philosopher of Malmesbury, who held that Law, or the State, is the origin of all rights and duties. In the state of nature, every man is at war with every man, and in such a state there are no rights or duties, - " The notions of Right and Wrong, Justice and Injustice, have there no place." From this state of nature man emerges into society, and the civil body, or the State, is, as a matter of self-defence, coInstructed. This it is which gives law, - and thus arises duty and the nature of right. The doctrine "thlat every private man is judge of good and evil actions," he pronounces a poisonous and seditious doctrine, dangerous to the State; "whereas it is manifest that the measure of good and evil actions is the Givil Law." To him who lives in civil society "the Law is the public Conscience by which 7* 77 Ir HISTORIC SKETCH. he hath already undertaken to be guided." This anni hilates at a blow iman's moral nature, and resolves imorality and duty into the power of the civil arm. Alight makes right. These principles were received with very little favor, and called forth many replies. As Whewell very justly remarks, however, these tenets, so startling and offensive, were very far fi'om being new. "The whole of this controversy had agitated the schools of philosophy many ages earlier." It was in substance the same question which comes up for discussion so fi'equently in the dialogues of Plato and of Cicero, whether right and wrong are independent qualities of actions, or whether they are merely terms to denote the advantages or disadvantages that result from certain courses of behavior. This question, discussed, as we have seen, by Cynic and Cyrenaic, by Stoic and Epicurean, runs through the whole history of morals. Ctcuworth. One of the principal opponents of this scheme of Hlobbes \vas Ralph Cudworth, who, in his Treatise concernzing Eternal and 1imuttable [orality, takes the ground that our perception of right and wrong is an ultimate fact in our nature, that these ideas are simple and incapable of analysis, and that the mind is able to form them antecedently to positive institutions. He shows that the doctrines of Hobbes were but the revived dogmas anId sophistries of earlier schools - essentially the very (logmas against which Plato argued in condemning the doctrine of Protagoras, that all our knowledge is derived fiom sense. With Plato, he maintains that some of our ideas proceed not from sensible objects, but from tho mind's own activity; among these the idea of right and wrong; and that these ideas, thoughl existing only in the mind, are not creations of the mind, but realities eternal and immutable. 78 NATURE ANDt) GROUND OF RGIGIT. Doctrine of Locke. - The doctrines of Locke have been the occasion of much dispute. It is by no means easy to assign to this distinguished man his true position in philosophy and morals. It seems clear, however, that whatever may have been his own personal views and feel ilgs, the tendency of his philosophy was quite in the opposite direction to the system of Cudworth and the independent moralists. Deriving all our simple ideas from sensation and reflection, or the observation of things without, and of our own mental operations, he seems to leave no place, according to this account of the matter, for the ideas of right and wrong. These, consequently, are not simple and original ideas, but derived - the result of education. Accordingly, moral good and evil are not, in this philosophy, independent principles. "Good or evil are nothing but pleasure or pain, or that which occasions or procures pleasure or pain to us. Moral good and evil, thus, is only the conformity or disagreement of our voluntary actions to some law whereby good or evil is drawn on us by the will and power of the law-maker; which good and evil, pleasure or pain, attending our observance or breach of the law, by the decree of the law-maker, is that we call reward and punishment."- (Book II., ch. 28, ~ 5.) This manifestly places Locke in the lower school of moralists, in distinction from the higher ground of Plato and Cudworth. The morality of his system is that of consequences rather than of eternal and immutable distinctions. The tendency of his philosophy, it may be remarked, was much further and stronger in this direction than he himself was probably aware. Like most great minds, he seems to have held views inconsistent with his own system. His philosophy led to results which he would by no means have adopted. 79 HISTORIC SKETCH. (,Ictrke and Price.- In opposition to the views otf Locke, and in accordance with the system of Cudw(ortli, Dir. Samuel Clarke maintins the eternal nature aid indce)endent character of moral distinctions. These eternal differences and relations of thlings determine the essential fitness and reasonableness of certain courses of conduct, and the unfitness and unreasonableness of the opposite courses. With reference to this fitness, the will of God always chooses; and creatures ought also to choose with reference to the same. Duty, obligation result firom this source, independent even of the divine will, and of all prospect of reward or gain. -Dr. Price, also, in opposition to Locke, ascribes the originl of our ideas of right and wrong to the understa-t(ing, or the reason, which terms are used to denote the general faculty of intelligence, and which is affirmed to be "itself a source of new ideas." We reach these ideas by means of an intuitive perception, or intuitive judgment. They express qualities of actions, and not mere impressions and sensations, pleasurable or painful, of our own minds; realities, eternal and immutable. Shagtesbury, tfftcheson, tIIme.- With the writers now named, there comes into use a new mode of expressing and accounting for our moral ideas and perceptions. It was now asserted that there is a peculiar faculty of the mind whose office it is to perceive these distinctions, and to this ficulty the name of thae moral sense was given. Slaftesbttry, himself an advocate of the independent and original nature of moral distinctions, introduced this use of terms. He speaks of the sense of right and of wrong, and calls it the moral sense. He likens it to the natural sense of the sublime and the beautiful. Hutcheson gives greater prominence to this view, and makes it the basis of his system. We have a natural sense or instinct for the right, as 80 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGIll1'. we have for the beauty of color or sound -as we have in stincts and affections for other specific objects. Iftmne, adopting this view, and carrying it to its extreme results, makes virtue and vice, as well as beauty and deformity, matters of mere taste or sentiment. Right and wrong do not denote any independent quality in the object thus designated, but only an effect or sensation produced in our own minds; just as sweet and bitter, the pleasant and the painful, are merely our own sensations, and not properly qualities of objects. Referring to the doctrine - supposed to be fullly proved in modern times -" that tastes and colors, and all other sensible qualities, lie not in the bodies, but merely in the senses," he adds: "The case is the same with beauty and deformity, virtue and vice." - (Essays, Part I. Essay XVIII.) Thus we are brought back again, in the revolving cycle of opinion, to the old doctrine of Protagoras, that nothing is true or false, any more than sweet or souri, in itself, but only with reference to the perceiving mind. Whatever anything seems to be, to any mind, that, and that only, it is. Butler. —The writings of Butler have justly placed him in the front rank of English moralists. He asserts, more clearly, perhaps, than any preceding writer had done, the existence of a moral faculty, while he nowhere closely or sharply analyzes the precise nature of this faculty. His principles are those of the independent school of moralists, that right and wrong are something in themselves, and not merely in their consequences. Still, these prinnciples are nowhere very distinctly announced or systematically defended. lie seems purposely to have avoided technical or philosophical terms, and to have expressed himself in contlnon and popular language, in treating of this class of subjects, -a language not always sufficiently definite for philosophical purposes, He is classed among 81 HISTORIC SKETCH. the unsystematic moralists by Whewell. Notwithstanding some vagueness of expression, however, Butler clearly maintains the independent nature of moral distinctions. There is a difference, he holds, among our faculties, not of degree, merely, but of kind,- some are superior to others, of higher authority; and the faculty to which belongs an authority and supremacy over all the rest is conscience. Warburton.- Dissatisfied with the doctrines of Cudworth, Clarke, Price, and Butler, on the one hand, as placing the ground of morals in the eternal fitness of things, and also with the moral sense of Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and their disciples, as reducing morality to a mere sentiment or taste, a class of moralists arose who maintained that the will of God is the basis of morality and source of obligation. We need look no further than this. To know that the divine will requires a given thing, is of itself sufficient to put us under obl)lig:ition to do that thing. There is no morality without law, no other b'sis of obligation than the divine command. Suchll was the view of Warburton. He lays it down as an axiom that "Obligation necessarily implies an obliger." The action is thus regarded not as right or wrong in itself, and obligatory because right, but only as comma tced. This view became, for a time, the prevalent mode of thought, and gave character to the moral teachling, especially of the university of Cambridge. It is the view maintained essentially by Law, Professor of Moral Philosophy in the university, and still more fully by Waterland, laster of Magdalen College. Paley and his followers.- This view received still filir ther development and modification at the hands of a writer more vigorous and popular in his style, and far more widely known, than either of those just mentioned. I refer to the celebrated Dr. Paley. To resolve all obligation into the mere command of God, might seem somewhat 82 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHIT. arbitrary. Is there not a reason why God commands what he does? Seeks he not always the happiness of his creatures? Is not this, then, the real and ultimate criterion of duty? Paley was not the first to combine these two principles. MIr. Gay, Fellow of Sidney College, Cambridge, author of the dissertation on the Nature of Virtue prefixed to King's Origin of Evil, had already advanced this view. "Thus the will of God is the criterion of virtue, and the happiness of mankind the criterion of the will of God; and therefore the happiness of mankind may be said to be the criterion of virtue but once removed." Gay, accordingly, defines virtue to be "conformity to a rule of life, directing the actions of all rational creatures with respect to each other's happiness; to which conformity every one, in all cases, is obliged." The same doctrine is also advanced by Tucker, author of the "Light of Nature Pursued," a work frequently referred to by Paley. This author regards the highest good "to be none other than pleasure, or satisfaction;" and speaks of it as absurd to talk of things as being right i) themselves, without regard to consequences, inasmuch as "things are rendered right by their tendency to some end." We are now fairly and fully again upon the morality of consequences, of utility, and expediency, - no new doctrine, as we have seen, in the history of morals. It is evident, likewise, that Paley is by no means original in advancing this system at the time when he wrote. The writings of Law, and especially of Gay, and Tucker, and Rutherforth, had fuilly prepared the way for it. Paley defines virtue to be "the doing good to mankind, in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of everlasting happiness." It has been firequently and very justly objected to this scheme, that it recognizes only one class of duties- those to mankind; and also that it seems to mnake it essential to a virtuous act that it should be done 83 HISTORIC SKETCH. for the sake of future reward. In carrying out this philos. ophy, Paley loses sight of the idea of right, and of duty as based on the right, and resolves all obligation into mere command, without reference to the question wxhat we ought to do. In this he follows Warburton and the Cambridge moralists; but goes further than they had done, inasmuch as he makes moral obligation the result, not from the will of God alone, but from any command or will of another which we cannot well resist. The sum and substance of duty is to act with regard to the highest expediency. Priestley and Bentham. -The philosophy thus introduced anew to public notice, became immensely popular. It was at once adopted in the university of Cambridge, where, as we have seen, the same doctrine had for sometime previously been taught. Among those who, about this period, take substantially the same ground, must be reckoned two distinguished writers on Political Science, - Priestley and Bentham,- neither of whom, however, is to be regarded as properly a follower of Paley. Indeed, Priestley had, in his Essay on Government, published some seventeen years before the appearance of Paley's works, distinctly announced " the greatest happiness of t/e greatest number" as the true and only proper object of government. Bentham founds his system of political morality expressly on this principle -utility; by which he means, as above, the greatest happiness of the greatest number. There is no essential difference between this doctrine and that of Paley. Stewart. -In opposition to these views, Dugald Stewart, in his Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers, takes decidedly the ground of the earlier English moralists, and holds moral distinctions to be eternal and immutable. The words right and wrong express qualities of actions, and not consequences merely. When we say, of an act of 84 NATURE AND GROUND OF RIGHT. justice, that it is right, we do not mean, with Shaftesbury and Hutcheson and Hume, simply that it excites pleasure in the mind, as a particular color pleases the eye; nor, with Hobbes, that society and the strong arm of the state require it; nor, with Warburton and the Cambridge men, that the will of God makes it imperative, and that is the end of the matter; nor yet, with the school of Paley and Bentham, that it is expedient, useful, for the highest happiiess of all; but, on the contrary, to say that such a thing is right, is to assert that respecting it which is quite independent of our constitution; as much so " as the equality of the three angles of a triangle and two right anigles."- "For my own part," he says, "I can as easily conceive a rational being so formed as to believe the three angles of a triangle to be equal to ole right angle, as to believe that, if he had it in his power, it would be right to sacrifice the happiness of other men to the gratification of his own animal appetites." Hall.- There were not wanting among the theological and popular writers of England, many to raise their voice against the dangerous tenets of the school of Paley. Robert Hall, among the more modern writers, thus indignantly rebukes this false philosophy: "How is it, that on a subject on which men have thought deeply, from the moment they began to think, and where, consequently, whatever is entirely and fundamentally new must be fun damentally false -how is it, that in contempt of the experience of past ages, and of all precedents, human and divine, we have ventured into a perilous path, which no eye has explored, no foot has trod; and have undertaken, after the lapse of six thousand years, to manufacture a morality of our own - to decide by a cold calculation of interest, by a ledger-book of profit and loss, the preferenco 8 85 HISTORIC SKETCH. of truth to falsehood, of piety to blasphemy, and of hu. manity and justice to treachery and blood?" Americat Moralists.- In the preceding sketch, I have confined myself thus far to the opinions of English writers. Of the French and German philosophers, in so far as they have discussed the particular topics now before us, the limits of the present chapter do not allow me to speak. In our own country, the two great systems- that of independent morality, and the morality of consequences - have each had their adherents. Edwards, the distinguished theologian, in his dissertation on the Nature of Virtue, regards virtue as "the beauty of those qualities and acts of the mind that are of a moral nature," and defines it as consisting essentially in "benevolence to -Being in general," and more particularly in love to God, as the greatest and best of beings. This benevolence he regards as a higher principle than that moral sense, or conscience, that is natural to mankind. D)-. Waylan(l. - Dr. Wayland regards the ultimate rule, the basis of morals, as consisting in, and arising out of, the essential relations of things; as, e. g., the relation of parent and child, of state and citizen, of creator and creature. These relations once known, certain obligations and duties also become manifest. -Dr. Hickok.- According to this eminent moralist and philosopher, the highest good, the ultimate rule and test of action, the basis of moral obligation, is worthiness of spiritual approbation, conformity to the spirit's own intrinsic excellency. This ultimate right is simple, immutable, and universal. 86 DIVISION SECOND. PRACTICAL ETHICS IL PRACTICAL ETHICS. PRELIMINARY ANALYSIS AND CLASSIFICATION. OUR attention has hitherto been directed to those principles which lie at the foundation of ethical scienceprinciples, a correct understanding of which is of the highest importance, if not indeed indispensable to our progress, as we enter upon the second of the two great departments into which moral science was divided at the outset. Before proceeding to the consideration of the several duties of which this part of our science is to treat, it seems necessary to fix upon some convenient classification of these duties; to this end, a general survey of the field we are about to investigate, and some analysis of the several branches of duty, become desirable. General -)ivisioi. - As we cast our eye over the various lines of conduct which constitute the practical duties of life, a general division strikes us at once. Some of these duties seem to have more direct reference to ourselves, others to our fellow-men, others still to our Maker. These would seem to be the natural divisions into which this department of the science falls. And yet, such is the nature of duty, that a wrong done 8* PRELIM3INARY ANALYSIS. to one's self, is also a wrong done to society and to God; and so of all the other departments of duty. It is impossible to neglect or violate a duty to society, or to God,, without injury to self,-so closely interlinked is the whole circle of duties, and of interests, each with the other. Only in a general sense, then, and merely for the sake of convenience, can any such division be made as that now proposed. In like manner, we may regard the bodily organism as composed of different members, or parts, - the head-the trunk-the limbs,-while at the same time the system of bones, of veins, of nerves, pervades the whole; and to injure one of the members, or parts, is to injure the whole system. Further Analysis. -Adopting the general division already indicated, we have, I. The duties which relate more directly to SELF. Of these the principal are, 1. The duty of Self-support. 2. Of Self-defence. 3. Of Self-control. 4. Of Self-culture. II. The duties which relate more directly to OUR FELLOW-MEN. Of these, some are general, relating to man as such, or to society at large. Of this class are the duties respecting Life, Liberty, Property, Reputation, Veracity. Others, again, arise from the particular institutions of so. ciety, and the relations that thus spring up between the different portions of the community, as thus united. Of this class are the duties arising from the Family Relation, as those of Husband and Wife, Parent and Child; and also the duties pertaining to the State, as those of the Citizen or Subject, of the Government, and of States among themselves. III. The duties which more directly relate to THE SuPREMmE BEING. Of these, the principal are the duty of Reverence, of Love, of Obedience, of Worship. 90 PRELIMINARY ANALYSIS. Summary of Classes. - Omitting now the more general divisions, the following principal classes or departments ot duty present themselves for investigation, in their order: I. DUTIES TO SELF. II. DUTIES TO SOCIETY. III. DUTIES TO THE FAMILY. IV. DUTIES TO THE STATE. V. DUTIES TO GOD. These will constitute the several parts of the second division of our science, i. e., of Practical Ethics. 91 PART I. DUTIES TO SELF. IT is necessary, as we proceed, to bear in mind the renlarks already made, that no duty is to be regarded as exclusively a duty to ourselves, nor yet to society, nor to the state. The duties which we owe to ourselves are also, in a sense, duties which we owe to the fimily, to society, to the state, and to our Maker. These all receive injury by any neglect or injury of ourselves; and these all have an interest, accordingly, in the faithful observance of the duties due to self At the same time, there are certain duties which relate more specifically and directly to ourselves. Of these the chief are, Self-support, Selfdefence, Self-control, and Self-cutlture. These will be considered in successive chapters. CHAPTER I. SELF-SUPPORT. General Statement. -There are certain things which every one must do for himself, which others either cannot, or, under ordinary circumstances, will not do for him. Among these is the duty of providing for his own physical wants the duty of self-support. Every one owes it to I SELF-SUPPORT. himself to make such provision for his own wants as not to be dependent on the charity of others. Nature intends this, and makes provision for it by conferring upon us those powers andl faculties which are requisite to the various pursuits of industry, and by attaching to honest labor the reward of success, to idleness the penalty of inevitable suffering and want. These are the laws and conditions of our being, established by the Creator, fixed and immutable. He that will not work, neither shall he eat, is the universal law of the race. Labor is requisite in order to the production of the fruits of the earth. The food that sustains us, the fabrics that clothe us, the dwellings that shelter us from the inclemency of the seasons,- whatever contributes to the comfort and supplies the varied and innumerable wants of man,- is the product of labor. Now, this labor, that is universally requisite to supply the wants and gratify the desires of men, is something which every one is bound to perform for himself. No one has a right to require another to labor for him unrequited. I may exchange labor for labor, -I may give money, which is simply the representative of labor already performed, for the labor of others which I wish to procure. Lacking this, I must earn my bread by nmy own toil. I have no right to compel another to labor for me without reward. Nor has another any right to require this of me. Excel>tions to tle Rule. - The only exceptions, I suppose, to this law of self-support, are those cases in which there is a real inability to labor. When, in consequence of sickness, casualty, or constitutional deformity, there is lacking, either wholly or in part, the power to provide for one's own subsistence, to that extent is the person thus incapacitated ficed fiom the duty of self-support, on the obvious principle that it is unjust to require of any man 93 SELF-SUPPORT. what he cannot possibly performt. Hence the duty of others who are able to labor, or who possess ill abundance the means of life, to provide for the necessary wants of the sick and suffering; but not to support in idleness those who are able to labor. Conditions essential to Self-support.- In order to make suitable provision for one's personal wants, certain conditions are absolutely essential. Industry is necessary - the diligent, faithful pursuit of some honest calling; but not industry alone. To acquire is merely one part of the business. If we expend our acquisitions as fast as we make them, there is no provision for the future. Frugality is necessary, as well as industry. No man has a moral right to expend all that he earns, if by so doing he leaves himself, or those dependent on him, without adequate provision for future support. Industry and frugality become virtues when directed to this end; and the want of them becomes a sin against God and man. It is the duty of every man, not absolutely incapable of the thing, to take care that neither himself nor those dependent on him shall become a tax upon the industry and toil of others. Hence the duty both of industry and frugality on his part. It was a wise remark of an ancient Greek philosopher, that wealth consists not so much in great possessions as in small wants. It is not the man that acquires the least who is the poorest, nor is he the richest and most prosperous who gains the most. 94 SELF-DEFENCE. CHAPTER II. SELF-DEFENCE. Reasonable. - The same rule that makes it a duty to provide for the further subsistence of the body, in order to the preservation of life, justifies and requires its defence firom lawless aggression and violence, for the same end. If it is duty to preserve life by supplying the bodily wants, it is a duty to preserve it by guarding against needless injury and destruction. If it is incumbent on us to take precautions against disease and accident, it is equally our duty to ward off the attacks of sudden violence, whether of man or beast; and if, in order to this, a resort to extreme measures becomes necessary, then we are justified in resorting to such measures. The reasonableness of this view will appear, if we reflect that every man is by the constitution of nature, in an important sense, his own guardian. He is to look after his own interests, and attend to his own wants. No one else can do this for him. His own life and safety are of vastly more consequence to him than they are to any one else. If he is too negligent, or indolent, or cowardly, to protect his own life and person against lawless aggression, he is false to himself. Hence, it is the instinct of nature, as well as the dictate of reason, to defend ourselves when in danger. It has been called, not improperly, Nature's first law. It is a constitutional impulse, and he who implanted it in the human mind had a design to be accomplished by it. In yielding to this impulse, within due bounds, we are simply carrying out this design. 95 SELF —DEFENCE. Dtue not to Otrselves alonie.-Nor is this a matter merely allowable —a thing to be justified, merely. It rises to the rank of a duty, and that not to ourselves only. It is not a matter in which we only are concerned. Others have an interest in it. Our lives are of value to many beside our selves. If we fall under the blows of the assassin, we leave others, unprotected and helpless, it may be, depend ent on the charities of the world, to struggle with mis fortune and want. This calamity we have no right to entail upon them. We owe it, also, to many who are not directly depend ent on us. Were it understood that, whether from Jack of right or lack of courage, men would not defend themselves when attacked, acts of violence would be much more numerous than they are. Every instance of resolute self-defence acts as a preventive of similar crime. The safety of the entire community is in a measure entrusted, in such cases, to our keeping. Objection.- But do not the Scriptures forbid self-defence? Did not Christ command us, when smitten on one cheek, to turn the other also? I reply, it was not the intention of our Saviour, in those words, to forbid self-defence in cases of real danger, but only the exercise of a revengeful and quarrelsome spirit. Better even to suffer a repetition of the wrong and abuse, than on slight and needless grounds to engage in controversy. That Christ did not mean to forbid self-defence in cases of serious danger, is evident from his permitting his disciples to armn themselves, on at least one occasion. " He that hath no sword, let him sell his garment and buy one." - "And they said, Lord, behold here are two swords." - "And he said unto them, it is enollgl]." One of these swords was actually used in defence of his Master, by one of the disciples, but a short time after these words were spoken. Now, al 96 though the purpose of Christ required that he should be given up at this time to his enemies, and therefore defence w.as not necessary, and so not allowed, still, our Saviour would not have spoken in this manner, much less have permitted his disciples actually to arm themselves, and even to draw and use the sword in the instance referred to, had he regarded all self-defence in such cases as sinfuil, and therefore to be condemned. Fturther Objectio)ns. But it may be said, why not leave the defence of person and property to the law, which is the properly constituted gua'dian of the rights of the community? I reply, in all cases where a resort to the law is possible, this should be done. We are entitled, as citizens, to the protection of the civil arm; and where the case admits of appeal to that protection, it is undoubtedly the proper mode of defence. But in many cases, such an appeal is out of the question. When attacked by the midnight robber and assassin, the protection of my life or property is, by the very circumstances of the case, committed to my own hands. I must resolutely and instantly defend, or tamely surrender them. Now, when it comes to this, as it often does, which of the two shall die,- the assailer or the assailed, - no reason can be shown why I should prefer the life of the aggressor to my own. He deserves to die. The very act of violence which he is perpetrating forfeits his claim to life. I have the right to live, and to defend myself that I may live. Limitations of the R?ule.- Within what limits, it may be asked, and on what occasions, is the resort to extreme measures justifiable in self-defence? The case already supposed sLuggests, I think, the true limit. I am author ized to take the matter of protecting my person and property into my own hands only when there is no other appartcut and probable mode of defence; and I am at liberty to 9 SELF-DEFENCE. 97 SELF-DEFENCE. resort to extreme measures in the case only when milder measures will not answer the purpose. If a simple w'.iiining, or the mnere presentation of a weapon, is sufficient to deter the aggressor from his purpose, I ami not justified in doing more, since self-defence in that case does not require it. But if I can preserve my own life only by taking his, or if I have reason to believe that this is the only alternative, the measure is justifiable. It is to be observed, moreover, that it is only fiom lawless vio,ence that life is to be preserved at tlhe expense of life. Suppl-)ose, when attacke(l, I act upon the principle of self-defence. The assailant becomes lhimself assaile(l, and it may be that his life, in turn, is in d.nge,Ie. Is it for him now to proceed upon the principle above stated, and preserve his own life by taking mine? Would he be justified in so doing? Manifestly not. The violence from which I defend myself is lawuless; that fiom which he defends himself is lawftl. He had no right to put my life in danger; I have the right, in self-defence, to endanger his. On the same principle, the prisoner under sentence of law, or under arrest, is not at liberty to set himself free by an attack upon his keeper. The right of self-defence does not belong to him under those circumstances. -Further Limitationt. —It niay admit of serious question, whether, for the defence of property aloe, where life is not also at stake, it is right to take human life. A robber assails me on the highway. Ile demands my property merely, and promises that my life,and person shall be un harmed, in case I surrender my purse. Hle has no right to make that demand, much less a right to threaten my life, in case of refusal. I can protect my property only by taking the life of the aggressor. Have I a right to do so? In the eye of the law, I should be guilty of no crime, in the case now supposed, were I to do this. But have I a 98 SELF-DEFENCE. moral right? Where my life is in peril, and can be pre served only by the death of my assailant, I am at liberty to defend myself to the last extremity, since my life is, (t least, of equal value with his. But is it certain that my property is of equal value with the life of the assailant? This is not so clear. There may be cases in which tile protection of property may be justifiable, even at the expense of life. But, where any doubt remains, it were certainly better to part with any amount of property, rather than to incur the guilt of unlawfully shedding human blood. -Defence of the Rights of Others.- I would by no means be understood as limiting the right of defence to those cases in which our own life, person, or property is in danger. The same principle extends to the rights of others. The lives, the safety, the property of others, may be committed to our care, and dependent on us; in that case, the same reasons that render the defence of our own lives or property justifiable, require us to defend tlcirs. Every man owes it both to himself and to his family, to defend from danger those who look to him as their natural guardian and protector. A Questionable Case.- It may sometimes happen, in other cases besides those of lawless aggression, that our own lives, or property, can be protected only at the expense of the life and property of another. My neighbor's house and my own are both in danger of destruction, by fire, at one and the same moment. There are means of preserving one of them, but not both. Which shall it be? Does duty to mnyself require me to protect my own property at the expense of his? A plank, floating on the water, comes within my reach as I am struggling for life. It is sufficient to bear up one alone. At my side is another person, also struggling for life. Does the law of self-pre- *i ~ * ~ 99 SELF-CONTROL. tection apply in such a case? It is difficult to lay down any rule that shall apply to all such cases. They must be determined according to circumstances. As a general' principle, it is better to suffer harm ourselves, than to protect ourselves at the risk of injustice to others; better always to suffer wrong, than to do wrong; and where there is danger of wronging another, in the act of protecting self, it would be the impulse of a true and generous heart to forego the claims of self-protection. There can be no doubt on which side we shall be most liable, ini such cases, to err. The dangelr is, that selfishness will prevail over a due consideration of the rights of others, and that the instinct of self-preservation will prove stronger than all our scruples. CIHAPTER III. SELF-CONTROL. PROMINENT among the duties which we owe to our selves, is that of self-control. This relates to the govern ment of the temper, and of all those appetites, propensi ties, and passions, which, while having their foundation in the constitution of our nature, require to be kept under restraint, subject to the dictates of reason and discretion. As relates to the Temper. - Every man owes it to him self to maintain perfect control over his own temper. I refer more particularly to those feelings of indignation and resentment wMhich naturally arise in view of injury received, and which is properly called anger. These feelings require to be held in check with a firm and steady hand. Unre strained, they trample on all that is sacred, and subject 'rdason, judgment, principle, the man himself, to their :-1-. 100 SELF-CONTROL. petty tyranny. They destroy character and influence, and shorten life itself. The man who has no control over himself ill this matter,l; whose anger breaks forth, lawless and ungovernable, on every provocation, -is wholly at the mercy of events. He is not his own master. He is like one afflicted with the St. Vitus' dance, who has no control over his own movements, but must go when the fit takes him, wherever he may be. Nay, worse; it is in the power of his enemies to bring the fit of anger upon him, and make themselves merry at his expense. These feelings are capable of control. By due care and self-discipline, they may be broulght into subjection to reason and the will. But to do this, requires effort, resolution, vigilance. It is the work of time. There is, however, no nobler conquest for any man to make than the conquest of himself; none, perhaps, more difficult; must I add, none more seldom made. It is easier to subdue kingdoms, and lead armies captive, than to subdue and lead captive one's own rebellious passions. Hence it is, that "HIe that is slow to anger, is better than the mnighty; and he that ruleth his spirit, than he that taketh a city." For want of this control, many of the greatest men in the w-orld's history, most distinguished for valor and brilliant achievement, have been really among the weakest of men- objects of compassion rather than of envy to every sensible mind. The hero who wept that there were no more worlds to conquer, seems never to have learned that within his own bosom lay a restless and turbulent kingdom, over which, with all his armies and all his power and valor, he had as yet attained no dominion. As relates to other Passionis aid -Propensities. - But self-control relates not to the temper alone; it implies the 9* 101 SELF-CONTROL. due restraint of all our passions, appetites, and pl'opens. ties. It includes what we mean by temperance, in its %wi(lest sense - abstinence fi'om all those excesses and vices which inijure the health, impair the strength and activity of body and mind, weaken the character and influence, cut short the life. To yield to the passions and appetites of the animal nature, without restraint, involves these consequences. They may be remote, and slow of approach, but they are sure. The eternal and immutable laws of nature have established this connection, and decreed these results. They are not to be avoided. Ihence, it is one of the plainest dictates of prudence, one of the first and most imperative duties which we owe to ourselves, to keep these appetites and propensities of the animal nature under strict control. If to defend the person from the violent assault of robber or assassin, be a duty, much more to defend the mind and moral nature fi'oni injury and ruin. Sensuality ruins both body and soul. He who yields to this foe is lost. It may be difficult, in many cases, to assign the precise limit within which indulgence of the appetites is allowable, and beyond which it becomes a crime. Such limits there are; and it is for each one, by carefuil observation, to determine for himself where they lie. One thing is certain, that lie who finds the demands of appetite increasing upon him beyond his power of successful resistance, has already passed that limit. Objection.- It may be urged by some, that, inasmuch as the passions and propensities of our nature are a part of our original constitution, and, in a sense, the gift of the Creator, it is therefore right to indulge the same, without other limit than that which nature itself imposes; in other words, without restraint. This is the practical phlilosophy according to which too many, doubtless, are disposed 102 SELF-CONTROL. to govern their conduct. It is a philosophy, however, as false as it is shallow - at war not more with reason and revelation than with the common sense of mankind. The fact that a given propensity or passion is founded in the nature with which the Creator has endowed us, is surely no warrant for the indulgence of that propensity or passionr beyond the limits which the Creator has himself assigned. He who indulges his passions without restraint, transgresses these limits, and, in reality, does violence to his own nature. Self-control, firm and habitual, is not less the dictate of reason than the command of God. -ecessury to Self-reslpect, and the -Respect of Others. The exercise of a due self-control, both in regard to the temper and the various animal propensities of our nature, is necessary to all true self-respect. No man who is under the dominion of his baser appetites and passions, can truly respect himself. He knows his own Weakness and degradation; knows and feels that he is a slave, that the sceptre has departed firom him, that the crown of his integrity and honor is in the dust. The effect of this is most disastrous upon the character. He who has lost his self-respect, has lost that which no gold can buy. His courage and his moral strength are gone; nor can virtue long maintain its ascendency in the absence of this principle. Self-control is necessary also in order to the respect of others. No man can for any length of time receive the real homage and respect of others, who lacks the mastery of himself. Station, power, wealth, may do something for him; native talent and genius, still more; but not even these can ultimately keel) back firom merited contempt the helpless slave of his own miserable passions. Sa.d indeed is the spectacle, of one born to high honors, and endowed by nature with princely gifts, fi'om whose hand is stricken the sceptre of dominion over his own spirit. 103 SELF-CULTURE. CHAPTER IV. SELF-CULTURE. Statement.- To abstain fiom those things which injure us, to avoid those excesses and undue indulgences of the natural appetites and propensities which work mischief and ruin, is a duty, but not the whole duty which every intelligent rational being owes to himself. There are things to be attained, as well as things to be avoided; positive, as well as negative duties. Self-culture, not less than selfcontrol, becomes imperative. I have no right to neglect my own highest welfare and advancement. My duty is only in part performed when I refrain from that which positively injures and degrades my mental or bodily powers. It is my duty to develop and cultivate those powers to the highest degree of which they are, under the circumstances, susceptible,- to make the most of the faculties with which nature has endowed me. This is the duty of every man- a duty which he owes first of all to himself, but not to himself alone. The family, the state, society at large, the Creator - all have an interest in this matter, and are concerned in its performance or neglect. The highest wrong is done not to self alone, but to others, by every instance of such neglect. Exten)(s to )what.- The duty of self-culture includes in its proper province the entire range of our natural faculties, whether of body or mind. It includes physical culture not less than mental. A healthy and well-developed physical organism is one of tlhe very choicest goods of life; and, in so far as it is a result to be attained by careful training and 104 SELF-CULTURE. culture, it is a duty imperative on every man to make that attainment, and to put forth the effort necessary to it. A sound mind in a sound body, is a maxim true in philosophy and true in mnorals. The history of the Greeks shows what may be done in this branch of education. In modern times, and more especially among our own countrymen, this department of education has fallen into disrepute, and been very generally overlooked. The theory with us is to discipline and develop the mind, and let the physical powers take care of themselves. Our institutions of learning, our whole educational system, look chiefly to this. It admits of serious question, whether in this we are not committing a radical mistake. So intimate is the connection between the physical and the mental state, that the highest condition and most favorable development of the latter can hardly be secured without due attention to the training and discipline of the former. Irnclu,(es also i,ental -Discipliie.- Self-culture extends also to the improvement of the intellectual and moral powers. No man is at liberty to neglect his own mental discipline and culture. Not even are the claims of business paramount to this. No pressure of professional or business engagements can justify the neglect of mental discipline. No man in this busy world has a right so to involve himself in the pursuits and cares of active life, that it shall be out of his power to give both time and care to the improvement of his own mind. Nature never intended this. HIe who miade the mind, and endowed it with its wondrous faculties, had no such intention. Nor is the culture of the mind to be made subordinate to success in the various employments of life, and to be pursued merely as a means to that end. A means to that end it unquestionably is. But that is not the whole or the chief reason why it should receive attention. The im 105 SELF-CULTURE. provement of the mind is, in itself, a good of inestimable worth, aside from all the gain that comes of it in the more successful pursuits of life. A well-cultivated mind, richly stored with the best acquisitions, is itself a treasure with which no material wealth can compare. "For wisdom is better than rubies; and all the things that may be desired are not to be compared to it." Not limited to the Intellect. Nor is the duty of which I speak limited to the culture of the intellect alone. MIemory, imagination, judgment, the reasoning powers, taste, conscience- all are to be educated and strengthened; but the seisibilities also claim regard, and likewise the wtill. These great departments of the mind's activity are not to be overlooked in the process of mental training. The heart requires education and discipline, as well as the lhead; the feelings, no less than the intellectual Ip)owers. -le only is the symrnmetrical, fully develop)ed, well-educated man, with whom all these faculties of his higher and spiritual nature h.Lve received due care an(l trining. He who fails of this, fails in one of the first duties which he owes to himself. Encouragemnents to tthis work. -Very great are the inducements, very pressing the motives, to the faithful performance of this duty. Other acquisitions are external, and of precarious tenure; these, a part of the soul itself-so much of real value added to the man. Other riches may take wings; this is the true wealth that remains, vhile the mind itself has any being, its inalienable inheritance. Nor does success in this work depend wholly on early advantages. In the absence of these, amid the pressing cares of active life, much may be done by judicious method, industry, and perseverance, to repair the deficiences of early training. Many of the bri-ghtest names in literature and science attest the truth of this. 106 PAItT II. DUTIES TO SOCIETY. CHAPTER I. DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. Value of Life. - Of the duties which we owe to our fellow-men in general, one of the most iml)erative is the regard which is due to human life. Life is one of the igreatest goods, one of the first and chief rights of nature. In comparison with it all other natural goods and possessions are of little account; since, when life itself is at an end, all those possessions and enjoyments which pertain to and depend up)on it are also ended. "All that a man hath will he give for his life." Hence, to take human life, has been regarded in all ages as a great crime. It is to rob a man of all his possessions and enjoyments at a stroke, to cut himn off firom all his plans of business, or of pleasure - fio'm all the l)ursuits and all the friendships of life, and to usher him, without warning or preparation, into the scenes of a new and untried existence. The injury thus done is irreparable. Property taken by fraud ol violence, may be restored; reputation unjustly assailed, nlay be made good; health may be regained; )ut life itself destroyed, it is not inii the power of man tQ DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. make good the loss. Hence a peculiar sacredness at taches to human life. It is the gift of Deity. Man cannot impart it; and what he cannot bestow, he has no right to take away. Only he who gave it can authorize its destruction. Distinctions Recognizedl. - The laws of the state make certain distinctions in the crime of taking human life; as murder, manslaughter, etc. It is sufficient, in morals, to draw the broad distinction between the premeditated and intentional, and the merely accidental taking of life. The former incurs the highest guilt; the latter may be innocent. It is not a violation of the moral code, provided it is not the result of carelessness which might and should have been avoided. If, by reckless driving through the streets of a crowded city, life is sacrificed, the doer of the mischief is responsible for his carelessness, though not guilty of murder. If, by the recklessness of an engineer, the vessel, or the car, with its freight of life, is driven to destruction, the author of the calamity, though not justly chargeable with intentional murder, is by no means free from the guilt of taking human life. In such cases, the laws of most nations arraign him for matislatighyter, making the distinction between that and the premeditated and intentional taking of life, which is denominated murder. When the crime is not only premeditated, but secret in its execution, the agent not exposing his own life by giving the victim an opportunity of self-defence, there is added to the guilt which otherwise and necessarily pertains to the act, the meanness of cowardice. The murderer under such circumstances becomes the assassin. When an unlawful assault is committed, such as from its nature must be more or less dangerous to life, should such assault ultimately result in death, although such result may not have been strictly intended by the assailant, 108 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. still, as the act was itself unlawful, a crime, and not an accident, the author of the violence is not free from responsibility for the fatal consequences. He is guilty of manslaughter. In general, with respect to injuries inflicted upon the person, malicious intention is inferred from the act itself; and whatever consequences result, are presumed in law to have been intended, unless there are some mitigating circumstances to excuse the act, and to show that it was unintentional. When-one person kills another in the heat of passion, in a sudden quarrel, arising from provocation, and without previous intention to take life, it is also, in English and American law, termed manslaughter; but if the passions have had time to cool, and the person provoked afterwards kills the other, it is regarded as murder. The term homnicice is usually, in law, applied to denote, in general, the taking of human life, whether by design or unintentionally, including murder and manslaughter, etc. When the act is purely unintentional and accidental, it is termed excusable homicide. The Jewish law, even in such cases, gave no protection to the slayer, unless he took refuge in certain cities specially designated as places of refuige. The English law imposes a fine on the person who has committed excusable homicide, - a fine which, however, in practice, is remitted, - and also makes him forfeit the instrument with which the offence was coinmitted. This is termed a deodand, and the law exacting it is still in force. Hoomicide Justifiable in what Cases.- There is a distinction in law between justiflable and excusable homicide. The cases just referred to, where the slaying is simply accidental, are instances of excusable homicide, though not perhaps justifiable. Homicide in an unpremeditated af 10 109 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. fray, though strictly in self-defence, is in English law also regarded as excusable rather than justifiable. This is termed chance-medley. When death occurs as the result of any game which is likely to end in blood,- as of boxing, sword-playing, etc., - or as the consequence of any dangerous and unlawful act,-as shooting, or casting stoues in a town,- the homicide is not in law justifiable: it may o0 may not be excusable. By the public laws of Athens and Rome, he who killed another in the public games authorized by the state, was not held guilty of homicide; so by the English law, death resulting from the exercise of any sports and games authorized by the king, is regarded as excusable homicide. By the old Jewish and Roman laws, as well as by the laws of England and of our own country, homicide is justifiable when committed in self-defence fiom any unlawful and violent assault, or for the prevention of any atrocious crime. If any one attempts robbery or murder, and is killed in the attempt, the killing is justifiable. The Jewish law justifies the slaying of the robber only in the act of breaking open a house, and that only in the nigyht tine: "If the sun be risen upon him, there shall be blood shed for him." The Roman law was similar, with this difference, that a thief detected by day might be slain, should he defend himself with a weapon, provided the slayer first make outcry for help. Roman law allowed any one to slay a person assaulting him with a weapon, whether the assailant were a robber or not, provided the assailed was in fear of his life, and could in no other way effectually protect himself. English law allows the same. The laws of Solon make the same distinction as the Jewish and Roman law between the slaying of the robber by night and by day. The ground of this distinction is evidently this: that in case of night attack, greater danger 110 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. to life may fairly be presumed on the part of the person assailed, inasmuch as he cannot so fullly know the precise extent of his danger, and cannot so readily obtain help. He may therefore be justified to the extent of his supposed danger. By day there are other means of redress. -Execution of uaw. - There are cases in which human life becomes forfeited by crime, and the laws of the land and the voice of universal justice demand the payment of the forfeit. In such cases, not justice to the criminal alone, but justice to the whole community, and the safety of the whole, require the death of the criminal. The very sacredness of human life demands this protection from the hand of violence, and makes it all imperative necessity that *Whoso sheddeth mnan's blood, by man shall his blood be shed." In no other way can the proper protection be thrown about the innocent and defenceless, than by making the life of the murderer the penalty of his crime. When an officer of justice, in pursuance of the sentence of law, takes human life, under such circumstanees, he is of course not guilty of a crime, but, on the contrary, is discharging a high and solemn duty. In other cases,- as where an officer, in the discharge of his official duties, is violently resisted and assailed; as, for example, by a prisoner seeking to make his escape, or resisting the process of arrest and imprisonment, - a lecessity may exist for the resort to extreme measures; and, in such a case, should the person thus resisting be killed by the officer, in the attempt to discharge his duty, the act must be pronounced justifiable. Palliating Ciircymstauces. - The instances to which I have referred( may be regarded as cases of justifiable homicide. They all fall under the law of self-protection, or the protection of society. There are many cases, however, which do not properly fall under that rule, yet where the ill DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. circumstances are such as, while they do not justify, at least palliate, in some measure, the guilt of homicide. Some offence, perhaps, has been committed, which the law either takes no cognizance of, or which is beyond the power of law adequately to redress. The provocation is great, the injury deeply felt, the course of justice slow and uncertain, and even at the best, the punishment of the offender, provided, by some defect of evidence ol some quibble of the law, he do not ultimately escape conv iction altogether, is likely to be small in comparison with the injury committed. The temptation, in such a case, is great for the injured man to take the law into his own hands. There may be cases in which circumstances shall seen* to palliate, in a measure, the wrong of such a procedure; but no circumstances, however they may excuse, can justify the taking of life by way of revenge, or redress for wrong committed, whether the injury be to the person or to the character and reputation of the injured party. Whatever be the loss, whatever the dishonor, the person injured has no right to be himself the judge or the executioner of justice. He has no right to touch the life of his enemy. The law alone has that right; and if not man, yet God is just, and will avenge the injured and the innocent. Were every man, when wronged, to take the law into his own hands, and become his own avenger, the consequences to society would be disastrous in the extreme. The _iDel.- There is a form of homicide, or attempted homicide, which differs fiomn any other form of assault with intent to kill, chiefly in the fact that it is made with the knowledge and cooperation of the party assailed, the attempt being mutual. This may be done with more or less of previous formality. When the challenge to such an encounter is previously given and accepted, and the 0 tio I DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. combat is conducted in accordance with certain rules acknowledged in such cases, it is termed a duel, or an affair of honor; when without such ceremony, it is simply termed a hostile encounter, and differs little from chancemedley, a sudden affray, except that it is premeditated by one or both the )parties, and not unfrequently anticipated by the other. In either case, it is an assault with the avowed intent to kill, with more or less of premeditation and mutual consent. The history of the duel is not to be overlooked in estimating its character. It is, beyond doubt, a very ancient customn. It seems to have originated in the earlier stages of civilization, among rude and barbarous nations, of war like habits. It was virtually an appeal to the Supreme Ruler of men and events, to decide the uncertain question of right or wrong, innocence or guilt, between the contending parties. It is closely analogous, in this view, to the trial by ordeal, and the judicial combat. Whatever apology for this custom may have been found in those earlier and ruder times, when law was a less efficient protector of the right and of human life, and when every man was under the necessity, in a measure, of taking his defence into his own hands, no such apology or excuse can ordinarily be urged at the present day. It is a relic of barbarism, utterly unworthy of the civilization of the nineteenth century. As a means of justice, it is utterly senseless and absurd. At the best, it is an equal chance which party shall prevail, the guilty or the innocent. Skill in the use of weapons must usually decide this; and the skill and the strength that shall give advantage in the combat are quite as likely to be on the side of the wrong as of the right. To speak of obtaining satisfaction by submitting a dispute to any such process, is simply and purely ridiculous. 10* 113 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. In one respect, the duel is certainly more honorable than secret assassination, or some other forms of homicide, inas much as it gives the assailed party warning, and an oppor tunity for defence. Still it is, when not a mere farce, intentional murder, and is accordingly so regarded and treated by the laws of nearly all civilized nations. No man has a right to take human life in order to avenge any real or supposed personal insult or injury; nor has any one a right to expose his own life, in this manner, to the murderous assault of a foe. S!iciele. - The same reasons that forbid one to take the life of his fellow-man forbid him to take his own. Hle has no more right to cut short his own life than that of another. Life is sacred - the gift of the Creator -a treasure which it is not allowed us to trifle with, which we cannot confer, and therefore have no right to take away. Nor is it a wrong done to himself alone, when, with rash hand, a man cuts short his own life. Society is wronged. Society has a claim on him for life, and labor, and valuable service. There are those dependent, it may be, on his care and toil, who have a still higher claim upon him. He has no right to desert them- no right to betray his trust, and leave those who are dependent on him to struggle alone with misfortune and want. It is his duty, rather, to stand up like a true man under the heavy pressure of whatever trials and calamities may befall him, manfully bearing the lot of life, and by his presence and example, not less than his toil, helping others to sustain the heavy load. It is a striking instance of the insufficiency of the light of nature as a guide to duty, that among the ancients suicide was regarded as not merely allowable, but, in certain cases, commendable; and was resorted to by some among the wisest and the best of the truly great men of that time, as an escape from the calamities and burdens of life. 114 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIFE. It rs a melancholy spectacle of the imperfection of human reason and the human conscience. It was for Christianity to reveal the true philosophy of human life,-to make known the sacredness of life, as such,- to teach the far lof tier courage and heroism of ])atient endurance,- to direct the eye of the desponding sufferer to that "far more ex ceeding and eternal weight of glory" for which the pres ent sorrows were intended to prepare him, and to which they are the necessary avenue of approach. It bade him run with patience the race set before him, fixing his eye upon Itimn, the great heroic sufferelr, "who endured such contradiction of sinners against himself;" and "who, for the joy that was set before him, endured the cross, despising the shame, and is set down at the right hand of the Majesty on HiTgh." It may be added, that the reasons already urged iagainst suicide apply equally to any course of conduct by which life is shortened, or its energies weakened. No man has a right to shorten his days, or impair his vital energies, by any course of vicious indulgence or excess This is only an indirect form of suicide. Too firequently is this fatal error committed by those who, in the heat of passion or the ardor of youth, yield to the impulses of the sensitive nature, regardless of consequences. And not alone by those whlo yield to the dominion of the lower appetites is this guilt incurred. In the pressure of business, or the ardor of intellectual pursuits, the body and the mind may be, and too frequently are, overtasked, resulting in the premature decay of the vital powers, and an early grave. It is not by direv~ and intentional acts alone that life is destroyed, and( the guilt of suicide incurred. I would not be understood, in what has been said, to imply that life, however sacred, is to be preserved at all hazards. There are other interests higher and dearer than lit$ 116 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. life itself- interests which we may not sacrifice for the sake of preserving even life. Rather than betray the cause of truth and right, rather than desert the principles of justice and honor, an(l prove recreant to duty and to faith, a man may well die. In defence of the innocent and helpless, in defence of the right, in defence of his family and his country, in defence of his religious belief, he may well lay down his life, if need be. As a martyr, as a patriot, as a lover of truth and justice, there may be occasion io die. Life is not the highest duty nor the most sacred treasure of man. CHAPTER II. DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. Liberty a Natural Right.- One of the first and plainest natural rights of man is the right to himself, -that is, to liberty, - a right to the disposal of his own time and industry and personal movements as he sees fit, within such limits as the rights and safety of others allow. That this is the intention of nature, is evident from the constitution of man. He desires liberty, and is never happy when deprived of it. He pines for it, dreams of it, toils for it, risks everything to obt.tin it. To deprive him of this light, without due cause, is to inflict upon him one of the greatest wrongs. There is nothing, next to life itself, with which a man will not sooner part than his'.berty. 2ocles iin which one may be cleprived of it.- Of this right man may be deprived in various ways. Sometimes it is justly forfeited by his own conduct; and in that case, society has the right to take it from him. Sometimes lihe DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. is unjustly deprived of it by the violence and cupidity of his fellow-man. Imprisonment for Crime.-1. Society may justly deprive a man of liberty by imprisonment for crime. This the law has a right to do. The protection and safety of the community require it. He who violates the rights of others, forfeits his own; and the principles upon which society is constituted require it, as a measure of selfdefence, to restrain the liberty of him who abuses his' liberty to the detriment of others. It may justly imprison him for trial; and after trial and conviction, it may justly imprison him for punishment. It may justly require of him, while thus in confinement as a convict, such amount of personal labor as shall at least be sufficient for his support. The extent and mode of such imprisonment is to be determined by law. When it is protracted beyond due limit, or is attended with unnecessary severity,- when the term of trial is needlessly delayed, or when a degree or mode of punishment is inflicted beyond what the nature of the offence strictly demands, -the coercion thus exercised become unjust, and society is in turn the aggressor. Conyftnement of the I)tsaCte. - 2. For the reasons already mentioned, it is the right of society to place insane persons in confinement, provided the safety of their families and friends, or even their own safety, requires such restraint. It is a measure of self-defence, and even of benevolence; nor is any wrong inflicted upon the sufferer in such a case, provided the deprivation of liberty be not attended with any unnecessary severity, or any real unkindness. Captivity in Var. -3. Another mode in which one may be deprived of liberty, is by ccaptivity in war. If war itself is juistifiable, under any circumstances, then it is allowahle for the victorious party to make such disposal of its captives taken in war as shall prevent them from tak 117 118 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. ing further part in hostilities against itself. This can be effectually done, perhaps, only by imprisonment; and this imprisonment may continue until the close of hostilities, unless previously terminated by the exchange of an equal number of prisoners taken by the other party. Formerly, all captives taken in war were reduced to slavery. This was the great source of supply of slave labor, not only in Greece and Rome, but in the powerful empires of earlier origin. Homer, and the Greek tragedians, represent the lot of those conquered in war, and also of their wives and children, as one of servile and hopeless bondage. Among civilized nations, this mode of conducting war is by univer. sal consent abandoned. Involuntary Servitucle. - 4. Still another mode in which liberty may be taken away, is that form of involuntary ser. vitude known as slavery. As this is a matter of much importance, and one upon the morality of which conflicting views are entertained to some extent, especially in our own country, it seems to require a more full and careful consideration. It will, therefore, constitute the principal topic of the present chapter. It will be to the purpose, in the first place, to define slavery; the way will then be prepared to inquire whether slavery, as thus defined, is a moral wrong; what its effects are upon the nation, both as respects morals, and financial prosperity; and, finally, what arguments may be adduced in favor of it. These topics, in their order, as now stated, will be discussed in the following sections. ~ I.- SLAVERY DEFINED. When the right of personal ownership and personal control, that properly belong to a man, are taken from him, for no fault and by no consent of his own, and vested DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. in another, giving to the latter control over the person and industry of the former, the man thus subjected becomes a slave, and the one to whom he is subjected is termed the master. I say for no fault, and by no consent of his own, -for imprisonment for crime, of which I have already spoken, is not slavery, though it may be accompanied with some degree of involuntary service; there is control, but not owvershil,); nor are we at present concerned withi volutttary servitude, in any of its forms. Slavery, as now understood,- that is, as an actually existing institution, -. always implies o)?,ership) on the part of the master, and iz,voltc,tary servitecke on the part of the slave. This ownership is complete, and, to a great extent, irresponsible. The slave is in the same category with any other property or possession- as truly the property of the master as the horses or dogs that belong to the same plantation. The control of the master over the one is as complete, unlimitedl, and irresponsible, as his control over the other. His time, his labor, his acquisitions, his person, his children, are not his own, but his master's. He is to be bought, and sold, and worked, and whipped, at the master's pleasure. He has no rights of his own. Slave Laws accord with this -Deyi)ition.- This is the character of complete slavery, as recognized by the laws of other nations, as well as our own. "Slaves," says Gaius, the distinguished Roman jurist, "are in the power of the masters. Which power, indeed, is one recognized by the laws of nations; for among all nations, it is to be observed, that the power of the master over the slave has been the power of life and death, and whatever is acquired by the slave, is acquired by the master." This we knoQw to have been not only Roman law, but Roman custom. The slave had neither security of life, nor property in any 119 120 DUTIES PERTRAINING'rO LIBERTY. thing ho might acquire. He belonged to another, and not to himself. The institution of modern slavery is based on the same principles. The slave is the property of the master, and has no right to himself. The laws of different states vary, but the principles of the system are essentially the same in all. According to the code of Louisiana, "The slave is in the power of'the master to whom he belongs. The inaster may sell him, dispose of his person, his indlustry, his labor; he can do nothing, possess nothing, nor acquire anything, but which must belong to his master." According to the laws of South Carolina, "Slaves shall be deemed, taken, reported, and adjudged to be chattels personal in the hands of their masters, and possessions to all intents and purposes wiatever." These, then, I take to be the essential elements of slavery -viz., ownership, property, absolute control. Where these exist, there is slavery. Liniitations of Po?cer. - Certain limitations of the power of the master, may or may not exist in the different states, according as the slave code may be more or less str;3ct. In some cases, the master is forbidden to put his slave to death, or treat him with unnecessary cruelty. Practically, such a limitation amounts to little, when it is remembered that the testimony of the slave is not admitted on evidence in the courts of' law, and also that it is for the interest of the masters to sustain each other in the exercise of discipline and authority over the slaves. It must in the nature of the case be extremely difficult, if .ot impossible, under such circumstances, to obtain clear and satisfactory evidence of cruelty on the part of the master, and equally d(liflicult to secure the impartial administration of justice, even in cases of notorious violation of the law in question, where the interests of both judge and DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. 121 jury so clearly identify them.with the offending party, and where the safety and permanent existenice of the system is seen to depend on firmly sustaining the power and authority of the master over his slaves. But, even if such limitations could be, as they cannot be, practically carried out and enforced, they do not change the essential character of slavery, as already defined. They do not make the master less an owner, or the slave less property or a chattel. They do not invest him with any rights. They are merely a concession to the natural feelings of humanity. They are of the same nature, is Whewell well remarks, with "the English laws against cruelty to animnals. It is now penal in this country to torture a horse or a dog; but a horse or a dog are still only objects of possession, without any rights, or any acknowledged moral nature." ~ II. - SLAVERY, AS THUS DEFINED, A MORAL WRONG. It can hardly admit of serious question that slavery, as thus defined, involves a moral wrong. In the strong language of Whewell, it is "contr ary to the fundamental principles of mnorality." It is a wrong, inasmuch as, 1. It violates the 2iatitral riyhts of man. It reduces him from a person to a thing-than which no greater wrong can be inflicted on humanity. The victim of this injustice is no longer, in the eye of the law, a man; he has become a mere thing, has no rights, and, consequently, can suffer no wrong. He stands on a level with the brute. He has his pleasures and his pains; so has the brute. He has his natural impulses and desires; the brute also has his. The strong affections, the tumultuous passions of our nature, that agitate the bosoms of other men, stir also in his; they have their counterpart, also, to some extent, in 11 -122 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. the affections and passions of the brute. Nor, in the eye of the state, are these feelings of any more value and c()nsequence in the one case than in the other. Witlh all their natural instincts, thoughts, feelings, passions, affections, they are both, the man and the brute, and the one e(!?clly with the other, the property of the master. Yet this creature, this thing, has that which the brute has not-a rcitio)ictl a(cl moral nature, anid no man, no society of men, nor any human legislation, has the right to dleprive himn of it. The law tli:at d(oes this, or attcmnl)ts to do it, is a laIt) wit]hout (i 2i.na(t. To treat a ri.ition.'l, moral beiiig as if he were an iiiration.l and irresl-)onsille creature, - a nman as if he were a brute, - is to inflict the highest indignity and injustice which human nature is capable of receiving. So palpable is this, that even the Roman jurists admit that no man is a slave by nature. Another Elemneitt of Injtstice.- 2. Slavery is a wrong inasmuch as it not only deprives the slave of his natural right of self-disposal and control, but subjects him to the lawless will of a mnaster. Irresponsible power is a dangerous thing. It is never safe to trust any man with it, however humane and well-disposed. There is in the human bosom, implanted among its native elements, a love of power - power over whatever lies about us - power over our fellow-men especially, as being the most difficult of control, and affording therefore, when brought under subjection, a higher sense of pleasure, amounting to a sort of triumph. The man who can command his fellow-man, feels his own superiority much more than he who can exercise his authority only over the lower orders of creation. Now, whenever this power becomes complete and unlimited; when its word is law, and must be obeyed; when it becomes the power of absolute ownership; when DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. the being who is subject to it has no will nor voice of his own, no mode of redress, no rights; when he is the mere property of another; when he and all that is his-the body with all its organs and powers, the mind with all its faculties of action and capacities for enjoyment and suffering, the fi'iends that may gather around him, the wife and children that may cling to him as their natural protector - all, all are entirely at the disposal of another, in the power of't master, and that power, for the most part, and to all practical purposes, unlimited and irresponsible to any earthly tribunal, - who will say that such power as this can safely be confided to any man over his fellow-man? Who will say there is no risk in all this - no danger that a power so far-reaching and absolute and fearful may be abused? The True Question.- Now, it is precisely this risk, this danger of abuse, this almost certainty that, in many cases at least, the power in question will be abused, that consti tutes in no small degree the guilt of the entire system. It is no answer to say, that in many cases the power is not abused. Undoubtedly- this is true. Unquestionably many masters are kind and humane. That is not the point. Even if it could be shown that the great majority are so, -that kindness is the rule, and cruelty the except tion,-it would not in the least affect the present argu. ment. It is precisely these exceptions, liable at any mo. ment and anywhere to occur, impossible of pr,cevention -it is this liability to abuse that constitutes one of the ilmost appalling features of the system. Is there no wrIono in subjecting a man endowed by the Creator with all tho rights and privileges of humanity, possessing a rational, spiritual nature that places him, however degraded he may be, at an infinite remove from the beasts that perish - is there no wrong in subjecting this rational and accountable being to a servitude worse even than that of the 123 124 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. brutes by so much as his nature is superior to theirs? Is there no wrong in subjecting him to a power which may be at any moment and to any degree abused, and against the abuse of which he has no safeguard, no pro tection, no mode of redress? A Third -Element.- 3. Slavery is a wrong, inasmuch as it dleprives the slave of that intellectual, 9)oral, and religious culture which is his right. It is essential to slavery, as a system, that the slave be kept in ignorance. Any considerable amount of instruction would prove fatal to the perpetuity of the system. If the slave were once to know what are his rights, and in what manner it would be possible to regain them, it is obvious that he would no longer rest passive under the weight that is crushing him to the earth. He must not have access, then, to the thoughts that are stirring the mind and heart of the race to which he belongs. He must be shut up in a night of deepest intellectual and moral darkness. It were not safe even that he should know so much as to be able to read and write. To some extent, oral religious instruction might perhaps be safely imparted; but even this must be kept fully within the control of the master. It would be inconvenient, for example, should the conscience of the slave, by reason of religious training, interpose itself as a barrier to the absolute will and caprice of the master. Nor would it be by any means expedient to place the Bible, without note or comment, in the hands of a slave capable of reading and understanding its pages. That book which has proved the great instrument of fireedom, civil and religious, in the history of the world, -the magqna chartac of human rights, - might teach him truths which, as a slave, it were better he should not know; might teach him that God has made of one blood all the nations of the earth; that to one and the same God DUTIES PEFRTAINING TO LIBERTY. master and slave stand alike responsible f); thle things done in the flesh, and that this God is no respecter of persons. Act?al Policy of the System.- -We find, accordingly, that the actual policy of the system is to keep the slave as much as possible in ignorance. To teach him to read or write is made, in many of the slave states, an offence p)unishable with fine and imprisonment; while to place in his hands any document containing information calculated to make him discontented with his servitude, is thought worthy of the most severe and sunmmary punishment. Need it be said that this is a moral wrong? Is not mental and moral culture the 7right of every human being endowed by nature with an intelligent and rational soulof every being made in the image of his God, made moral and accountable? Is not the revealed will of God the birthright of every child of Adam- of every fallen, ruined being for whom Christ has died? Have I any right, for purposes of my own convenience or profit, to deprive him of this? Does the system into whose very foundation such a prohibition enters, and which could not exist for a day without it, involve no moral wrong? .Essential, as distingtisIhedl from Itcidental Wrongs. - In discussing the moral character of this institution, I have spoken only of those evils which seem inseparable fi'om any system of complete slavery. Of those wrongs which are incide)ntal to the system, as it exists in this or in other countries, and which constitute the worst features, in many respects, of such a system, - as, e. g., the separl tion of families by sale, the disregard of the marriage tie, the nameless and shocking barbarities which are of too firequent occurrence wherever slavery exists, -I purposely forbear to speak in this connection. I can conceive of 11* -. 125 126 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. system of servitude that should dispense with the shame and guilt of these peculiar features, that should be fiee fiomn the odium of such vices and b.arba:rities; but I cannot conceive of any form or system of complete slavery that shall be fi'ee firom the wrongs NlNiicli have been discussed in the present section. Wlherever there is ownership and property in man, and that entire control and disposal of his person, faculties, and services, which such ownership implies, there are, and must be, and always will be, as the legitimate and inevitable consequence, the wrongs of which I have spoken, viz., the violation of the natural rights of man, by reducing him firom the condition of a person to the condition of a thing; by subjecting him to the irresponsible, lawless will of a master, with the imnminent dancgei that that power will be abused, and with 11no protection against such abuse, nor redress fiom any wrong or outr,age that may be inflicted; and, finally, by shutting him ul) in more or less complete ignorance and darkness- depriviniig lhim of that mental and moral culture which is his ri,ghlt. And, in view of these necessary and essential features of any and all systems of complete slave,'y, I cannot but pronounce any and every such system a grievous wrong in morals. ~ III.-EFFECT OF SLAVERY ON THE NATIONAL MORALS AND THE NATIONAL WEALTH. In order to a fair andl just appreciation of the real chlaracter of any system, we must observe its effects, its practical working, and the consequences that actually flow from it. It is not enough to reason a p-iori as to whlat the moral character of sl:avery nmust be. It is necessary to verify such reasonings by actual observation. If the effects are,disastrous, the system itself cannot be right. The ~ e DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. tree must be judged by its fruits. There are two points of view from which the system now under consideration may well be regarded in its actual working, viz., its effect on the morals, and on the financial prosperity, of the state. I. 0O) J,Iorals. -There can be little doubt that the arrangement which places one man, or a considerable number of men, at the entire disposal and control of another, subject to his absolute and irresponsible will and power, is a system of things not the most favorable to moral excellence, whether of the master or the servant. The exercise of such authority must, in the nature of the case, tend to foster a spirit of pride and arrogance —to make a man overbearing and haughty in temper, quick and irascible, impatient of restraint and contradiction. The passions of our nature, the animal propensities, ever ready to assume the mastery, and requiring to be kept in check with firm hand, finding now no barriers to their indulgence but those which are self-imposed, will be likely to break over those feeble barriers, and acquire unrestrained course and dominion. The tendency of the system to these results in morals, so far as the master is concerned, is inevitable. AIany and honorable exceptions there will be; but the tendency is still the same. It must be so while human nature is what it is. The temptation to abuse of power over those who cannot or dare not resist, -to undue severity of punishment, where the passioI0s of the master are roused, and there is none to say what doest thou, - to the gratification of the baser appetites in their various forms, -must be too great for ordinary and unaided human virtue. The tendency of such a system must ever be, not to progressive refinement and moral culture, but to barbarism. We should expect to find in connection with such a civil polity, a state of 127 128 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. society and of morals somewhat peculiar, - acts of rio. lence and barbarity not infrequent, the street affray, the duel, the murderous assault, the unrestrained indulgence of the animal appetites. This it would be reasonable to expect; and this, unless all history is false, we do find, the world over, to be the general state and tendency of things where the system of slavery prevails. Eject on the Slacve.- Nor is the effect on the morals of the slave more favorable; on the contrary, it is even more disastrous. In proportion as the feeling of self-respect and self-dependence is taken away, and a man is taught to look upon himself as merely the tool in the hands of another, the instrument of another's will and pleasure, without responsibility of his own, just in that proportion the foundation of moral character is undermined. Nothing can be more demoralizing in its effect uponi the character. Strip a man of all that constitutes manhood, -of all self-reliance and self-respect, of all the rights which nature has conferred upon him, and all the faculties with which the Creator has endowed him; take away from him all control and disposal of himself, all ownership of himself,- and all that can stimulate to activity, and incite to noble attainment and excellence, is gone at once. lIe sinks down to the level of the brute. What inducement is there for him to hope or strive for anything other or better than his present lot, and the enjoyment which the moment may bring with it? He becomes, as a matter of course, improvident and reckless, content with the gratification, so far as may be, of his merely animal appetites; indolent- for why should he be otherwise? deceptive and dishonest -for what motive has he to honesty? governed only by fear of the lash, with little thought of anything future, with little knowledge of that hereafter whence are derived the most powerful motives to present virtue. His DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. mind shrouded in ignorance, his moral nature almost wholly uncultivated, his condition is little above that of the beast with whom he toils, and with whom he perishes. Exceptions there may be, many and remarkable, to this general law. As in the case of the master, so in the case of the slave; some will rise above the influences that surround and drag them down, and, in spite of all these depressing and demoralizing influences, will maintain their integrity. But such is not the rule, such is not the tendency of the system. No one who has either reflected on the matter, or observed the actual working of the system, can honestly suppose that it is. It is a notorious fact, that, as a general rule, wherever this system exists, the slave is indolent, deceitful, dishonest, improvident,-not to be trusted away fi'oin the eye of his master. Can that be a right system which produces such effects on those whom it most directly concerns? II. Effect of the National Waetlth. - It can hardly admit of question that slavery tends greatly to impoverish a country. It exhausts the resources of the most fertile soil, and seeks ever new and unexhausted territories on which to plant itself. From these, again, it must in turn migrate, if it would thrive. We have only to compare the slave and the free state, lying side by side, in our own country, alike in climate, soil, and productions, - the same mountains and rivers and skies common to both, - the same constitution encircling and the same flag floating over them; -we have but to mark the thrift and enterprise and accumulating capital of the one, and the comparative stagnation and poverty of the other, - the crowded streets, the busy industry, the numerous population of the one, the sparsely settled condition and neglected aspect of the other, - to be satisfied on which 129 180 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. side of the dividing line that separates freedom from sei'vitude the sources of prosperity lie. Nor is it difficult to perceive why it should be so. In the states where servitude is the established institution and order of things, labor becomes disgraceful; in the free state, industry and honest toil are honored and rewarded; and all classes of citizens labor, each in his own way and at his own employment. The difference is that which always holds, by the laws of nature, between idleness and industry, -viz., poverty and wealth. It is an essential principle, moreover, in political economy, that in order to the most efficient and productive labor, a man must have some personal interest in that on which he labors, else the highest incentive to effort will be wanting. This is precisely what is and must be ever wanting in any system of involuntary servitude. HIe who labors not for himself, but for another, and wvlose chief motive to effort is the fear of the lash tier than any hope of reward, is not likely to be the most industrions or profitable of servants. The system which depends on such labor, violates the fundamental laws of nature, and cannot prosper. ~ IV. - ARGUMENTS IN FAVOR OF SLAVERY. It is not enough, in the consideration of a matter so important as the present, in its bearings on the happiness and welfare of the race, to look merely at one side of the question, without inquiring what may be said on the other. The result of our inquiries thus far has been adverse to th.e system in question: it is no more than f.Tir to consider the arguments in favor of the system. -Defenced on the ground of Farnzily Governent. Some writers place the matter on the ground of family DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. government, and defend it on that ground as right and to be justified, when the authority thus exercised seeks, as in tlie government of the family, the best. good of the governed, and is administered solely with a view to that end. To this it may be replied, in the first place, that the supposition now made by no means holds good of the system as a whole. It is not true that slavery, as it actually exists in the world, or ever has existed in its true and complete form, is a system the real design and aim of which is the welfare and highest good of the slave. I-Iiumane and l)pious masters there doubtless are, andl lhave been in all periods of the world's history, who have sought to make their power consistent, so far as possible, with the welfare of their slaves. They have not been unmindful of the good of the governed. But that, even in such1 cases, the welfare of the slave has been the direct aim and end of the institution, the thing for wtzhich it exists, rather than merely an inci(clei?t(l benefit secured in spite of all the opposite tendencies and natural results of the systemL,' no one, I think, can intelligently maintain; much less that such is the real end and object of the system as a whole. Everybody knows that the end aimed at in the institution of slavery is not the good of the slave himself, but the gain of the master; and to assert the contrary is simply absurd. If any one were to assert that the efforts now making, by government, and individuals, to introduce and domesticate the camel in this country, were prompted by a simple and pure regard to the comfort and happiness of tlhat valuable animal, we shlould( esteem himn as a person of lhuiane disl)osition, but sonewvhat weak in understand ilig. Were we to cite, in confirmation of this theory, tlic laws wvllicll )iohilbit cruelty to animals, and the many in stalnces in which camels have ben well treated, we should, while gratified to learn these facts, hardly regard them as 131 132 DIJTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. establishling the point in question. That the system of involuntary servitude, which reduces man from the condition of a person to that of a thing, makes him a mere piece of property, like a horse or a dog, takes away from him all power of self-direction, and makes him subject to the lawless and irresponsible will of a master - that this system, so repugnant to all natural ideas of right and justice, has any claim to be regarded as an eleemnosynary institution, designed to promote the highest good of the slave, remains to be proved. -Further Reply.- The argument rests, moreover, on the assumption that the slave is not capable of self-government,- which has never been shown to be true, but which, on the contrary, facts seem to contradlict,- and that, consequently, inasmuch as he is not capable of owning, directing, and governing himself, the master has the right of owning and governing him, - which by no means follows. Is the slave unfit to be his own masterl? And, even if he is, does that give me as an individual the right to govern him? How came he into that relation to me, and I to him, that places him in my power, and gives me the authority to govern him? Have I really any right to sustain that relation to any of my fellowbeings? Granted: that this man, left to himself, might not order his affairs so wisely and so well as I could order them for him- what then? Does it follow that I have the right to take out of his hands the ownership and control of himself, and make him my property? Argzment from Inferiority.- The ground on which the defence of the system is more' fiequently placed, is that the negro is by nature inferior to the white race. His proper position in the scale of being, that for whichl DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. nature evidently intended him, is the condition of servi tude. We are depriving him, therefore, of no right when we subject him to bondage. This argument is invalid in its premises, and false in its conclusion. It is not true that the negro is by -atttre- wlh.tever he may be by the circumstances of his position - essentially inferior to the white race. Facts prove the contrary. Placed under influences equally favorable for mental and moral development, with equal advantages and equal inducements, he has uniformly shown himself capable of equal attain. ments. He is endowed by nature with the same mental and moral faculties that belong to other men; and those faculties are susceptible of the same culture. Hle has the same affections and passions with other men; the same sense of right and justice, the same moral nature. The very laws which forbid the teaching of slaves to read and write, are of themselves a sufficient contradiction of the theory of his native inferiority. But, even if it were as now assumed, could it be showni that the negro is inferior by nature to the Caucasian race, it is by no means a legitimate conclusion that the Cau casian is for that reason entitled to reduce the former to bondage. The very fact of inferiority, if it be a fact, con stitutes a reason, not for reducing him to a still deeper and more deplorable degradation, but for elevating him to a higher and better condition. It is a circumstance which calls not for severe measures, and the wresting fiom him in his feebleness and ignorance what light and what strength he has, but rather for compassion and gentleness; it is a reason, not for making him my property, and de priving him of all ownership and control of himself, not for making him a mere chattel, a thing to be used and abused at my pleasure, but rather for instructing and ele vating him to something higlher and better than he is. 12 133 134 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. Besides, the question naturally arises, tfow came he to be thus inferior? Viewed in its present condition, nluder all the depressing influences of a state of hopeless servitude, the slave population may well be supposed inferior ill many respects, both mentally and morally, to the dominant white race. But how came it to be so? Is it cause, or consequence? Does the condition of servitude result firom the perceived inferiority, or the perceived inferiority from the condition of servitude? If by force or fraud I succeed in catching a man and putting out his eyes, that surely will not entitle me to make him my slave after that, because he is blind! The question would be asked, What occasioned that blindness? Argument fromn Scripture.-The position which the advocates of slavery often assume, and of late more frequently than formerly, is that the -Bible recognizes anad sustains slavery. If this be so, it is certainly a strong presumption in its favor, and will go far to weaken and impair, if not altogether to set aside, many of the alguments already presented. It requires, therefore, a careful and candid consideration. That slavery is recognized in the Scriptures, both of the Old and New Testament, is evident; that it is not expressly and directly coitcemne1d or prohibited in either, may also be admitted; that it is jttstified, either by the spirit, or precepts, of the sacred writings, is not true; on the contrary, it is emphatically and diametrically opposed to both. Under the Jewish economy, slavery, in a modified form, existed, and was suffered to exist- was tolerated, not justified. It stood on the same ground with polygamy, and similar kindred vices. MIany things were suffered then to exist which a true and strict morality could by no means sanction, and which are nowhere sanctioned, but, on the DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. contrary, condemned by the whole spir'it of Christianity. Such, for example, was the ancient Jewish law and custom of divorce for the slightest offences, and even for no offence, but the caprice of the husband. Such the law and custom of polygamy. On the same ground we may also place the institution of slav-ery, so far as it then existed. Jewish and Jfoclern Slavery unlike. -It must be remenmbered, however, that the system of servitude known and practised under the Jewish economy, was in many respects essentially different from the slavery of modern times. It was another and a very different thing. The difference was as great, as that between an absolute, and a constitutional and limited monarchy. The power of the Jewish master over his servant was closely and strictly limited. The servant was not, in the modern sense, a slave - a mere piece of property, a thing. He wvas still a man. He had his rights, and they were carefully guarded and secured by law. The master was not, either in theory, or practically, irresponsible. In purchasing a servant, he purchased not so much the man himself as the right to the labor and ser vices of the man, and even that utnder certain important restrictions. The purchase was to be made, in the first place, Tf some foreign nation. If the servant found his situation disagreeable, and effected his escape, he was not to be deliverel up to his master (Deut. xxiii. 15, 16); nor was the servitude in any case to be perpetual. Every fiftieth year witnessed the release of every servant from bondage throughout the land. Religious rights were especially guaranteed to the servant. He was to have full opportunity for religious instruction and worship. If the master maimed or otherwise abused him, he was to be set fiee (Ex. xxi. 26, 27); if the slave were killed while under the master's correction, the master was to be pun ished (Ex. xxi. 20). 135 136 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. Now, it is evident that these are very important restri( tions. A system of servitude thus modified and limited, would be a very different institution from any known as modern slavery. When these limitations and restrictions shall have been adopted into the slave-codes of those states where men are now held in bondage; when it shall be tunla(tfiel to deliver to his master a slave that has escaped; when every fiftieth year shall set fiee all that are in bondage; when every slave that receives personal injury, to the loss of an eye or a tooth even, by severity of treatment, shall go free for his eye's or tooth's sake; when the death of the slave under the hand of his master shall subject the master to severe and certain punishment; when the full privileges of mental and religious instruction shall be secured to the slave, -then, and not till then, it will be time enough to plead the system of Jewish servitude as a precedent for modern slavery. Such restrictions, it is perfectly obvious, are quite incompatible with the system as it exists among us; they would bring it to a speedy end. Greek and _Roiman SlaCvey. - But the slavery which is recognized in the New Testament, it is said, was much worse than that of the Jewish state. In the GreCian and Roman states the master's power over the slave was unrestricted, amounting even to the power of life and death. It was to slavery in this its severer and more complete form, that the New Testament writers had reference. This is true But do these writers justify such a system, or merely recognize its existence? Is it approved, or merely tolerated? Is it anywheice defended, and placed on the high groundl of moral right, or merely recognized as an existing civil institution? These are important questions. It is for those who undertake to defend slavery fiom the Bible, to show that the sacred writers justify the system of DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. servitude then in vogue; that they recognize not merely its existence, but its moral rightness. This cannot be shown. So far from approving and justifying anything of the kind, the whole tenor of the sacred writings, and- especially of the New Testament, is directly opposed to all such systems, laws, and practices. The spirit of the divine precepts, the sum and substance of that law which is to govern our conduct, is contained in that universal rule, "All things whatsoever ye would that men should do unto you, do ye even so unto them." Our regard for the rights and happiness of others is to be measured by our regard for our own welfare, and our ownI rights. Is such a rule compatible with the existence of such a system of slavery as prevailed in Greece and Rome, or as still prevails among modern nations? Is it not, on the contrary, utterly subversive of any and every such system? Were this one precept carried out, slavery, in whatever form, and whatever land, would as surely and as speedily terminate, as night ceases when day begins. -Duties of Jfltsters and Servants prescribed. -But, it is said, the New Testament prescribes the duties of master and servant, and so tacitly gives consent to the system. It is true, the gospel enjoins upon the master the duty of forbearance, and kindness, and of rendering to the servant that which was just and due, and upon the servant the duty of obedience to the master. But these duties are enjoined, not on the ground of the rightfqtlness of the rela tion, hut simply as that which, under all the circumstances, was the best course to pursue, and would be most pleasing in the sight of God. Precisely in the same way, and on the same principle, the disciples of the Christian faith were advised to submit to tlhe arbitrary and tyrannical decrees and irresponsible power of tyrants, such an one as Nero even, not because such exercise of tyrannical power was 12* 137 138 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. a thing to be justified, a right thing, but because to sub. mit and to suffer wrong was, under all the circumstances, better- better for them, situated as they were- than to resist. "Vengeance is mine, I will repay, saith the Lord." Does this justify Nero? On the same principle, the Chris tian disciple was bidden to turn the other cheek to the hand that had already smitten, since it was better, on the whole,- better at least for him, as a Christian,- to suffer outrage patiently than to take his defence into his own hands. Does this justify acts of personal assault and violence? They who defend slavery on this ground, must, on the same principle, if they reason consistently, defend any system of civil oppression and tyranny, however arbitrary and unjust, and any personal violence inflicted by lawless and angry men upon the victims of their ferocity. In the well-expressed language of an able writer and moralist, Dr. Hickok: "This obedience was by no means required on the ground that slavery was righteous, and the master's authority morally valid. It would be more prudent for the slave to obey, and tend most to cultivate his piety. He was required to be obedient 'not only to the good and gentle, but also to the firoward;' even obedient where cruelty and wickedness led to the'buffeting' of the slave'for doing well.' It was expedient to obey; just as, when you cannot escape from a tiger, it is expedient not to provoke him. It by no means justifies the usurped authority. It was better for the slave to obey; and especially it would serve to augmnient piety, and recommend the religion of Him, who in his humiliation was smitten and'opened not his mouth."' Why not directly forbicd(len.-BBut why, it may be asked, was not the system directly forbidden, or -it least declared to be unjust and morally wonig, if snehll is illeed its true character? I reply, it is really forbiddenu by the DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. spirit and the precepts of Christianity - really, though not directly and explicitly. The rule to do unto others whatsoever we would that they should do unto us, as really forbids that involuntary servitude which exacts of a fellowbeing unrequited service, and robs him of all his dearest rights, as if the practice of such a wrong were mentioned by name, and specially prohibited. A reason doubtless existed for not thus designating it in so many words. It was a social evil, incorporated into the whole fabric of civil society and governmient. To have singled out the evil, and by direct precept to have prohibited it, would have been, perhaps, neither the wisest nor the surest mode of re dress. It would have been a direct interference of Chris tianity with civil government. In the language of Dr. Wayland: "If it had forbidden the evil, instead of subvert ing the principle,-if it had proclaimed the unlawfiilness of slavery, and taught slaves to resist the oppression of their masters,- it would instantly have arrayed the two parties in deadly hostility, throughout the civilized world. Its an nouncement would have been the signal of servile war; and the very name of the Christian religion would have been forgotten amidst the agitations of universal blood shed. The fact, under these circumstances, that the gospel does not forbid slavery, affords no reason to suppose that it does not mean to prohibit it; much less does it afford ground for belief that Jesus Christ intended to author ize it." The lfo(le of Red(ress. - We have been occupied in the p)receding pages with the discussion of the moral character of this institution of slavery. It is no part of the business ,)f the moralist, strictly speaking, to point out the best methods of redressing the wrongs and evils of society. This it is for others to do. One thing, however, I may properly say in this connection. Whatever nmeasures are 139 140 DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. adopted, looking to this end, must necessarily be gradual in their operation, in order wisely and well to accomplish their purpose. The social fabric is not to be rudely shaken, nor its whole structure ]rtdic.ally changed in a day. Time is requisite, and the slow grokvtll of principle. Much is to be hoped from the progress of society, and the gradual prev alence of more enlightened views, and of a loftier and purer morality. In proportion as society advances, and Christian ity obtains a firmer hold on the mind and heart of the race, this system, so utterly at variance with all just notions of right and duty, and so repugnant to the feelings of conmmon humanity, must and will g,radually disappe)car, as the shadows firom the mountain side, and the mists fiom the bosom of the lake, whenl the sun mounts the heavens in his strength. Progress of European Society. - If we look at the social organization of the European nations, we find them, in the course of centuries, passing through a series of chlanges, from the state of absolute servitude of the laboring classes, to that of more or less perfect equality and freedonm. For some two centuries or more after the Norman conquest, the greater portion of the cultivators of the soil in England were serfs, or villeii's, as they were then termed, bound to the soil, and owing service to the proprietor thereof. The peasant belonged to the soil, and, with all his family and descendants, fiom generation to generation, was at the disposal of the lord of the manor. These unlimited labor-rents were gradually, during the succeeding centuries, commuted into more definite services, and the peasant acquiied legal righlt, or copyhold, as it was termed, to tlhe lands whiclh lie cultivated. It is only about two lhundreid vears since the cultivator of the soil in England cease(d to be hleld in personal thraldom. In ln-ally patLs of (aermliy, serfdom still exists; in otlhers, DUTIES PERTAINING TO LIBERTY. the peasant is no longer attached to the soil, but, instead of unlimited service, pays his landlord some definite amount of labor as land-rent; in other cases, this is commituted for rent in grain or money, and the servitude beconmes.lmnost nominal. In Russia, the serf was little better than a slave, except that his service was limited. He was bound to work for the owner of the soil a certain number of days in the week, laboring for the rest of the time, for his own subsistence, on lands allotted for the purp)ose. Nor was it until the accession of the present government that this system was abolished. Senttime)zt of Paley.- Soon after the close of the strugrgle by which the American Colonics became independent of England, Archdeacon Paley, referring to the system of slavery, and to the part which the En,glish government had taken in upholdling it, made use of the following Ianguage, in his work on Moral Philosophy: "The great rev olution which has taken il)ace in the Western world may probably conduce (and who knows but that it was de signed) to accelerate the fall of this abominable tyranny; and now that this contest, and the passioins which attended it, are no more, there may succeed perhaps a season for reflecting, whether a legislature which had so long lent its assistance to the support of an institution replete with human misery, was fit to be trusted with an empire the most.extensive that ever obtained in any age or quarter of the world." Could this excellent moralist, after the lapse of three quarters of a century, be l)ermitted to look upon this Western world as it now is, and behold the present greatness and prosperity of the country that was then just commencing its career, as he beheld with astonishment this dark blot still uil)on our escutcheon, would he not, and with jutsti,e, repeat, with reference to our own nation, the 141 142 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. question then so forcibly put, with reference to the British government, "whether a legislature that had so long lent its assistance to the support of an institution replete withl human misery, was fit to be trusted with an empire" so extensive and powerful? CHAPTER III. DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. MAN has not only the right to life, and to liberty, but also to property, or the possession and enjoyment of whatever he may, by his own industry or good fortune, or the gift of others, have honestly acquired. Prominent amoiig the duties, therefore, which we owe to our fellow-men, - that is, to society,- are the duties which have respect to property. The principal topics to be considered are the right of property, the uses of such an institution, the modes in which it may be acquired, the different kinds of property, crimes against propelrty, and the various limitations of the right of property. ~ I. FOUNDATION OF THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. Labor and not Law. -Whatever man produces as the result of his own skill and labor, is properly his, and no one else has the right to take it from him. It is his property by a natural right. There is need of no law, or social organization and compact, in order to this. His title to use, possess, and enjoy what he has himself produced, by I DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 143 virtue of his own powers and his own industry, is just as good before as after, without as with, any such legislation or compact. Law and social organization, with its appliances, may confirm and protect him in his right, but do not create it. .)ifrecerpt Theories. - According to the view now taken, it is tile labor expended in originally acquiling, or subsequently inmproving any object of possession, that constitutes the right of property in the same. In the case of land, the labor of cultivation renders it more valuable, and so confers the right of continued possession on him who has created that value. This is the view maintained by Locke, and many others. Another view of the matter is, that, inasmuch as God, the Creator of all things, prqvidcd the gifts of nature for the use of all his creatures, therefore every one has a right originally to all hlie needs. In this manner, land, as wcll as other things, comes to bc the property of the individual. This is a rule of somewhat indefinite application; and if carried out, would lead, perhaps, to the disorganization of society as at present constituted. As regards strictly the gifts of nature, it is doubtless true that they were intended for all. Light, air, rain, sunshine, and the like, are firee to all, and in their nature cannot, under ordinary circumstances, be appropriated. But it is otherwise with that on which, by my toil or skill, I have conferred a value. Water is free to all; but not the water of the well that I have dug for my own convenience. Fire is a commodity which nia ture lplaccs within the reach of all; but not the fire which my laboir has kindled for my own use. So land may orig inally have been free to the first comer; but when he has once taken possession, and expended labor and created value, it is not free to others, so long as he chooses to occupy it. 144 DUTIES PElRTAINING TO PROPERTY. Paley's View.- Paley makes the foundation of property to be the law of the land, as carrying, out the will and in tention of the Creator. "It is the intention of God that the produce of the earth be applied to the use of man. This intention cannot be fulfilled without establishing property. It is consistent, therefore, with his will that property be established. The land cannot be divided into separate property without leaving it to the law of the country to regulate that division. It is consistent, therefore, with the same will that law should regulate the division; and, consequently,'consistent with the will of God,' or'right,' that I should possess that share which these regulations assign me." This resolves all right into the will of God, -which is Paley's theory of right, -and it also supposes that the laws of the land are in all cases an expression of that will, - which is by no means certain. Now, it is perfectly clear that law regulates the conveyance of property, defines what is and what is not property, maintains and secures to the righltfill owner that which properly belongs to him. It maintains and defends, but it does not create the right to own. It regulates rather than originates that right. Constitutiowi of thae Mid. - The right, in itself considered, or in the abstract, is found, if I mistake not, in the nature and constitution of the human mind, -just as society itself originates from that same nature and constitution. This, indeed, reduces itself ultimately into the divine will; inasmuch as the nature and constitution of men areic fi'om God, and it was for him to fonrm us with what nature, and endow us with what propensities, he pleased(. Still, we need go no firther than to the constitution of humI an natra'e to discover the origin of the principle in question. The desire to possess, to approp)riate, lies among the native and implanted principles of the mind, DUTIES PPRTAINING TO PROPr,RTY. t45 It slhows itself in earliest life. The child apl)Iopiia.tes to I!iinself the toys tlatt are given him, and feels injured if tlcy are taken firom him by another. The structure of language shows that this is a universal principle. Whereever we finl in human speech the use of possessive pro. nouns, or other forms of language fullfilling that office, we find the expression of this principle. MAlen, universally, fceel that there is a right violated, a wrong done, in taking by violence or fraud that which has been appropriated by another. Hence, they demand not mere restitution, but the punishment of the offender. But while we seek in the structure of the mind itself the origin and foundation of the right of property in general-of the right to appropriate, in itself consideredthe condition on which that right depends-i. e., the right to appropriate this or that thing, in any given caseis the circumstance already pointed out: namely, that labor has been originally bestowed in the acquisition of these thiings, and value created as the result of that labor, to which value the laborer is justly entitled, as something he has himself produced. Objections. -If it be said that we possess many things, which we call property, on which we have not bestowed labor, - many values which we have not ourselves created, as, for example, property inherited or bequeathed, or the gifts of firiendship, -I reply, these values were originally acquired or created by labor; they became the property of the original owner in that way; and the right of possession has been conferred by him on the present possessor. The only exception to this rule, which occurs to my mind, is the accident of discovery: as when, walking by the bank of a stream, I find a piece of gold ore, or a pearl, amrnong its sands. In this case, there is certainly no labor 13 I 1I6 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. bestowed on the acquisition further than that of picking up and apl)propiating what I have discovere(l. Thle tct of appropriation constitutes my right in this case, atd lholds good as against others, on tle ground that no one else has bestowed labor on the things in question, nn* therefore no one else has any claim to themn. Were it otlherwise,were the treasure found not a natural p-iodctit, but the result of human labor, as, e. g., a bracelet of pearls, or a purse of gold coined for use, - my (is(ovey of tlhe article wolll(d not constitute a riglit oi l)ossessiol-.',gainst tlhe claim of the real owner. E ven in thle case sUll)osed,(l tl}e owner of the soil in which the gold ole or th-e jewels is found, nmay preseit a counter claim, on the ground( tlat, in purchasing the soil, he purchased wl.hatevei value it may produce or contain. The soil itself is his property, and no one else has a right to take away fi'om it any of its values. In like mannieri, were a meteorite to fall firom the sky upon my land, my right to that value would depend not merely, or so much, upon the accident of discovery, as upon my previous right to the premises, - a right purchased by labor in some form. Vietew of Whactely.- Archbishop Whately, in his Logic, has made use of this very illustration to prove the opposite doctrine, viz., that the right of property does not depend, ultimately, on labor. The labor expended in the production of values is, according to him, not essential to the existence of value and to property in the same, but is merely accide )ttcal, -a circumstance that, indeed, usually, but not always or necessarily, accompanies the possession of wealth. The meteorite that falls in my yard has a value quite independent of human labor. It seemis to me, however, that in this instance, Whately, while attempting to cori'ect a popular fallacy, as lie regards t, has llimself f.allen into a still more serious error. Ir we DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 147 look at the real wealth of the world, the chief values thait constitute the property of men, we certainly do find theii to be, in great prolportion, the result of human labor. TIhe exceptions are so few and so slight, as compared with the \whole amount, that they scarcely deserve to be taken into the account; and instead of calling labor an acci(let(il circunmstance sometimes accompanying the possession of' wealth, it were certainly much nearer the truth to call it the rule, and its exceptions the accident. Relatioit of the State to private Proj)erty.-According to the view of some, the state is the supreme and ultimiate proprietor and controller of all property. The natural right must, in all cases, be held subordinate to the public authority. It is for the state to determine what shall be considered as the property of every citizen, and no man can hold any property, or'call it his own, except as under the law of the land. All individual right is thus resolved into state right. Such is the view maintained by some able writers, amnong others by Dr. Ilickok. According to this view, the individual right to property is derived fromi the state. The natural right is no right unless the state sanctions it. This view seems to destroy individual right and liberty,- to merge the individual citizen, with all his rights and powers, in the state,- thus making the state all in all, as in that theory of political organization which Plato has left us. In reality, the state confers no right, as to property, which did not previously exist, and which would not llavee existed even had there been no such thing as a state. It confirms and establishes existing rights. It regulates the sale and transfer of property. It inquires into the validity of titles and the terms of contract, and takes care that those terms shall be fulfilled. The state is merely a social organization, contrived for the purpose of more effectually 148 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. securing and maintainin g t he rights and liberties of the whole body of individual citizens, -in other words, the public good. It has no power, except that of the individual arms that compose its aggregate strength; no rights or autlhority, except such as may be conferred on it by the body politic. It owns, and can own, no propei'ty, except such as belongs to the citizens that constitute the state, either in tlheir private, individual capacity, or as a public body. Whatever right or control of property the state has, it derived originally from the people. In order to carry out the purposes for which the state is created, it must have control and disposal of so much of the public property as is necessary to the subsistence, defence, and well-being of the state; must have power to lay out roads, levy taxes,' etc.; and, whenever, in pursuance of such objects, the public claim comes into conflict with individual claim, the latter must yield to the former, on the principle that the majority govern. When, for example, the land held by any citizen is needed for some public purpose, as a road, for instance, the state has the right to take it fiom him for that purpose; but not without equivalent to the full value of the property taken. Otherwise, government becomes a despotism, and there is no longer security for individual right. ~ II. -ADVANTAGES OF THE INSTITUTION OF PROPERTY. Granting the right, which has been already discussed, the question may still arise, Of what use is the institution of property, or private possession? Why may not society hold its goods in common, every man taking fi'om the common stock that which he needs for his own present wants, and that only? Why should one particula.r por DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 149 tion of the soil, for example, be set off to my share, with its various products, and another to my neighlbor? What advantage results from such distribution? Cositrib~ttes to the Comfort a,dl IJl()piness of JXan. That there are some disadvantages resulting fi'om the distribution of property, cannot be denied. On the other lhand, there are many and obvious advantages; prominent among which must be reckoned the contribution thus made to the comfort and happiness of the race. Man is so constituted, as we have already seen, that he naturally desires to possess, andl call his own, the objects that min ister to his wants. He enjoys that which is his own and not another's. The waters firom his own spring, the fruit from his own tree, that he has himself planted and nurtured, the game which his own bow has brought down, or his own net captured, are sweeter and pleasanter than any other. He not only enjoys more what be thus possesses, but he possesses more in consequence of this arrangemnent. Were there no such thing as property, there would be no division of labor; every man would be obliged to hunt, and fish, and cook, for himself; to make his own clothes, and his own hut, or tent; to provide for all his own wants. lie would, in consequence, be very poorly provided. His implements of labor would be rude and clumsy; his conveniences of living, scanty. His time and attention being divided among so many pursuits, he would acquire little skill in any of them. By devoting himself to some one art or profession, he becomes expert in that; and by exchanging the products of his skill and labor for other commodities, which in like nianner have been produced by other laborers, the objects of enjoyment at his com mand become greatly augmented. But this implies prop 13* 150 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. erty in what is thus produced, as otherwise there can be no rioght of exchange. A4qmerats the Piro(1cce of the -Ec'th. -It is a further advantage of the arran.gemient in question, tThat it greatly increases the products of the soil. In order to fertility, and tile gieatest productiveness of the earth, therc mnust be labor and due cultivation. It produces little spontaneously. But where there is no property in the soil and its products, where they are the common possession of all, where those who do not labor share equally with those who do, there is no incitement to labor - no itniducement to put forth the exertion requisite to the proper cultivation of the soil. Tillage will inevitably be neglected, and the community will grow poor together, in proportion to that neglect. The products of the earth, as every one knows, are our chief source of national wealth - the foundation, in fact, on which other modes and sources of p)roductive ness must ultimately rest. The effect of leaving land and produce to be held in common, is seen in the neglect of agriculture by the North American native tribes — gathering a precarious and scanty supp)ort from an amount of territory sufficient, under proper management, to feed and clothe a hundred fold greater population. It has always been observed, also, that where, amniong civilized communities, a piece of ground or other property has been held in common, it is of little use to any body. The fruit of a tree that grows by the roadside, and is regarded as public property, is seldom a.llowed to come to maturity. It would be much the same with all other products, in like circumstances. Promotes Civilization. - Without individual possession and right of property, there can be no division of labor, as I have sa,id; and without division of labor, there can be little progress in civilization. The advantages of civ. DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 151 iltzed over savage life, depend in a great measure on those mechanic arts which supply the conveniences and luxuries of refined society, and which, in turn, (,an never be carried to any degree of perfection, where the workman is not permitted to derive the benefit of his own skill and industry. The state of Europe during the middle ages, when despotic power prevailed, when the laborer belonged to the soil that he cultivated, when the rights of private property were little regarded, and the wish of the strongest was law, as compared with the state of the same countries at the present day, when peace and constitutional law have given security to private rights, is a striking illustration of this truth. We see the same thing illustrated also in the present state of Syria, and other countries of Asia and the East. Despotic power prevails, and the laborer is not sure that he shall be permitted to enjoy the product of his field. His grain, his flocks, his produce of whatever kind, are liable to be taken firom him at any moment, by the rapacity and extortion of the lawless agents of government. There is, consequently, no inducement to labor, more than is necessary for absolute subsistence. Agriculture is neglected, and the mechanic arts. Society lingers in the twilight of barbarism.' On the contrary, wherever, under free and well-ordered gov. ernments, we find the rights of private property respected and secured, there we find the arts and agriculture flourishing, property accumulating, society rapidly advancing. Ie)quality of Distribution. - But, while the institution of property has its obvious advantages, it is not to be denied that certain disadvantages, and perhaps abuses, flow from it. Nothing seems, at first sight, more unjust than the extreme inequality with which property, the actual wealth of the world, is distributed among men. One man 152 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY.' has a for'tune, another is reduced to beggary. One rolls in luxury, and counts his millions, and mealsures I,is estates by the square mnile; another toils for the meriest I)ittance, and barely subsists on the soil which he cultivates for another. Nor is it always the most industrious, the most talented, or the most deserving, that reap the largest reward. The weak, the profligate, the idle, the vicious, may be, and often are, the favorites of fortune, revelling upon the proceeds of the sweat and toil of honest industry. Paley's Illuestration. - This anomaly has been very forcibly represented by Dr. Paley, in the well-known allegory of the flock of pigeons: "If you should see a flock of pigeons in a field of corn, and if (instead of eaclh picking where and what it liked, taking just what it wanted, and no more) you should see ninety-nine of them gathering all they got into a heap; reserving nothing for themselves but the chaff and the refuse; keeping this heap for onethat, the weakest, perhaps worst pigeon of the flock; sitting round and looking on all the winter, whilst this one was devouring, throwing about, and wasting it; and if a pigeon more hardy and hungry than the rest, touched a grain of the hoard, all the others flying upon it, and tearing it to pieces; -if you should see this, you would see notlinig more than what is every day practised and established among men. Among men you see the ninety-nine, toiling and scraping together a heap of superfluities for one (and this one, too, oftentimes the feeblest and worst of the whole set-a child, a woman, a madman, or a fool); getting nothing for themselves but the coarsest of the provision which their own industry produces; looking quietly on while they see the fiuits of all their labor spent or spoiled; and if one of the number take or touch a particle of the hoard, the others joining against him, and hanging him for the theft." DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 153 Fallacy of this Statement. -It is important to be borne in mind that, in the present constitution of things, all property represents, and is the product of labor, performed at some time, and by somebody. The labor expended in the product may not have been put forth by the pres ent possessor of the product, but at some time long pre vious, and by some one whom he has never seen. It may have come into his hands by inheritance from some remote ancestor. However that may be, it is none the less the product of labor. So far as other men are concerned, it is the same thing as if the present possessor had acquired it by his own industry and skill. So much industry, so much toil, so much skill, lie embodied and represented in this wealth which is accumulated in the coffers of the present proprietor. His lordly mansion, his nobl. acres, his fine grounds andl estates, are the product for which a full price has been paid, in that which is the ultimate price of all requisitions, viz., human labor. The illustration of Paley overlooks this fact. The pigeon which he describes seated in the midst of the flock, enjoys the products of the labors of those around him, to which he has no right. It is not his labor; it is not his product. He has no claims to it; it belongs to those who are engaged in heaping it together. But in the distribution of property among men, it is not so; the rich man has that only which he has acquired by his own toil and economy, or which has rightfully descended to him from those who in the first instance acquired it in this manner. He has a claim and a right to all that he calls his. The poor man, on the other hand, has equal claim and right to all that he produces, be it more or less; and, so far fiom hanging him if he touches it, or preventing him from the full enjoyment of it, society protects him in that right, So far as designed to represent the ule 154 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPIE'TY. qual distribution of property, then, the illustration of Dr. Paley, while amusing and ingenious, is by no means a fair and correct representation of the case. The argument which it conveys is sophistical. ~ III.-MODES IN WHICH PROPERTY MAY BE ACQUIRED. The First Ownershi.- The first ownership of all things lies with the Creator of all, and is his gift to his creatures. So far as I have need of these things, and no one else has, by any reason, a higher claini to them, I may regard that which I find ready at my hand, and adapted to my wants, as the gift of the Creator to me, his creature. That I need it, and can have it without interfering with the rights of others, in itself constitutes in some sort a title to the thing. Such is the case as reg,ards the spontaneous productions of the earth, game running wild in the forest, unclaimed lanids, etc. Such, in the primitive state of society, was the case with most of those values which were in that rude stage of civilization possessed. Acquisitioni by Efort. - But, aside fiom this primitive acquisition by gift fiomn the Creator, the chief mode in which property may be acquired is by labor. As society advances, and man's wants increase, he no longer depends on those spontaneous productions of the earth found ready at his hand, and which may be regarded as the direct gift of God to man. The cave which has hitherto sheltered him, is exchanged for a more comfortable abode; the simple fruits that have satisfied his hunger, are replaced by food of greater variety and abundance; the skins of animals, that constitute as yet his clothing, are laid aside fo)r some more convenient apparel; and these advances are all the product of labor. To obtain these better accommodations DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 155 hlie fells the forest, he builds, he tills the ground, he plants, he weaves, he spins; and what he thus acquires as the result and reward of labor, becomes his own, because the labor with which it was procured was his own; and no one has a right to take it fi'om hilm without his consent, and without just compensation. There is, however, a limitation to be here considered. He who acquires property by labor is entitled to the pro ceeds of thalt labor only, and not to the proceeds of those previous values on which that labor may be expendedl. If I cultivate land belonging to another, ol make use of tools and impllements which are the )property of another, this land, these tools and implements, are already existilng values, onI which the labor of others has previously been bestowed; and when I unite my labor with thleirs, as I do in making use of these things, I am entitled manifestly not to the whole, but only to a share of the proceeds. It is right that hlie who has bestowed labor on the land, in acquiring possession of it, and preparing it for cultivation, and on the tools and implements which hlie has invented and manufactured, and which I have used, should receive the benefit of his labor, as well as I of mine. Acq?tisitiogn by Exchange. That which I have acquired, and which is rilghtfully my own, I may not choose to keep. It may be more in quantity than I need for my own use; or I may prefer some other value in place of it. I may part with it, therefore, for something in return; and this is excha(tge. This is still another mode of acquisition; and whllat is thus acq(llire(l, becomes my property as really and rightfully as if my own 1;,bor had beell explended originally and directly ill its )pro(iuction. A gr,c:lt 1)a.t of the actual possessions of any man in civilized society are thus acquired; comparatively few of 156 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. the things which he calls his own are the direct pro)duct of his own industry. For the most part, we neither build our own houses, nor make our own garments, nor prepare our own food, but employ the labor of others for these purposes. Acquisition by Gift and Inheritance.-Another mode of acquisition is by the conferring of value gratuitously, as when I receive a gift from a friend, or when property is left me by inheritance. The rightful owner of any possession may, if he chooses, part with the same without receiving an equivalent in return. It is at his disposal, and he may convey the right of ownership now vested in him to whomsoever he pleases. When this is done informally, it is called a gift. When property is conveyed by will, or by due forms of law, at the decease of the original owner, it is termed inheritance. Qtuestion as to Right of Possession. - Does mere possession, in any case, confer the right to possess? Suppose I have, by dishonest means, obtained possession of valuable property; suppose, moreover, that the rightful owners are all dead, and that no one has now any better claim than myself to this property-that is, no one has anv claim at all; -does my possession, the fact that it is now in nmy hands, entitle me to keep possession of it? Dr. Wayland answers yes; I have no moral right to the property, but I have the right to exclude others from it, who have no better claim than I have. This may be; and yet I may have no10 right to retain possession of it myself. The state, in such a case, becomnes the proper recipient. I may not be under obligation to give uip the property to any individual claimant, but I may be uiier obligation to give it up to society for the benefit of the whole, The mere fact thait DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 157 thie property is now in my hands gives me no right to retain possession, inasmuch as it came into my hands unfawfully. There may be cases where simple possession entitles the holder to retain; as where no right of another is violated in the original acquisition; where the object acquired is, previous to its acquisition, the property of no one individual, as in the case of fruits growing by the roadside, or nuts in the forest, or game on the prairie, or land lying unclaimed in a new and uninhabited territory. In such a case, simple possession holds good against all subsequent occupancy by another. But such is not the case now supposed. The principal modes in which property may be acquired, are those iiow stated - viz., by the direct gift of the Creator, by labor of acquisition and production, by exchange, by donation and inheritance. ~ IV. -DIFFERENT KINDS OF PROPERTY. Personal and Real. It has become usual to divide property into two kinds or classes - personal, and real; the latter including possessions in land, houses, etc.- whatever is in its nature a fixture, not easily moved; the former including all other species of property, such as admits of transfer firom place to place. That which we term real estate, was not probably, at first, recognized as property at all, but became so only as society and civilization progressed. The cave that sheltered the wanderer, and the pasture that fed his flocks, were his only so long as he occupied them. After that, they were free to the next comer. History of Property.- The first objects of property were probably the fruits of the earth, the spontaneous pro 14 158 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. ducts of the soil, which became the property of the indi. vidual by the simple act of gathering and appropriation to his own use. The labor of acquiring these fruits might have been very slight; but it was sufficient to constitute a difference between him who had, and him who had not, in - this manner acquired possession. Soon the products of the chase would be added to the list of rightful possessions; and these, as they would require more labor and skill in the acquisition, would for that reason belong, by a still clearer right, to the individual who had acquired them. In like manner, tools and implements for the chase, or for the gathering and preparing of the fruits of the earth, tents, weapons of protection, and whatever of the like sort was early found necessary to the comfort and subsistence of man, would come to be regarded as property. In the progress of time, flocks and herds of domestic animals would constitute a portion of the wealth of man. Not until the country became somewhat thickly inhabited, and man began to turn his attention to the cultivation of the soil, would land itself come to be regarded as property; and then only as each occupant expended labor on the soil, and mingled his products with it, would he acquire a igliht of individual appropriation. Accordingly, among the earlier and less civilized nations, we find no trace of property in land. The North Amierican native tribes seem to have known nothing of it. The Scythians, while they appropriated cattle and horses, left their land in common. When Cesar invaded Britain, lie seems to have found no traces of property in land. This species of property came to be a permanent possession, probably, not until the organization of society, and of civil government, fixing by law the right of the individual to DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 159 the soil he cultivated. Previously, it was property only by possession and actual occupancy. Property as Regulated by Lat. - Inasmuch as land is less obviously the property of an individual than are those possessions which he can carry with him firom place to place, and as the right of ownelrship is, therefore, maintained with more difficulty, this species of property is made more directly and peculiarly the object of legislation. The ancient law of England regards land as the chief part of pi)roperty, all other things being treated as only appendages to persons. Hence the distinctive terms, real property, and personal property. * The cultivator and the proprietor of the soil are not always the same person, nor of the same class. In such a case the rights of each are determined by law- the cutltivator giving to the proprietor a certain share of the proceeds, which is termed rent. This may be given in produce, as in Asia, where the proprietor, usually the sovereign, receives one-fifth, commonly, of whatever is raised on the land; or, it may be in labor, as in Russia and Germany, where the peasant pays his rent by working a definite portion of his time for the exclusive benefit of the landlord. The cultivator is then termed a serf. In other countries of Europe one-half the produce of the land goes to the owner of the soil, one-half to the cultivator. In England, between the landlord and the cultivator,; we find an intermediate class, termed farmers, who give to the owner of the soil his rent, and to the laborei his wages, retaining what is left after these deductions as their own profit. Feudal Systemn. - There prevailed for some centuries in Europe, a system of land tenure, according to which the 160 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. proprietor held himself bound to protect the laborer as against other persons, and the laborer in turn was bound to render to his superior certain fixed and valuable services. The relation of the two was one of mutual dependence, the lord requiring the service of the vassal, and the latter the protection of the lord. On this condition the vassal held certain lands as, in a modified sense, his ownpaying fixed dues to the lord, and yielding also personal service as a soldier in arms. The land thus held by the laborer was termed a Fetect, or Fee; hence the expression, Feudal System. The land thus held was not the absolute property of the laborer, however, nor yet even of the lord; but its ultimate ownership vested in the sovereign. The laborer who held no fees or feuds, was termed a Villein, and was little better than a serf. ~ V. - CRIMES AGAINST PROPERTY. There are three principal modes in which the right of property may be violated. One may take what belongs to another, clandestinely, without the owner's knowledge. This is theft. Or, he may take it by violence, as when a highwayman presents a pistol and demands money, or when a band of armed men storm a castle, or ravage a territory, and plunder its treasures. This is robbery. Or, yet again, the consent of the owner may be fraudulently obtained, by deceiving him as to the real nature, or the market value, of the commodity offered. Theft. -To take the property of another without his knowledge, and fuill, free consent, with design to appropriate it to our own use, is a violation of the right of property, and is justly regarded as a crime. It matters little whether the amount thus clandestinely appropriated be large or DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 161 small, whether it be of great or trifling value, whether its loss will be severely felt by the owner or not; in any case it is a violation of right, and, as regards the moral character of the act, it is essentially one and the same. Even if it should so happen that the owner has no objection to the transfer, still, so long as we presume upon this willingness, without first obtaining his consent, we are guilty of theft. Robbery. -In case of violence offered for the purpose of obtaining consent not otherwise given, the crime is aggravated. The double offence is committed, of violence to the person, and violation of the property. I have no right to threaten the life or personal safety of another; no right to take his property; still less a right to accomplish the latter object by means of the former. The offence is aggravated, and deserves, and is everywhere held to deserve, the severest punishment. To compel consent by means of violence, is a greater crime than to take the property by force, and without the semblance of consent. Cheating. - But it is not enough that consent be attained, and that it be freely given; this may be, and still the right of property be violated. That consent must be honestly and not fraudulently obtained, else the transaction is criminal. The greater part of the crimes against property are of this nature. The number of burglars, thieves, highway robbers, is small, in comparison with the numiber of those who, in business transactions, hesitate not to cheat and defraud their fellow-men. The latter are as really guilty of crime, though not perhaps,'in some respects, of so great a crime, as the former; nor is the one a more respectable and honorable mode of procedure than the other. The command, "Thou shalt not steal." is as really broken in the one case as the other. Nor has 14* 162 DUTIES PI'ERTRAINING TO PROPERTY. hlie who cheats his fellow in a small way, and under cover of a business transaction, the same apology for his crime that the more daring offender may often urge. The man who breaks into my house, or who demands my purse on the highway, may be driven to his desperate course by want and absolute starvation. The man who, pretending fair and honorable commerce, cheats me out of a few pennies, can plead no such apology for his dishonesty and meanness. [oles of CAleati?,g. - There are various modes in which this species of dishonesty may be practised. It may be done by presenting for sale goods that are damaged, or in some way inferior to what they seem and are taken to be, deficient in quality or in quantity, a poorer article than we represent, and than we intend that the buyer shall suppose. This is as really a fraud as if we were slyly to abstract just so much in value from the pocket of the purchaser. Another mode is to mislead the buyer as to the market price of the article sold. When a man devotes himself to the business of exchanges, he is understood to possess some skill in the-matter of purchasing, and to receive a fail- compensation for that skill, as well as for his time and trouble; he is understood also to furnish goods at the ordinary market prices. If, now, his skill in any particular instance fails him; if he finds that he has purchased at a given price what is not really worth so much; or if, the article being good, the price falls while it is upon his hands, he has no right to remunerate himself at the expense of his customers -no right to take advantage of their ignorance, and sell to them at a price beyond the real value, on the ground that it cost him at that rate. This is to deceive the customer, and, in reality, to defraud himn. If the trader is at liberty to reap the benefit of a rise of prices while the goods are in his possession, he is, DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 163 on the same principle, bound to give the buyer the benefil of an accidental decline of prices. If, on the other hand, hle adopts the rule of selling as he bought, he is bound to apply it equally to both cases, and give the customer the benefit of a purchase below the present market price. It is always understood that the trader furnishes his goods at the ruling price in the market. Hle takes care to have this understood. Hlis credit and success depend on it. ilence he is bound to fulfill an expectation in itself so reasonable and universal, and which he has himself contributed to form. This obligation is violated, not merely by assuring the customer that he can procure the article in question nowhere at a cheaper rate, -which, in the case supposed, would be a direct falsehood,- but equally by silence; since where nothing is said, the buyer presumes, and has a right to presume, that he is giving only the ordinary market price. False Information. - Closely allied to this very common species of dishonesty is another-the circulating false information respecting the value, quantity, or price of any kind of goods, with a view to effect the sale; as, for ex. ample, when the stock broker, by false reports circulated on'Change, seeks to raise or depress the price of stocks; or when the speculator, monopolizing a given article, conveys the impression of a scarcity, when in reality there is an abundance of that commodity. This latter method of procedure becomes the more culpable when it affects, not the luxuries and conveniences, but the very necessaries of life, as in the case of monopolies of flour and grain. .Monopoly. -The question may here arise, whether, aside from any false impression thus conveyed of a scarcity which does not really exist, the monopolizing an article of trade for the purpose of raising the price, is in itself a 164 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. species of dishonesty. Suppose a merchant, for example, to purchase all the ivory, or all the indigo, or saltpetre in the market; suppose him to extend his transactions in this line to all the commercial cities in the country, pur chasing all that can be procured, wherever found; slp)pose him then to raise the price of the article, depending on the demand to ensure a sale at the advanced rate. Where, it may be asked, is the dishonesty of such a proceeding? Everything is fair and open in the transaction. The mnerchlant has simply to say, I hold in my possession such and such goods, and you can have them if you like at such a price. It is true they have been often sold at a much lower price, but they are not now to be obtained except at the rate mentioned. Buy, or not, as you please. What is there of dishonesty in this? I cannot see that there is, properly speaking, any dishonesty or fraud in such a proceeding. It is not deception; it is not cheating. The goods are offered at what is, for the time, the market value,-that is, they cannot, for the present, be obtained for less, in other markets. In a word, the merchant in question has it in his power to fix the market value of the goods, and does so. This he certainly has the right to do, in the case supposed. If the articles in question were necessaries of life, he would have no moral right to establish a monopoly, and then fix on them a price that should place them beyond the reach of all except the rich. But such is not the case supposed. But, while we may not class such a transaction with the various forms of dishonest dealings, it must be admitted that public sentiment, and the common sense of mankind, very generally disapprove of this method of procedure, as not altogether just and honorable. It is taking what seems to be an undue advantage of the community. The profession of the merchant is one that is supposed to be DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. 165 for the public good. He comes between the producer and the consumer, for the advantage of both. It is better for both that there should be a class of men Nwlo shall devote themselves to the business of exchanges. But when the merchant, taking advantage of his position, puts upon his goods such a price that the community is rather injured than benefited by his transactions, no reason can be shown why such a business or profession should exist. The public good requires that it should cease to be. Dishoiiesty of the Btyer.- It is hardly necessary to remark that the same rule applies to the buyer as to the seller. He is under obligation to pay a fair profit to the trader, in remuneration for the skill, labor, and capital employed by the latter in the business of purchasing; and any attempt to defraud him of this remuneration, by any of the tricks of trade, or by underrating the true value of the goods, is a species of dishonesty. Excuses. -The various modes of dishonest dealing which have been mentioned, are firequently justified, by those who employ them, on the ground that such practices are nearly universal; that if they did not practise them, others would; that the competition is so great, that they could do no business; that in no other way can they live, and support their families. I reply: these excuses even granting the validity of the statements - make the practices in question none the less immoral and dishonest. If every other person employed in the traffic cheats his customers, by giving them light weight and short measure, diluted and adulterated liquors, damaged in place of perfeet articles, or by selling at a higher than the true market value, it is none the less a fraud for me to do the same. If the competition is such that I cannot carry on the 166 DUTIES PERTAINING TO PROPERTY. business without resorting to such artifices, it is quite time that I was out of it, and in some more honest employment. As to the argument from the necessity of living and supporting one's family, "it is obvious," says Dr. Wayland, "that, were this plea allowed, it would put an end to all questions of morals; for there never was an iniquity so infamous as not to find multitudes who were ready to justify it on this plea." Limitations of the Righty of Prop)erty.- In this connection may be noticed certain questions respecting the limitation of the right of property. Cases may arise in which there shall seem to be a necessity for taking the property of others without their consent. Of the right of the state to take so much of the land of any citizen, with the buildings and improvements thereon, as may be necessary for the public good, in laying out roads and constructing other public works, I have already spoken. Such right must be conceded, and that irrespective of the owner's consent, though not without a fair equivalent. On the same principle, the individual is bound to meet his given proportion of the public expenses, in the shape of taxes; and if he refuses to do so, the state may take so much of his property as is necessary for this purpose, without his consent. But, aside from these and the like instances, in which the state comes into conflict with the citizen, cases may arise in which the private individual, or a company of individ nals, may find it necessary, in order to the preservation of life, to appropriate the property of another. A ship is in a storm at sea, and, in order to the preservation of all on board, it may be necessary to throw overboard a portion of her cargo. That, however, is private property, and to obtain the consent of the owner is, under the circumstances, impossible In such a case, no one can hesitate. Life is DUTIES PERTrAINING TO Ise PUTATION. 167 more valuable than property; and even if it were not, the property fares no worse than it would if the ship went down with all on board. It will be lost, in either case. Nothing is gained to the owner by the attempt to save it. In like manner, and on the same principle, if the provisions fail in a ship, and the passengers are in danger of starving, there can be no question that they have the right to appropriate so much as may be necessary of the ship's cargo to their own support. These, and the like, are cases of necessity, against which there can be no law. Jurists accordingly, both ancient and modern, have admitted that, utinder such circumstances, the right of property must give way to higher rights and interests. Whether, under other and ordinary circumstances, a starving man has the right to take food not belonging to him, may admit of question, inasmuch as society usually makes provision foi his relief in another mode. CHAPTER IV. DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. .Relnitatto( a l -ight. -Among the springs of human action, there is none more powerftil, or more universal, than the love of esteem. It has its seat in the constitution of our nature. Reputation is one of the goods which every man desires to get and to keep; among the first and greatest, indeed, of those goods - than which no possession is more valuable, no right more sacred. A good name is better than gold. No wealth can purchase it; once lost, no treasure can replace it. Hence it is held always among 168 DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. the dearest and most precious of earthly possessions. Its loss may entail the most serious consequences. Society is bound to protect every man in the possession and enjoyment of whatever justly belongs to him; hence it is bound to protect him in this, as one of his most valuable and sacred rights. This is a principle recognized by the laws of civilized society, both ancient and modern. "Est enim famae, ut et vitae, habenda ratio"- Reputation, as well as life, is to be regarded in law - was a maxim of Roman jurisprudence. The laws of England and of our own country, in like manner, take cognizance of injuries affecting the reputation, no less than of injuries affecting the property and the life. There is reason and justice in this. One who by industry, skill, and patient toil, has built up a fortune, is justly entitled to the possession and enjoyment of the same. If now, by the same industry and skill, he has acquired a reputation, as artist, merchant, or professional man, is he not by every principle of justice and right entitled equally also to that? And is not the latter often much the more valuable acquisition of the two? To diminish the esteem in which he is held, and rob him wholly or in part of his justly earned reputation, is to inflict on him a much more serious injury than to rob him of money. The violation of the right now under consideration is known under the general name of slander; and in treating of this crime, it will be to our purpose to define whalt this term properly includes; to inquire further what the law of reputation requires and forbids, and in what cases it is allowable to speak to the injury of others; and, finally, to show reasons why we should not, without cause, speak evil of any one. These topics will be severally discussed in the following sections DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. 169 ~ I. - SLANDER DEFINED. I understand this term to include all forms of detraction. It is the utterance of anything calculated to injure the good name and character of another, without due cause, whether maliciously, or inconsiderately. The utterance may be nmalicious-designed to injure. All enemy, or a rival, may take that way to gratify his revenge, or to pull down a comnpetitor whom he cannot successfully encounter in a more open and honorable way. This is the height of meanness, and a crime of no ordinary turpitude. Or the act may be an inconsiderate and thoughtless one. There may be no special, set design to injure another's reputation. The mere love of gossip, the desire to say or to hear some new thing, and especially the gratification which it affords to one's self-esteem and self-complacency to dwell upon the foibles and weaknesses of others, may be the real motive and spring of action; and the injury which is to result to the good name and character of the person spoken of, may not occur to the speaker at the moment. This is, however, none the less slander. There may be a difference in the degree of guilt in the two cases, but both are crimes. The consequences are much the same in either case. We cannot excuse ourselves by saying, the mischief was not intended. A proper regard for duty, and for the rights of others, would have led us to pause before we uttered the injurious words, and to look at the consequences of what we were about to utter. Our forgetfillness and thoughtlessness of consequences by no means firees us from responsibility from those consequences, be they what they may. Nor is it essential that the thl)ing said should be false, in order to constitute it a slander. It may be a true thing; yet, if maliciously spoken, with design to injure, or even thoughtlessly uttered, without due and sufficient cause 15 170 DIJTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. why it should be said, it is none the less slander. No one has a moral right to injure his fellow, without cluse, cvill by publishing what is strictly true of him. Doubtless there is more guilt ill uttering falsehood maliciously, than in uttering tr?eth maliciously; more guilt in intentional than in inconsiderate slander; all these, however, are forms of slander, —all are crimies. Perhaps the most common folrm of slander is that where one seeks to detract firom the good opinion whiclh a fiiend, or benefictolr, or the communlity, elt(lt:,ii of a person whom he dislikes; to aw.aik:n slluslicion or distrust witlh regard to him,, a,nd so change his relation to the I,atties concerned, and to society. In a thlous.nd ways this mischief may be dlone, this object accoInl)lish(el. With due secrecy, and injunctions of secrecy upon those to whom the disclosure is made; with every precaution to avoid detection; what is more, with great al)parenit relucta)ce to make the statements which are made, and with professions of fi'iendship for the injured party, may the work be done. These are the usual subterfuges and pretences of the slanderer. All such disguises are more or less hypocritical, and, as Paley has well remarked, they are all so many aggravations of the offence, inasmuch as they indicate deliberation and design. ~ II.- WHAT THE LAW OF REPUTATION FORBIDS. From the definition already given of slander, as includ, ing all forms of detraction, the rule itself, of which this is a violation, becomes evident. The law of reputation forbids us, in general, to say anything, without imperative reasons, that shall detract from the good name and reputation of another; it requires us, on the other hand, to sustain that good name and reputation by all due and proper means. DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. 171 _aking public the Ftautlts of Others. -More specifically, it forbids us needlessly and without cause to give publicity to the faults, or even the aggravated offences of others. We may know that which the public does not know, and which, if it were known, would tend veiry grieatly to the injury of the individual concerned. Now, there may be circumstances which would require us, firom a regard to the public good, or for other reasons whichl will be hereafter considered, to disclose the facts which have come to our knowledge. But, aside from these, we have no right, thoughtlessly, needlessly, without weighty and sufficient reasons, to make use of our information to the discredit and injury of the offending party. What, ever publicity he may give to his own actions, and whatever, in the natural course of justice and of divine providence, they may acquire, is another matter; but the mere knowledge, on my part, that he has acted dishonl. estly, is not a sufficient reason why I should speak of it to his injury, and gives me no right to do so. " One man," says Dr. Hickok, "has no right to be injuring the good name of another; even by reporting, that which may be true of him, unless some grave interest of the public may demand it." The person to whose injury we are tempted to speak, may be himself deeply conscious of his own faults, and earnestly making efforts to overcome them. Or the particular offence that we have in mind may have been committed in former years, and under circumstances 9f peculiar temptation; it may be something of which he has long and bitterly repented, and firom which his whole subsequent life has turned away utterly. To give publicity to the matter, under such circumstances, would be to work infinite mischief and causeless ruin. Judging of the Xotives of Others.-On the same principle, and by the same law of morality, we are for 172 DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. bidden to judge of the motives of others, either by assign. ing to their conduct wrong motives, where right ones may reasonably be supposed, or by suggesting that the action proceeds from some other motive than that which is apparent and professed. We have no right to suppose or presume any such thing. The motives of men are for the most part known only to Him who sees the heart. We do great injustice to the character of others, when, on such imperfect and insufficient data as we have, and without due cause, we set aside the professed intent and design of an action, and attribute it to some unworthy source. We like not to be ourselves judged in that. manner, and have no right thus to judge the motives of others. Hol(liag Others up to Ridciciele.-Any deliberate attempt to bring others into contempt, by ridicule and railleiy, and thus to detract firom the esteem in which they would otherwise be held, is likewise a violation of the rule. The shafts of ridicule are, of all weapons with which one's reputation may possibly be assailed, the most fatal and venomous. They are the most difficult to meet, and for this reason both the more mischievous and the more cowardly. On this point the remarks of Dr. Wayland are forcible and just: "It is but a very imperfect excuse, for conduct of this sort, to plead that we do not mean any harm. What (lo we mean? Surely reasonable beings should be prepared to answer this question. Were the witty calumniator to stand concealed, and hear himself made the subject of remarks precisely similar to those in which he indulges respecting others, he would have a very definite conception of what others mean. Let him then carry the lesson home to his own bosom." Jlisinterpreti?ng Others.- The law of reputation forbids DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. 173 us likewise to put a wrong construction on what others say and do,- to interpret their langiagec or conduct as meaning one thing, while in reality it is susceptible of a very different interpretation, and then to make use of this false and forced construction to the injury of the party concerned. This is a course of procedure at once mischievous and despicable. When intentionally done, it is dowright dishonesty; when inadvertently, it is still a wrong and a crime. This is a form of slander to which the critic and literary reviewer, the disputant, the controversial writer, are too frequently tempted to resort, in answering an opponent, or pointing out what they may regard as error. The words and statements of an author are wrested, whether consciously or inadvertently, from their true meaning, and he is held up to public odium, on chlnrges not less false than injurious. Even the records of theological controversy are not, it is to be feared, wholly free from this fault. In what Cases Silence not reqtired.- Here the question may arise, whether, in al] cases, we are bound to observe silence respecting the fiults or crimes of others. Does the law of morality, as regards reputation, require us in all cases to conceal firom the public eye what we may happen to know that is derogatory to the character of another? If not, then what are the exceptions? I reply, whenever the good of the conmnunity imnperatively requires the exposure of the faults or follies, the mistakes or crimes of another, then is the law of reputa. tionI superseded, set aside by a higher claim, and we aile at liberty to make known what has come to our observation; but not otherwise. Thus, for example, a man may be enjoying a higher reputation as a scholar, 3 man of science or for virtue and general worth, than he -5i 174 DUTIES PERTAINING TO REPUTATION. may seein to me to deserve. Tll.at gives me no righlit to (liminishl his reputation, and bring him down to the level which, in miy opinion, he ought to occupy. Hlis reputation is his own acquirement and possession, and he has the right to enjoy it. If, however, this involves manifest injustice to another, theni there is adequate cause for inter. ference, and for setting the matter right. So, in like manner, if I have reason to suppose that any person is plotting the injury of another, or of the community, I have no10 right to keep silence, out of regard to his reputation. Or if a crime has been commnitted, and I know the authors, I am not at liberty to be silent where the ends of public justice and the public good require the disclosure of the guilty. These ends are of still hilghe moment than personal reputation, and the law of procedure in all such cases is plain. ~ III. -REASONS FOR OBSERVING THE LAW or REPUTATION The law which has been stated as binding upon us, in the matter of speaking to the injury of others, is by no means a law without a reason. On the contrary, it is enforced by considerations of the most weighty and imperative character. -Baseness of Slcan(er.- One reason why we should not, without adequate cause, speak evil of any one, is, the base.:ess of so doing. Slander is justly regarded as one of the basest and meanest of crimes. Some crimes find their apology in the strength of the natural appetite which prompts to their commission. But no man can plead, I suppose, a natural appetite for slander; and even if he should, it would not be likely to raise him in our esteem, or to be taken as an excuse for his crime. Slander injures another, without benefit to one's self; destroys and lays wasto DUTIES PERTAiNING TO REPUTATION. 17t) without cause, wantonly, and for the mere sake of mischief. It is evil inflicted gratuitously, and for the evil's own sake. It is a course prompted by envy, or the desire of revenge. It has its source in the darkest and most malignant passions and principles of our fallen nature. There is nothing noble or magnanimous about it. It is a false, dishonorable, cowardly thing. No man can be guilty of it and retain self-respect, or the respect of others. He sinks himself in the estimation of all honorable men, and brands himself with the ignominy which he vainly seeks to fasten upon his victim. Efect on) the Community. -It is to be considered, also, what would be the effect on the community, were men to indulge freely in the habit of speaking evil one of another, and exposing one another's faults and follies, without adequate cause. lMIanifestly such a state of society would be almost intolerable. No one is free from faults; and if every one were at liberty to expose to the public gaze the imperfections and weaknesses of all with whom he is conversant, scandal must become the order of the day, and the great staple of conversation. Universal suspicion and distrust would be awakened; the tenderest and most sacred relations of life would be involved; and all social intercourse and organization must speedily come to an end. Nothing so weakens the restraints of crime and the regard for public virtue, as free converse of the failings and follies of others, especially of those who stand high in public estimation as persons of worth and character. Suty of the Citizens ard of the Press. -It is incum bent, then, on every good citizen, as he values the public welfare, the order and harmony and virtue of the community, to abstain firom the needless utterance of that which would tend to derogate from the respect in which 176 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. another is held; and not only to abstain from this himself, but to discountenance it in others, and brand it withl his disapprobation and scorn. Especially is this incumbent on the public press. It is bad enough to give publicity to the failings of others in the limited circle of one's private acquaintance; it is a greater mischief and a greater crime to publish them to the world. How sad the spectacle, when the press of a nation debases itself to the low work of slandering a political opponent or party, or of giving needless publicity to the failings of men high in authority and public esteem! CHAPTER V. DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. Evidence that Veracity is a Duety.- Among the duties which we owe to society, is that of speaking the truth in our varied intercourse with our fellow-men. That this is a duty, is evident from the demands of our moral nature, fr'om the whole structure and fiamework of society, which in a measure depends on and presupposes this duty, as well as from the explicit commands of Godcl's word. We are so constituted as to place confidence in the testimony of our fellow-men; and our moral nature, our sense of right and justice, is violated when we find ourselves de ceived. We are also naturally inclined to speak the truth, ind it is only under strong temptations to the contrary that we are induced to pursue an opposite course. WhenIever we yield to these inducements, our moral nature is violated; we are conscious of wrong and self-deg DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 177 radation; we are cast down from our integrity. This moral nature, this disposition to credit others, this im pulse to truthfilness, this loss of self-esteem and consciousniess of wrong when we deviate firom the truth ill our statements, is ill itself an indication of the will of the Creator, too plain to be mistaken. This nature of ours is his workmanship. The effects, moreover, which would result if truth weie to be abandoned in the intercourse of man with man, the disastrous consequences to society of that general distrust and want of confidence which would necessarily ensue, may be taken as evidence of the will of the Deity, and of the obligation of veracity. To this have been added the explicit declarations of Scripture, forbidding, in the plainest and most positive terms, deceit and falsehood, and assuring us that lyilg lips are an abomination to the Lord. Into that heavenly felicity which awaits the righteous, there can in nowise enter, wNe are told, anything that maketh a lie. We can hardly be mistaken, then, in regarding veracity as a duty. In treating of it, our inquiries may have reference to truthfulness in ordinary discourse, or as regards the l)romises made between man and man, or in the more solemn form of the judicial oath. ~ I.- TRUTHFULNESS IN COMMON DISCOURSE. Where lies the Obligation to this. - That we are under obligation to speak the truth in the ordinary conversation and social intercourse of life, is hardly to be questioned. A question may arise, however, as to wha.t co)?stitutes, or where lies that obligation. Dr. Paley places it on the ground of virtual promise. Truth is expected, and con 17 DUTIES PERTAINING TO Vl,ERACITY. versation implies a tacit promise to meet that expecta tionI; otherwise we should not be at the trouble of conversing. "A lie is a breach of promise." The pernicious consequences which, directly and indi. rectly, result to society and to the individual from the want of truthfulness in discourse, may also be regarded as constituting an obligation to veracity. A lie destroys the confidence of man in man, and so strikes at the very foundations of society. It is pernicious, and wholly so in its tendency. The business of life would( be at once interrupted, and all social intercourse destroyed, if false hood, and not truth, were to become the rule and basis of human discourse. The individual suffers, no less than society, from any violation of the law of truth. The spiritual nature is degraded, and moral principile weakened, if not destroyed, by every such violation. At the s:iine time, the highest indignity is offered to the moi:.l naturie of (others. The attempt at deception and inlmposition wlhichl every false statement involves, is in itself an insult of the grossest nature, to whomsoever it is offered. Every honorable man so'regards it. We need, then, inquire no flirther for the ground of obligation to speak the truth in all our converse with our fellow-men. Lies Defined.- The crime against the laws of veracity in comimon discourse, is known under the general name of a lie. But what exactly constitutes a lie? Are all untrue statements lies? Evidently not. A lie is the utterance of an untruth with intention to deceive. The deception is the essential element. Now, in very many cases, where statements are made that are not according to strict truth, there is no intention to deceive, and no actual deception. Of this nature are parables, fictions, DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 179 dramas, allegories, and all that class of writings, as also the biurlesque, and other species of wit. The intention of the author is simply to amuse, or, at most, to convey insl'uction, through the medium of the fiction, and the interest thus awakened; and it is understood, firom the first, that the course of the story is not an exact narrati-ve of events that have actually happened, in the precise order and manner as there described. The statements alre not according to strict truth, yet there is no intention to deceive. Tlhey are ill one sense false, yet they are not lies. Oil the other hand, there are some lies that are not properily falsehoods. Some truths, even, are lies. When uttered with intention to deceive, they are virtually lies. A statement may be true literally, and in the exact sense, and yet not true in the sense in which the he:trer o) ireader is likely to understand it; and if I take advan ta.-e of this purposely to deceive him, although my state. ment may be strictly true, yet, as I use it, and intend it to be taken, it is really a lie. Of this nature are very many of the prevarications, subterfuges, and r' served meanings, which have been justified by casuists, esp)eciallly of the Romish faith. Not of necessity Oral.- It is not essential to a lie, that it be an oral, or even a written statement. It may be expressed in sigIns, which are intelligible as a medium of communication, and which, as in the case of the deaf mute, may constitute in faict a lan,guage in themselves. A lie may be acted, as well as spoken. When, in answer to a question, I reply by means of a look, a movement of the arm, a turning of the head, a pointing of the finger that is my statement, my answer; and it is either true or false. In the latter case it means deception, if it means anything, and is, therefore, a lie. Nay, more; even silence nmay be itself a lie, The simple omission or suppression 180 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. of the truth, may be as real deception, and may as really be so intended, as the statement of the opposite. If, in the statement of evidence before a jury, I omit some part essential to the real merit and aspect of the case, my omission - my silence - is a virtual falsehood, and that with intent to deceive. So of the instance mentioned by Dr. Paley, of the historical writer, who, in his account of the reign of Charles the First, should suppress any evidence of that ruler's despotism; he is understood to be rela.ting the whole truth, and the omission of an important part of that truth may justly be regarded as a lie. Whether Tustifable in any Case. - Are lies ever justifiable? Are we in all cases bound to speak the truth, be the consequences what they may? Suppose, for example, I meet a madman, or a robber, who threatens personal violence: shall I divert him from his object by telling a falsehood, and thus save my property, or my life, olr, perhaps, the lives of others? According to Paley, a filsehood in such a case is not a lie, - that is, is not criminal, - because no great harm is done. The immediate consequence is, by the supposition, beneficial; and the worst that can happen is that these men, once deceived, will not be likely to trust me again. But then, as they are not likely to come again in my way, this disadvantage, he maintains, does not outweigh the positive advantage gained by the falsehood. It may so happen, however, that some one else shall meet this madman, or this robber, even if I do not; and in consequence of my falsehood, and the distrust thus awakened, this personi may lose his life. I purchase my own safety, in such a case, at the expense of the safety of others. Because my statement has proved false, the DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 181 statements of another, even when speaking the truth, may not be believed. A False Principle.- Besides this, the principle here assumed is a false one. It makes the obligation to speak the truth depend on the inconvenience resulting from false statements. This is by no means the case. If this were so, there were an end to all morality. If the truth may be set aside, and falsehood uttered in its place, whenever it shall seem to be, on the whole, for the advantage of the speaker so to do,-when there is some end to be gained by it which to him is of some importance, - the law of veracity is not merely weakened, but essentially destroyed. If there is no higher obligation to truth, or any other virtue, than the advantages immediately resulting from it; and if it is left to the individual, in every case, to decide whether it is, on the whole, more expedient for him in the present instance to practise virtue or its opposite, then the whole system of morality rests, it must be confessed, on a very precarious basis. Under the influence of passion, of fear, of strong temptation, it can hardly be doubtffl how, in most cases, men will decide. The present gain will outweigh the ultimate advantage, and vice will be preferred to virtue. Men will do evil that good may come; they will justify their crimes by the plea that great advantage is to result. This is the principle of the casuist and the bigot, in all ages, that the end justifies the means. But, it may be said, the person to whom we speak has no right to demand information: are we, in that case, under obligation to inform him? I reply: we may be under no obligation, perhaps, to give him information which he is not entitled to ask; but this does not authorize us to tell him a falsehood, in place of the truth. We 16 I 182 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. are not obliged to answer his inquiries at all; but, if we do, we have no right to tell him a lie. It should be remembered, moreover, that even though there may be no obligation on our part to the questioner, we may, nevertheless, owe it to ourselves, to speak the truth, and that only. He who puts the question is not the only person to be regarded in the case. Something is due to our own sense of honor and self-respect, and to that unblemished integrity of character, at the loss of which even life itself were dearly purchased. Objection. - It may be said that, where life is in dan ger, the right of self-defence, which has already been conceded, involves the right of deception and falsehood, if necessary to the preservation of life. If I may justly kill my assailant, in order to save my own life, why may I not lie, in order to save it? Falsehood is surely not a greater crime than the taking of human life. To this I reply, that the right of self-protection firom lawless violence does not necessarily imply the right to defend ourselves in all possible ways, and under all circumstances. There may be methods of defence which are not justifiable, and this may be one of them. It is only in extreme cases, as when I must either kill or be killed, that the law of self-defence allows me to take the life of my assailant. In such a case, by the very supposition, falsehood will not answer the purpose. But, even if it would, it does not follow that the right to defend myself or others from law, less violence, by opposing force to force and weapon to weapon, involves the right to protect myself or them in another and a very different manner, viz., by falsehood. There is a meanness and dishonor about the latter course, in stooping to which, even to save life itself, I incur a selfdegradation and self-contempt, which, to the high-minded and honorable spirit, will justly seem one of the greatest DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 183 calamities. It does not follow, that because I have the right to protect my person and my life by a manly and vigorous defence, I therefore have the right to do so by resorting to a mean and dishonorable artifice. It may be better to forfeit life itself, than honor and self-respect. It may be better to take the life of the aggressor, already forfeited, than to do either. Treatment of the I)tsane. - The question may arise, whether the law of veracity is strictly to be observed in our treatment of that unfortunate class in whom reason no longer holds her seat. The practice, if I mistake not, very generally prevails, of resorting to deception and direct falsehood in such cases, in order to effect an object not otherwise readily attained. Such a course can be justified only on the ground that the insane person is, by reason of his condition, an irrational and irrespontsible being, and, as such, an exception to all ordinary rules; and that a regard to his own highest good requires him to be so treated. In such a case, the law of benevolence may possibly set aside the law of veracity. How far such a course is actually wise and expedient, - how far it is likely to be successful in accomplishing the objects in view, - whether honesty and veracity are not, even in such cases, in the long run, the best policy, -is, to say the least, an open question. Importance of Truth in Trijes.- It is of the highest importance to form a habit of speaking the truth, even in matters of little moment. Such a habit, securely and firmly fixed, is one of the surest bulwarks against the encroachments of vice. It is essential to a truly noble and virtuous character. Untrutithfiilness in little things, leads to deception in more impdrtant matters, and on a larger scale. "White lies," it has been well said, "always introduce others of a darker complexion. I have seldom 184 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. known any one who deserted truth in trifles, that could( be trusted in matters of importance." "There is no vice," says Dr. Wayland, "which, more easily than this, stupefies a man's conscience. He who tells lies frequently, will soon become an habitual liar; and an habitual liar will soon lose the power of distinguishing between the conceptions of his imagination, and the recollections of his memory. I have known a few persons who seemed to have arrived at this most deplorable moral condition. Let every one, therefore, beware of even the most distant approaches.to this detestable vice." ~ II. VERACITY AS REGARDS PROMISES. Whence the Obligation. -The obligation to keep a promise, according to some writers, arises from the necessity of such a course to the well-being and even exist ence of society. Men act from expectations founded upon the assurances of others; and if no confidence could be reposed in such assurances, the varied intercourse of life could not go on, and society would be at an end. This is doubtless true, and it furnishes a strong and in itself imperative reason for the fulfillmnent of promises. In the absence of any other and higher principle, this would of itself constitute an obligation to such a course. But it is by no means true, that there is no higher principle applicable to the case. The law of expediency, however weighty, is not the only law, nor is it the ground of obligation in the present case. It is not a sufficient account of the matter. Aside firom all considerations of this nature, from all results of evil to the community and to the individual, have I a moral right to awaken expectations which I do not intend to meet, and thus to disappoint and deceive my fellow-men? Is it not a species of DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 185 fraud, of dishonesty, which is in itself a crime, aside from its ruinous consequences to society? Does not the law of veracity, which makes it binding on me to speak the truth in my ordinary conversation, oblige me also to keep my promises? In whctt sense to be i,te2:preted. - How is a promise to be interpreted? Shall it be as the promiser himself understands it? But he may intend to deceive. He may so frame his explanations as intentionally to convey a false idea to the party receiving the promise,-saying one thing and meaning another. Is he, in that case, bound only by his own meaning and intention? A man promises to pay me a certain sum of money for certain services, really in. tending to make payment ill some worthless or depreciated currency. Is he bound, in that case, only to fulfill his orig inal intention? This, of course, cannot be conceded. Shall we say, then, that the promise is to be inter preted as the party to whoin the promise is made understands it? But here again there is a difficulty; for the receiver may, on his part, misunderstand the promise, and the real meaning of the promiser. In the case supposed, I may understand the promise of my employer to be that I shall be paid in gold, while he really means and promises nothing of the sort. It would be manifestly unfair to hold the promiser bound to fulfill his promise, not according to its real meaning, but according to any construction that the whim or fancy of the other party chose to put upon it. Obviously the only just rule is to take the words in their natural and proper signification, as meaning just what they would naturally be understood to mean by any one not specially concerned in the matter; in other words, as he who made the promise supposed that it would, and intended that it should, be understood. The promiser is bound to abide by this interpretation, and to 16* 186 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. meet the expectations which he has thus formed, and which he intended to form. If he fails to do this, he is guilty of dishonesty. In illustration of this principle, Paley refers to the his torical incident of the treachery practised upon the garrison of Sebastia, who were promised that, if they would surrender, no blood shotucld be shed; but who were, on surrendeiring, buried alive;- the promise being kept as to its letterl but broken in reality. In what cases not binding. -As a general rule, there can be no doubt of the obligation to fulfill a promise once made. And yet there are exceptions to that rule. Not every promise is binding. What, then, are these excep tions? Suppose, for example, I have promised to do what is in itself unlawfil, -to commit a crime, to lie, to steal, to commit murder, in any way to violate the laws of society or the laws of God,- am I under obligation to keep such a promise? Unquestionably not. There can be no obligation on any man to do wrong. It is a contradiction of terms to say that a man ought to do what he ought not to do. In case the unlawfulness of the act contemplated was known at the time the promise was made, then the promise itself was a guilty one, and the sooner it is broken the better. The guilt of such promises, it has been well said, lies not in the breaking, but in the making. In case the unlawfulness was not known, but the thing promised was, at the time, supposed to be lawful, this supposed lawftilness was manifestly an implied condition of the promise; and a failure of the condition, implies a failure of the obligation. The promise is to be taken in its plain and obvious intent; and if there was 1no intention to do a wrong act, no promise to do a known wrong, of course DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 187 there is no obligation in the premises. This was the case with HIerod, whose promise was to give his daughter whatever she might ask; but who, in making that promise, had no thought of her asking what she did. In taking the life of John the Baptist, under such circumstances, that ruler committed the crime of murder in order to avoid breaking a promise which, in reality, he never made; and which, if made, he had not only no obligation but no right to keep. In like manner, a promise obtained by any misrepresen tation or fraud on the part of the person receiving the pronlise, is not binding, when such fraud or misrepresentation is discovered, inasmuch as the condition on which the promise was made proves false. If a beggalr for instance, obtains my signature for a sum of money to relieve his apparent distress, and I afterwards discover that he is an impostor, and his distress counterfeit, my promise, which was made on the strength of that representation, is no longer morally binding. Imj)ossibilities.-Nor can a promise bind any man to perform what proves to be an impossibility. "We cannot be under obligation," says Dr. Wayland, "to do what is plainly out of our power." If, however, at the time the promise was made, we ourselves k)new that it was an impossibility to perform the same, we are really guilty of firaud; since a promise is an implied belief that the thing promised is possible. Itcre, again, it is not the breaking, but the making of the promise that is criminal. No one has a right to promise what he does not believe can be done, much less what he knows cannot be. Thus, for example, the proprietor of a stage, steamboat, or other vehicle, has no right to promise to convey me to a certain place within a specified time, if he knows, or has any reason to believe, that, owing to the state of the roads, or state of the 188 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. weather, it will be impossible to reach the given point until after the time specified. The builder or contractor hlas no right to promise that the house which he is erecting shall be ready for occupancy at a given time, when in all probability it cannot bie completed, as he very well knows, until some weeks, or even months, after that date. All such promises are dishonest. I am well aware that nothing is more common than promises of just this nature; insomuch that it has come to be almost proverbial that no dependence is to be placed, in regard to such matters, upon the word of those who perhaps would scorn to be guilty of falsehood in other things. It is none the less a falsehood and a fraud, however, because of frequent occurrence. Nor is it any justification of such a course, to say that the thing promised was in its nature impossible of fulfillment. This we should have thought of before we promised. We had no right to promise an un certainty, much less an impossibility. Extorted Promnises.-A promise may be extorted by violence-by an appeal to fear. Placed in imminient peril, I promise the highwayman or the assassin that, if he will spare my life, I will not betray him, or give iniiformation that shall lead to his arrest. Am I bound to keep that promise? This is a point upon which moralists have greatly differed, and which it is not easy to decide. On the one hand, it may be said, that were such promises in a few instances broken, confidence would no longer be reposed in them, and whoever should fall into the hands of the highwayman would be murdered as well as robbed. On the other hand, justice andl the safety of the public demand the arrest of the criminal. MIy silence may cost many lives. I have no right to purchase my own safety at the expense of the lives and safety of others. And then, aside DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERAClTY. 189 from this, -the advantage or disadvantage to the community,- am I under obligation to keep a promise forced from me under such circumstances? As the obliqgation of one party always implies a corresponding iight of the other, I am surely not bound to give what he who extoits the promise has no right to demand. Nor has he the right to demand the fulfillment of a promise which he had in the first place no right to procure. But, had he any right, under the circumstances, to make me promise what I did? Had he a right to rny life, a right to put me in peril and in fear, a right to the violence and threats by which he extorted the promise ill the first instance? If not, then what becomes of his right to demand the fulfillment of a promise thus extorted; and if he has no right to demand it, then, as far as he is concerned at least, I am under no obligation to keep it. Were the circumstances otherwise- had I, by my own carelessness, or curiosity, or folly, placed myself in the power of such a person, and then purchased my life by promise of secrecy, the case had been different, and the argument, as above.given, would no longer hold. Contracts. -A contract is a mutual promise between two parties, - one engaging to do one thing, provided the other will do another thing. It comes, therefore, under the same general rule with promises. I am bound to fulfill a contract, for the same reasons that I am bound to keep any other promise that I have made. The same rule which applies to the interpretation of promises, applies also to contracts. They are to be taken according to their plain and obvious signification, as meaning that which they would naturally be understood to mean by any intelligent and unprej(udiced person. The rule given by Paley is to the same effect: "Whatever is iO0 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. expected by one side, and known to be so expected by the other, is to be deemed a part or condition of the contract." The failure of the party, with whom we contract, to fulfill his part of the obligation, releases us firom ours, since it is the failure of the condition on which the contract was made, and on which it entirely depends. A society, or company of men, it hardly need be said, is under the same obligation to fulfill its contracts, as an individual; the state, as the citizen. Nations and states, in their dealings with each other, are under the same laws and obligations of veracity and honesty in regard to all their treaties and compacts, as those which bind the conscience of the private citizen. ~ III.- VERACITY IN RESPECT TO OATHS. I. Siqgnifcance of the Oath.- It is often of the highest importance to secure the most exact truthfulness of statement-to make sure that what is asserted is not false. To secure this most effectually is the object of an oath. This is calling on the Supreme Being, the omniscient and omnipotent ruler of the universe, to witness that what we say is true, and to deal with us in strict justice if it be not true. We thus place ourselves under the highest conceivable obligations and motives to truthfulness; since, to make this solemn appeal to the majesty of Heaven, and then directly, and in the face of it, to utter that which is false, in the very ear of Him whom we have called to witness our truthfulness, would be an act of impiety the most daring and reckless of which we can well conceive. He who has any just, or even remote idea of the value of the divine favor, and the danger of incuring the displeasure of Him who DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 19J holds our very breath in the hollow of his hand, will not for the sake of any present advantage, venture to offer so deliberate an insult to the Supreme Being. By imnprecat ing upon ourselves the divine displeasure and curse if we speak falsely, we place ourselves under the highest possible mnotives to truthfulness. And this is the theory and sig. nificance of the oath. Forts) of -E.ression.- The usual form of expression in the Englishl oath is, "So hell) ne Go(,"- in which the emphatic word is the particle so; that is, may God be my helper anl( friend, in all things wherein I need his help, now and hereafter, in life and in death, in time and eternity, only so far as, and on condition that, I now speak the truth. To add still further solemnity to the act, the jutror places his hand on the word of God, or lifts it to heaven in sign of solemn invocation and appeal. This latter was the ancient Jewish custom, whence ours is probably derived. With tlhe Greeks and Romnans it was customary to slay a victim, onl solemn occasions, when it was desired to give special imiportance to the transaction. Hence, fiom the strik ing down of the beast, the expressionferirepactuni, whence our own phrase, to strike a bargain. II. Differenit Ap))lications of the Oa(th.- There are two different kinds, or!, more properly, different applications of the oath. I may take oath that I will testify truly, or that I will perform some engagement. The oath of testimony places me uIinder the most solemn obligation to state that which I know respecting a given matter, without addition, or suppression, withoutt exaggerating, or mitigating, or falsely coloiing auglht. The oath of engayemen t binds me to the faithful performance of any duty whichl may be assigned me, or the fulfillment of any office of tirust committed to me, or of any engagement which I voluntarily 192 DUTIES PIERTAINING TO VERACITY. assume. Afore frequently, oaths of. this class are either oaths of office or of trust. As regards the latter, it seems an obvious propriety that, where interests of great moment are intrusted to the keeping of successive guardians, in, it may be, successive generations of men, every precaution should be taken to secure the fidelity of those thus trusted. This is the case with corporate bodies, to whom is com mitted the business of executing an instrument, or appro priating a charity according to the designs of the testator or founder. Our institutions of learning, and other benevolent and charitable institutions, which depend, for the most part, on funds given for the purpose, are managed by boards of trust, the members of which, when they enter upon their duties, take oath to administer the trust according to the intention of the instrument, and the will of the donor. Oath of Office. - The common oath of office is, perhaps, of more questionable propriety. When the duties of the office assumed are of such a nature as to require the added security and solemnity of an oath; when the office is one of great importance, or of unusual difficulty; and when much depends on the fidelity and skill with which its duties are performed,- there can be no doubt as to the propriety and utility of the oath. Such is the case when men are called to the high and important offices of the state- to the administration of public affairs. Whatever can add to the sense of moral obligation, and quicken the conscience, should be brought to bear in such a case. The oath should be imposed, however, only on occasions of importance. Its too frequent imposition tends rather to weaken than to strengthen the sense of obligation, and the restraints of virtue. In proportion as it becomes a familiar and common thing, its sacredness is impaired, its efficacy destroyed. It comes to be regarded as a mere DUTIES PERITAINING TO VERACITY. 193 form, and takes no hold upon thle conscience. Such a ulse of it must tend greicatly to obliterate all moral distinctions, ill nice perceptionis of duty and sense of obligation, firom the mind. This effect is very greatly increased by the senseless iand unmeaning manner in which the oath is, in such cases veriy generally administered by the official whose duty i) is to induct into office the new incumbent. The words aire hurried over with extreme rapidity, and in the most careless manner, as if they were the merest form, or as if whatever meaning they had were something to be ashamed of, rather than to be carefully pondered. It were much better that all such oaths should never be administered. They are productive of more evil than good. Even aside firom this irreverent and senseless manner whichl too firequently accompanies the administration of the oath of office, why, it may be asked, is it necessary to make ulse of the solemn sanctions of religion to secure fidelity in the disclharge of every petty office and employment to which men may be called in the details of public duty? "Why should one man," it has been well said, "who is called upon to discharge the duties of a constable, or of an overseer of common schools, or even of a counsellor or a judge, be placed under the pains and penalties of perjury, or under peril of his eternal salvation, any more than his neighbor, who discharges the duties of a merchant, of an instructor of youth, a physician, or a clergyman?" On this point, the remarks of Dr. Paley, with reference to the frequency of oaths, are worthy of consideration, as equally applicable to our own country. "This obscure and elliptical form, together with the levity and fi'equency with which it is administered, has brought about a general inadvertency to the obligation of oaths, which, botli in a religious and political view, is much to be 17 194 DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. lamented; and it merits public consideration, whether the requiring of oaths on so many fiivolous occasions, especially in the customs, and in the qualification for petty offices, has any other effect than to make them cheap in the minds of the people. A pound of tea cannot travel regulairly fiom the ship to the consumer, without costing half a dozen oaths at the least; and the same security for the due discharge of their office - namely, that of an oath - is required from a churchl-w:tirden and an archbishop, firom a petty constable and the Chief Justice of England." III. -LI(1tit tless of Oaths.- There are certain religions sects, as the iIoraivians, and the Quakers, which regard the oath as unlawfil on any occasion, and, on the ground of these scruples, refuse to swear. In support of this view they cite the words of our Sayiotr, in Matthew v. 34, 37: "I say unto you, swear not at all," "Let your communication be yea, yea, and nay, nay; for whatsoever is more than these cometh of evil." Tlhat our Saviour intended by these words to prohibit the solemn judicial oath, there is not the least evidence. On the contrary, his words evidently refer to the uise of oathls in common conversation; that is, to profane swearing, and to all irreverent and unauthorized appeals to Heaven in confirmation of our veracity, without judicial form and sanction. The Jews seem to have distinguiishedcl between swearing by the name of God, and swearing by other and less sacred objects, as the heaven, the earth, Jerusalem, the head, etc., -regarding the latter forms as less sacred and binding than the former one. Christ forbids all such use of langluage, as irreverent to the Supreme Being, and his direction therefore is, swear not at all; that is, not in any of these ways: they are all improper and profane. That, in so saying, he intended to forbid the DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 195 judicial oath, there is no evidence, but the highest improb. ability. Sanctioned in Scripttre. - No attentive reader of the Scriptures can fail to observec the ftct, that the solemn oath is repeatedly recognized and sanctioned in the sacred writings. Our Saviour himself was once put on oath by the high-priest, and made reply, when "adjured by the living God," to declare whether he was the Christ, the Son of God. God repeatedly swears by himself, in the Old Testament Scriptures. In order to show the inimutability of his counsel, hlie confirmed his own covenant with the Jews by an oath. "For when God made promise to Abraham, because he could swear by no greater, he sware by himself." "For men verily swear by the greater; and an oath for confirmation is to them the end of all strife. Wherein God willing more abundantly to show unto the heirs of promise the immutability of his counsel, confirmed it by an oath" (Heb. vi. 13, 16, 17). "I have sworn by myself, the word is gone out of my mouth in righteousness, and shall not return" (Is. xlv. 23). "The Lord God hath sworn by himself, saithl the Lord the God of hosts" (Amos vi. 8). "For I have sworn by myself, saith the Lord, that Bozrah shall becomne a desolation" (Jer. xlix. 13). Among the precepts of the law given on Sina.i we find the following: "Thou shalt fear the Lord thy God, and serve himrn, and shalt swear by his name" (Deut. vi. 13). The same is repeated in Deut. x. 20. The judicial oath is probably referred to in these passages. Still more explicitly in the following: "Then shall an oath of the Lord be between them both, that he hath not put his hand unto his neighbor's goods" (Ex. xxii. 11). Paul, in his epistles, repeatedlly calls God to witness, in the most solemn manner, for the 196 DU7TIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. truth of what he says. "For God is my witness" (Rom. i. 9). "Moreover, I call God for a witness upon my soul" (2 Col. i. 23). From the above examples it is evident that oaths, solemnn and judicial, are by no means condemned in the Scriptures, but, on the contrary, sanctioned both by precept and example. Necessity of the Oath. - That the frequent and irreverent use of the oath, on trifling occasions, tends to'cvil, has already been admitted; that its use can be, or need be, entirely dispensed with in judicial transactions, and on public occasions of soleinn moment, I am not re(ady to admit. The state needs to employ it; nor can the ends of justice be well secured without it. Reputation, property, life itself, and all the interests that are dear to man on the earth, depend on the sanctity of the oath. So long as human nature is what it is, it is absolutely necessary to throw around the forms of justice, and the offices of high public trust, the solemnity and sanction of a direct appeal to the omniscient and omnipotent Ruler of men and things. Where Religious Beief is wanting.- The state may have occasion for the testimony or public services of those who have either no religious belief, or a widely different one from the commonly received faith; as, for extmple, of one who believes in Mohammed, or in the deities of the I)agan world; of one who, as the Jew, believes in God, but not in Christ; or of one who rejects the doctrine of a future state, or of future retribution. In such cases, of what avail is the oath, in its usual form and significance? I reply: if the faith of the testator in God, and in the retriI)utions of the fiituie, be not wholly wanting, his oath may be upon and according to his faith, whatever that may be, whether Jewish, Pagan, or Mohammedan; and, as his DUTIES PERTAINING TO VERACITY. 197 religion is more or less practical, and pure, and exerts more oi less restraint and influence on his life, so his oath will l)c more or less binding on his conscience, and his testiinony will be more or less worthy of credence, in that pr,poition. If, however, either the existence of the Supreiiie Being, or a state of fiuture rewards and punishments, be not an object of earnest belief to the testator, it is difficult to see of what validity the oath can any longer be. It has ost its significance, so far as he is concerned, and his testi. inony, if taken, must be taken with allowance, and for what it is worth. 17* PART III. DUTIES TO THE FAMILY. WE have as yet considered only those duties which man owes to himnself, to society, and to his fellow-meii in general. There are other duties, not less important, of a more specific character. There are in the world two great institutions, - both of divine origin, both founded in mIan's moral and social nature, both placing him in new and peculiar relations, and requiring of him new and peculiar duties,- I mean tihe F(imily and the State. Of the former I am now to treat. The duties which belong to this class divide themselves naturall y into those of the arritfge relation, and those of the parental relation; or, the duties of husband and wife, and those of parent and child. CHAPTER I. DUTIES OF THE MARRIAGE RELATION. The famnily is a distinct and peculiar institution, standing by itself; a distinct organic community, complete within itself;-having its own laws, its own lig,lts and privileges, D1)UTIES OF T-HE MARRIAGE RELATION. 1i9)O) its own interests, its own duties. The family is, in an iml,oitant sense, thefottclatiot of the state, which is a cortlini,ity or society of families, gathered into one organizations, rather than a casual combination of individuals otherwise isolated. At the basis of this arrangement stands the marriage relation, itself an institution of divine origin, \itile, at the same time, its foundation is in the constitution of our nature. It is the oirigin of all the domestic aelations, and of all civil society. The continuance and progress of the race firom age to age depends upon it. _TNcture of this Relation.- MIarriage is the union for life (oI one of either sex with one of the other. It is a mutual 'omnaa,,c and a voluntary one, having for its basis, not mere personal Tesspect and regard, not merely the convenience anud interest of the parties, but mutual affection. Where this is wanting, with whatever forms the rite may be celebirated, and whatever advantag,es or disadvantages it may ensure, it is after all but a form, a solemn mockery. The ground of this relation exists in the very constitution of our nature. Those natural desires and propensities which relate to the intercourse of the sexes, look forward to this relation as their end, and are at once regu-. lated, refined, and chastened by it. Without such an influence, and such an end, these desires would constantly tend to the degradation of man, and the disorganization of society. Under the influence of the marriage relation, these disturbing forces are curbed and tranquillized, security and confidence are imparted, society is established on a firm basis. The parties united in this sacred relation - joined, not in person merely, but in heart -become one in all the interests and duties, the joys and the solrows of life. But, while founded in the constitution of our nature, the relation of which I speak is not the less a divine institu i 200 DUTIES OF THE MAPRPIAGE RELATION. tion. That nature is itself the wolrk of the divine Creator, lhaving reference to this end, and teirmilnl.tiIlg in it. Ile who desi(,ned the constitution of the human mind, and the liiuilan body, and planned all the circumstances of his earthly condition, designed also that man should not live alone upon the earth. Hence the social nature and wants; and hence marriage, which is the result of that nature, may be regarded as an institution of divine origin. But while nature lays the foundation for such an institution, and that in accordance with the design of the Creator, it is still a matter to be regulated and ratified by pululic authority. The parties are not alone concerned. The public welfare demands that a relation of this kind should not be formed clandestinely, or without official authority and due forms of ratification. The law takes cognizance of this relation, prescribes the due forms and conditions, and concerns itself with the due observance of the same. This it is the proper business of the state to do, through its appointed legal authorities, in order to the permanence and security of the rights and interests involved in the new relation of the parties. The relation thus formed and authorized is for life. Only one crime -that of infidelity to the marriage bond -can rightfully be made the ground of separation. Such, in brief, is the nature of the marriage relation: a compact between two persons of different sex, fieely and voluntarily formed, by the mutual consent and choice of each, on the ground of affection, -a union of heart and person and interests, authorized by due forms of law, and to continue while life continues. I)ifferent Viewts of Marriage. -The conception of the nature and rights of the marriage relation, and of the duties which it imposes, has varied in different ages and DUTIES OF TIIE MARRIAGE RELATION. 201 among different nations. With some, polygamy and con. cubinage have been tolerated, and divorce has been allowed on frivolous grounds. Still, the idea of complete and perfect marriage has, with almost all nations, been tla.t now indicated, - the exclusive union of one man and one woman for life. The practice of'polygamy seems to have been more or less prevalent in the early periods of Jewvish history. Still, in the beginning it was not so; but the marriage institution, as it carne from the hand of God, was the union of a single pair, and they two were one flesh. It has been well remarked by Dr. Hickok, that, "If polygamy was practised by the patriarchs with God's permission, it still had no divine sanction; God's legislation has been always against it, even when, for other reasons, he has not enforced it." By the Roman laws, polygamy was not allowed. The Institutes define marriage as "the union of a man and a woman, so as to constitute an inseparable, habitual course of life;" and in the Digest it is spoken of as "partnership for life - the mutual participation of divine and human rights." The law of Justinian expressly forbids having inore than one wife. "It is not lawful to have two wives ait the same time." Concubinage was, however, allowed. So, also, in the Grecian states. The heroes of Homer, it has been remarked, applear never to have had more than one spouse, - aoXos, while sometimes represented as living in concutbinage. This shows that even in that early period and rude stage of society, the true idea of inarrinage was still entertained. English law Iregar(ds the husband and wife as but one person, the legal existence of the woman, during marrinage, being incorporated in that of her husband. She can bring no legal claim or suit in her own name alone; nor can the husband, by legal act or conveyance, grant any 202 DUTIES OF TiHE MARRIAGE RELATION. thing to his wife, - she being one and the same with him. self in the eye of the law. Even in criminal prosecutions, lhusband and wife cannot be evidence for or against each other, on the ground that, according to established maxims of law, "no one can be a wvitness in his own cause," and 'ino one is bound to accuse himself." This differs fi'o-ii Roman law, ill which husband and wife are two distinct persons, and each may hold property, contract debts, etc. According to Roman law, Roman citizens could only marry Roman citizens, - union with those of otlheI nations not being regarded as valid mareriage. Restrictions of a similar nature exist, or have existed to some extent, among otller people, limiting the marriage union to the families of the same nation or tribe. It is for the laws of every state to prescribe the limits witl-hin which malrilge may be contracted; and in most, if not all, civilized niations, there are certain restrictions of tlhis sort, as respects naiarli.age within certain degrees of ki1ndred. As mnarinage is not merely a civil but also a religious institution, the state is not alone concerned in its (duec observa.nce; hence, in the ceremonies attending its )public authorization, civil and religious rites are usually conjoined. A mere legal contract does not express its true idea and full import.* The sanctions of religion arc combined with the sanctions of law, in its true and proper solemnization. The sentiment of duty is addressed, as well as the sentiment of citizenship. The custom of performinicg the marriage ceremony ill churches, however, does not seem to have prevailed prior to the thirteenth century. Divorce. -Divorce, or the separation of the marriage union, -was allowable among the Jews, unlder certin regulations, whenever the husband for any reason chose to p)ut away his wife. Suclh was not the original and true design DUTIES OF THE MARRIAGE RELATION. 203 of the marriage relation, which was intended to be permanent, holding the parties in union for life. It was a perversion of that design, tolerated, but never sanctioned by the Divine Law-giver. There were reasons for this toleration. The cruelty and hardness of men, the barbarism of the age, rendered divorce a less evil to both, when affection no longer hel(d the parties in mutual regard, than would be an inseparable union, fioni which all love had fled, and in which woman, as the weLker and more likely to be abused, would suffer the greatest inconveniences and injuries. English law does not recognize the right of divorce. A special act of Parliament is necessary to provide for each case of the sort as it comes up. In our own country, the facilities and occasions for divorce valy in the different states; but in all, it is to be feared, the tendency is to a separation of the marriage tie for reasons of too slight a nature. In proportion as div(,rcc becomes easy, the security of the domestic relations is inpl).ired, and woman is degraded from her true position. The law of God is explicit in this matter; and so far as state policy departs from this rule, it defeats its own end, which is, the highest welfare of the body politic, I),ttties of the Xarriage Relation. - Fidelity is the first law of the marriage state, -the faithful observance of the solemn contract. This is broken by whatever is contrary to the law of chastity, Not merely criminal intercourse with other persons, but whatever weakens or destroys that exclusive affection on which the contract is founded, is really a violation of that contract. The evils resulting firom infidelity to the marriage vow are among the greatest and most serious with which society is afflicted. The peace an(l harmony of the domestic relations are destroyed, 0i DUTIES OF THE MARRIAGE RELATION. families are broken up, the most sacred ties are severed, discord and misery reign where all should be happiness and love. Hence, in all ages, and by all laws of Gad and man, it has been treated as an aggravated and serious offence. By the Jewish law it was punishable with death. By the law of nature and of the Scriptures, the husband is the head of the family,- with him is vested the chief authority: hence the duty of respect, and, so far as there is any occasion for it by reason of the conflict of opinion or diversity of choice, the duty also of obedience, on the l).lrt of the wife. This authority, of course, gives the husband no right to abuse his power by acts of unkindness and severity, or any harshness of demeanor;'or, on the other hland, does it derogate in the least from the honor and dignity of woman. To submit and obey, is not more the sphere than the highest grace and ornament of the gentler sex; as sulch, it is explicitly enjoined in the sacred writings In ruder states of society, and in earlier ages of the world, as even now wherever barbarism exists, woman has been but the slave of man. His brute strength has prevailed over her weakness, and abused her gentleness and uncomplaining, patient endurance of ills and wrongs. The Roman law allowed the husband to treat the wife with severity, and even with personal violence. But where Christianity comes, it elevates woman from this degraded position, and makes her the equal companion of the stronger sex; and, while it still enjoins upon her the duty of obedience and subjection to the husband, it clothes that very subjection with a dignity and beauty more attractive than any outward adorning. But, while it is the part of the gentler sex to yield, it is the part of tile stronger to support, protect, and treat with uiiiform kindness and courtesy, the weaker. Strength and authority give the husband no right to tyrannize over the DUTIES OF TIlE MARRIAGE RELATION. 205 wife, or manifest his power by acts of'unkindness, or any want of that respect and affection which are ever her due. He is to provide for her physical wants, her comfortable maintenance and support. He is to protect her, so far as possible, fiom injury and insult. IIe is to be her guardian and defender. She is to lean upon his strength, and feel secure, as the vine clings for support to the sturdy oak, whose rude, strong arms are able to defend it against the winds and storms. Nor is the relation of the wife one of entire dependence, but rather of reciprocal aid. She has her part to bear, and to perform, of the duties and struggles, the cares and toils of life. She is not to hang as a mere useless weight upon the stronger arm, but rather to stay and strengthen that arm, and make it firmer and bolder for its work. The labors of providing for the physical wants and nmaintenance of the household, are to be shared in common; the duties of the husband lying, for the most part, in labors without, and those of the wifb in labors performned within the house. In these she is to bear her part cheerfully, and with good courage; and whether ill wealth or in poverty, in sickness or in health, in comfort or in distress,- whatever the varied lot of life may be, - she is in all to be a sharer and a helper. If the atrm on whose protection and strength she relies is disabled and stricken down, she is, so far as possible, to assume the cares and duties which have hitherto devolved upon the stronger, -as the faithful vine still clings to the broken branch,- and hold iup in its weakness that on which she has leaned for support. Still another duty devolves on those who sustain to each other the marriage relation, - that of 2mt?ttual affectios. Where this is wanting, or where, having once-existed, it is suffered to die out, the marriage tie becomes irksome, and that which should lend a charm to life, only adds to its 18 '206 DUTIES OF TIIE PARENTAL RELATION. burden. There must be respect, kindness, courtesy, honor, fidelity, fiom each to each, -these, but not these alone; there must be something more than these, or the principle on which the marriage contract is based is wanting, and the contract itself becomes virtually null. Where there is no true affection, marriage is but a form, fi'om which the soul has fled. This, then, must in truth be regar(lel as one of the first and most imperative duties of the marriage state, -to cherish each that pure and true affection for the other which the sacred bond implies, and which is essential to the happiness, if not to the continuance of the relation. That bond and sacred vow are in reality broken, let it ever be remembered, not mnerely by unlawftil intercourse with others, but by any neglect, unkindness, desertion, withdrawal of mutual confidence, and mutual regard. The want of affection is itself a violation of duty, and where it continues, amounts to a virtual sundering of the marriage tie. CHAPTER II. DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. ~ I.-DUTIES OF PARENTS. IT is the duty of the parent to provide for the physical wants of his children, and also to educate them, in such a inanner as shall best prepare them for the duties of life, and the stations which they are to occupy in society, and best conduce to their happiness, temporal and eternal. The end in view, in all family nurture and training, is, directly, the welfare and happiness of the child, both DUTIES OF TIlE PARENTAL RELATION. 207 present and future; indirectly, the demands of society and the state; ultimately, and as inclusive of all others, the claims of God. The family, as we have already seen, is an institution peculiar and complete within itself- having its own laws, its own rights and interests, its own end. Nevertheless, it does not exist for itself alone. It has its relations to other objects and other institutions, its duties to perform, its office to accomplish. Prominent among these duties, and one chief end for which it exists, is the training and preparation of the children for those duties which they owe to themselves, to society, and to their 2caker. WVhatever tends to promote this, furthers the great design and end of the family as an institution; whatever interferes with and prevents this, frustrates that design. This general object includes several specific ends or duties, for which the parent is responsible. 1. MAINTENANCE. -The duty of the parent is to support the child during his years of minority, and provide for all his physical wants. Infancy and childhood are helpless and inexperienced, unable to provide for themselves, dependent of necessity on the watchful care and protection of the parent. Without that care and provision, they must inevitably perish, unless, indeed, some other takes the place of the parent. Parents are the natural guardians and providers for the wants of their children. The deep and strong affection which nature has implanted in the bosom, looks to this end, and was designed( as the basis and security for the discharge of this important trust; nor can this trust be devolved upon another, except in case of death or inability, without positive violation of duty. Iu8 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. The manner in which this duty shall be performer must depend upon the circumstances of the family, and the general position in life which the child may properly be expected to occupy. The children of the rich and the poor cannot be alike provided for; the one will have more and better food and clothing than the other. The parent does his duty when he provides for the support of his children according to the best of his ability and jludgment, and according to his own circumstances. Nor need he reproach himself, when this is done, because his limited means have not allowed him to bring up his children in that affluence which others can command; since the simn. ple habits of firugality and industry, which the lessons of honest poverty are most likely to teach, are in themselves of greater value to the household, than any amount of wealth, or any degree of refinement. 2. GovERNfrENT.- The family is a little society, a min. iature state; and every society, every state, must have its laws, its government. The government of the family is entrusted to the parents, both by the nature of the case and by divine authority; and the faithfil administration of this government is a duty which they owe both to the household, to the state, and to G(od. For the manner in which they discharge this duty, they are directly responsible to Him who instituted the family relation, and who placed in their charge this solemn trust. The end of the family institution is to train its members for the service of the state, and the service of God, in whatever stations they may hereafter be called to fill; and both the state, or society in its organized capacity, and God, have a claim upon the parents for the faithful performance of this important trust. "The family," it has been well said, "is but a nursery DUTIES OF THE PARENTRAL RELATION. 209 for higher and broader spheres of action. In it are to be planted the seeds, and there are to be nurtured the germs, which are to have their full development, and bear their fruit, in future years, and in other worlds." It is not merely, then, the happiness and welfare of the household, as such, while gathered under one roof, - although this is in itself a most important end to be secured, - but it is also the welfare and highest usefulness and happiness of its members, when they shall be no longer under the sheltering roof that covered them in the happy days of childhood, but shall have their own part to act, and their own, it may be, arduous and trying duties to perform in the busy, toiling world,- it is this higher and ultimate end that is to be reached, if at all, by means of family government. Where this is duly administered, the household is trained to habits of order and obedience; the child grows up under a system in which he learns the cardinal virtue of submission to authority, and is thus fitted to become a useful member of society. Where, on the contrary, parental government is not enforced, the lessons of obedience are not learned, and the child goes forth into society, unused to the wholesome restraints of law, untaught to submit to the will and authority of those whose right it is to govern, unfitted for the responsible duties of the citizen; in many respects, a useless, if not positively dangerous member of the community. To whom entrusted. - The duty of maintaining authority, and administering the government of the household, is, by the law of nature, and the relation of the parties, entrusted to the parents. It is their province and right to govern - the province and duty of the child to obey. This is a divine arrangement, the foundation of which lies in the constitution of our nature. It is not a merely 18* 210 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. arbitrary and conventional arrangement, but the design and law of the Creator. No duty is more clearly enjoined in the Scriptures, and none entails a severelr penalty on those who neglect and violate it. The parent is not, however, to use this authority as abusing it. He is not to govern, merely for the sake and from the love of governing, in an arbitrary and unreasonable manner. He is ever to keep in mind the end of discipline, as already pointed out; that is, the highest welfare and happiness of all the members of the household. As a satfeguard against abuse, Providence has wisely thrown around this delegated authority the restraints of parental affection. The power to govern is lodged in safe hands; the heart of the parent pleads for mercy, while his sense of justice demands the punishment of the offender. As the parties united in marriage are one, the authority of the parents is a joint and concurrent authority; and inasmuch as the end of all family discipline is one of common interest to both the parents, there can, ordinarily, be little danger of any conflict of views or interests in its administration. Should such difference arise, as there must be some ultimate appeal, the supreme authority rests, by common consent, by the nature of the case, and by the laws of the land, with the fither, as the rightful head of the family, and source of ultimate authority. 3. EDUCATION.- The duty of the parent is not entirely discharged when provision has been made for the physical wants of the household, and for its due government. The child is not only to be fed, and clothed, and governed, but suitably ecltcatee(; and this education must have reference to the whole development and training, both physical and noral, as well as intellectual, DUTIES OF THE PARlNTAl, RELATION. 211 I'hysical Cultur'e.- It must have reference to the physical traiJ)g. A good physical constitution is one of the greatest earthly advaintages; and this, so far as it depends on any care and skill of treatment after birth, is to be secured by every means in the power of the parent. Parental ignorance and negligence have, doubtless, much to do with the feeble health, the broken constitution, the life of suffering, and the premature decay and death, of many a household. The physic al culture, the health and strength of the child, is the first and most important object to be attained; and due attention to this object is the first and most imperative of parental duties. Care must be taken to regulate the food, the dress, the exercise, the hours of rest, the entire habits of life, as affecting the physical constitution; to avoid all such indulgtl,ence on the one hand, and all suchl hardship and exposure on the other, as shall endanger the health, or injure the constitution of the child. For all this the parent is responsible; and if, by carelessness, neglect, or want of skill, he fails in the perforlmance of his duty, not himself only, not the child only, nor the family only, but other and wider interests receive an injury; society suiffers, the state is a loser, and claims still higher than these are forgotten. As regards both the service of the state, and the service of God, the true end of family culture looks, first of all, at the physical health and vigor,-aims to secure that, - and fitils of its grand and ulterior designs very much in proportion as it fails in that. If that is overlooked; if, by neglect, or mistaken indulgence, habits unf ivorable to health and manly development are formed; if, as sometimnes happens, the selfishness and avarice of the parent lead him to expose his child to an amount of toil and hardship unsuited to its tender yeair's, - then, whatever suffering may ensue, whatever loss to the child 212 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. in subsequent years of life, whatever to society, and to the cause of God, the responsibility and the guilt must rest with fearful weight upon that negligent, that indulgent, or that selfish parent. Intellect'al Ctlttre.- The intellect, also, is to receive its education. The germs of wl)latever power and great ness it may afterward.qttain, lie in the mind at the outset; they are to be developed and nurtured by careful and skilful training. The intellect comes to matulrity, and possession of its own proper strength, only by culture and discilliae. Left in ignorance, its faculties imlperfectly unfolded and developed, its condition will inevitably be that of weakness and imbecility, as compared with what it might be, and was designed to be. A thorough education, if not invaluable, is, at least, of higher value to the child than any amount of treasure, or any position in society which mere wealth or the accideint of birth can command. It is itself the highest fortune, the richest treasure. He who has it cannot well be poor; he who is destitute of it, whatever else he may have, cannot be truly rich. The parent has no right to send his child out into the world uneducated, and, in consequence, unfitted for the highest duties of life. The process of education, wisely and well conducted, will always have regard to two things, - the habits and mental peculiarities of the child, and also the condition and station in life for which it is to be fitted. If either of these is overlooked, the great end of education- that is, the highest happiness and usefulness of the child in future life- will not be attained. The care of this mental training, at first devolving chiefly on the parents, may, as the child progresses, be in part, but gever wholly, transferred to other teachers; never to triansferred as that the parent shall be 1no longer respon. DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. 213 sible for the manner in which the process is conducted, and for its ultimate success or failure. No pressure of other duties can atone for any neglect of this; nor can any fidelity and skill of the teacher compensate for the want of that time and attention which the parent should still bestow on the intellectual culture and progress of the child, and which are indispensable to the most sue cessful results. 2oral CTGtr-e. Nor is the moral education of the (child to be overlooked. The manners, the disposition, the heart, the religious belief, are nmatters requiring carefil attention and culture. If the mind is to be edufcated, not less the heart. Eternal destinies, and not merely the present welfare and happiness of the child, depend on the manner in which this part of his education is conducted. Those destinies of the future are in an important sense entrusted to the decision of the parent. He is to educate and train the child, not merely for honor and usefulness on earth, but for immortality and eternal life; not merely to be a valuable member of society, but a citizen of the heavenly kingdom, and a partaker of the heavenly felicity. This duty neglected, all is neglected; this lost, all is lost. The moral education includes not merely the culture of religious feeling toward God, as the direct object of adoration and love, but of all morally right feeling and action -of all that is pure, and lovely, and of good report. It includes the checking and restraining of all the evil desires and propensities of the child's nature; the development and careful fostering of all generous, pure, noble sentiments and principles of action; the vigilant guarding against all evil and seductive influences to which the inexperience of childhood and youth may be exposed, and iy which it may so easily be led astray. It includes precept; it includes example, without which precept will 214 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. avail nothing. It includes the thousand influences of a well-ordered religious home, constantly, and to himself perhaps unconsciously, surrounding the child, and as by silken threads leading him in the way that he should go. Hflappy the child that is thus led; happy the home to which that child belongs, and ill which such influences dwell. ~ II. - DUTIES OF CHILDREN. The duties of the parent and of the child are, for the most part, reciprocal - the obligation resting upon the ole necessarily implying a corresponding obligation on the part of the other. The obligation of the parent to govern, implies the duty of the child to obey; the obligation of the parent to educate, involves the duty of the child to yield to and be guided by this care and culture. There are also duties arising firom the relation in lwhich the parties stand. The superior wisdom iand intelligence of the parent, no less than his authority, demand respect and reverence firom the child. The care and love which have watched over the helplessness of childhood, and provided for its wants, and sacrificed much for its good, demand in return filiall gratitude and affection. These, then, as determined by the nature of the case, are the principal duties of the child toward the parent, viz., obedience, docility, reverence, filial affections. 1. OBEDIENCE. - It is the duty of the child to yield iiireserved and unquestioned obedience to the authority and( commands of the parent; and this obedienlce nmust be iirrespective of the why and whe,efo'e of the command, of the wisdomi and necessity of the course priesclril)ed; it raust be rendered a,s obedience to authority, and to the DUTIES OF TIIE PARENTAL RELATION. 215 will of the parent, becaese it is his will. In no10 other way can the end of famnily government be atta.ined, the peace and order of the lhousehold be promoted, the welfare of the child secured. The duty of obedience is manifest not only firom the nature of the case, and froli the end of fanlily g,overnment, but fiom tile wvord of God. No duty is more explicitly and emphatically enjoined in the Scriptures than this: "Children, obey your parents in the Lord; for this is right" (Eph. vi. 1). And again, "Children, obey your parents in all tlhings; for tl-his is well-pleasing unto the Lord" (Col. iii. 20). To disobey the commands of the parent, is, then, to be guilty of a double crime: it is to violate at once the law of thsohousehold, and the law of God. Limiit of Atithority. -But here an important question arises, respecting the limits of parent'l authority. Are there any limits? Is the child under obligation to yield obedience to any and cill commands of the parent, wthatever they necty be? Suppose the parent order him to do thlat which is manifestly wrong, as, to break thle Sabbath, or to steal, or to lie, or in any manner to break the laws of the state, or the laws of God; is he then to obey? I reply, by no means. The parent has no righyt to give such commands, and, therefore, they are not binding on the conscience of the chlild. Whenever the child is ordered to do that which hle knows and futlly believes to be wrong, he is under no obligatioll to obey; nay, lie has no rigiht to obey. When the law of tl:he parent comes into couflict mnanifestly and directly with the law of the state, or with thle law of God, these, which,ire higher laws, must be obeyed. Tlhe autlhoiity of tlhe state is above that of the l)parent; and the authority of the Supreme and( Alligi,llty Ruler is above both. Thle clhild must (lo igi,llt, ld suttfler the consequences; the responsibility rests with the parent. 216 DUTIES OF TIlIE PAP.RENTAL RELATION. When there is any doubt as to the real character of the act required, -any uncertainty whether it is, in fact, a wrong act, and in conflict with the divine connmand(s,- it seems to me that the authority of the parent shoul(l in all such cases be held as decisive, until at least clearer light can be obtained as to the path of dluty. Under ordinary circumstances, the parent, from his superior intelligence, and greater experience, is certainly more likely to know what is right and proper than the child; hence, in matters of doubtful character, it is safer to follow the decisions of the parent, even at the risk of doing wrong, than to incur the at least equal risk of doing wrong by disobedience. 2. DOCILITY.- AS the duty of the parent is to teach, to educate, so the duty of the child is to learn. It is for him to yiel(l, with docile spirit, to the culture and training which the parent sees fit to adopt. In physical nature, and mental discipline; in the education of the inanners and the lieart; in all that pertains to the culture, in its highest and most comprehensive sense, of body, mind, and soul, - the child is to hold himself ready, within those limits already specified, to be instructed, inoulde(l, tr-ined, by parental wisdom and care. In fault of this, all efforts of instruction will be unavailing, and the great end of faimily nurture andl discipline will be unattained. A stubborn and unyielding spirit, that sets itself in opposition to the wisdom and the counsels of the parent, and refuses to be guided thereby, is in itself a sin most deserving of rebuke, and which incurs, wherever found, the special d(lispleasuire of God. Very marked is the condemnation bestowed upon this sin in the Scriptures. Under the Jewvish lawe, it was even 1iunishable w-ithl death. "If a man have a stubborn and rebellious son, which will not obey the voice of his father, or the voice of his mother, and that, when they have chastened DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. 217 hiin, will not hearken to them: then shall his father and his mother lay hold on hiiii, and bring himr out unto the elders of his city, and unto the gate of his place; and they shall say unto the elders of his city, this our son is stutbborn and rebellious, he will not obey our voice; he is a glutton and a drunkard. And all the men of his city shall stone him with stones that he die; so shalt thou put evil away firom among you, and all Israel shall hear and fear" (Deut. xxi. 18-21). Very full and explicit are the precepts which inculcate the duty of cherishing the opposite spirit. "My son, keep the instr-ction of thy father, and forsake not the law of thy mother. They shall be an ornament of grace unto thy head, and chains about thy neck" (Prov. i. 8, 9). "Keep thy father's commandments, and forsake not the law of thy mother" (Prov. vi. 20). "A fool despiseth his father's iinstructions" (Prov. xv. 5). "A wise son heareth his flther's instructions, but a scorner heareth not rebuke" (Provr. xiii. 1).. 3. REVERENCE. - It is the duty of the child to treat his parents with that deference and respect that belong to those who are his superiors in age and wisdom, as well as in authority. Nothing is more unbecoming in a child than any want of respect toward his superiors, and especially toward his parents. They sustain to him a relation which peculiarly demands of him this deferential regard. They are the authors of his life. To themn he is indebted for the care and attention which have watched over him from infancy, provided for his wants, directed his education. To them he is rightfully subject by the laws of God and man; and to those sustaining to him this relation, and exercising this authority, he is bound, by the laws of nature 19 218 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATIOH and reason, to yield a respect and reverence which are idue to no one else on the earth. Nor is this claim abrogated by any rank or attainments on the part of the child, or by any deficiency of intellectual, social, or even moral worth andcl rank, oni the part of thle parent. These circumstances alter not thec relation of the two parties. The child,,as he growvs to maturity, may come to be wiser, wealthier, more distingllisledl, more virtuous even, than those who gave him birthl, aind brotught him up fiom infaicy to youth and malll.lo()(1. Hle is not, on these accounts, excused firom paying to them, so long as lic lives, and( they live, that respect and( reverence which ai( still their (due, and( which evely g,enerous iand manly spirit will esteem it a delight and an honor to shovw. The end of the fimlily institution, so fair as the child is concerned, is to fit him for the service of the state, and the service of his God; to be an honorable and useful member of society, and a candidate for immortal blesse(dness. In no way is this end more surely defeated, than by the want of due respect toward the parents; in no way more directly promoted, than by the carefuil observance of this duty. He who has not learned, or who has scorned to pay due respect and reverence to his parents, will not be likely to bow with submission and reverence before the majesty of the law. He who is wanting in deference to his earthly superiors and protectors, will not bc likely to yield the homage of the heart to his heavenly Father, or to humble himself, in adoration and lowliness of mind, before the Majesty of heaven and earth. He is poorly fitted for the duties of life, for the service of the state, and the service of his God, who knows not how to honor his parents Nothing is more graceful and fitting, nothing more honorable and ennobling to the character, than the exercise of this virtue; nothing, on the other hand, more unseemly, DUTIES OF TIlE PARENTAL RELATION. 219 and dishonorable, than the opposite vice. The blessing of God attends the one; his frown and curse, the other. "Honor thy father and thy mother - which is the first (onmmnandment with promise -that it may be well with thee, and thou niayest live long on the earth" (Eph. vi. 2, referring to Ex. xx. 12). "Cursed be he that setteth light by his father or his mother; and all the people shall say, Amen" (Deut. xxvii. 16). And yet again: "The eye that mnocketh at his father, and despisetli to obey his mother, the ravens of the valley shall pluck it out, and the young eagles shall eat it" (Prov. xxx. 17). 4. FILIAL AFFECTION AND GRATITUDE. -The duties which have already been named are incomplete without this. Those offices are to be performed not merely as duties, and because they are required by the laws and customs of society, by self-respect, and by the divine command, but from a higher principle than the single sense of duty,- firom love, the pure affection and deep gratitude of the heart. The relation in which our parents stand to us, entitles them to our sincere affection and gratitude. To no human beings are we so much indebted as to them. They have given us being; they have provided for our physical wants; have fed and clothed us; have watched our steps by day, and our slumbers by night; have denied themselves, that they might make better provision for us; have educated us in whatever of useful learning and of good manners we have acquired; have done what they could-it is to be hoped -to train us for usefulness and happiness here and hereafter. As we grow up, we may possibly perceive faults of character in them,- faults, perhaps, in their mode of educating and governing us; but no such defects, whether real or imagined, can ever discharge the obligation on our part of true and earnest gratitude and love. 220 DUTIES OF THE PARENTAL RELATION. The character that is wanting in this, is wanting in all that is manly and iioblc. The heart that lacks this emotion, is essentially a mean and selfish heart. Nor is this duty one that ceases to be required of us as we come ourselves to manhood. Time, in its never-ceasing progress, reverses the order in which life began: the child becomes a parent, and the parent by-and-by becomes again a child. The arms that held us in infiancy, require now the strength of our more robust and vigorous forms; the hands that toiled and the feet that moved so readily for all our wants, must now depend on us for support. By every little act of kindness and attention, by all the sweet and soothing ministry of love, it is for us to discharge that debt. Happy for us, if, over the grave of a parent, we never have occasion to drop a tealr of regret that we were in any measure negligent of this sacred duty. PART IV. THE STATE. CHAPTER I. NATURE AND FOUNDATION OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. IT has already been remarked that there exist in the world two great and distinct institutions,- thie Family and the Stctte,- having each its own organization, its own laws, its own object, its own proper duties. Of these, the former has already occupied our attention, and we approach now the consideration of the latter. The State what.- In order to clearness, we must ascertain precisely what is meant by the state. I understand by the state, a community organized under one form or system of government, and dwelling together, under that government, in one and the same territory. Those thus associated for purposes of government, compose the state. The word is frequently employed in a somewhat differ-. ent sense firom that now given,- sometimes, to denote the idea of civil government in the abstract, without reference to the aggregate of individuals tlhat compose the state; sometimes, also, to denote the pow-er that exercises autlihoiity iind administers law in tlhe community thus organized 19* DUTIES TO NATURE AND FOUNDATION as when Louis Fourteenth of Franuce (decluired, "I am the state." The true idea, however, of the st.:.tc, I take to be that already given. When we speak of the family, or of the state, as institutions, we do indeed use tlhose terms abstractly; but when we come to define mnore flully our meaning, we say, the family is a little community, consisting of those related by ties of mairriage and consanguinity, dwelling under one roof, and holding, property in coinmon; and, in like mannelr, we say, the state is a lager community, organized under one form of government, and dwelling together in the same country or territory. Not every Conmmnzity a St(te. - It is not every and any community, or company of men, that constitutes a state, even though they may inhabit the same teiriitory. They must be an organized community, and tlhat foi the lpurpose of government -a united whole, bound togetlhei by one and the same system of civil administration. A hlerd of wild beasts roanling together over the western prailies is a community; a horde of savages, scarcely less wild and lawless, may dwell together without the forms of civilized society; but neitl-her of these communities is a state. Those who came over in the pilgrimn bark, the MIay-Flower, were a community, united in one and the same great enterprise, yet only a collection of separate families and individuals, and nothing more, until, in the cabin of that little vessel, there was drawn up the inistrument that constituted them an organized community, and l)rescribed the form of their filture government; that instriument drawn and signed, they became firom that moment a state. It will be to our purpose, in the further discussion of the subject prol)osed( for consideration in the piescit clhapter, ')22 OF CIVIL GOVERNMrIENT. to inquire as to the origiya and object of civil government -hoWn suchl an institution ever came to be,'and for what ends designed; also, as to thie fout.,datiot on which it rests - whence comes its authority. These topics will be discussed in the following sections. ~ I.- ORIGIN AND OBJECT OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. ORIGIN OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT.- If we inquire for the origin of this institution,- the mnanner in wiichli such a thing as the state, or civil government, camne to be,-we must go back, doubtless, to a very early period of civilization- to the flist rude beginnings of human history. The germ of civil authority lies, if I mistake not, in the ftnily; the members of which, united by closest ties of sympathy and common interest, are subject to the parental authority and control. This is the first form of obedience, and the first kind of government. "A family," it is well said by Paley, "contains the rudiments of an empire. The authority of one over many, and the disposition to govern and to be governedl, are in this way incidental to the very nature, and coeval, no doubt, with the existence of the human species." It is easy to see how, from this simple beginning, the lprinciple of civil government, taking its rise, may have extenldedl, till, as now, it embraces nations and centuries in its sweep. The respect and homage due to the wisdom and authority of the parent, do not cease when the children app)roach the maturity of riper years. Around the tent of the father gather, in process of time, the tents of the children; the government of the family becomes gradually the government of many families, all united by ties of consanguinity and common origin, all owing and owning allegiance to a common ancestor. The general direction and 223 NATURE AND FOUNDATION control of the little community, thus enlarged by suces sive generations, would, by common consent, be vested ir the hands of that aged and honored ancestor, the patriarc, of the flock, the chief of the tribe. And thus we have the second step in the formation of civil government. The rapid increase of such a community would enlarge the boundaries of the original dominion, until, in course of time, the chief or patriarch of the tribe becomes the rulei of the nation. Large communities and empires would grow out of small ones, not only by the laws of natural growth, and increase of population, but by accessions of smaller and weaker tribes forming alliance with the stronger, for purposes of mutual advantage. The patriarch of the tribe, or chief of the clan, would be likely to gather about him many followers, in the capacity of servants and retainers, dependent on his bounty, and obedient to his command. Possessions, also, of land, cattle, jewels, and other treasures, would accumulate in his keeping. To the aristocracy and influence of birth there would in this way be added the authority which wealth bestows. In process of time, as the wealth of the tribe increased, and its numbers augmented, the temptation would be felt to employ these resources in the subjugation of neighboring and weaker tribes. The chief who should thus employ his personal wealth and followers to enlarge the boundaries, and extend the power of his tribe, would add not only to the authority of his clan, but to his own power as ruler; and so to the aristocracy of birth and of wealth would be added that of military prowess. This latter, ill process of time, and of human affairs, might come to be of more consequence than either of the former as an element of sovereignty. It is easy to see how, in the natural course of things, 224 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. these causes, combined, or even singly, would lead to the formation of great and powerful empires, from such small beginnings as we have indicated. And it is easy also to see how, starting with the idea of paternal government as its source and germ,- that is, of a power lodged in the hands of one, to be administered at his discretion, - the form of civil government should have been, in theory and in fact, essentially the power and authority of one over the whole; that is, monarchical. Whatever theory we adopt as the foundation of civil government,-whether we regard it as of direct divine authority, or as foiunded in social compact, or in the nature of man,- there can be little doubt that, as a matter of history, its origin and progress have been essentially what I have now indicated. OBJECT OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT.-Viewing civil government as an existing institution, we may naturally ask what is the end or object which it proposes to accomplish; what is the use, the advantage, the necessity for anything of the sort; why should not every man be his own ruler and sovereign? The sovereignty of the individual, I reply, would be inconsistent with the rights and fireedom of the whole. Every member of the community has an interest in the conduct of every other member. Every man is a conmposite element of the whole, and is bound to consult tIhe interests and wishes of the whole. If he were to have his own way, and consult only his own pleasure in everything, his choice would often interfere with that of others, and thus would result a conflict of choices; and not only would injustice thus be d(lone, often, to the weaker of two parties, but the general peace and order of the whole 225 NATURE AND FOUNDATION would be disturbed. "The fieedom of the individual," it has been well said, "is the bondage of the community." Objectioi. - But will not the same thing occur if gov ernment exists? it may be asked. Will that insure to every man his choice? Will not government itself inter fere with the choice of the individual, and restrain his freedom? So far as that freedom interferes with the general fieedom and the general order, I reply, it will doubtless be restrained under any system of wise and efficient government; and so far as this, it nleec(s to be restrained. In the nature of things, not every man call have his choice. The nearest approximation to this is, tlhat the choice of the greatest numnber shall prevail; in other words, that the will of the majority shall govern. In proportion as any government carries out the will of tlhe majority, and legislates for the good of thle whole, it accompl)lishes the great end of all civil governiiient; and lii so fir as it loses sight of this, or fails of this, it fails of reachling that end. Suppose, now, that, under existing government, an individual finds himself ill-suited,-his choices interfered with, his wishes disregarded, his rights taken from him,what redress, it may be asked, remains foi such a one? I reply: there will at least remain one resource, after all others have been tried in vain. If he finds it impossible to obtain justice, and to enjoy his rights in the community where lie is, let him peaceably withdraw from it, and join some other which he likes better; or, if none such can be found, it is in his power to cut himself off entirely firom his fellow-men, and live in a desert or a cave. It may be a hardslhip to (lo this; but it were betteri that a few should suffer hardship and loss, than that the many slhould be exposed to the dangers of lawlessness and anarchy. 226 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. Ends to be secured. - There are two leading objects ever to be kept in view and secured by civil government - public order and public freedom; - the formner for the sake of the latter, and the latter in the greatest degree that is compatible with the former. These ends will be most effectually secured in connection with the highest civilization and most rapid progress of the state. What ever promotes the one, promotes also the other. While, therefore, the state may not propose to itself, directly, as an end, the moral and religious culture and character of its citizens, it may, and must, aim to secure this as a nmeans, and a necessary means, to the end which it legitimately pursues, viz., the public order and fireedom. Virtue and religion are indispensable to the highest civilization and elevation of the people, and so to the public welfare, and cannot therefore be overlooked by any wise and intelligent government. These not the only Objects of Civil Government. — I have spoken of order and freedonm as leading objects to be secured by civil government; I would not affirm that they are the only objects for which government exists. It is possible, certainly, to conceive of a state of society in which every man should be upright and honest; in which the most perfect order should be realized; in which there should be, therefore, no crimes to punish, no lawlessness to rebuke, no irregularity or disorder to provide against. In such a community, as there would be the most perfect order, so also there would be the highlest possible degree of public freedom; consequently, there would be no need of government for these ends. If these were the only objects for which civil government exists, then there would be no need of government at all. Yet, even in such a commiunity, there would still be 227 NATURE AND FOUNDATION something for government to do. Its occasion and its proper functions would not wholly cease. There are certain matters of public utility and convenience - as, for example, the coinling of money, the making of roads, the disposal of property left without heirs, the regulation of commerce and of intercourse with other countries- which could not well be arranged without the existence of some form of government. In such matters, it would be necessary that some persons should be authorized to act in behalf of the whole; and such authority would constitute, in fact, a government. ~ II.- FOUNDATION OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. Having considered, in the preceding section, the origin and object of civil government, we are prepared now to inquire as to itsfootndcation. On what does this institution rest as its basis and support? Whence does it derive its authority? How comes government, in the person of magistrate, legislator, judge, and in' the form of law, written or unwritten, to have power over me, to restrain and govern my conduct, - a power extending to my person, my property, and even my life? What right has it to do this, and whence does it obtain this right? Suppose I should deny this right, and refuse this control-what then? Theory of DI)ivine Right. -There have been various theories respecting this matter. Accoiding to some, civil government is founded in the will of God: it rests on the basis of a divine right. This theory supposes that civil government is an ordinance of God; that as marriage and the family relation were of direct divine appointrient, so likewise the state; and that as we had no agency in instituting, so we have no choice in submitting to either 228 OF- CIVIL GOVERNMENT. of these arrangements, and no right to alter or dispense with either, but must take both as established facts, - part of the scheme of Providence and of the divine order of things, to which it is the duty of all men to conform. We are under government, and we must obey it, for the same reason that it is our duty to obey God in anything else that he may prescribe for us; and this obedience must be without hesitation or question. This view derives support from the fact that civil government origi)zates, as we have seen, from the family institution, -having its root there, and progressing, by slow and natural degrees, to its full and mature development. Now, unquestionably, the family is an institution of divine appointment, - a fact which exists by special arrangement and design of Providence. The paternal government is one under which we find ourselves on coming into the world, and which, whether we will or not, we are obliged to obey. And as, out of this existing fact, this authority independent of our will, civil government takes its rise, and by natural stages grows to be what it is, the inference seems plausible, that this also, like that from which it proceeds, is of special divine authority. Paley's View. -A modified form of this theory was advanced by Dr. Paley, who bases the obligation to obey civil government on the will of God as collected from expecie)cy. This view differs from the preceding, chiefly in that it assigns a reason for the will of God being what it is, viz., the expediency or advantage of such an institution to human welfare and happiness; whereas the former, somewhat more arbitrarily, refers the whole matter to the divine will, and leaves it there, without explanation or reason. The argument of Paley is summed up, by himself, in the following propositions: "It is the will of God that 20 229 NATURE AND FOUNDATION the happiness of human life be promoted." "Civil society conduces to that end." "Civil societies cannot be upholden, unless ill each the interest of the whole society be binding upon every part and member of it." Hence the conclusion, "that so long as the interest of the whole society requires it,-that is, so long as the established government cannot be resisted or changed without public inconvenience,-it is the will of God (which will universally determines our duty) that the established government be obeyed, and no longer." The argument is, not that government is expedient, and therefore we must obey; but that it is expedient, and therefore it is the will of God; and because it is his will, therefore we must obey. Theory of Social N-ature. -Dissatisfied with this manner of explaining the subject, others have taken a different view of the matter, and have sought the foundation of government in the moral and social nature of man. It is no longer, according to this view, the arbitrary and sovereign will of God, nor yet that will as governed by a regard to expediency, but rather the nature and constitution of man, that is the basis oin which civil government reposes. That nature fits him for, and leads him to adopt such an arrangement. It is his own institution, his own choice, his instinctive, natural preference. He frames laws, and appoints rulers, and submits himself to the control of those laws and those magistrates, on the same principle that the bee and other insects observe a certain order in the arrangement of their social affairs, and maintain a certain government, following the direction of their leader, because such is their nature. In like manner, the nature and constitution of man fit him to be a member of society and of the state, even as they fit him to be a member of the family. He adopts this method, and continues it, not because he finds these in 230 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT stitutions ready made, and imposed on him by the will of the Creator, arbitrary or otherwise, without choice of his own, but because he finds them exactly suited to his nature and wants. This theory was held by many of the ancient philosophers. It was the view maintained by Plato and Aristotle, among the Greeks. Aristotle calls man 7roXtTKov Zwov - a political animal. Theory of Social Compact.-There is still another tlheory of government, differing in some important respects from either of those already mentioned, - a view advocated by many distinguished writers, and, indeed, the prevalent one of modern times; I refer to the theory of social compact, as it is called. This view -advanced by Hobbes, adopted by several subsequent philosophers of note in England, and on the continent, by Shaftesbury, and essentially by Locke and his disciples -has come to be, if I mistake not, the prevalent view, both in England and our own country, and has been widely adopted by jurists and members of the legal profession, as the prin ciple on which civil government is supposed to rest. Ac cording to this theory, civil government is of the nature of a contract between man and man, in which each binds himself to fulfill certain conditions, and abide by certain rules, mutually agreed upon; which rules and conditions are binding so long as the contract stands. To these conditions it is the duty of every member of society to conform, for the same reason that it is his duty to abide by any other obligation or contract, or to keep any other engagement. Those who enter into this arrangement - and every one who lives in society, and enjoys its advantages, virtually and tacitly gives his consent and adherence to the arlangement -mutually agree to relinquish each certain 281 NATURE AND FOUNDATION individual and natural rights into the keeping of the whole, and for the benefit of the whole; in return for which, they are to receive certain privileges, and be guarded and pro tected in the full enjoyment of all their rights, personal and( civil. It is for the advantage of each to abide by these rules, and that others should do the same; hence the insti tution exists, and is continued from age to age. Objections to this Theory.- The view now proposed is by no means free firom objections. If civil government rests upon a compact, -a mutual agreement, or engagement, formed among men, -then when, and where, and by whom, was this agreement made? Where are the records, and what the history of the transaction? "No social compact similar to what is here described," says Paley, "was ever made or entered into in reality; no such original convention of the people was ever actually holden, or in any country could be holdlen, antecedent to the history of civil government in that country. It is to suppose it possible to call savages out of caves and deserts to deliberate and vote upon topics which the experience and studies and refinements of civil life alone suggest. Therefore no government in the universe began from this original." To this it may be replied, that the question is not now as to the origin of civil government -how it began -but as to its basis - on what it rests - what is the ground of the relation which we find existing between the citizen and the state, the governed and the governors. It is no answer to the theory under consideration, to say that no government ever began in that way. The question is not how and when it began, but, having a beginning and existence, as a matter of fact, does it, or does it not, rest upon the consent of the governed; is it, or is it not, of the nature of a contract? 232 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. Nor is it enough to say that no record of any such transaction exists-that no10 such contract in reality was ever made. Even if this were true, - which is by no means certain,- it might be none the less true that the existing governments are really of the nature of a contract or agreement among the people, that they virtually rest upon no other basis than the consent of the parties governed, even though we cannot point to any formal engagement to that effect, drawn up in so many words, and at such a time and place. Whether we can point to such original transaction or not, the real nature of the bond that holds society together as an organized body, may be precisely that of a mutual contract; and it may be very important for us to know, and to admit this truth. No other form of expression may so well and truly indicate the precise relations which exist between the different members of the body politic, and the reciprocal rights and duties of each, as that now in question. Further Reply. -It is by no means to be conceded, however, that there is not in existence, as a matter of fact, any such contract or mutual agreement as we are now speaking of. It is not a mere figment of the imagination, but a historic reality. There are, at least in every civilized nation, certain fundamental principles of law, and of civil polity, which, whether written or unwritten, are acknowledged, andl acted upon, as the basis of all civil administration of affairs. These, modified from time to time, and gathered at last into complete form, compose the constitution of the country, or the state. This constitution is an existing historic fact, and the fundamental principles which compose it existed in the public mind, and were acknowledged as such, long before they were collected into one body, reduced to form, and adopted as 20* 233 NATURE AND FOUNDATION a constitution. These principles and maxims, written or unwritten, are the terms of the social compact; and when, in the process of time, out of these principles, the constitution, as such, takes its distinct, manifest shape and form, that is the written, formal contract, by which all parties in the state agree to abide. As such it is regarded and treated by business-men, jurists, statesmen, lawyers - all, in fact, who have to do with affairs of state, whether in theory or practice. The constitutions of the several states of this republic are such compacts; they recognize themselves as such, and contain in themselves the articles of compact. Thus the constitution of Massachusetts: "The body politic is formed by a voluntary association of individuals. It is a Social Compact, by which the whole people covenants with each citizen, and each citizen with the whole people, that all shall be governed by certain laws for the common good." The constitution of Connecticut recognizes the same principle: "All men, when they form a social compact, are equal in rights." So, also, the opening words of the constitution of New Jersey: "All the constitutional authority ever possessed by the kings of Great Britain over their dominions, was by compact derived from the people, and held of them for the common interest of the whole society." Nor is this use of language unauthorized; for the vote of the English Parliament which deposed James-the Second, charges him with having broken the original conmpact between king and people. It is not true, then, that no such thing as a social contract exists in reality. Every state constitution, whether more or less complete and formal, is, in faict, such an instrument; all its articles are articles of mutual ngreement; and all those fundamental principles and maxims, of which it 234 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. is the collection and embodiment, are, and were before they were thus collected, and while as yet they lay unexpressed in the common mind, a virtual compact, having for its object the defining and securing to every one his rights. Another Objectio)z. —It is also objected, by Dr. Paley fnd others, to the theory now under consideration, that it supposes, what in general is not true, that men have actually given their consent to the government under which they live; whereas, in fiact, they have had, for the most part, no opportunity either to give or refuse their consent. The question has never been asked them, "Are you satisfied with this present arrangement of affairs, or do you desire a change?" But such consent, it is argued, is always implied in a voluntary engagement or contract; and where it is wanting, the transaction, what ever else it may be, is no contract. To call it so, is a misnomer - an expression both false and useless. Supposing that my ancestors framed and entered into such an agreement, called the constitution: how does their action bind me? What voice have I, what voice have I ever had, in the matter? Or what has any one of the fifty thousand or five hundred thousand inhabitants of the same city or state with myself, to do in the matter? And what right has any man, ancestor or not, to bind me in this way, without my consent? It must be confessed there is no little force in this objection. It must be confessed that men find themselves, by birth, members of whatever form of civil society exists around them, and that they have usually very little to do wnith shaping and forming the government under which they are to live. In this respect the state is clearly analogous to the family. It is not for a man to choose whether he will belong to this nation, or to that; to this family, 235 NATURE AND-FOUNDATION or to another, or to none. These things are decided for him. He is by birth a member of the family, and subject to parental rule. I-e is also by birth a member of civil society, and must take it as hle finds it; at least, for a considerable part of his life. Nor is it any answer to say, that such an arrangement is for the best good of the subject. Doubtless it is so. The question just now is, not whether it is a wise and beneficial arrangement, but whether it is binling; and if so, way, and on what ground? Suppose I lo Inot choose to be trammelled by this arrangement, which somebody else, a few centuries ago, thlought to be wise and expedient- what then? Suppose, even, I do not choose to submit to arrangements which are in reality for my own good? What right has one age and generation to bind another age, against its will, even to its own benefit? The true answer to this reasoning I conceive to be, that, by the very nature of human society, the engagemients of one generation must be held as binding upon those that come aftel, until at least they are directly rejected and annulled by the latter. Until such act of rejection, consent may fairly be presumed. Silence gives consent; the simple living under and complying with the conditions of such an arrangement, gives consent. As Paley himself says with respect to the laws which regulate the administration of justice: "The law of nature, founded in the very constitution of human society, which is formed to endure through a series of perishing generations, requires that the just engagements a man enters into should continue in force beyond his own life; it follows that the private rights of persons firequently depend upon what has been transacted in times remote from the present, by their ancestors or predecessors, or by those under 236 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. whom they claim, or to whose obligations they have suec ceeded." Now, this is true; but, as Dr. Whewell very justly re marks, it is no more true of private rights, than of any other; no more true of engagements which bind man and man, than of those which bind man and the state, since public rights, as well as private, and for the same reason. depend often on what was done by those who preceded us. The True.Explan ation.- I am far from maintaining, however, that the theory of a social contract is free from objections. Nor, on the other hand, can this be affirmed of either of the theories previously adduced. Each of them expresses an important element of truth. Neithei of them, as it seems to me, conveys the whole truth. Nor are these different theories necessarily exclusive of each other. On the contrary, it is only by combining whatever of truth is contained in each, with whatever is contained in the others, that we reach the complete expllanation, the true philosophy, of civil government. It is doubtless true, for example, that existing constitutions and forms of government are of the nature of a social contract, in which the parties bind themselves to observe certain conditions, for the sake of securing certain advantages; the parties being, severally, King and People; or King, Lords, and Commons, on the one hand, and people on the other, as in the case of the English government; or,,as in our own country, every man withl the whole people, and the whole people with every man. Nor is this the less a compact because formed and entered into by those who preceded the present generation. This, then, is the first fact which meets us in our inves-. tigation, -starting from the present actual condition of 231 NATURE AND FOUNDATION civil society, -the first step in the explanation of the phenomenon of human government. But if we were to stop here, we should leave much unexplained. How came man to form such compacts- everywhere, in all ages, and nations? Is it accidental? Is there not rathler a foundlation in his very nature for just this condition of things? Is he not, even, as Aristotle said, a political aninmal? Here, then, we must bring in a second theory, and place it beside, or rather beneath the first, - civil government is founded in compact, but that compact is founded in the social nature of man. Nor would I stop here. How comes he by this nature? Is it not the gift of God -an endowment conferred upon the creature by the all-wise Creator? Did not God, in making man as he is, and conferring upon him this social nature, intend that he should be subject to civil authority? Here, then, we bring in still a third theory, -that of the divine will, - and place it at the foundation of the whole Civil government is founded in compact; but that cornm pact, again, depends on the nature of' man; and this, in turn, rests ultimately on the will of God. Of -Divine Authority in what Sense. - According to the view now presented, civil government is of divine authority in this sense, and in this sense only, -that by the constitution of things, and of human nature, God has settled it that civil government, of some sort, there shall be; but of what sort it shall be, he has left it for men themselves to decide; and this they do decide, each community or people for itself, by some sort of social compact or agreement. It is not in the nature of things for any community of human beings to consent to live together without any form of government; and, in point of fact, the rudest and wildest community on earth will be found 238 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. to have provided itself with some kind, and some degree of civil government. i III. - HISTORIC SKETCH. - DIFFERENT OPINIONS AS TO THE NATURE OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. In the preceding sections the nature and foundation of civil government have been discussed as regards their general principles. It may serve to fix these principles more definitely in our minds, and perhaps contribute to the clearer apprehension of them, if we trace, in its general outlircs, the history of the topic now under consideration, as regarids the opinions which have been held by writers of distinction respecting the nature of civil government. Opiniois of the Ancients.- The idea of the state as a natural and a necessary institution, having its foundation in the very nature and constitution of man, was familiar to the ancients. Thus Aristotle: "It is manifest that the state is one of- the things which exist by nature; and that man is by nature a political animal. A man belonging to no state is less than man, or more." This view, however, by no means prevented them from regarding civil government, at the same time, as of divine origin, founded in the will of Deity. "All laws," says Plato, "came from God. No mortal man was the founder of laws." Aristotle coincides with this view. "Law," says Cicero, "is nothing else but right reason, derived firom the divinity, and government an emanation of the divine mind." The classical scholar need not be reminded that the writings of the ancient masters are pervaded with this sentiment. Nor, again, does this divine origin of governlnent prcclude, in their opinion, the consent of the governed, as in 239 NATURE AND FOUNDATION reality the proximate source of power. Locke is not, as often stated, the author of this theory of government; on the contrary, it is a principle recognized in substance by the most distinguished political philosophers of the ancient world; and that in perfect consistency with their view of the divine origin of government. The idea of a social compact is no novelty in the world. Plato makes "a tacit agreement between each member, and the whole community," to be the foundation of the state, and affirms that they who violate the laws, violate the agreement. "The civil law," says Aristotle, "is that which takes place amongst a number of free persons, who are members of the same community, in which they live on a footing of equality." "The state," says Cicero, "is not every assemblage of men anyhow gathered, but a community united together by common laws, common interest, and a common consent." In like manner, Livy affirms that the force of the supreme command is based on the consent of those who obey. Of the [oderns. - Among the moderns, the doctrine of the dlivine origin of government has been very generally held by English divines and statesmen. Subjection to the civil power, in the language of B)ishop Horsley, is "a coIInscientious submission to the will of God." "Civil government," says Bishop Btetler, "is that part of God's government over the wvorld which he exercises by the instrumentality of men. Considering that all power is of God, all authority is properly of divine appointment." The view of D). P)(ley has already been stated. He bases the autlhority of government on the will of God as collected from exlpediency. The following is the language of Edmund Burke: "All dominion over man is the effect of the divine 240 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. disposition. It is bound by the eternal laws of him that gave it, with wliielh no humana authlority can dispense. * * * YWe are all born in subjection -all born equally, high and l(w, governors and governed, in subjection to one gieat, immutable, preexistent law, prior to all our devices, and all our contrivances, paramount to all our ideas, and all our sensations, antecedent to our very existence, -by which we are knit and connected in the eternal frame of the universe, and out of which we cannot stir. This great law does not arise out of our conventions, or compacts; on the contrary, it gives to our compacts and conventions all the force and sanction they caii have." Coincident with the views now expressed is that of the great theologian Calving: "The reason why we should be subject to magistrates, is, because they are al)pointed by the ordinance of God. Since it has pleased God( so to administer the government of this world, he who resists their power, strives against the divine ordinance, and so fights against God. Because, to disregard his providence who is the author of civil government, is to go to war with him." These words are a comment upon a passage in the thirteenth chapter of the epistle to the Romans, in which the divine authority of civil government is very clearly set forth, and which may be regarded as not merely the Pauline, but the general Scripture doctrine of human government. iVeot InSconsistent with Social Compact.- But, while maintaining the views now stated respecting human government, as founded in the will of God, and ultimately deriving its authority from that high source, the writers whom I have quoted by no means maintain that the variOtts forms which human governments practically assume are also and equally of divine authority. On the contrary, 21 241 NATURE AND FOUNDATION they recognize the form as a matter of human invention and choice; and so, and that not inconsistently, they recognize, in mnany cases, the principle of the social compact. So, also, as we have seen, did Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero, while, in like manner, tracing back all law to a divine original, nevertheless admit the consent of the governed as the proximate source of authority in the state. Thus Bishop ftorsley, whom I have already quoted, while maintaining " that all government is in such sort of divine institution, that, be the form of any particular government what it may, the submission of the individual is a principal branch of that religious duty whichll each man owes to God," is careful to admit "that all p)articulcar fourths of government wlhich now exist are the work of human policy, under the control of God's overruling providence." They have not thought it, therefore, at all inconsistent with their theory of the divine authority of civil government, to inquire into the origin and sources of political power, as a thing of human contrivance and social compact. For, as has been well stated by Puffendorf, in his Law of Xature and Nations, "he who affirms sovereignty to result imnmediately from compact, doth not in the least detract firom the sacred character of civil government, or maintain that princes bear rule by human right only, not by divine." The doctrine of Social Compact has been held, in fact, by almost all the chief writers on Moral and Political Philosophy in modern times. Puffendorf, Grotius, Montesquieu, Blackstone, Milton, Bacon, Sidney, Locke, Barbeyrac, Burlamaqui, John Q. Adams, Jefferson, are among the more prominent names which occur in this connection. Of these, it will be sufficient to quote as authority Grotius and Blackstone. The former says: "Men, not iiluenced by the express command of God, but of their own accord, having 242 OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. experienced the weak defence of separated families against the assaults of violence, united themselves in civil society, the effect of which was civil power, styled on this account, by St. Peter, the ordinance of man." Blackstone hlolds the following language respecting "the original contract of society." "This contract, though perhaps in no instance has it ever been formally expressed at the first institution of a state, yet in nature and reason must be always understood and implied, in the very act of associating together; namely, that the whole should protect all its parts, and that every part should pay obedience to the will of the whole; or, in other words, that the community should guard the rights of each individual member, and that, in return for this protection, each individual should submit to the laws of the community." The same authority, than which none is higher, pronounces the coronation oath taken by the monarchs of England on ascending the throne, to be, without dispute, an express and fiundamental contract. This has always been the doctrine of the English Whigs. They acted on it when they brought Charles I. to the bar, and deposed James II. As already stated, the constitutions of these United States are based on the same great principle -the Social Compact. CHAPTER II. VARIOUS FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. THE origin and object of civil government, and also the foundation on which it rests, have occupied our attention in the preceding chapter. A glance at the various forms 243 VARIOUS FORMS which government assumes in its actual working, and at the dlistribution of its several powers, will enable us the better to comprehend tlhe practical duties, growing out of these several relations, as they miay come up for consideration in the subsequent chapters. ~I. L-ANALYSIS OF THE SEVERAL FUNCTIONS AND FORMS OF GOVERNMENT. It has been already observed, that every state is sovereign and independent-the power of directing its own affairs lying wholly in its own hands. The state, in its aggregate capacity, however, cannot administer government, nor eniiact laws, nor execute justice. The whole mass of the people cannot leave their places of business, assemble in one body, and so devote their personal attention to the affairs of government, the devising of suitable laws and regulations, or the trial and punishment of offenders. Evidently, this is out of the question. Hence the necessity for delegated authority. The state, which is the real sovereign, - that is, the people, - must commit its power, for the time, into the hands of those duly appointed and authorized to act for it, and whose acts, when thus commissioned, shall be in reality the action of the state. Now, as these officers, charged with the administration of government, vary as to number, and mo