I ILLINOI S UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS AT URBANA-CHAMPAIGN PRODUCTION NOTE University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Library Brittle Books Project, 2013. COPYRIGHT NOTIFICATION , In Public Domain. Published prior to 1923. This digital copy was made from the printed version held by the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. It was made in compliance with copyright law. Prepared for the Brittle Books Project, Main Library, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign by Northern Micrographics Brookhaven Bindery La Crosse, Wisconsin 2013 SOLON OF ATHENS THE POET, THE MERCHANT AND THE STATESMAN An Inaugural Lecture delivered before the University of Liverpool BY C. F. LEHMANN-HAUPT, LL.D., PH.D. GLADSTONE ON FRIDAY, PROFESSOR OF GREEK FEBRUARY I6, 1912 AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS OF LIVERPOOL 1912 57 ASHTON STREET. NoTE.-The small type numerals in the text refer to the notes at the end. The fragments of Solon's poems are quoted according to the numbering in Hiller-Crusius' Anthologia Lyrica (' H.-C.'). ERRATA Page Io, paragraph 3, 1. 6, read icar'. Page 25, 1. 9, read ' IT 5/6: 10/9.' Page 30, VII, 1. 8, read 'Seisachtheia ' Page 5o, 1. 2, strike out 'other.' Page 51, n. 15, 1. I, read ' f.' ; n. 16, last but one line, after Dialekte insert ' p. 368 f.'; p. 51, last line, read ' rir.' Page 52, n. 26, 1. 4, p. 53, n. 31, 1. I, and p. 54, n. 34, 1. 6, read ' Uber.' Page 55, n. 41, 1. 2., ' Aristoteles.' lead ' weltbeherrschende '; n. 45, read SOLON The Poet, the Merchant, and the Statesman T HE study of Greek is at present in a critical state, not only in England but also in Germany and other countries. The Greek question may indeed be considered an international one. Greek will soon cease to be a compulsory part of higher education. The place of compulsion will be taken by freedom of choice, and, whether we regret the lowering of the general standard, or welcome liberty as a most effective element of true learning and research, as the Greeks themselves have taught us, we have to face the fact, and we face it with good confidence. For not only have the treasuries of Greek thought and Greek culture which underlie our own always succeeded in attracting and holding the youthful mind, but our own times have witnessed a marvellous increase of these treasuries. The three names, Mycenae, Crete and Egypt, suffice to call to our mind some of the chief sources of this increase. Our knowledge of the civilisation of the mainland and the islands of Greece has been extended far backward to many centuries before the Trojan War, a period when the soil, which was later inhabited almost exclusively by the Greeks, was being prepared by people of a very different race, and thus was produced the mingling of races which more and more proves to be an important element in the development of civilisation. And Egypt, owing to the peculiarities of her climate, has begun to show her gratitude for the benefit of Greek culture by rendering from her 3 p S7700 bosom literary treasures which have been entrusted to her keeping for many centuries. And, lo, Aristotle's' Constitution of Athens' and Menander's Comedies, Timotheos' nomos 'the Persians,' the poems of Bacchylides, the mimes of Herondas, Didymos' Commentaries to the speeches of Demosthenes and a most valuable Greek historian have, among others, been in part given back to us,1 along with an inexhaustible fund of other papyri relating to Greek and Hellenistic law, government, religion and finance. This wealth, growing day by day, tends not only to enrich our material but to deepen the knowledge of Greek life and Greek achievements throughout. Greek philology then has, apart from its intrinsic merits, the great advantage of being an evolutionary science, and this in itself is one of the greatest enticements to student and scholar. Philology has for its primary object the knowledge of the language and the verbal interpretation of the author's meaning. This in itself is a vast field, comprising as it does, the knowledge not only of all the different styles and kinds of speech in prose and poetry, but also of the dialects for their own sake and as a necessary preliminary to the comparative philology of the Greek language as one of the chief branches of the great Indo-European family of speech. And I may be allowed to add as the result of the short experience I have had in teaching Greek in this University, Greek philology necessarily also includes the knowledge of the sound and the rhythm of the language in poetry and in prose. Our chief aim in learning Greek must not be to know how to translate Greek into English but to understand Greek in itself, and to delight in the music of its language without translating it into a modern idiom. In our efforts towards this result in England we shall I am sure, be greatly helped by the unity of pronunciation lately recommended by the Classical Association. But philology, in its true sense, has a much wider application. It involves the lofty duty of fully understanding and exhausting the meaning of the Greek authors, not only as to the language, but as to their full scope and content. That the writings of the Greek philosophers can only be understood by a combination of philological and philosophical training and education, will be universally acknowledged. Philology, however, is furthermore a historical science. In the first place it deals with language, which as long as it is spoken is a living organism, only to be grasped historically. And secondly it should go without saying that a Greek historian cannot be read with anything resembling a true profit for the reader without a knowledge of Greek history, or at any rate the ardent desire to acquire it. Thus philology and history are not opposed or distinct but intimately linked with each other. It is, therefore, perhaps not without significance that two successive Professors of Greek should have been appointed in the University of Liverpool, who have made history their chief pursuit. Again, what use is there in reading descriptions of Greek life and Greek authors without a knowledge of the arrangements and institutions of public and private life, of which the key is held by Archaeology, either by itself or combined with history,--not to speak of jurisprudence in its application to private and public law. Two chief points of view would therefore present themselves for an illustration of the principles of Greek philology; the importance of the new material, and the necessity of taking philology in its deepest and widest sense. What theme, then, should a new Professor of Greek in this University, who wishes to emphasise these two points, choose for his Inaugural Address ? It is the Gladstone Chair to which he has been appointed, and since the study and teaching of Greek in this University are for ever associated with the memory of a great statesman, born in Liverpool, who was at the same time a Greek scholar of no common order, the first idea would naturally be to select a subject from the range of his research and to discuss some of the innumerable and deeply interesting problems of Homeric study, or to discuss Gladstone's view of Homer as a whole. This, however, was admirably done by my predecessor, Professor Myres. But the fact remains that the Chair of Greek was established in memory of a statesman whose high character and devotion to his country were recognised by friend and foe alike. Our minds are thus naturally directed to that Greek statesman, the integrity of whose character and intention is universally acknowledged, and who through his love for his native city and his insight into the exigencies of her development, laid the foundation for her future greatness. Though at first sight it would appear to be a merely historical subject, yet none could be more appropriate to the present occasion. For Solon was not only a statesman who left his mark in Greek Literature, but also--a fact not sufficiently recognised--a poet whose writings have the unique merit that they show us the political and social ideas of the statesman at different moments of his career, giving the programme of his reforms, illustrating his opinions from various points of view, defending what he had achieved against attacks and reproaches from all sides. Hence the general scope and the unity of his aspirations are preserved to us in a delightful variety of momentary impressions and changing moods. How rare an occurrence this is, we shall realise in glancing at a document which bears a certain relation to these invaluable utterances of Solon's ideas, the so-called Monumentum Ancyranum in which the Emperor Augustus summed up his deeds and the achievements of his life. Here also the originator of a new departure in the constitutional history of one of the most important peoples of antiquity attempts to convey to posterity his political principles as well as the chief stages of his career. And it has recently been shown that most probably this document, though claiming to be written in the last year of Augustus' life has a much longer and more complicated history.2 Still it breathes the same premeditated consciousness throughout. In the nature of the case we should look in vain for the delightful spontaneity and naivete of Solon's kaleidoscopic expressions, and when we consider other autobiographical productions of statesmen of antiquity' their distance from Solon's sayings would appear all the more pronounced. I was justified then in applying the term unique to this part of Solon's literary productions. This very important point has as yet not been sufficiently emphasised. It is true that it could not have been recognised with the necessary clearness before Aristotle's 'Constitution of Athens' had been found in Egypt; for, firstly, some very significant fragments of Solon's political poetry have thus been brought to our knowledge. Secondly, the intimate connection between Solon's poetry and his statesmanship has never been brought out so distinctly as in the words of Aristotle that the Athenians elected Solon to be their archon and their conciliator, since he had composed a certain elegy, hitherto unknown to us, in which he gave vent to his grief at the troubled state of affairs in Athens defending the struggling parties one against the other.4 Solon then, in whom the poet and the statesman are linked together inseparably, would attract us, but there is another feature which adds greatly to ,the interest we take in him on this occasion. The University of Liverpool is prominent among a number of new Universities, all of which have been established in great city centres, and are intimately connected with the life of the community. But whereas most of these cities are industrial centres, Liverpool is the most important of the very few among these new seats of learning, whose life depends on the sea. Solon was not only the law-giver and ruler of a city which was to be one of the greatest sea-ports of antiquity, but he was himself a merchant, and what he strove to do and did for Athens cannot be rightly understood if this very important point is overlooked or undervalued. Solon as a merchant was fully aware that the way to greatness for his native city lay in the field of commerce, and it is he who consciously opened out the path for her development in this direction. Now the new Gladstone Professor of Greek, who has the honour of addressing you, having been born and educated in the greatest commercial city of Germany, which has been and is in very intimate connection with the great commercial city of Liverpool, has naturally been imbued with, the knowledge of and a high regard for the importance and the civilising mission of commerce both in bygone and in present times. There is, besides, a great movement for founding a new University in his native City of Hamburg. Furthermore, he himself has come to Liverpool after long experience as a teacher in one of the youngest but now the foremost among the German Among his students in Berlin were Universities. several of the younger English scholars who have won distinction in the field of Greek and of Ancient History. The friendly competition and the intimate connection between England and Germany in the field of Classical studies is not only universally acknowledged but also emphasized in this University of Liverpool, her regulations enforcing that Honours in Classics can only be taken by a student who is able to use German authorities for his work. So the new Gladstone Professor of Greek hopes that, in speaking to you about Solon, the merchant, who was at the same time a great statesman and a poet, an undercurrent of mutual understanding, reaching beyond a common interest in Classical studies, will prevail and be felt at the present moment and hereafter. I Now in turning to Solon, and before considering his personality in the three aspects which call for our attention, let us first make clear the chief facts of his life and the state of Athens before he began to shape her destiny. Solon died in 561 B.c., advanced in years. He may have been born about 640 or between this year and 625. His year of office and legislation was 594, after which he went abroad for ten years, 593/2-584/3. All his most incisive measures were carried out in this one year when he held the office of Archon. Indeed it is very significant that though the powers with which he was entrusted as public conciliator went far beyond the limits of this office, he never wished to be more than Archon himself. The preceding history of this office is all we know of the former history of Athens. Here, as elsewhere, there had been kings in olden times; but when the kingship lost its significance and dwindled into a merely religious function, the real ruler in the state was the Archon ca' goxjvY. At first he held office for life, but after an attempt at usurpation by Alcmaeon, the head of the Alcmaeonids, whose ambition was to prove a definite factor in the evolution of Athenian history, he was appointed for ten years. From 683 B.c. he held office for only one year, which was designated by his name, and hence the title Archon Eponymus. A third, the Archon Polemarchus, had also been instituted for purposes of war, and these three together with the six Thesmothetae, instituted not later than the seventh century, constituted the College of the nine Archons under the presidency of the Archon Eponymus. It is, however, worthy of notice that it was in fact Solon himself with whom the collegiate character of the Archonship really originated, for whereas different buildings had been allotted to the Archon, the Polemarch and the Thesmothetai, Solon united all of them in the Thesmotheteion. 5 And the remarkable fact that the great work of IO arawing up the new code was carried out in less than a year, is evidently accounted for by the help which the legislator received, at least in minor matters, from his colleagues, especially the Thesmothetai.5 To speak of Solon chiefly as the legislator, is not merely a convenient abbreviation. Solon, it is true, was more than a legislator in the general meaning of the term: he was the founder of But it will not only appear Athenian democracy. that all his measures of constitutional reform were embodied in his code of laws but, what is more, and what has been emphasised in Alfred Zimmern's brilliant book on the Greek Commonwealth, 6 Solon was the founder of the Athenian democracy, not so much because he gave the people power in public policy but because he secured them justice or fair play. This we shall realise at once in glancing upon those three of Solon's achievements which Aristotle, who had Solon's poems to guide him, singled out as specially far-reaching in the direction of democracy.7 'First and most important of all, he forbade men to borrow money on the security of their own persons. Secondly he allowed any one, who wished, to exact legal vengeance for those who were suffering wrong.' This would sound rather strange to us if we did not know that formerly only the one who had been wronged could himself apply to the Areopagus showing which law had been infringed to wrong him.8 'Thirdly, and this is what they say gave the mass of people their greatest leverage, there was the appeal to the people's court; for once the mass of the people are masters of the verdict they become masters of the constitution.' Athens up to Solon's time had had only a very II modest share in the great evolution, at one economic, social and commercial, which is characteristic of Greek life in the eighth and seventh centuries, and which originated chiefly in the Ionian cities of Western Asia, when agriculture could no longer sustain all the members of the aristocracy on the narrow .and not always productive fringe of the coast of Asia Minor, inhabited by the Greeks when colonies were founded all over the Black Sea and over the North West coasts of the Mediterranean, except where the Phoenicians and the Carthaginians had settled before and prevented it. Then riches began to pour in, and to the old nobility of birth the distinction of wealth was added. Agriculture and commerce, landed gentry and merchants, came into social and political competition. The whole standard of life began to be changed, the ideals of the knighthood began to fade, Greek mediaeval traditions made way for modern views, not without a struggle, to be sure. The Ionian inhabitants of Euboea, especially the cities of Chalcis and Eretria, joined in this development, in which also some Dorian communities on the continent of Greece, especially Corinth, Megara and Aegina were involved. An outcome of this fermentation is the growth of a new kind of monarchism, the tyranny. The men who established this form of absolute government were as a rule of noble or of mixed origin, but, having been raised to eminence by the wave of popularity, they were to a certain degree the advocates of the unenfranchised classes. As to the origin of the tyranny, an ingenious theory has lately been started, namely, that the commercial development which is characteristic -- I2 of the time at which tyranny flourished in Greece, was not only a contemporary phenomenon, but the reason for the development of tyranny itself.9 The founder of the tyranny 'would have been the man who turned to greatest advantage for political purposes the unique commercial conditions of the age in which he lived '; a theory which certainly has its merits, but will probably not be considered as the only explanation of this phenomenon. Now if Athens' share, especially in the commercial aspect of this new development, had hitherto been more than modest, it was not because there had been no need for commercial activity. On the contrary, if the mainland of Greece is stony and lacks a liberal supply of water, 10 these drawbacks are a peculiar feature of Attica, where the fertile plains are as rare comparatively as in Palestine, or rarer still. The inhabitants of Attica, then, had to look to commerce and industry as a means of gaining what the soil of their native country refused to yield in abundance. Pottery especially was taken up, and the vases found near the Dipylon and the like, bear ample testimony to the mastership of the Athenian craftsmen in early times. To the workers in clay, those in stone are to be added. Some other classes of skilled Athenian earners are enumerated by Solon himself in one of the poems of his old age," the only one which has been preserved to us completely, and in which he sums up the true goal and aim of life and endeavour.1 2 Here the metal worker and the weaver are mentioned along with the poets or rather reciters, the diviners and the doctors. But side by side with the skilled farmer the trader takes his place. And 13 the Athenian pottery at. least had begun to be exported on a large scale along with that of Miletus and Corinth, and in the same way as that of Crete! in heroic times. A general desire, moreover, for commercial expansion must have been alive when in the seventh century18 the colony of Sigeion was founded on the coast of the Troad. Sigeion was situated near the straits which led from the Aegean to the Black Sea, and through which the commerce with the grain of Southern Russia, to speak in modern terms, had to :ass. But Athens was kept from entering into free commercial competition by her immediate neighbours, the Megareans on one side, the Aeg-inetans on the other. In the meantime the consequences of the new economic departure began to bear upon the social and political life of Athens. The smaller farmers, who worked for the rich nobility and had to hand over to their masters a considerable part of theproduce of their fields," ' fell into debt which was followed by bodily servitude. The industrial and commercial part of the population was opposed -o the nobility, and contested their rights. Profiting by this state of affairs, Theagenes, tyrant of Meg:ra, tried to get the better of Athens by an escapade, carried out by his son-in-law, a rich Athenian, named Kylon. The Kylonians occupied the Acropolis, and Athens would have become subject to Megara, but for the vigilance of the Alcmaeonids. But in overwhelming the Kylonians, the Alcmaeonids incurred the guilt of blood, and were banished from Athens. The importance of this. fact and its further consequences cannot be dwelt upon here. The 14 immediate consequences for, Athens were the purification of the city by, Epimenides, who came from Grete, the home of ancient legislation, and the attempt at a mitigation of the social contrasts in Athenian life by Dracon's code of laws. Solon by the circumstances of his life may have witnessed the Kylonian outrage in his youth or his childhood. He certainly must have remembered the institution of Dracon's laws and his constitution, if such there was.1 5 It is worth while to bear in mind that little more than a quarter of a century separated Solon's from the preceding legislation. Both were to a certain degree brought about by the strained relations between Athens and Megara. The chief point of quarrel between the two city states was the island of Salamis which bars the Bay of Eleusis. Its possession was a vital question for the Athenians, and it was all the more ardently defended by their adversaries. At this point Solon's career in public life as a poet and patriot really begins. II What we value most in Solon's poetry is the insight which his verses give into his political views and their development. He is not so much the poet in the highest sense of the word, the conceiver of lofty views and of striking and picturesque metaphors, swayed by intense emotions of the heart, which find their vent in passionate and sounding verses: he has himself characterised the purport of his poems, at the outset of his activity as a politician and a poet, in a manner that cannot be surpassed. After a hard struggle the Megarians had at last 15 got the better of the Athenians and had definitely occupied Salamis and, if tradition is right a law had been passed forbidding the citizens even to mention the name of the island. One day, however, Solon appeared in the market addressing his fellow citizens in an ode, the beginning of which I am able to quote in English verse. That this can be done here and in many following instances is due to the kindness and ability of Mr. R. C. Lehmann which, I am sure, will be greatly appreciated by my audience. I with a song on my lips, from Salamis came as a herald, Deeming a rhythm of words better than prose in a speech ! This in truth holds good for all his poems as far as they refer to public life. In fact, though speeches were certainly made as Solon himself hints, the literary form of speech had not yet been developed; there was no prose literature, though Draco and Solon in framing their laws, are to be looked upon also as the founders of Attic prose writing. The difficulties which Solon encountered in shaping his laws are especially referred to by Aristotle; they lay to a great degree, though of course not entirely, in the matter of language. The bulk' of Solon's poems, then, were speeches in verse and this accounts for the fact that they are sometimes rather commonplace in their style and that not all of Solon's metaphors are of the same striking and suggestive vigour. But, besides, there certainly are many qualities in Solon's poems which are essential to the poet, and which we shall at once discover in examining the few other fragments which remain of his poem on Salamis. i6 Would I could then declare, ' Pholegandros or Sikinos owns me; No man of Athens am I: lo, I have changed my abode.' Yea, for a rumour would run, and a man would say to his neighbour ' Salamis he has betrayed being of Attican breed.' Onward to Salamis all, to fight for the beautiful island, Onward in honour and faith, dropping the burden of shame ! (H.-C. i) The last two lines, being evidently the conclusion of the whole poem or speech had the effect, of forcing the Athenians to follow Solon as their leader and to conquer Salamis. There is, then, a ruling passion in Solon not concerned with his private affairs, the passion of patriotism and of the courage it inspires, and this passion is combined with a considerable fervour of indignation against cowardice and lukewarmness. As for Solon's devotion to his country, it possesses a special feature inasmuch as Solon is, at least as far as we can see, the first advocate of Athenian and Attic patriotism. He considers, and to a certain degree rightly considers, Attica as the oldest country of the whole Ionian tribe, and he wishes to bring Athens into a position worthy of this privilege. He is the first author who consciously mentions the Attic language as a separate unity ; this he does in one of his most noticeable poems, which we shall consider later on. And withal Solon is the first who ever used the Attic language for literary purposes, introducing Attic instead of Ionic forms into his elegiac and iambic poems, 6 thus also in the sphere of literature anticipating the greatness of Athens, which he was about to build up. If this feature of his poetry sprang from his high-minded patriotism, there is apart from that 17 a remarkable power in Solon's language, the faculty of forming new words, which likewise is one of the qualities that constitute a poet. When he wishes to bring home to the Athenians the shame of their attitude with regard to Salamis, he forms the one word 'aXZaxuva0b'rjC,' the relinquisher of Salamis, and pictures the ordeal of an Athenian abroad passing through a crowd of foreigners pointing with their fingers at him and whispering this contemptuous word. And again, when the poet Mimnermus of Colophon had wished to die without previous sufferings as a man of sixty years, Solon-whether younger or older than Mimnermus has been much discussed, but is of very little consequence 7-- advises him to put eighty years instead of the sixty (H.-C. Mimn. 6; Sol. 19). MIMNERMOS : If, free from grief or sickness, a man might yield his breath, When sixty years have crowned me I fain would find my death. SOLON : Oh let me still persuade you to cancel what you said, Nor chide me if I show you a better way instead. Change, change your song, sweet singer and take a longer breath; Add twenty years to sixty before you think of death. I would not have a death-bed where every cheek is dry ; May there be friends who weep my loss when I shall come to die. Here Solon not only follows his contemporary in the formation or application of the word sexagenarian, it by octogenarian, replacing i ?covra~'rl, 3yoicovTrarfs, but also addresses his fellow poet by a name which has greatly puzzled modern interpreters and which has only lately been shown not to be a family name, or anything of the kind, but a word formed by Solon in a genial way calling Mimnermus the limpid singer: the xtryv's otSo's becomes a Atyvo-T6rds. III Another important characteristic of Solon's poems is their reference to foreign countries visited by their author. The travels which he undertook after his Archonship, in search of fresh experience as well as for the sake of trade, are thus confirmed. But a fresh light is thrown on the growth and development of Solon's personality, by the fact, as yet not universally admitted, that even in his youth long before his work as legislator, he had undertaken voyages in pursuit of merchandise. If we consider the allusions in the poems as referring to his later journeys alone, we may gather that he visited Egypt, and especially the great emporium of Ionian and Greek commerce, the city of Naucratis, 'near the mouth of the Canobian arm of the Nile' (H.-C.z5); Cyrene and Cyprus, to which Lydia must be added; not, of course, on account of the legendary interview with Croesus, discredited for chronological reasons even in Plutarch's day, though he refused to reject a story so celebrated, so well-established, so thoroughly in harmony with Solon's character, and so worthy of his high-minded wisdom. For all that, we need not discard as a pure invention the story that Croesus in his misfortunes recalled 1 words uttered by Solon," for if, as was undoubtedly the case, Solon visited Lydia during the reign of Alyattes, he would in all probability have been consulted by the king, and his words of warning and advice would be remembered afterwards in the day of Lydia's misfortune. '9 That Solon's advice was sought for after he had become renowned as the legislator and reformer of his native city, is proved by his verses to Philokypros, King of Soloi in Cyprus. You, may you dwell in your city, and hold a long kingship in Soloi, Living at ease in your house, girt with your people, your own. But for myself, may Cypris, the violet crowned, the divine one, Grant that I sail unscathed, swift from the glorious isle; So shall my honour increase with her favour for helping to found you, Soon to be sped, as I wish, safe to the land of my sires. (H.-C. 18) From these verses we see that Solon had assisted the king in founding the city of Soloi. We also see that Cyprus and Soloi were the last stage of Solon's ten years' absence from Athens after his Archonship, and that he returned direct to Athens with the ship which King Philokypros manned for him. But let us now turn to Solon's early travels. Everyone who knows that Solon in his later years went to sea for commercial purposes would necessarily infer that this was not a taste acquired in later years, after his having risen to the highest place in the esteem of his fellow-citizens. And, furthermore, there is ample intrinsic proof that many of the chief measures of Solon as the statesman and legislator could only have been initiated by a man who was professionally versed in commercial matters--but we are not limited to this internal evidence alone. Plutarch in his life of Solon, which is in great measure based on the poems of Solon or upon sources which utilised them, " says expressly that Solon went out for the sake of commerce as a young man; and he gives as the reason that his father Exekestides, had spent a good part of his fortune in helping others and that Solon, although there would 20 have been many who would have liked to help him, preferred to make his own way, being descended from a noble house which was accustomed to help others. " And it is again Plutarch who tells us that the verse referring to Naucratis was written by Solon not with reference to his visit after his legislation but on a previous occasion, thus evidently alluding to the journeys of Solon the youth. 2 ' That Solon in this way took commerce for his vocation is significant in itself, as it shows that Athens too was becoming affected by the general social and economic development which had originated in lonia. But with Solon this step meant more. It involved the dawn of the greatness of Athens ; for Solon, the merchant of high statesmanship, consciously made it his aim to open out the path for commercial development of his native city as a condition of political supremacy. IV Let us first consider the state of the ancient world at the time when Solon carried out his journeys in his young and also in riper years. The downfall of Nineveh in the year 607, when Medians and Babylonians conquered and burned the great Assyrian capital, occurred only thirteen years before Solon's archonship." Let us also bear in mind that about the same time, and possibly in the same year in which Draco's laws were drawn up, the Deuteronomy was proclaimed in Judah. The Western and the Eastern coast of the Aegean were never alien to each other. The measures of capacity which King Pheidon of Argos introduced 2I in the Peloponnesus, and which were also used in Athens until Solon abolished them, were identical with those used by the Hebrews, and had evidently been brought to Greece by the Phoenicians." So it may be more than a mere coincidence that at the same time when the men of the East abolished vicarious punishment by the legislation of the Deuteronomy, the men of the West in a tablet contemporary with Draco's laws and sacred to the gods of Olympia,' declared that they would no longer see the son punished for the father, thus proclaiming the great principle of individual responsibility.'" One year before Nineveh was destroyed, King Josiah of Judah, under whom the Deuteronomy was passed, met his fate in the Battle of Megiddo, vanquished by King Necho II of Egypt, a member of that dynasty to which Egypt owed her revival after the Ethiopian invasion and the Assyrian conquest, this restoration being prepared and furthered by the wise rule and legislation of King Bokchoris of Sais. Solon, when he was in Egypt during the journeys of his younger years, may have witnessed the preparations for the Egyptian war against Judah. 25 The ten years of Solon's later journeys are crowded with notable events, the war waged by King Hophrah of Egypt and by Zedekiah of Judah against Nebuchadnezzar, the conquest of Jerusalem and the Battle of the Halys between King Alyattes of Lydia, the father of Croesus and King Kyaxares of Media. The peace concluded between Lydia and Media, brought about by the mediation of the Kings of Babylonia and Cilicia, helped to some extent to set Alyattes free to renew the attacks upon the Ionian 22 cities which had been begun by Gyges the founder of the Mermnade dynasty. Gyges (about 66o B.c.) had conquered Kolophon and Magnesia on the Maiandros. And though Smyrna and Miletos succeeded in resisting him, still these Lydian enmities could not fail to weaken the power of the Ionians. Though the invasion of northern barbarians, the Kimmerians, prevented the Lydians from renewing their attacks, still the Kimmerians only brought new sufferings to the Ionians, and besides it was practically certain that the Lydian kings after once mastering the Kimmerians would continue to harass the Ionian cities. Solon no doubt, acquainted with the state of affairs by the journeys of his youth, foresaw this and, as we shall see, acted upon this insight. It must have been a singular satisfaction to the Athenian traveller that his forebodings came true, and that the peace with the Medes was followed by the final expulsion of the Kimmerians and the conquest of Smyrna by King Alyattes (575 B.c.). V But Solon's attention was certainly not confined to political events. And among the laws and customs of the Eastern nations the state of monetary affairs, being of great consequence to the merchant, was sure to appeal'to him most strongly. Here we meet the fact that although different systems had sprung up, yet underlying all of them there was one general system, which in some of the countries most prominent in commerce, e.g., Lydia, persisted in its original form. We may call or even the it the Babylonian bimetallistic, oriental trimetallistic system, a proportion being 23 fixed and officially upheld between gold, silver and copper. The Babylonian weight, like all the other measures of Babylonia, was built up according to the sexagesimal principle, sixty forming the basis of the whole numerical notation. The reasons for this preference of the number sixty and the great advantages of this system cannot be considered here. Suffice it to say that it has astronomical, geometrical and arithmetical reasons. 26 And let us remember that every dial of a clock or watch with its subdivision into sixty is a living testimony to the Babylonian influence reaching down into the present time. Now the Babylonian pound was called a mina; sixty minas were a talent, and even with the Greeks this proportion of talent and mina held good. The mina was sub-divided into sixty shekels, and the shekel was the unit for weighing unminted gold. But since commerce, and especially commerce in precious metals, was international, and the sexagesimal principle did not appeal to all the other oriental people alike, a new mina of fifty shekels was formed as the unit for gold, and this gold mina consequently was 5/6 of the mina of weight. The proportion between silver and gold arrived at by the Babylonian priests for economical as well as for astronomical and astrological reasons was 40:3 =13 1/3 :I. It prevailed through the centuries, and when the Lydians had invented the coinage of money it regulated the Lydian and the Persian monetary systems. Now if you have a piece of gold weighing about a sovereign, its equivalent in silver being more than thirteen times heavier is, of course, quite out of the question for a piece of coin. But you 24 may arrange that ten pieces of silver according to this proportion should be equal to one piece of gold. A silver mina consisting of fifty such pieces will then be 4/3 the weight of the gold mina, and consequently, since the gold mina was 5/6 of the mina of weight, the silver mina will be 4/3 of 5/6, i.e., 10/9 of the mina of weight; or in other words the mina of weight, the gold mina and the silver mina were in the proportion of I :5/6 :5/9The two chief systems of coinage in silver, current in Greece when Solon began to travel as a merchant, were developments of the Babylonian silver mina, the Pheidonian mina upon which the Aeginetan coinage was based, 7 being I/10 higher than the Babylonian silver mina, whereas the Euboean mina was I/5 less, this later development being probably due to a temporary change in the valuation of copper. Between silver, again, and copper there was the proportion of I2zo: i, and if I2o silver minas or two silver talents of copper, were equal to one silver mina of silver, then the equivalent of one talent Thus of copper was half a silver mina of silver. the half mina of the silver standard, forming the connection between silver and copper, was even more important as a unit than the full mina of the silver standard. It is this half mina of the silver standard which forms the oldest weight used by the Romans. The proportion between the mina of weight, the mina of gold and this half mina of silver, which was also used for copper, would be I : 5/6 :5/9. If, however, copper gained a higher value, being rated by the proportion 96:I, then the equivalent in silver would have to be lowered by I/5 ; in this manner the Euboean silver mina, being 4/5 of the Babylonian silver mina, originated." 25 We shall see that all these matters and proportions were very well known to Solon, and that he applied them in more than one direction. VI It is, of course, always a problem in which moment of a statesman's career the consciousness of his political purposes was clearly established. For the gift of political insight and the faculty of using the right circumstances in any given moment certainly go very far in the case of a man who is lifted to an important position among his fellowcitizens. But we can certainly date this consciousness in Solon from the very moment when he undertook a measure which, as no other, shows how intimately the merchant and the statesman were blended together in him. When Solon changed the monetary system of Athens, introducing the coinage of Euboea instead of that of Aegina, which had hitherto been in use in Athens, he must have been fully aware, as my teacher Ulrich Koehler2 9 has shown, that this involved a declaration of commercial war against Aegina, the Dorian island in the neighbourhood of Athens, which, in monopolising the commerce in the Western Aegean, made any free competition impossible for Athens. Not that the average Athenian had felt the necessity of such a competition; this insight on the contrary is an essential part of Solon's merits, though on the other hand it would be mis-stating the facts if we considered Athens as a city devoid of commercial aspirations before Solon's times. The foundation of Sigeion, and the fact that 26 Solon himself turned to commerce in his young years, would alone be sufficient to disprove such a view. But what Solon intended, and brought about, was on a far higher scale. It meant breaking the connection with, and the commercial subjection to Aegina and joining Athens commercially to Euboea, thus directing his fellow-citizens to take up the intercourse and follow the path of Euboean, that is to say, chiefly the Chalcidian and Eretrian trade. Thus Thrace and Macedonia, with their riches in wood and metals, and, furthermore, those harbours of the Black Sea where the corn of Scythia, or to speak in modern terms, of Southern Russia, was exported in abundance, were brought within the scope of the commercial activity of the Athenians. The cities of Euboea, and especially Chalcis, also kept up a very lively trade with the West, where in Southern Italy and in Sicily many colonies had been founded by their exertions. But although Solon, far-sighted as he proved himself to be, may have considered this side also of the new departure, still, Corinth having the commercial sway in the West, and Aegina being the intermediary between Corinth and the Ionian East, his first and strongest motive for adopting the Euboean system lay in the possibilities which it opened out in the North and the NorthEast.so Athens was to take her stand in commerce, and through commerce in politics, as the oldest city state of lonia; and to realise the ambition suggested by this claim, she was to take the place which up to that time Miletus and the other Ionian cities had held and which they could no longer maintain 27 owing to the ravages of the Cimmerians and the enmity of the Lydian kings. When some forty years later Ephesus, one of the most powerful cities of Eastern Ionia, was conquered by King Croesus of Lydia, and the inhabitants were forced to leave their homes in the mountains near the mouth of the Caystrus and to settle in the plain near the old temple of Artemis, an Athenian (named Aristarchus) was called from Athens to guide and superintend the new institutions. This may be considered as an acknowledgment of the fact that Eastern Ionia had been overshadowed by Athens. And since it was a struggle between Western and Eastern Ionia, the element of race involved in this monetary change from Dorian Aegina to Euboea certainly was of no little weight with Solon, for thus he rallied the forces of Western Ionia against their kinsmen in the East. There are many more sides to this numismatic and metrologic change, but there, is one especially which again shows how deeply Solon's mind was imbued with the experience of the market both abroad and at home. The weight used for the standard of the coin was also naturally to be the normal weight throughout. Now the Euboean unit-we should say the pound--was, as we have seen, smaller than that of Aegina, which had been hitherto used in Athens. But the fact that both the unit of coin and of weight were lessened might trouble the thoughts of the average Athenian, though in truth the reciprocity of the decrease might have excluded such fears. Still Solon foresaw and knew how to meet them. In Babylonia and throughout Western Asia a curious custom prevailed. Kings and temples had 28 a claim to a weight higher than the regular one in the payment of all supplies, payments and revenues Besides the common weight there existed, then, an increased weight, surpassing the common standard by 1/36, 1/24 or I/20. Of these three increased forms two were based upon the duodecimal, or rather the sexagesimal system, whereas the last and highest one was adapted to the decimal system. "' Thus throughout antiquity we find in all the different systems of weight as well as of coinage the combination of or the option between a common and an increased form of the standard. When I discovered this fact and worked out its far-reaching consequences, I was not aware that the same curious dualism existed in the Middle Ages: for instance, in France under Philip le Beau, besides the Marc du Paris, there was the Marc du Roy, surpassing it by 1/48, and in England under Henry VII and VIII the pound of the Tower and the pound Troy, which was I/I5 higher. " And the existence of the sovereign and the guinea in our own days, though not having originated in this way, certainly points to a similar line of development." Now this custom could not of course have escaped Solon's observation during his commercial travels, and he made rather surprising use of it. Changing the old oriental privilege of kings and priests into a popular measure, he enacted that for the use of the market, not the common Euboean weight should be used, but one surpassing it by I/20, thus introducing a royal form of this weight, but as a help for the Athenian household; for on behalf of the reciprocity between the unit of coin and the unit of measure, the Athenian purchaser received a greater quantity of goods for his coin. The price 29 of a pound of salt would, for instance, be constant, and an increase of the weight would be a net profit to the purchaser; or to speak in modern terms, by paying a sovereign or any part of it, the purchaser would obtain a guinea's worth of goods or an equivalent proportion. But more than this: the English pound, avoirdu-pois, by which all of us reckon in everyday life, is nothing but Solon's mina of a raised standard, preserved like many other ancient standards down through the centuries to our days." VII Any statesman and legislator who profits by the economic and financial conditions of a neighbouring country, is sure not to limit himself to coins and weights and measures, and consequently we are by no means surprised to find that Solon's legislation was influenced especially by that of King Bokchoris of Egypt. Not only are his most famous economic measure, the Seisachteia, and the very noteworthy law punishing idleness and lack of profession referred to this oriental source, but, what is more, the whole legislation concerning commercial intercourse, regulating the Law of Contracts, is reported to have been suggested by this Egyptian Code of Law. 5 And if, as has recently been justly remarked, 6 Athens in the fifth century was able, owing to the excellence of the Solonian Laws, to establish a network of commercial treaties between herself and each individual member of her league, this most effective element of coalescence for the development of her empire was due to the knowledge of foreign commercial laws which Solon the merchant had acquired in his journeys. 30 As to the law forbidding idleness it has several other features calling for our attention. It is one of the not very numerous laws which, apart from those concerning capital punishment, Solon took from the legislation of Dracon, abating the fine prescribed by his predecessor. We see, then, that Solon was not the first to consider oriental examples with a view to Athenian legislation, and most probably this older influx of Eastern legal ideas is not restricted to Athens but may and will also have worked upon the older Greek bodies of laws, the Cretan laws, those of Zaleukos of Lokroi and of Charondas of Catana. Now this law evidently bears witness to the fact that Solon encouraged crafts and arts, and it is very interesting to see that this was not an entirely new departure but that Draco had preceded him. The general result of modern investigation, that Solon's legislation is not merely a reversal of Draco's law,87 but partly a development of germs which it contained, is thus confirmed. And this very law enables us to illustrate this relation between Dracon and Solon and the advance of the latter beyond his predecessor. For Solon added the law, freeing a son, whose father had not caused him to learn a craft or trade, from the duty of providing for his parents in old age. And he added another far-reaching law, encouraging immigration and the naturalising of foreigners. Whereas, formerly citizenship could scarcely ever be acquired by a non-Athenian, he only forbade the bestowal of citizenship on any but such as had been exiled from their own country for ever, or had settled with their whole household in Athens for the sake of exercising some manual trade." Solon and the statesmen who followed him 31 succeeded beyond all expectation in this line of action. They attracted to Athens, 'a constant stream of immigrants, and set newcomers and old residents at work together in developing and diffusing the national resources.'" 9 Among Solon's laws which, curiously enough, have, to my knowledge at least, not been fully collected and scientifically treated in recent times, there are several other ordinances showing his intimate knowledge of economic and commercial life. There is, e.g., the law forbidding the engraver of a seal to keep an impression for himself which might have been used for purposes of forgery. Of greater consequence is the law enforcing the protection of the olive trees and their growth, and forbidding their exportation ; for combining it with another law forbidding the exportation of any other agricultural product, we learn from it, that Solon tried-and this successfully--to reconcile agriculture and commerce, encouraging the growth and the exportation of the one product which Attica could be made to yield in abundance. The range of these laws, then, goes far beyond the mere interest of commerce and economics; they concern the public welfare, which indeed is the ruling point of view throughout Solon's legislation. And we shall be able to appreciate the value of this statement, when we turn to the oldest body of laws preserved to us, the code of Hammurabi, King of Babylonia, circ. 2000 B.c. at the latest, in which the needs of agriculture and commerce are altogether the principal factor.' 0 Specially characteristic of this point of view is Solon's law inflicting severe punishment on any member of the community who in case of political unrest does not join one of the parties ; a principle 32 to which he himself held true, in his old age, when Peisistratus had attained to tyranny in Athens. Solon, being too old to take arms himself, signified his opposition by putting his arms, shield and spear before the door of his house. Almost as remarkable is the ordinance which while prohibiting that the honour of the public meal in the Prytaneum should be conferred too often, at the same time punishes a man who is offered this honour and refuses it. The same point of view holds good in the protection of youth, especially against immorality in schools and gymnasia. To keep the highest office, that of the Archons, free from doubtful elements, Solon prescribed that immorality in a citizen would cause him to forfeit his right to this office, and an Archon who was found in a state of inebriation was severely punished. Those who fell in warfare were to be publicly interred and their families cared for. And when we think of Pericles' funeral.speech as the grandest testimony to the greatness and the immortal soul4 1 of Athens, let us bear in mind that it was Solon who made it possible, not merely by the law we have mentioned, but also because it was he who by a law, evidently passed with special reference to the Alcmeonids,' 2 enabled them to return to Athens. The Alcmeonids, it is true, were banished again, but it is Solon who definitely freed them from the guilt of blood they had contracted and thus restored to them the possibility of partaking in the life of their native city state. And again, let us not forget that it was a fatal moment in the history of Athens when Pericles, in order to please those Athenians who grudged to foreigners the benefits which in course of time had accrued to the citizenship, brought 33 forward a law cutting off the influx of immigrants, thus departing from the principle laid down by Solon as a corner-stone of his policy. This law was only abolished when, in the course of the Peloponnesian War, it was too late to give an effective increase of strength to Athens by the infusion of new blood. VIII Solon was called to be Archon and conciliator after he had composed the elegy (already quoted above) in which he expresses his grief at the decline of the oldest land of Ionia. ' Sorrow fills my heart, seeing the oldest country of Ionia on the way to her ruin,' 4 ---these are the opening lines of this important poem, of which only a few other verses seem to be preserved. But another poem, dating from about the same time, has been preserved to us glowing with love for his native city and at the same time imbued with wrath against the wealthy leaders of the people whose immoderate aspirations tended to ruin the state. It beginsNay but by Zeus his decree, by the will of the Gods everlasting Nought can shatter our state, destined for aye to endure. We have a great-souled Warden, our high-fathered PallasAthene. Stretching her hands to protect us and the city from harm. Nathless the men of the State themselves would ruin its greatness, Madmen, who strive to destroy, lured by the glitter of gain. Wicked in heart are the chiefs; for the sin of their pride overweening Vengeance follows them fast, woe upon woe in its train. Fools ! For the pleasure they have they take not in quiet and order, Over-indulge in their feasts, check not their arrogant deeds. (H.-C. 2.) 34 Although Solon was himself convinced that the troubles in the state were due chiefly, if not solely, to the rich, still he would not have been the wise and deep-sighted politician, the p o as Aristotle characterises him,4 4 had he thought that by merely reproaching the privileged class he could further the welfare of his beloved Athens. On the contrary he had to fight for each of the parties against the other, as he did, according to Aristotle, in the elegiac poem, which immediately preceded his election; this is his boast in several of the poems in which he afterwards defends his work. 'I stood holding a mighty shield over both, and did not allow either of them to conquer unjustly' as he declares in one of his elegiac poems. -;roXtgrr (H.-C. 3.) There were, then, also claims of the poorer classes which Solon could not or did not care to fulfil. The liberation of all those who had been suffering from bodily servitude was the chief of the measures which Solon took towards the mitigation of the social difficulties, and it is this measure which he himself considers as the greatest of the benefits conferred by him on the poor. At the same time he ordained that all outstanding debts should be cancelled. This measure called the Seisachtheia, the shaking off of the burden-in itself an imitation of a step taken by King Bocchoris of Egypt-was evidently necessary both to prevent the immediate return of the occasion for bodily servitude, which he had abolished for ever, and to help the smaller land owners to free their property from mortgages. But he disappointed the expectations of the unenfranchised, in declining to make a new division of the land, a measure which would have stripped the gentry of part of their inherited property. 35 And if Solon is rightly proud of the abolition of bodily servitude for debt, and of the Seisachtheia, he also is deeply convinced of his merits in refusing to touch the inherited rights of the landowners. The reproaches of those who considered themselves wronged by this restraint were answered by Solon in the beautiful iambic poem already mentioned. But I who bound the people into one, Did I then cease from striving for the ends For which I bound them, ere the ends were gained Aye, but for this a witness might be called Before the court and judgment-seat of TimeThe mighty mother of th' Olympian gods, Black Earth herself, from whose deep bosom I Plucked out the stakes that pinned her everywhere, Who was a slave aforetime, but is free. And to their Athens, to their fatherland, The God-created, many brought I home Who had been slaves, a human merchandise, Some by the narrow letter of the law, And some without a law to warrant it. Those, too, who went as fugitives for debt, Forgetful of their Attic mother-tongue, Since they had wandered much and far afield; And those, who, suffering bondage here at home, Quaked at their masters' every change of moodAll these I freed; and this by strength I wrought, Blending together might and right in one, And as I promised so did I perform. Laws too I made for good and bad alike, Ordaining justice strict for every man. But had some other grasped, as I, the goad, Some evil-counselled avaricious man, How had he held the people ? Had I willed The things that pleased my adversaries then, Or had I wished what their opponents planned, Our State had been bereft of many men. And, therefore, seeking help from every side, I turned and twisted like a wolf at bay, Encompassed by a multitude of hounds. (H. -C. 32.) 36 ? IX The Seisachtheia as well as the liberation of Solon's fellow-citizens was, of course, a single political measure. But the recurrence of the same difficulties, and the future servitude of poor Athenian citizens could only be avoided by incorporating this prohibition in the body of Solon's laws, and so we see that ordinances which Aristotle considers as a characteristic part of Solon's democratic institution have been parts of his legislation, so that the distinction between laws and polity which Aristotle theoretically holds in his Politicsdoes not hold good for Solon's code of law. In fact the most important of Solon's laws must have been those regulating the constitution; and " Wilamowitz, 4 is evidently right in assuming that just this part of Solon's legislation was singled out to be written down on columns of stone called ,cuppeC, which were set up in the oTOd /aoiXeso9, whereas the whole of Solon's laws were originally written down for publication on the caoves, wooden boards painted white and put together so as to revolve round a central pivot. Certainly the offices and their functions, the institution of the assembly of the people, the EKccxn&a, the rights and duties of the council, who had to prepare the business of the ekklesia, and those of the old council Hill of Ares, the 'Areopagus,' had to be regulated in ordinances to which those concerned in them could refer--and where else should this be done except in Solon's laws ?46 The matter ought not be open to discussion at all, for we know that the Solonian law regulating the 37 treasurers of the goddess continued in use down to the time of Aristotle. 47 The law is, in itself, interesting in more than one respect. It ordains that these officials are to be elected by lot, showing that this manner of election was an element in Solon's constitution, as indeed it had, to a certain degree, been in use even before. The treasurers of the goddess are to be sifted out by lot from the most wealthy class of the citizens, evidently with the intention that there should be a sufficient guarantee in their own personal wealth against mismanagement of the public funds. But which was this wealthiest class of citizens, and what meaning had the classes in Solon's constitution ? The population of Athens had formerly been divided into the following three classes:knights (i7rre),who fought on horseback ; citizens who could provide their own armament (vy~ra)' 48; and, thirdly, To this original distribution the labourers (O6Tes). a new departure had been added for the sake of financial classification: the most wealthy of the knights were assigned to a separate class, who, according to the minimum of their income, the were called the 'five-hundred-bushellers,' Ilevrafcoo-top &vootY-this name in itself showing the whole class to be of later origin than the three other ones with their natural and merely descriptive names. These classes evidently existed before Solon, and were used for the purpose of a political division of the citizens-though in which way exactly would not be easy to tell : the question of Draco's constitution lies out of the range of our discussion to-day. Solon certainly used these four classes in the first place for the distribution of political rights, and for 38 this purpose he had (in his laws) to determine and to limit them anew. Wealth or a higher income no longer rested with the nobility, consisting merely of landed proprietors who consumed their own grain. The olive-growers who were to be oil-traders at the same time had to be considered; and chiefly, if not for their sake it was arranged that the metretes, the measure for liquids, was considered equal to the bushel in reckoning the income for the purpose of dividing the classes. Furthermore, wealth no longer being a privilege of the nobility, those merchants who did not deal with agricultural products, and the craftsmen, had to be taken into consideration, so both the units of capacity were equalled to one drachma. To the first class there belonged those citizens who had at least an income of 500 measures in corn or liquid productions, or of 500 drachmai. The Knights had to have a minimum income of 300. The Zeugitai 150, at least, according to Solon. The lower limit of this third class was, however, raised to 200 in later times--a fact which has given rise to serious misunderstandings. 4 9 All those whose income did not reach the limit of I5o belonged to the fourth class, the labourers. The admission to the offices was graduated according to the classes, the lower ones only being open to the Zeugites also. As this extension of public rights was democratic in itself, Solon had to be careful that at least the standard of the classes should be kept up in the former sense. Now the lowering of the monetary standard would in itself, and by the principles of metrology, have brought with it a decrease of the units of capacity, which would have meant a considerable 39 lowering of the classes from their former standard, and would have added greatly to the democratic effect of Solon's reform. But even here Solon's wise moderation found the right solution by arriving at an increase of the measures of capacity, without changing the base of his metrological system. A metretes would formerly have been equal to the cube of the older Pheidonian foot, making it about thirty-six litres in capacity; the Solonian foot being smaller, the metretes would have measured only twenty-six litres, instead of which Solon made it to be one and a half cube of his foot, the result being that the metretes was about three litres more than the older one and is in the same way the measure for dry material; the medimnos having formerly been 5/4 of the metretes was made to be 4/3 of the new one, the result being an increase of the metretes by ° seven litres. 0 Those citizens, whose income did not reach I50 measures ordrachmai,--the thetes -onlyparticipated in the assembly of the people, the ekklesia, by which also the magistrates were elected, and in the courts of justice formed out of the members of the ecclesia. These courts-juries with a very great number of members--served as courts of appeal for every matter which did not come under their jurisdiction in the first instance. Thus every matter, and especially every decision of a magistrate, which came to be questioned, was subject to these popular courts of justice, and in this institution, one of the three measures which Aristotle calls the most democratic, the thetes participated. X The most important of all the Athenian offices was that of Archon Eponymus, and Aristotle 40 distinctly and rightly points out that all the troubles and factions had their chief origin in the struggle 5 about this office." Now since Solon was elected, as mediator, to eliminate the causes of the troubles, we might be sure that he would have sought for a means of moving this office out of the range of such civic struggles, even if there were no testimony to this effect. But such there is. And it is rather curious, merely from these general reasons, that this most important part of Solon's constitutional legislation should have been questioned by a number of distinguished scholars." The law, as Aristotle gives it, prescribes that forty citizens (ten from each of the four phylae) were elected by vote, and that out of these forty, the nine Archons, i.e., the Archon Eponymus and his eight colleagues, were appointed by lot. This of course meant that the office of the Archon had no longer the significance connected with it before, and that the real leader of the people was to be looked for in the officeless, but all the more important Sluaywryoys, or leader of the people. It also meant that the Archon Polemarchus could no longer be the commander-in-chief of the Athenian army for the particular year. He now could only be a minister of war, or even less than that, merely an official dealing with the preparations and materials of war, but not with strategy and tactics, which were to be left to the Strategoi; and as to this particular point, Solon may have had good reasons for this change, as he himself had been the leader in the struggle for Salamis, and had possibly to do away with the opposition of the Archon Eponymus then in charge. The only thing which Aristotle is not able to tell us, because he did not find it in his sources, was whether the Archons were 41 to be elected only out of the members of the first or out of those of the first two classes, and having stated before that the offices were open to the three upper classes, according to gradation, only the lowest offices being available for all of them, he now goes on to show that there was such a gradation by quoting the law concerning the treasurers of the goddess. This has led to the misunderstanding that the law concerning the election of the Archons was arrived at by Aristotle only as the result of an inference from the later state of things, and this error has been increased by the idea, just refuted, that Solon's laws were not concerned with the constitution. It is quite impossible that such a conclusion should here be in question. For Aristotle himself relates that after Solon the struggle for the Archonship began anew, and we know from Thucydides and Aristotle that the Archon was elected by vote, under the tyranny of the Peisistratids, and that the constitution of Cleisthenes only knew an Archon elected by votes. It was only in the year 487 that a mixture of vote and lot came into use for the office of Archon.53 The only possible conclusion which might have been drawn, if there had been no knowledge of the Solonian Law, would then have been that also under Solon the Archons were elected by vote. No, Solon's law concerning the election of the Archons is an undoubted reality, and knowing this, we discover another most important fact in the constitutional history of Athens. The change from the Archon elected by vote, to Solon's mixed procedure, was only effected by Themistocles in 482 B.c. It was a preliminary to the passing of his law concerning the creation of 42 an Athenian navy, the navy that won the Battle of Salamis; and Themistocles, the greatest Athenian politician, appears as the continuer of the policy of Solon, both in the way of democracy and in recognising that the greatness of Athens lay in her naval development. Thus a line of thought and of noble strife for Athens' might and glory connects the winner of the Island and the winner of the Battle of Salamis. XI Now bearing in mind that we are to see in Solon the far-sighted merchant, well acquainted with all the principles and details bearing upon the financial policy and the commercial usages of the East, we are in a position to show that Solon was in truth the first to introduce graduated taxation.-a theory which was formerly held but has been denied in modern times. As August Boeckh 54 has seen, when in the case of an emergency, an extraordinary income-tax had to be levied, this eisphora, as it was called, was taken by a percentage from the whole of the minimum income of the first class, whereas the Hippeis and the Zeugitai were only taxed according to a part of the minimum income of their respective classes, 1/6 of the income of the Hippeis and 4/9 of that of the Zeugites being left out of consideration. This is the same principle of income-tax abatement with which we are familiar in this country. Is it too fanciful to suggest that this slight amelioration of the lot of the over-burdened taxpayer may be traced back also to the suggestion of Solon, 5 as Grote" --though not in every respect quite rightly--understood it ? 43 One of the chief reasons alleged against B oeckh's most ingenious and persuasive explanation of the fragmentary indications left to us by the ancient writers falls to the ground as soon as we know that the lower limit of the third class was changed in 5 post-Solonian times." Of the other objections generally raised, the chief are that we do not know of any eisphora before that of the year 428 B.c., during the Peloponnesian War, and that the scale I : 5/6 : 5/9 would be too unnatural to have occurred and appealed to Solon. But it certainly does not appear so to us, who have seen that just the same progression held a significant place in the monetary system of Babylonia and Western Asia, with which system Solon by his journey and by his vocation as a merchant was acquainted. Experience teaches us that whenever numerical gradations have to be introduced, proportions well established by former usage are resorted to; though often unconsciously. We use the decimal system without always realising that it was suggested by the formation of our hands, and the duodecimal system without thinking of the twelve revolutions of the moon during the solar year, which are really responsible for it. Indeed, Aristotle himself, in the 'AOnvatov 'roXL-ia, explains the earliest constitution of Athens in the following way :-The state is divided into four Each cvXa, corresponding to the four seasons. of them is divided into parts, the trittyes, so that there are altogether twelve parts, as many as there are months in the year, and these thirds and twelfths are called cpapTpa. Each phratria was divided into thirty families, corresponding to the days of the month. Aristotle is right as to the facts, but is probably wrong in thinking that the division was 44 brought about in conscious reference to astronomical facts. But as this custom of leaning towards well-known proportions is to be acknowledged, no one can be surprised that Solon chose a proportion for his taxation which, well known as it was to every one versed in Eastern finance, proved to be useful for his purposes. Furthermore, to judge the intentions of any legislator, and especially one so far-sighted as Solon, from the question whether a law of his has come into force or not is, of course, to take quite a wrong view. One might even say that the more possibilities a legislator conceived and the fewer of them came into force, the wiser and the more far-sighted was the legislator. So to contend that Solon could not have had an extraordinary taxation in view because the necessity for such a measure never appeared-at any rate to our knowledge--until about 170 years later, is of course quite out of the question." On the contrary, the fact that such a taxation was necessary in a time of emergency, might persuade us that Solon, seeing that Athens would have to struggle for her greatness, could not but take such a case into serious consideration. Thus, historical and metrological research in recent times enables us to see that Solon's progressive taxation is a reality, in spite of all that has been set forth against it. XII One of the greatest merits of Solon, namely, that he resisted the temptation of establishing a tyranny over Athens, would be cancelled if there had been 'scarcely a possibility for the development of a tyranny, agriculture, industry and trade holding an equal balance,' as has recently been urged in 45 connection with the theory which sees the origin of the tyranny in capitalism.68 This would mean to underrate the merchant in Solon and the commercial possibilities existing in Athens about 6oo00 B.c. But besides we have an irresistible documentary proof in a poem composed by Solon after his Archonship, in which he defends himself against the reproaches of his friend Phokos for having neglected the opportunity of usurping the tyranny in Athens; a poem, parts of which were known before, whilst a very important fragment has been added by the papyrus of the Athenai6n Politeia. Shallow-counselled was your Solon, small the wisdom that he used When he scorned the noble offers and the gifts of God refused. When the prey was in the meshes, which himself had fairly set, Weak of will and reft of judgment he forgot to close the net. Had I grasped at power and gained it, taken riches for my own, Been a despot over Athens e'en for one short day alone, Quite content, aye very gladly, I had yielded-can you doubt ?All my body to the flayer, while my race was blotted out. (H.-C. 29.) If I spared my native country, keeping still a steady course Far removed from tyrant power and the ruthless rule of force, My renown must shine the brighter, free from stain and free from shame, And above the sons of mortals stand the honour of my name. (H.-C. 28.) Those who came agape for plunder in the hope that they might find Gain of gold and great possessions, each according to his mind; Those who thought to find me hiding all my roughness of intent In a mist of glozing language, all in vain their hopes they spent. Now their eyes are hot against me and their favour is forbid'Tis not right, for what I promised with the help of God I did. Other deeds too, I accomplished, not with tyrant's might and main, Yea I wrought them to a finish and I wrought them not in vain. For I hold that in our country--and on this I take my standRogues and heroes are not equal when they come to share the land. (H.-C. 31.) 46 So there was a possibility of Solon becoming a despot of Athens, and indeed his friends expected him to do so, and although these friends did not understand him rightly, and possibly were of the same set which had laid a snare for him when he abolished the debts,5 9 still to deny the possibility of a tyranny would, then, be to deny the philological genuineness of a most undoubtedly genuine literary production which in its very content, nay, in its very wording, bears the stamp of Solon's mind and Solon's poetry, quite apart from the authorities through which this poem has been handed down to us. Here at once we have a most striking example of the near relations between philology and history. From the finding and deciphering of the papyrus and its recognition as a well-known but hitherto lost work of Aristotle, down to the estimation of this Solonian poem as a test for the theory bearing upon an important feature of ancient political history, where is the boundary line between philology and history ? But the frame of our investigation has had to be stretched much beyond this intimate connection between Greek history and Greek philology. A much-neglected auxiliary science of history, metrology, the knowledge of weights and measures and of the monetary systems based upon these weights, has proved indispensable for the philological as well as the historical understanding of very vital points in the information which the ancient writers have handed down to us concerning Solon. Coins and weights and measures are implements of commerce, which, like commerce itself, are inter- 47 national, and were even more so in ancient times. Comparative metrology, then, helps us to scrutinise the history of ancient commerce. And how much ancient Greek life really depended on commerce has lately been shown, and is being more and more recognised in our days. It will, I hope, also have appeared in what I have been allowed to lay before you to-day. Commerce, however, prepares the ground for the influx of thought; and the Greeks have never withheld themselves from foreign influences. In fact, the greatness and peculiarity of Greek culture does not consist in its independence of foreign thought, but in the way in which the Greeks assimilated what they had received, so that it became a part of their own being, and reproduced it in a shape bearing the stamp of their genius. 6 o We must also bear in mind that the Ionians, who were the pioneers in the development of Greek commercial and social life and of the Greek philosophy which enlightened the world and continues to enlighten it to this very day, were, to a great part, politically members of great oriental empires--first the Lydian, then the Persian-which depended for their civilisation to a very high degree upon the achievements of Babylonia. Greek philology and Greek history cannot be separated from ancient oriental history, and if we feel ourselves indebted to Greece for the highest attainments of our own culture, we must never forget that much of what Greece has shaped and given us has its roots and sources in Ancient Egypt and Ancient Babylonia. If the study of Greek is conducted in all our Universities, and especially in this great commercial centre of Liverpool, in the large-minded spirit 48 suggested by all these associations, and also with the depth and thoroughness which every serious study demands, then we may feel justified in claiming for our Greek studies and for the University of whose work they are an intrinsic part, the protection of the great-souled warden, our high-fathered Pallas Athene :Toil yp peydOvpo Eriaorroo o/ptpo7rprl ex". HaXac 'AOrval Xeipac vrepOev 49 NOTES i. Fragments of Archilochus, Alcaeus, Sappho, Corinna, Pindar might be added as well as other fragments of the older Greek dramatists. For selections of the former see E. Diehl, Supplementum Lyricum (1908). 2. E. Kornemann, Klio, II, 1902, p. 141 if, III (1903), p. 74 if, IV (1904), 88 if, V (1905), 317. 3. Especially Caesar's writings, but compare also the lost autobiographies of Tiberius, Claudius and other Roman Emperors and statesmen. See G. Misch, Geschichte der Autobiographie, I, Leipzig, 1907. 4. Aristotle, Ath. Pol., 5. 5. Ath. Pol., 3, 5. Note also that Draco was himself one of the Thesmothetai. 6. Op. cit., p. 128 if. 7. A1th. Pol., 9, r. I here followed the translation given by Zimmern. 8. Ath. Pol., 4, 4. Cf. Alfred Zimmern, The Greek Commonwealth (I911), 131 if. 9. P. Ure, 'The Origin of the Tyranny,' 7ournal of Hellenic Studies (J. H. S.), XXVI (1906), 131 if. io. Alfred Zimmern, Op. cit., p. 36 f. II. H.-C., 12. 12. Cf. U. v. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Athen (1893), II, 314- Aristoteles und 13. To assume that Sigeion was not founded before the time of Peisistratus (so Beloch, Busolt and recently Ure, 7. H. S., XXVI, 135, n. 44) would be a mistake. Alcaeus and Pittacus, who certainly flourished about and before 6oo, fought against the Athenians in the Troad, and even the well-known Sigeian inscription written in Ionic and in Attic is certainly not much, if at all, younger than 600 u.c. Cf. also Ed. Meyer, Geschichte d. Altertums,. II, p. 636, 644 f. 14. On the &c7'rp.op(t)ot, see Ath. Pol., 2, 2. Plutarch, Solon, and Herychios, s. v. According to Aristotle, rav Tv r>pyc woroWy OwoOV (scil. 7'PV &,c'u) /plcr 7r-v rov e~ra ca'rc 7rXovooW aypov. According to Plutarch, EyecOpyovv eceivoe 7iov yevo0peyOV TeXOvreV. F. E. Adcock, Klio, XII 50 (1912), 2, n. 1, remarks, that Aristotle seems to him to 'say the same as Plutarch' (?),' whether he is right is another matter.' 15. Of Draco's constitution I have treated on p. 165 if, of my Griechische Geschichte his zur Schlacht bei Chaironeia in Einleitung in die Altertumswissenschaft, herausgegeben von A. Gercke und C. Norden, vol. III, p. 2, Izo. 16. Solon, of course, in his elegiac poems used the epic language to a great extent, and in his iambic poetry he could not but imitate to a certain degree the example set by his Ionian predecessors, but on the other hand it seems certain that Solon consciously introduced Attic forms into his poetry. His original language contains Ionisms, to be sure, and these caused ancient copyists and modern editors to transform Attic forms into the corresponding Ionic forms throughout. But the discovery of the papyrus of the Athenaion Politeia has shown that Solon used i~ purum, where the Ionians have q. So in the Iambic poem quoted on p. 36, the papyrus has plav which is changed into /31 v, H.-C. 32, 16. Cf. Thumb, Handbuch der Griechischen Dialekte and v. Christ-Schmid, Geschichte der griechischen Literatur, 1912, S. 25 f. 17. See my Griechische Geschichte, p. 72. 18. Cf. A. Zimmern, p. 176 and 22o f. 19. That most probably the Atthis of Androtion is the common source of the Solonian chapters of the Athenaion Politeia and of Plutarch's Life of Solon (in which Androtion is quoted among others), has been shown with great probability by F. E. Adcock, Klio, XII, I ff. Hermippus, then, who is generally acknowledged as being the immediate authority both for Plutarch and for Diogenes Laertius and their lives of Solon, must have had Androtion for one of his chief sources. 20. Plutarch, Solon, 2. About Solon's youthful travels, which are often overlooked, see my remarks, Klio, II, 334. 21. Plutarch, Solon, 26, cis ica "poTrepov auords b o~ " NelXov r spoxoow KavcPto9 yyvOev aclttr, See H. Prinz, Funde aus Naukratis, Klio, Beiheft VII, p. 4. 22. The destruction of Nineveh must have made a great impression upon the Greeks. It is, in fact, almost the only event of the history of Assyria that is really known to Herodotus. Nearly all his other information concerning Assyria and the Assyrians refer in truth to Babylonia and the Babylonians, this being due, as I have pointed out (Cf. Wochenschrift fur Klassische 51 Philologie, 1900, 962 f, n. 6; Klio, I [1900], 270 ff; VII [1907], 447, n. 5), to the fact that under Darius, Assyria and Babylonia formed one satrapy which was generally called Assyria but had Babylon for its capital. Thus the Logographoi and Herodotus, where he followed them, seem justified in speaking of the Assyrians as Babylonians. 23. This is shown by Epiphanius, De mensuris et ponderibus, (Metrologici Scriptores, ed Hultsch, I, 259 f), as I shall shortly prove. 24. A. Zimmern, Op. cit., p. 101 f. 25. But it is more probable that the foreign countries were at peace at the time when Solon visited them. Some data for the chronology of Solon's journeys might even be gained through this consideration. 26. For the origin of the Babylonian sexagesimal system see my papers: Uber das babylonische metrische System und dessen erbreitung, lerhandlungen der physikalischen Gesellschaft zu Uber die Beziehungen Berlin, Jahrgang 8, (1889), No. 15. zwischen- Zeit und Raummessung im babylonischen Sexagesimalsystem, Klio, I (1901), 381 if. Zur Entstehung des Sexagesimalsystems und des sexagesimalen babylonischen Liingenmaasses, Klio, I, 481 ff. Compare also the papers quoted in notes 28 and 31. We are justified by Herodotus' statement, III, 89 if. and by a number of other considerations in referring the fixed proportion between silver and gold to the Babylonians. As to the proportion between silver and copper, it probably That is originated with the Egyptians, (see Note 28). why I speak of the B a b y 1 o n i a n bimetallistic, but of the orienta 1 trimetallistic system, although the proportion of 120 : I is an outcome of the Babylonian sexagesimal system. For bimetallistic the origin and existence of the 'Babylonian' system, as first developed by Mommsen and Brandis, see my remarks and papers : Verhandlungen der Berliner anthropologischen Gesellschaft, 1895, 434; 1896, 447 ff. Die Sonderformen des (in collaboration with ' babylonischen ' Gewichts-systems K. Regling), Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenliindischen Gesellschaft, 63 (1909), 701 ff. Zum Wertverhiltnis von Gold und Silber, Klio, X (1910), 476 ff. Herodot's Berechnung der 2, persischen Tribute unter Darius, Klio, XII (1912), Heft z pp. 240-248. 27. See below, n. 31. z8. For the relation of silver and copper, and the origin of 52 the Euboean system, see p. 2o8 [44 ff.] of my treatise : Das altbabylonische Maass- and Gewichtsystem als Grundlage der antiken Gewichts-Mgnz-und Maassysteme (Actes du 8° Congras International des Orientalistes, Section Semitique (b), (1893), and p. 124 ff. of my paper: Zur metrologischen Systematik, Berliner Zeitschrift fur Numismatik, XXVII (1909), I ff. referring to E. F. Haeberlin, Die metrologischen Grundlagen der iltesten mittelitalischen Miinzsysteme, ibid. p. I ff. Of the two systems of the Babylonian weight, the heavy and the light one (the latter being just half of the former in all its units), I have only considered the light one in the text (although the heavy system is the original one). Note, however, that, just as the light half ' silver mina' is the equivalent of a light 'silver talent ' of copper, so the light 'silver mina' is the equivalent of a heavy 'silver talent' of copper. This is important for the origin of the Euboean mina, as mentioned in the text. 117 29. Mitteilungen des deutschen archaeologischen Instituts zu Athen, X, 151 ff. The identity of the Euboean and the Athenian standard, recently doubted by P. Gardner, The earliest coins of Greece proper (from the Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. V), p. 32 (cf. also p. I6 f.), is proved by the conditions of the treaty between the Romans and Antiochus III of Syria; cf. Hultsch, Griechische und ri'mische Metrologie' p. 2o 4 . The Solonian coinage is probably represented among the so-called Wappenminzen of the Euboean standard (so also Gardner l.c. p. 27). But even if Athens had begun to strike her own coins according to the Euboean standard considerably later, and had only used Euboean coins to begin with, our notion of Solon's reform would still hold good. 30. Note that the commercial competition and antagonism between Athens and Corinth was one of the chief reasons of the Peloponnesian War. 31. Uber altbabylonisches Maass und Gewicht und deren Wanderung, Verhandlungen der Berliner anthropologischen Gesellschaft, 1889, p. 245-328, furthermore, the treatises quoted in n. 28, and Gewichte aus Thera (in collaboration with F. Hiller von Gaertringen), Hermes, 36 (1900), II3 if, see especially the schedule before p. IIz. In these the discovery of the common norm of the Babylonian weight, which is at the bottom of all the most important weights of antiquity, has been evolved. The co-existence of the common and the 'Royal' weight has been acknowledged by F. Hultsch, Die Gewichte der Altertums (1897), E. F. Haeberlin (see n. 28), G. F. Hill and B. V. Head (see Historia 53 Nummorum, New Edition [I91], p. XXIV if). The Pheidonian weight, as used in Athens before Solon (see Zur 'AO vaiov 7roktTea, Hermes,XXVII [1892], 530 ff, especially pp. 538 ff. and P. 551 f.), belongs to the system of the common norm, and to this Androtion refers (Plutarch, Solon, 15), but the coins of Aegina generally show one of the royal forms of the same weight, and Aristotle, in Ath. Pol., X, has possibly in mind the relation between the Attic and Aeginetan standard, as usual in his days, Ioo drachmai of 4,366...(4,32 g., see Hermes, XXVII, p. 535) go Both being equal to 70 drachmai of 6,238 (6,17) g. Androtion's and Aristotle's views must be enucleated from amongst statements that are partly erroneous. 32. K. Regling, Zeitschrift der deutschen morgenlindischen Gesellschaft, LXIII (1909), 703. 33. ' The guinea, so called from the Guinea gold, out of which it was first struck, was proclaimed in 1663, and to go for twenty shillings; but it never went for less than twenty-one shillings.' (Pinkerton). 34. On the royal form of the Solonian or Euboean weight (increase by 1/20), as stated by Aristotle, Ath. Pol., Io : d'rolo-e 6 scat oraOc rps Too vt/pol.Ja, T[p]er /ad ;cov ra ,vavr, velcOflo-av [a T]pe? layovo-'a ical dtreE TO TXavTo, 3 ra8ol , see T rowe dXXot~ov vaL T o raTr)pe Ica' C. F. Lehmann-Haupt, Uber eine erhohte Form des solonischen Gewichts, Verb. Berl. anthropol. Gesellsch., 1892, p. 582, Hermes, XXXV (1906), 636 if. G. F. Hill, Numismatic Chronicle, XVII (1897), p. 297. The pound avoir-du-poids equal to a ' royal' form of the Euboean-Attic weight: see the schedule in Hermes, XXXVI (note 31 above) sub II (increase by 1/24). 35. For Solon's laws see the abstract in my Griechische Geschichte, p. 21 f. 36. A. Zimmern, Op. cit., 184. 37. Cf. pp. 21 and xo2 of my Griechische Geschichte. 38. Plutarch, Solon, 24. 39. A. Zimmern, Op. cit., 348. 40. See my treatise, Babyloniens Kulturmission einst und jetzt (1893), p. 43 if, and cf. Hammurabi'sCode, The Ninetsenth Century and After (Dec., 1903), p. 1035. The 43 years of Hammurabi would be 2194-2152 B.C., at the earliest, they cannot have begun later than about 1980 B.c. See Klio, III (1893), cf. X (1910), 476 ff. 135 if. (especially 157), VIII (1908), if. 54 and furthermore, among others, A. Ungnad, Zeitschr. d. deutsch. mnorgeniind. Gesellschaft, 61 (19o7), 714 ff. 41. ' . . .ihres verginglichen kleinen Vaterlandes unsterbliche, weltumfassende, weltheherrschende Seele'; Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Griechische Trag'dien, Band III, p. 194. 42. Plutarch, Solon, 19. Cf. my Griechische Geschichte, p. 22. 43. Ath. Pol., 5, I; H.-C. 27a, H.-C. 27b and c, probably belong to the same poem. 44. Thuc., VI, 54, Ath. Pol., ii, 2; 12, I.--F. E. Adcock, Klio, VI, 5. 45. See Aristotle und Athen, I, p. 45. Cf., p. 47, n. IO. 46. See my Griechische Geschichte, pp. 21 and 107 f. 47. Ath. Pol., 8, I, 47, I. ae 48. The right meaning of Evyiry has been pointed out by C. Cichorius, Zu den Namen der attischen Steuerklassen in Griechische Studien, Hermann Lipsius dargebracht, Leipzig (1894), pp. 135-140. The evy,lf is not he who has his own yoke of oxen, although of course, the peasants would originally be the chief, if not the only members of this class.-After the development of the Athenian navy the Thetes acted as rowers in the triremes and thus became a very important factor in the national armament. 49. See my Griechische Geschichte, p. 107 if. 50. eo Ath. Pol., 10, i 'T&v e7r' QteL8oEoeLv, ice vov yap EyEvcro. . . Ta ,,ETpa as explained by me, Zeitschrift der Deutschen MorgenlandischenGesellschaft, 63 (1909), p. 728 f, n. 5. 51i. Ath. Pol., 13, z. 52. For the following see my essay, Schatzmeister - und Archontenwabl in Athen, Klio, VI, 304 f. I cannot share the view taken by F. E. Adcock, Klio, XII, 6 f. Cf. foil. note. 53. ipxov'ro Aristotle, Ath. Pol., 22, 5...e7st TEAecrivov (the year might be also 486/5, see Klio, VI [90o6], 308, n. 4), Eivap Evo-av ToVScvva 3 Vr0 j T v fl/oTv iapxovas Ei reYTa/0oo-0Lv rpocpL evTe?, 1o by each of the old 8s4)ot, Twv 7rpoicpLBEvrov (instead of the 40 vX ai, we have here the by the 1oo being pre-elected from each Kleisthenian vuXj) TOTE /ETar TfV Tvpavvt8a 7rpTov. of & 7porTpot (s c. a f ter t h e tyran n y) 7rvTre av aipEoi. irpoicpto-ts, 55 54. See Die Staathaushaltung der Athener, Dritte Auflage, herausgegeben und mit Anmerkungen begleitet von Max Frinkel, I, p. 586 ff., II. For the foll, see Das Mindesteinkommen der Zeugiten und die solonischen Timemata, p. o107-110o of my Griechische Geschichte. 55. History of Greece, vol. III (1869), p. I19 ff. 56. See above, p. 39. 57- See my remarks, Hermes, 35 (19oo), 638, n. i ; Kho, VI, p. 30958. See above p. 13. 59. Aristotle, Ath. Pol., 6, 2-4. Plutarch, Solon, 15 60. Cf. my Griechische Geschichte, p. 6. C. TINLING AND CO., LTD. PRINTERS, 53 VICTORIA STREET, LIVERPOOL This book is a preservation facsimile produced for the University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign. It is made in compliance with copyright law and produced on acid-free archival 60# book weight paper which meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992 (permanence of paper). Preservation facsimile printing and binding by Northern Micrographics Brookhaven Bindery La Crosse, Wisconsin 2013